Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


What is the "logic" in Buddhist logic? By R. Lance Factor

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Revision as of 08:44, 15 December 2012 by VTao (talk | contribs) (Created page with "The history of Indian logic is usually divided into three periods, Old Nyaaya (circa 250 B.C. ) , Buddhist logic (sixth century A.D.) and New Nyaaya. ...")
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Jump to navigation Jump to search

The history of Indian logic is usually divided into

       three  periods,  Old  Nyaaya  (circa  250  B.C.  ) ,
       Buddhist  logic (sixth century A.D.) and New Nyaaya.
       The    Buddhist     logic    text,    Nyaayaprave`sa
       (Introduction   to  Logical   Methods) ,  had  great
       influence  upon Indian and Chinese Buddhism and also
       among   the   Jains.   As   a   pivotal   work,  the
       Nyaayaprave`sa  has received critical attention from
       historians  of religion, philologists, philosophers,
       and logicians.  As with all advances in scholarship,
       there is controversy over interpretation, but in the
       case of Buddhist logic, the controversy  cuts to the
       very heart of the issue of whether Buddhist logic is
       in any recognizable  contemporary  sense  a "logic."
       The received  view holds  that Buddhist  logic bears
       very close  similarities  to syllogistic  forms  and
       that it can be represented  and analyzed by standard
       deductive   techniques.(1)  A  much  different   and
       opposing  view has been argued by Professor  Douglas
       Daye in a series of papers. Daye maintains that "...
       the descriptive  utility of mathematical  logic with
       early  Nyaaya  texts has simply  been overrated";(2)
       that although  the Nyaaya texts contain  metalogical
       rules    for   evaluating    the   "legitimacy    or
       illegitimacy" of arguments, the distinction between
       validity  and  invalidity  does  not  apply;(3) that
       Nyaaya  models are not inferences  but  "formalistic
       explanations";  and that "...  Buddhist logic is not
       deductive, nor can it be formally valid nor is it an
       inference."(4)
           The  cumulative  effect  of these  claims  is to
       assert that Buddhist  logic is not a "logic" at all,
       at least  not in any sense  which  is recognized  by
       Western    philosophers.    There   is   a   radical
       incompatibility  between the Nyaaya methods of logic
       and  those  of  the  Prior  Analytics  or  Principia
       Mathematica.  Of course, there  will be differences,
       possibly  very  great  differences, between  any two
       traditions  so  diverse  as  fourth  century  (B.C.)
       Greece and sixth century (A.D.) India, but are we to
       go so far as to say that the Nyaaya does not contain
       inferences? The radical incompatibility thesis is, I
       maintain, a mistake; moreover, it is a mistake which
       can readily  be uncovered  by examining  the typical
       Nyaaya inference scheme. Of the notion that a Nyaaya
       scheme   could  be  a   "formalistic   explanation"
       without  being an inference, I shall say very little
       because I do not see how anything which functions as
       an explanation  could not involve inferences of some
       kind or other.  It is important  to know whether the
       Nyaaya  scheme  is deductive  or not, and  if it is,
       whether  all  of its  parts  are  essential  to  the
       deduction.  I will demonstrate  that  there  are two
       ways  of  reading  the  Nyaaya  form: one  which  is
       straightforwardly  deductive  and a second  which is
       best  understood  by what  the American  pragmatist,
       C.S.    Peirce,   and    later    Norwood    Hanson,
       call "retroduction."
           To  begin  with,  consider  this  representative
       example from the Nyaaya:(5)
           1. pak.sa (thesis) Sound is imprrmanrne
           2. hetu (mark  or  Reason)  -   Because  of  its
              property of being produced
                               P.184


           3.  d.r.s.taanta  (Exemplification)--Whatever is
               produced, is impermanent
           4.  sapak.sa (similar case)-  As with a pot, and
               so forth
           5.  vipak.sa (dissimilar case)- As (not with the
               case) of space, and so forth
           Tachikawa proposes the following scheme for what
       he calls the "three-membered Indian syllogism:(6)
           6.  There is property p in locus L
           7.  (because) there is property q (in L).
           8.  Wherever  there  is  property  q,  there  is
               property p, as in locus w
       Clearly, if this  schema  is  reversed, (8) and  (7)
       become premises for a valid deductive  inference  of
       (6) as the conclusion.  The reverse  of our  example
       becomes an instance of modus ponens.
           9.  d.r.s.taanta   -   Whatever  is  created  is
               impermanent.
           10. hetu - Sound is created.
           11. pak.sa - Sound is impermanent.
           Why is this instance of modus ponens a matter of
       dispute? The incompatibilists  point  out  that  the
       relationship  between  the  thesis  (pak.sa) and the
       justification  (hetu) is  always  expressed  in  the
       Sanskrit  ablative  case and that this  relationship
       cannot be represented  or translated  as the English
       "therefore"  (or  ergo).  Its  best  translation  is
       "because."   Thus,  for   the  incompatibilist,  the
       primary objection  to identifying  the Nyaaya scheme
       as a deductive  inference  is the  familiar  one  of
       ordinary   language  philosophers   who  resist  the
       translation  of expressions as `q because p' into `p
       ) q' on the  grounds  that  the causal or explanatory
       meaning    of    "because"    is   lost    in   the
       truth-functional conditional.
           This   objection   has  force,  but   one   must
       distinguish     between    the    assertion     that
       truth-functional connectives preserve or capture the
       meaning   of  `q  because  p'  and  the  claim  that
       truth-functional   connectives   can   represent   a
       deductive relationship  between propositions  within
       the  Nyaaya  scheme.  It  is the  latter  which  the
       received  view upholds: it is the former  which  the
       incompatibilist vehemently opposes. The issue is not
       joined, because  surely one can maintain  that there
       is a deductive  inference  in the  inversion  Nyaaya
       scheme  without  maintaining  that  it captures  the
       meaning  of or even  approaches  synonymy  with  the
       original.  In sum, the issue  between  the  received
       view and the incompatibilist  pivots on the former's
       willingness to invert the Nyaaya form and read it as
       a valid deduction  and the latter's insistence  that
       the form cannot be so reversed  without  losing  the
       special relationship  of the hetu.  Given the merits
       of both views and given the fact that both positions
       are  not explicit  contradictories  of one  another,
       there is a way to understand the Nyaaya scheme which
       allows both sides to have their cake and eat it too.
       I believe  that  the three-membered  Nyaaya  is best
       understood   as   a   retroductivc   inference.    A
       retroduction, as  it has  been  described  by C.  S.
       Peirce and
                               P.185
       Norwood  Hansonl  is a pattern  of  reasoning  which
       leads  from  some  phenomenon  or perception  to  an
       explanatory hypothesis of that phenomenon.  Its form
       is not truth-functional nor are the relationships of
       that premises completely rulegoverned.  Peirce said,
       "It must be remembered  that  retroduction, although
       hampered very little by logical rules, nevertheless,
       is logical inference, asserting its conclusion  only
       problematically or conjecturally...."(7)
           Retroduction  does have a recognizable  pattern,
       and indeed  it is very  close  to the three-membered
       syllogism  of Indian logic.  Its form,  according to
       Peirce, is:
           12. The surprizing fact Q is observed.
           13.  But  if P were true, Q would be a matter of
               course.
           14. Hence, there is reason to suspect  that P is
               true.
       As a schema, for retroduction we have:
           (12') q
           (13') q because p
           (14')p
       which  is isomorphic  with that of the Nyaaya  (that
       is, pak.sa, because  hetu  and  d.r.s.taanta;  hence
       there  is evidence  for the pak.sa).  The similarity
       (sapak.sa) and dissimilarity  (vipak.sa) cases serve
       as further  evidence  in support  of the explanatory
       justification.
           The  philosopher  of  science,  Norwood  Hanson,
       argued that retroduction  was a "logic of discovery"
       which  led  to  deductive-nomological  explanations.
       Like Peirce, Hanson pointed out that the reversal of
       a  retroduction  was  a  deductive  inference  'q, q
       because p', becomes 'p, if p, then q, hence q'.  The
       notion of reversal" or inverting" a retroduction  is
       not a technique  or rule of formal logic, but rather
       a simple psychological  description  of changing the
       order of premises.
           If the three-membered  syllogism is retroduction
       and    if   a   retroduction    is   part    of    a
       retroductive-deductive  pair, one should  expect  to
       find internal evidence  for the presence  or absence
       of a deductive fragment. To return to the Nyaaya and
       its commentary on this three-membered  syllogism, is
       there   internal   evidence   to   treat   it  as  a
       retroduction-cum-deduction?  A  crucial   point   of
       philological  interpretation  is the function of the
       ablative  "because"    and  the  meaning  of  "hetu"
       itself. The weakness of the standard view is that it
       disregards  the  special  features  of the  ablative
       "because"   and   translates    the   three-membered
       syllogism as if it contained conditionals. Following
       Daye, I suggest  that  that  move  is too hasty, and
       that  we must regard  the ablative  "because"  as an
       operator connecting the hetu and d.r.s.taanta to the
       thesis.  Since  the Sanskrit  ablative  expresses  a
       relation   of   physical   or  conceptual   removal,
       separation, distinction, or origin, it was  used  to
       convey  the notion of causal explanation.  This fact
       gives  prima facie evidence  for interpreting  it in
       the sense  of "a reason  for." Such an understanding
       is reinforced by the meaning of "hetu," which is the
       name of the explanatory part of the three-
                               P.186
       membered syllogism.  According  to Tachikawa, "hetu"
       primarily  means  'reason'.(8) This is solid  ground
       for reading  'q because  p' as: 'p is the reason for
       q', 'p is the explanatory hypothesis for q', or even
       the Peircean 'if p were true, q would be a matter of
       course'.
           Beyond   points   of  translation,  one  of  the
       strongest   reasons  for  seeing the  three-membered
       syllogism    of    the    Nyaayaprave`sa     as    a
       retroduction-deduction   is  the  existence  of  the
       five-membered   syllogism   in  the  earlier  Nyaaya
       tradition, particularly  the  Nyaaya  Suutra.(9) The
       five-membered  syllogism  of the  Nyaaya  Suutra  is
       perfectly  symmetrical  between  its  three  initial
       retroductive steps and its two culminating deductive
       steps:


           15. Thesis(pratij~naa)   for  example, there  is
               fire on the mountain.
           16. Reason (hetu)- The mountain smokes.
           17. Exemplification   (d.r.s.taata) -   Wherever
               there  is  smoke.  there  is  fire, as  (for
               example) on the hearth in the kitchen.
           18. Recapitulation of the reason (upanaya) - The
               mountain smokes.
           19. Conclusion (nigamana) There is fire on the
               mountain.


       If one were to picture  this pattern as an isosceles
       triangle, one side would represent  the retroduction
       from [15] the pratij~naa  reasoning through the [16]
       hetu to [17] the d.r.s.taanta, and the opposing side
       of  the  triangle  would  represent   the  deduction
       beginning with [17] the d.r.s.taanta to [18] upanaya
       and inferring the nigamana.
           The French  Indologist  Rene Guenon pointed  out
       that  after  the appearance  of the  Nyaaya  Suutra,
       there  were two abridged  forms of the five-membered
       syllogism, (10) in  which  either  the  first  three
       [15-17] or the  last  three  [17-19] parts  appeared
       alone.  Gutnon  also  pointed  out that  the  latter
       abridgment resembles the syllogism of Aristolle; the
       former  abridgment, of course, is precisely  the one
       found in the 6th century  Nyaayaprave`sa  and indeed
       the same smoke-fire example occurs there also. Given
       the  interpretation   I  have  offered,  it  is  not
       surprising  that there should be two abridgments  of
       the five-membered syllogism. One abridgment captures
       the  retroductive  move;  the  second  captures  the
       deductive  move.   Deduction  and  retroduction  are
       inversions of one another, and they can be separated
       by positioning  the  property-locus  statement.  One
       abridgment  reasons from the thesis statement  to an
       explanatory  generalization;  the  other  abridgment
       deduces  the  thesis  from  the generalization.  The
       Buddhist  logicians  Mere quite emphatic about which
       abridgment they favored. The Nyaaya quite explicitly
       says, "We say that these three  statements  make the
       members   of  the  syllogism   and  no  more!  "(11)
       Tachikwa's gloss on this statement indicates that it
       is  an assertion  that  only  three  statements  are
       necessary  for an inference.
           We may conclude that what "inference"  primarily
       meant to the Buddhist logicians was "reasoning to an
       explanatory causal hypothesis"; however, it would be
       wrong   to  further   conclude   that  they  had  no
       appreciation of the
                               P.187


       deductive  abridgment.  To them logic was a means  of
       bringing  others  to  a  recognition   of  particular
       statements;  it was  an upaaya, a heuristic  teaching
       device.    The   retroductive   abridgment   of   the
       five-membered  syllogism clearly teaches in the sence
       that it brings the hearer to an awareness of a causal
       or conceptual  connection.  The deductive  abridgment
       does  not "teach"  in this  sense  because  like  all
       deductions    its   conclusion   does   not   contain
       information  nor already found in the premises, Thus,
       from  the  standpoint  of an upaaya  the retroductive
       inference  is  enough,  or,  as  the  author  of  the
       Nyaayaprave`sa  put it, "...these  three members make
       the [retroductive] syllogism and no more."
           A further  point in favour of reading the Nyaaya
       inference schema as a retroduction  is that it makes
       the  remainder  of the  manual  on logical  methods,
       especially   the  detailed   sections  on  kinds  of
       fallacies, more intelligible and enljghtening.  More
       than  two thirds  of the text covers  identification
       and classification  of fallacies, but none bear  any
       resemblance  to the  formal  fallacies  of deduction
       such  as affirming  the  consequent  or denying  the
       antecedent, nor  does  the system  resemble  Western
       notions  of  an  informal  fallacy.   Fallacies   of
       irrelevance  such  as the  ad  hominem  or post  hoc
       propter  hoc call  attention  to the lack of support
       between  premises   and  putative   conclusion.   In
       Buddhist logic the classification  of fallacies does
       not attempt to circumscribe the ways premises can be
       irrelevant;  on the contrary  it fives criteria  for
       grading the strength or weakness  of the explanatory
       hypotheses.  This is precisely  what is required for
       retroductive  accuracy.  Weak hypotheses  emerge  in
       three circumstances: (1) the hetu is unrecognized by
       proponent or opponent, (2) the hetu is inconclusive,
       or (3) it is contradicted.  Inconclusive  hetus  are
       those  which are not supported  by further  evidence
       from   the  similarity   and  dissimilarity   cases;
       contradicted   hetus  are  those  which   prove  the
       opposite  of the  pak.sa.  Such  a contradiction  is
       established  by deducing the opposite property-locus
       assertion.  A hetu  can fail  to be recognized, that
       is,  it can fail as a teaching  device by not making
       the  auditor  (or speaker) aware  of the  connection
       between the assertion  statement  and its warranting
       hetu.  Thus, when hypotheses  fail to be understood,
       they engender fallacies of recognition, but when they
       fail in evidential  support they engender  fallacies
       of contradiction  or inconclusivity.  On the  whole,
       this   classification   of  fallacies   reflects   a
       sophisticated, but also  a commonsensical, means  of
       evaluating  hypotheses.  It  is  open  textured  as
       retroductive reasoning must be, and more importantly
       it does not attempt (as the Western notion of fallac
       does) to classify fallacious  reasoning as a kind of
       deductive argument gone awry.
           In this paper  I have attempted  to enlarge  the
       dialogue  about  the  nature  of Buddhist  logic  by
       arguing  that  it is  essentially  retroductive.  As
       philosophers    and   psychologists    continue   to
       investigate  the conceptual  and factual aspects  of
       hypothesis  formation, the study  of Buddhist  logic
       will increase  in importance  because, unlike  other
       logical   treatises,  the   Nyaayaprave`sa   is   an
       historyically  significant  document  about  ways of
       reasoning   and   misreasoning   to  an  explanatory
       hypothesis.
                               P.188
       NOTES
           1. Daniel H. H.  Ingalls, Material for the Study
       of Navya-Nyaya  Logic, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
       40  (Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1951);
       Hajime Nakamura, "Buddhist Logic Expounded  by Means
       of  Symbolic  Logic," Indogku  Bukkyogaku  Kenkyu  7
       (1958) :   375-395;   J.   F.   Staal,   "Means   of
       Formalization of Indian and Western Thought," Logic,
       Metlzodology  and Philosophy of Science, Proceedings
       of the XIIth International  Congress  of Philosophy,
       Venice,  1958;   H.   Kitagawa,  "A   Note   on  the
       Methodology  in the Study of Indian Logic," Indogaku
       Bukkyogaku   Kenkyu  8  (1960) :  380-390;   S.   S.
       Barlingay, A Modern  Introduction  to  Indian  Logic
       (Delhi:  National   Publishing   House,  1965) :  A.
       Charlene S.  McDermott, An Eleventh-Century Buddhist
       Logic   of  "Exists,  "  Foundations   of  Language,
       Supplementary Series, vol. 2 (Dordrecht, Holland: D.
       Reidel,  1970);  B.  K.  Matilal,  The  Navya-Nyaaya
       Doctrine  of Negation, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
       46 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press.  1968): and
       particularly  Epistemology,  Logic  and  Grammar  in
       Indian  Philosophical   Analysis,  Janua  Linguarum,
       Series Minor, 111 (Mouton: The Hague, 1971).
           2.  Douglas Daye, "Metalogical Incompatibilities
       In  the  Formal   Description   of  Buddhist   Logic
       (Nyaaya)," Notre  Dame Journal  of Logic  28, no.  2
       (1977): 231.
           3.  Douglas Daye, "Empirical Falsifiability  and
       the  Frequence  of Dar`sana  Relevance  in the Sixth
       Century Buddhist  Logic of Sankaravamin," Logique et
       Analyse 86 (June 1979): 221.
           4.  Douglas Daye, Comparative Issues in Buddhist
       and  Angle-European   Formal   Logics   (unpublished
       manuscript), p. 121.
           5.  Musashi  Tachikawa, trans., "A Sixth Century
       Manual   of  Indian  Logic  (the  Nyaayaprave`sa) ,"
       Journal of Indian Philosophy 1, no. 2 (1971): 114.
           6. Ibid., p. 115, Norwood R. Hanson, Patterns of
       Discovery  (Cambridge: Cambridge  University  Press,
       1958), pp. 93-105.
           "Is There A Logic of Discovery," Current  Issues
       in Philosophy of Science, edited by H.  Fergland and
       G.  Maxwell  (New  York:  Holt-Rinehart  &  Winston,
       1961), pp. 20-35. Also Aristotle, Prior Analytics II,
       25.
           7.  C.  S.  Peirce, Collected  Works (Cambridge:
       Harvard  University  Press, 1933), vol.  1, p.  188.
       Also vol. 6, pp. 522-28.
           8. Tachikawa, p. 116.
           9.   A.  B.  Keith,  Indian  Logic  and  Atomism
       (Oxford: 1921), p.  21.  The author dates the Nyaaya
       Suutra at 200-450 A.D.
           10. Rene Guenon, Introduction generale a l'etude
       des doctrines hindous(Paris: 1930), pp. 226-227.
           11. Tachikawa, p. 122.

Source

ccbs.ntu.edu.tw