Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "The Significance of Nāgārjuna Śūnyatā Doctrine"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " <poem> by Jointu Chakma Introduction: Nāgārjuna is a great figure of Madhyamika school of Mahayana Buddhism who was lived between in the 1st and 2nd century ...")
 
 
(4 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 
+
{{DisplayImages|2083|273|730|862|1197|2061|942|1622|1100|1106|1658|1332|45|1219|1285}}
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
  by Jointu Chakma
+
  by [[Jointu Chakma]]
  
 
Introduction:
 
Introduction:
  
[[Nāgārjuna]] is a great figure of [[Madhyamika school]] of [[Mahayana Buddhism]] who was lived between in the 1st and 2nd century CE.[1] He was born as a "[[Hindu]]," which in his [[time]] connoted [[religious]] allegiance to the [[Vedas]], probably into an upper [[caste]] [[Brahmin]] family and probably in the southern Andhra region of [[India]].[2] According to David J.Kalupahana, [[Nāgārjuna]] has been considered as the [[second Buddha]] and has occupied a second position in the line of [[patriarchs]] in almost all [[schools of Buddhism]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] represented an [[excellence]] [[doctrinal]] [[teaching]] against Śarvāstivādins and Puggalavādins {{Wiki|dogmatic}} dharma-s [[doctrine]] which gained popularity among every {{Wiki|society}} [[people]].  [[Nagarjuna]] wrote [[Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way]] ([[Mulamadhyamakakarika]]), by which after his passing away a school is emerged named as “[[Madhyamaka]] or [[Madhyamika]]” ([[middle-way]]). [[Nāgārjuna]] attempted to make understand about the [[world]] beyond neither believing on [[existence]] (atthita) nor [[non-existence]] (natthita) but everything is dependently co-arising ([[pratityasamutpāda]]) and [[empty]] of [[self-nature]] ([[svabhāva]]) of things. His [[doctrine]] of [[emptiness]] ([[Śūnyatā]]) rejects [[two extremes]] of [[existence]] and [[non-existence]] of things and follows [[middle way]] (madhyamapratipāda).  
+
[[Nāgārjuna]] is a great figure of [[Madhyamika school]] of [[Mahayana Buddhism]] who was lived between in the 1st and 2nd century CE.[1] He was born as a "[[Hindu]]," which in his [[time]] connoted [[religious]] allegiance to the [[Vedas]], probably into an upper [[caste]] [[Brahmin]] [[family]] and probably in the southern [[Andhra]] region of [[India]].[2] According to David J.Kalupahana, [[Nāgārjuna]] has been considered as the [[second Buddha]] and has occupied a second position in the line of [[patriarchs]] in almost all [[schools of Buddhism]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] represented an [[excellence]] [[doctrinal]] [[teaching]] against [[Śarvāstivādins]] and [[Puggalavādins]] {{Wiki|dogmatic}} [[dharma-s]] [[doctrine]] which gained [[popularity]] among every {{Wiki|society}} [[people]].  [[Nagarjuna]] wrote [[Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way]] ([[Mulamadhyamakakarika]]), by which after his passing away a school is emerged named as “[[Madhyamaka]] or [[Madhyamika]]” ([[middle-way]]). [[Nāgārjuna]] attempted to make understand about the [[world]] beyond neither believing on [[existence]] ([[atthita]]) nor [[non-existence]] ([[natthita]]) but everything is dependently co-arising ([[pratityasamutpāda]]) and [[empty]] of [[self-nature]] ([[svabhāva]]) of things. His [[doctrine]] of [[emptiness]] ([[Śūnyatā]]) rejects [[two extremes]] of [[existence]] and [[non-existence]] of things and follows [[middle way]] ([[madhyamapratipāda]]).  
  
 
In this short [[writing]] I will briefly attempt to analyze the [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] with comparison to early [[teaching]] of the [[Buddha]]. I have been attended that almost many of [[scholars]] roughly misunderstand the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[emptiness]] as [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] [[doctrinal]] [[teaching]]. From my position I will summarize to make understand about the significance of [[Nāgārjuna]] [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] with historical background, why [[Nāgārjuna]] reinterpreted the [[doctrine]] of “[[Anatta]]” ([[no-self]]) and “[[Paticcasamuppada]]” ([[dependent co-arising]]) of the [[Buddha]], is neither a [[doctrine]] of [[nihilism]] nor {{Wiki|eternalism}}.  The [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is the fundamental [[doctrine]] of the [[Buddha]] will be examined.
 
In this short [[writing]] I will briefly attempt to analyze the [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] with comparison to early [[teaching]] of the [[Buddha]]. I have been attended that almost many of [[scholars]] roughly misunderstand the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[emptiness]] as [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] [[doctrinal]] [[teaching]]. From my position I will summarize to make understand about the significance of [[Nāgārjuna]] [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] with historical background, why [[Nāgārjuna]] reinterpreted the [[doctrine]] of “[[Anatta]]” ([[no-self]]) and “[[Paticcasamuppada]]” ([[dependent co-arising]]) of the [[Buddha]], is neither a [[doctrine]] of [[nihilism]] nor {{Wiki|eternalism}}.  The [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is the fundamental [[doctrine]] of the [[Buddha]] will be examined.
Line 11: Line 11:
 
The meaning of the term “[[Śūnyatā]]”:
 
The meaning of the term “[[Śūnyatā]]”:
  
[[Śūnyatā]] is a [[Sanskrit]] term, which generally translated into English as ‘[[Emptiness]]’ or ‘[[Nothingness]]’ or ‘[[Voidness]]’, is a {{Wiki|concept}} of central importance in the [[teaching]] of the [[Buddha]].[3] In [[Pāli]] it is called Suññata which stands on the same meaning in English as ‘[[emptiness]]’ or ‘[[voidness]]’ and sometimes it has translated as un-substantiality, phenomenality, freedom from [[lust]], [[ill-will]] and [[dullness]].[4] The [[word]] [[Śūnyatā]] comes from adjective [[śūnya]] (in [[Sanskrit]]), [[suñña]] (in [[pāli]]), śūna (in {{Wiki|vedic}}). These three words are translated as the same meaning of ‘[[empty]]’ or ‘[[void]]’.[5]  [[Empty]] of something else or [[empty]] of [[permanent]] [[substance]] ([[svabhāva]] [[śūnya]]). Actually, this term “[[Śūnyatā]]” is the [[gradual]] development of [[Buddhist]] [[scholasticism]].
+
[[Śūnyatā]] is a [[Sanskrit]] term, which generally translated into English as ‘[[Emptiness]]’ or ‘[[Nothingness]]’ or ‘[[Voidness]]’, is a {{Wiki|concept}} of central importance in the [[teaching]] of the [[Buddha]].[3] In [[Pāli]] it is called [[Suññata]] which stands on the same meaning in English as ‘[[emptiness]]’ or ‘[[voidness]]’ and sometimes it has translated as un-substantiality, phenomenality, freedom from [[lust]], [[ill-will]] and [[dullness]].[4] The [[word]] [[Śūnyatā]] comes from {{Wiki|adjective}} [[śūnya]] (in [[Sanskrit]]), [[suñña]] (in [[pāli]]), [[śūna]] (in {{Wiki|vedic}}). These three words are translated as the same meaning of ‘[[empty]]’ or ‘[[void]]’.[5]  [[Empty]] of something else or [[empty]] of [[permanent]] [[substance]] ([[svabhāva śūnya]]). Actually, this term “[[Śūnyatā]]” is the [[gradual]] [[development]] of [[Buddhist]] [[scholasticism]].
In early [[Buddhist]] literatures “[[emptiness]]” (suññata) was described in the three perspectives, treating it (1) as a [[meditative]] dwelling, (2) as an attribute of [[objects]], and (3) as a type of [[awareness]] release. For example, the [[Buddha]] at [[Samyutta Nikāya]] referring to [[ānāpānasati]] “[[mindfulness]] by in and out [[breathing]]” says:
+
 
“[[Monks]], in this connection, a [[monk]], going to the {{Wiki|forest}} (araññagato) or going to the [[root]] of a [[tree]] (rukkha-mūlagato) or going to an [[empty]] place (suññagāra-gato), sitting cross-legged, holding the [[body]] straight, setting [[mindfulness]] in front of him, mindfully breathes out and in”.[6]
+
In early [[Buddhist]] literatures “[[emptiness]]” ([[suññata]]) was described in the three perspectives, treating it  
 +
 
 +
(1) as a [[meditative]] dwelling,  
 +
 
 +
(2) as an attribute of [[objects]], and  
 +
 
 +
(3) as a type of [[awareness]] [[release]].  
 +
 
 +
 
 +
For example, the [[Buddha]] at [[Samyutta Nikāya]] referring to [[ānāpānasati]] “[[mindfulness]] by in and out [[breathing]]” says:
 +
“[[Monks]], in this connection, a [[monk]], going to the {{Wiki|forest}} ([[araññagato]]) or going to the [[root]] of a [[tree]] (rukkha-mūlagato) or going to an [[empty]] place ([[suññagāra-gato]]), sitting cross-legged, holding the [[body]] straight, setting [[mindfulness]] in front of him, mindfully breathes out and in”.[6]
 
   
 
   
 
  Again in the [[Saṃyutta Nikāya]] the [[Buddha]] explained about the notion of [[emptiness]] when [[Ananda]] asked to the [[Buddha]] in thus;
 
  Again in the [[Saṃyutta Nikāya]] the [[Buddha]] explained about the notion of [[emptiness]] when [[Ananda]] asked to the [[Buddha]] in thus;
“[[Venerable]] Sir, it is said the [[world]] is [[empty]], the [[world]] is [[empty]]. In what [[respect]] the [[world]] is [[empty]]? The [[Buddha]] replied, “Insofar as it is [[empty]] of a [[self]] or of anything pertaining to a [[self]] ([[suññam]] idam attena vā attaniyena vā); thus it is said, [[Ananda]], that the [[world]] is [[empty]]”.[7]
 
  
  The [[Buddha]] clearly explained that the [[self]] is so-called [[world]], and it pertain [[non-self]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] too, explained the meaning of [[Śūnyatā]] in this way, as he denies about the [[existence]] of intrinsic [[self-nature]]. The [[Heart Sutra]] of [[Mahāyāna Buddhism]] declares that the [[skandhas]], which constitute our [[mental]] and [[physical]] [[existence]], are [[empty]] in their [[nature]] or [[essence]], i.e., [[empty]] of any such [[nature]] or [[essence]].
+
“[[Venerable]] Sir, it is said the [[world]] is [[empty]], the [[world]] is [[empty]]. In what [[respect]] the [[world]] is [[empty]]?
 +
 
 +
The [[Buddha]] replied, “Insofar as it is [[empty]] of a [[self]] or of anything pertaining to a [[self]] ([[suññam]] idam attena vā attaniyena vā); thus it is said, [[Ananda]], that the [[world]] is [[empty]]”.[7]
 +
 
 +
  The [[Buddha]] clearly explained that the [[self]] is so-called [[world]], and it pertain [[non-self]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] too, explained the meaning of [[Śūnyatā]] in this way, as he denies about the [[existence]] of intrinsic [[self-nature]].  
 +
 
 +
The [[Heart Sutra]] of [[Mahāyāna Buddhism]] declares that the [[skandhas]], which constitute our [[mental]] and [[physical]] [[existence]], are [[empty]] in their [[nature]] or [[essence]], i.e., [[empty]] of any such [[nature]] or [[essence]].
 +
 
 
  “[[Sariputra]], the [[Characteristics]] of the [[emptiness]] of all [[dharmas]] are non-arising, non-ceasing, non-defiled, non-pure, non-increasing, non-decreasing."[8]
 
  “[[Sariputra]], the [[Characteristics]] of the [[emptiness]] of all [[dharmas]] are non-arising, non-ceasing, non-defiled, non-pure, non-increasing, non-decreasing."[8]
  
The [[word]] “[[Śūnyatā]]” has been interpreted and used for various purposes by the [[Buddha]] himself, and mainly in  [[Nāgārjuna]] [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] it used to denote the [[empty]] of own [[self-nature]] (svalaksana).
+
The [[word]] “[[Śūnyatā]]” has been interpreted and used for various purposes by the [[Buddha]] himself, and mainly in  [[Nāgārjuna]] [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] it used to denote the [[empty]] of [[own]] [[self-nature]] ([[svalaksana]]).
  
  
 
The background of [[Nāgārjuna]] [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]]:
 
The background of [[Nāgārjuna]] [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]]:
  
The [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] evolved during his [[life]] [[time]], it is believed that he was a historical [[human being]] who lived sometime between 150 and 250 CE.[9] The main purpose of developing the [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] is due to [[Abhidharmikas]] interruption against the [[Buddha]] [[teaching]]. [[Abhidharmikas]] developed a [[doctrine]] among many [[Buddhist]] schools that the all [[dharmas]] are [[exists]] in the three period of [[time]]. Therefore, [[Nāgārjuna]] invented the restatement of “[[anatta]]” [[doctrine]] and “[[paticcasamuppada]]” of the [[Buddha]] to answer the dharma-theory of [[Abhidharmikas]]. There are several [[Abhidharmika]] schools by which majority of [[people]] were influenced, such as [[Sarvāstivādins]], Vaibhāsikas, [[Sautrantikas]] and Vātsiputriya. [[Sarvāstivāda]] was the most influential [[abhidharma]] school at that [[time]] which had developed probably by the middle of the 3rd Century B.C.[10] This school opposed to [[Vibhajyavādins]], and claimed that “all [[exists]] ([[sarvam]] [[asti]])” in the [[sense]] of this [[manner]] is: the {{Wiki|past}} dharma-s have existed; the {{Wiki|future}} dharma-s will come into [[existence]]; the {{Wiki|present}} dharma-s are [[existing]]”.[11] All dharma-s in [[phenomenal existence]] are pratītya-samutpanna—dependently originated from an assemblage of [[conditions]]. According to [[Sarvāstivādins]] a [[dharma]] insist within which had in the {{Wiki|past}}, in the {{Wiki|present}} and in the {{Wiki|future}} is real [[existence]]. [[Sarvastivadins]] forwarded the {{Wiki|theory}} of “[[self]] [[nature]]” ([[svabhāva]]) and [[Sautrantikas]] introduced their {{Wiki|conception}} of [[self]] or [[person]] ([[ātman]], pudgala).On the other hand, the [[Vaibhāṣika]] eventually came to connote the {{Wiki|orthodox}} [[Sarvāstivādins]]. The [[Vaibhāṣikas]] maintain that everything [[exist]] for ever (sarvaṃ [[sarvadā]] [[asti]]) it means that all [[dharmas]] [[exist]] in the three periods of [[time]], and the emphasis put on the [[reality]] ([[svabhāva]]) of [[dharmas]] is indicative of the {{Wiki|conception}} that not only their {{Wiki|present}}, but their {{Wiki|past}} as well as {{Wiki|future}} transition, too, represent something real.[12] In the [[Abhidharmakośabhāṣya]] of [[Vasubandhu]] explains about the term “[[dharma]]” as follows:
+
 
“A [[dharma]] is so called because it sustains its own [[characteristics]]. This [[dharma]] faces ([[abhi]]) toward the [[dharma]] in the [[highest]] [[sense]] –[[Nirvāṇa]], or toward the [[characteristics]] of dharma-s, thus it is [[abhidharma]]”.[13]
+
The [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] evolved during his [[life]] [[time]], it is believed that he was a historical [[human being]] who lived sometime between 150 and 250 CE.[9] The main {{Wiki|purpose}} of developing the [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] is due to [[Abhidharmikas]] interruption against the [[Buddha]] [[teaching]].  
 +
 
 +
[[Abhidharmikas]] developed a [[doctrine]] among many [[Buddhist]] schools that the all [[dharmas]] are [[exists]] in the three period of [[time]]. Therefore, [[Nāgārjuna]] invented the restatement of “[[anatta]]” [[doctrine]] and “[[paticcasamuppada]]” of the [[Buddha]] to answer the [[dharma-theory]] of [[Abhidharmikas]].  
 +
 
 +
There are several [[Abhidharmika]] schools by which majority of [[people]] were influenced, such as [[Sarvāstivādins]], [[Vaibhāsikas]], [[Sautrantikas]] and [[Vātsiputriya]]. [[Sarvāstivāda]] was the most influential [[abhidharma]] school at that [[time]] which had developed probably by the middle of the 3rd Century B.C.[10]  
 +
 
 +
This school opposed to [[Vibhajyavādins]], and claimed that “all [[exists]] ([[sarvam]] [[asti]])” in the [[sense]] of this [[manner]] is: the {{Wiki|past}} [[dharma-s]] have existed; the {{Wiki|future}} [[dharma-s]] will come into [[existence]]; the {{Wiki|present}} [[dharma-s]] are [[existing]]”.
 +
 
 +
[11] All [[dharma-s]] in [[phenomenal existence]] are pratītya-samutpanna—dependently originated from an assemblage of [[conditions]]. According to [[Sarvāstivādins]] a [[dharma]] insist within which had in the {{Wiki|past}}, in the {{Wiki|present}} and in the {{Wiki|future}} is real [[existence]]. [[Sarvastivadins]] forwarded the {{Wiki|theory}} of “[[self]] [[nature]]” ([[svabhāva]]) and [[Sautrantikas]] introduced their {{Wiki|conception}} of [[self]] or [[person]] ([[ātman]], [[pudgala]]).On the other hand, the [[Vaibhāṣika]] eventually came to connote the {{Wiki|orthodox}} [[Sarvāstivādins]].  
 +
 
 +
The [[Vaibhāṣikas]] maintain that everything [[exist]] for ever (sarvaṃ [[sarvadā]] [[asti]]) it means that all [[dharmas]] [[exist]] in the [[three periods]] of [[time]], and the {{Wiki|emphasis}} put on the [[reality]] ([[svabhāva]]) of [[dharmas]] is indicative of the {{Wiki|conception}} that not only their {{Wiki|present}}, but their {{Wiki|past}} as well as {{Wiki|future}} transition, too, represent something real.[12] In the [[Abhidharmakośabhāṣya]] of [[Vasubandhu]] explains about the term “[[dharma]]” as follows:
 +
 
 +
 
 +
“A [[dharma]] is so called because it sustains its [[own]] [[characteristics]]. This [[dharma]] faces ([[abhi]]) toward the [[dharma]] in the [[highest]] [[sense]] –[[Nirvāṇa]], or toward the [[characteristics]] of [[dharma-s]], thus it is [[abhidharma]]”.[13]
 
   
 
   
In the Abhidharma-mahā-vibhāṣa-śastra it is said that [[dharmas]] have own-self [[character]] which can not be separated, explained in thus; “The [[entity]] itself is [its] [[characteristic]], and the [[characteristic]] is the [[entity]] itself; for it is the case for all dharma-s that the [[characteristic]] cannot be predicated apart from the [[dharma]] itself”.[14] [[Vātsīputrīyas]] [[ideas]] define those who had in believing a [[pudgala]] or [[existing]] [[person]].[15] [[Sarvāstivādins]] and [[Pudgalavādins]] were connected. The [[Pudgalavādins]] also had connection with Mahāsaṃgikas, i.e. [[Prajñaptivādins]].[16] On contrary of the Abhidharma-schools, [[Nāgājuna]] gave the [[doctrine]] of “[[emptiness]] or [[empty]] of [[self-nature]] or [[empty]] of [[existing]] [[dharmas]]” by which he recounts the “[[anatta]]” [[doctrine]] of the [[Buddha]]. This is the main [[reason]] to maintain the [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] against the dharma-theory of Abhidharmikas-schools.
+
In the [[Abhidharma-mahā-vibhāṣa-śastra]] it is said that [[dharmas]] have own-self [[character]] which can not be separated, explained in thus; “The [[entity]] itself is [its] [[characteristic]], and the [[characteristic]] is the [[entity]] itself; for it is the case for all [[dharma-s]] that the [[characteristic]] cannot be predicated apart from the [[dharma]] itself”.[14] [[Vātsīputrīyas]] [[ideas]] define those who had in believing a [[pudgala]] or [[existing]] [[person]].[15] [[Sarvāstivādins]] and [[Pudgalavādins]] were connected.  
 +
 
 +
The [[Pudgalavādins]] also had connection with [[Mahāsaṃgikas]], i.e. [[Prajñaptivādins]].[16] On contrary of the [[Abhidharma-schools]], [[Nāgājuna]] gave the [[doctrine]] of “[[emptiness]] or [[empty]] of [[self-nature]] or [[empty]] of [[existing]] [[dharmas]]” by which he recounts the “[[anatta]]” [[doctrine]] of the [[Buddha]]. This is the main [[reason]] to maintain the [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] against the [[dharma-theory]] of [[Abhidharmikas-schools]].
 +
 
  
 
[[Nāgārjuna]] “[[Śūnyatā]]” and the [[Buddha]] “[[Anatta]]” [[doctrine]]
 
[[Nāgārjuna]] “[[Śūnyatā]]” and the [[Buddha]] “[[Anatta]]” [[doctrine]]
  
In this sub-topic I would like to analyze with comparison between the [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] “Śūnyata” ([[emptiness]]) and the [[Buddha]] “[[Anattā]]” ([[no-self]]). The {{Wiki|concept}} of [[Ātman]][17] ([[universal]] [[self]]) was the foremost central [[philosophical]] problematic [[doctrine]] among 62 [[views]][18] in [[India]] during the [[time]] of the [[Buddha]]. The {{Wiki|concept}} of [[Ātman]] ([[universal]] [[self]]) is the [[essence]] of the [[human existence]] developed in the [[Upaniṣads]].[19] They believed that the [[Ātman]], the [[self]] which had to be a [[Self]] of some creature needed for itself a certain definiteness in this bond with certain [[substratum]]. In the same [[time]] they developed the [[idea]] of [[ego]], of [[Self]] to [[Brahma]] as [[Supreme Being]] with the one [[name]]. Hermann Oldenberg described in his [[book]] about the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[Ātman]] and [[Brahman]] in thus, “When they wanted to describe [[Ātman]], they said it was [[Brahman]]. If one asked for the [[Brahman]], they explained it as [[Ātman]].”[20] But the [[Buddha]] rejected such kind of {{Wiki|dogmatic}} [[doctrine]] and formed a new {{Wiki|pragmatic}} [[doctrine]] whereas he asserted in detail about “[[Atta]]” ([[self]]) and “[[Anattā]]” ([[no-self]]) in his [[Anattalakkhana sutta]] of [[Samyutta]] Nikayā as follows:
+
 
 +
In this sub-topic I would like to analyze with comparison between the [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] “Śūnyata” ([[emptiness]]) and the [[Buddha]] “[[Anattā]]” ([[no-self]]). The {{Wiki|concept}} of [[Ātman]][17] ([[universal]] [[self]]) was the foremost central [[philosophical]] problematic [[doctrine]] among 62 [[views]][18] in [[India]] during the [[time]] of the [[Buddha]]. The {{Wiki|concept}} of [[Ātman]] ([[universal]] [[self]]) is the [[essence]] of the [[human existence]] developed in the [[Upaniṣads]].[19] They believed that the [[Ātman]], the [[self]] which had to be a [[Self]] of some creature needed for itself a certain definiteness in this bond with certain [[substratum]]. In the same [[time]] they developed the [[idea]] of [[ego]], of [[Self]] to [[Brahma]] as [[Supreme Being]] with the one [[name]]. {{Wiki|Hermann Oldenberg}} described in his [[book]] about the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[Ātman]] and [[Brahman]] in thus, “When they wanted to describe [[Ātman]], they said it was [[Brahman]]. If one asked for the [[Brahman]], they explained it as [[Ātman]].”[20] But the [[Buddha]] rejected such kind of {{Wiki|dogmatic}} [[doctrine]] and formed a new {{Wiki|pragmatic}} [[doctrine]] whereas he asserted in detail about “[[Atta]]” ([[self]]) and “[[Anattā]]” ([[no-self]]) in his [[Anattalakkhana sutta]] of [[Samyutta Nikayā]] as follows:
 +
 
 
“The [[body]], [[monks]], is not self….'Feeling is not [[self]].... [[Perception]] is not [[self]].... {{Wiki|Mental processes}} are not self....Consciousness is not self…..”“Any [[feeling]] whatsoever....Any [[perception]] whatsoever....Any {{Wiki|mental processes}} whatsoever....Any [[consciousness]] whatsoever {{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|future}}, or {{Wiki|present}}; internal or external; blatant or {{Wiki|subtle}}, common or [[sublime]], far or near: every [[consciousness]] is to be seen as it actually is with right [[discernment]] as: "This is not mine. This is not my [[self]]. This is not what I am."[21]
 
“The [[body]], [[monks]], is not self….'Feeling is not [[self]].... [[Perception]] is not [[self]].... {{Wiki|Mental processes}} are not self....Consciousness is not self…..”“Any [[feeling]] whatsoever....Any [[perception]] whatsoever....Any {{Wiki|mental processes}} whatsoever....Any [[consciousness]] whatsoever {{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|future}}, or {{Wiki|present}}; internal or external; blatant or {{Wiki|subtle}}, common or [[sublime]], far or near: every [[consciousness]] is to be seen as it actually is with right [[discernment]] as: "This is not mine. This is not my [[self]]. This is not what I am."[21]
  
[[Nāgārjuna]] in his position sees the [[dharmas]] from an entirely different angle. He reinterprets the causal law ([[pratītyasamutpāda]]) to mean [[relativity]] ([[Śūnyatā]]) and, on the basis of that interpretation, undertakes a through examination of the dharma-theory[22] of the Abhidharma-schools. He criticizes to Abhidharma-schools while examining the dharma-theory in [[relation]] to anātma-doctrine. He rejects both the [[substance]] [[view]] (ātma-vāda) and the modal [[view]] (dharma-vāda). If there is [[no self]], how [[character]] of own [[nature]] ([[svabhāva]]) could be [[ultimate reality]]? In [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] he examines in thus;
+
[[Nāgārjuna]] in his position sees the [[dharmas]] from an entirely different angle. He reinterprets the causal law ([[pratītyasamutpāda]]) to mean [[relativity]] ([[Śūnyatā]]) and, on the basis of that [[interpretation]], undertakes a through {{Wiki|examination}} of the [[dharma-theory]][22] of the [[Abhidharma]]-schools. He criticizes to [[Abhidharma-schools]] while examining the [[dharma-theory]] in [[relation]] to anātma-doctrine. He rejects both the [[substance]] [[view]] ([[ātma-vāda]]) and the modal [[view]] ([[dharma-vāda]]). If there is [[no self]], how [[character]] of [[own]] [[nature]] ([[svabhāva]]) could be [[ultimate reality]]? In [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] he examines in thus;
  
 
In the absence of a [[self]], how can there be something that belongs to the [[self]]? From the appeasement of the modes of [[self]] and self-hood, one abstains from creating the notions of “mine” and “I” (ātmany asati cātmīyam kta eva bhavisyati, nirmamo nirahamkārah samād ātmātmani-nayoh). [23]
 
In the absence of a [[self]], how can there be something that belongs to the [[self]]? From the appeasement of the modes of [[self]] and self-hood, one abstains from creating the notions of “mine” and “I” (ātmany asati cātmīyam kta eva bhavisyati, nirmamo nirahamkārah samād ātmātmani-nayoh). [23]
 
   
 
   
Thus, [[Nāgārjuna]] rejects the dharma-theory of the Abhidharma-schools alike the [[Buddha]] rejects the “soul-theory” ([[ātman]]) of [[Upanisadic]] [[religious]] [[doctrine]]. According to many [[Buddhist]] [[scholars]], the theme of [[Śūnyatā]] emerged from the [[Buddhist]] [[doctrines]] of [[Anattā]]. Of course [[Nāgārjuna]] did not use “[[Śūnyatā]]” [[doctrine]] just only for reinterpreting “[[anattā]]” [[doctrine]], but meaningfully he tried to make clear [[vision]] on [[Abhidharmikas]] {{Wiki|dogmatic}} [[views]] and recounts the [[Buddha]] [[teaching]] that “all dharma-s are without a [[self]]” (sabbe [[dharma]] [[anattā]] ti). [24]
+
Thus, [[Nāgārjuna]] rejects the [[dharma-theory]] of the [[Abhidharma]]-schools alike the [[Buddha]] rejects the “soul-theory” ([[ātman]]) of [[Upanisadic]] [[religious]] [[doctrine]]. According to many [[Buddhist]] [[scholars]], the theme of [[Śūnyatā]] emerged from the [[Buddhist]] [[doctrines]] of [[Anattā]]. Of course [[Nāgārjuna]] did not use “[[Śūnyatā]]” [[doctrine]] just only for reinterpreting “[[anattā]]” [[doctrine]], but meaningfully he tried to make clear [[vision]] on [[Abhidharmikas]] {{Wiki|dogmatic}} [[views]] and recounts the [[Buddha]] [[teaching]] that “all [[dharma-s]] are without a [[self]]” (sabbe [[dharma]] [[anattā]] ti). [24]
 
Then how something do [[exist]] if there is neither-nor, is a common question was asked by [[Abhidharmikas]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] answered it by analyzing casual-law ([[pratityasamutpāda]]).
 
Then how something do [[exist]] if there is neither-nor, is a common question was asked by [[Abhidharmikas]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] answered it by analyzing casual-law ([[pratityasamutpāda]]).
  
Line 49: Line 83:
 
  “One who sees the [[dependent origination]] ([[pratityasamutpāda]]) sees the [[Dhammā]]; one who sees the [[Dhammā]] sees [[dependent origination]]”.[25]
 
  “One who sees the [[dependent origination]] ([[pratityasamutpāda]]) sees the [[Dhammā]]; one who sees the [[Dhammā]] sees [[dependent origination]]”.[25]
  
Here [[Dhammā]] (in the plural) meaning [[phenomena]] or things.[26] According to David J.Kalupahana, these are dependently arisen [[phenomena]] referred to earlier. They may also be described as [[elements]] of [[experience]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] in [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] said:
+
Here [[Dhammā]] (in the plural) meaning [[phenomena]] or things.[26] According to David J.Kalupahana, these are [[dependently arisen]] [[phenomena]] referred to earlier. They may also be described as [[elements]] of [[experience]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] in [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] said:
 
“One who sees all things as [[arising]] in [[dependence]], sees unregenerate [[existence]] and its origin, its [[cessation]] and the [[path]] to its [[cessation]] as they truly are.”[27]
 
“One who sees all things as [[arising]] in [[dependence]], sees unregenerate [[existence]] and its origin, its [[cessation]] and the [[path]] to its [[cessation]] as they truly are.”[27]
 
   
 
   
Line 61: Line 95:
 
“Nothing fails to happen in this way, nothing is not [[empty]].”[30]   
 
“Nothing fails to happen in this way, nothing is not [[empty]].”[30]   
  
[[Nāgārjuna]] represented this [[dependent origination]] [[formula]] of the [[Buddha]] to negate the [[conditions]] ([[pratyaya]]) interpretation of early [[Abhidharmikas]]. He says: “The [[self-nature]] of [[existence]] is not found in the [[condition]], etc.”[31] [[Nāgārjuna]] criticized the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[causation]] presented by the [[Sarvāstivādins]] and the [[Sautrāntika]]. He says: “whatever is [[subject]] to [[conditionality]], is by its very [[nature]] [[tranquil]] and [[empty]]” (Pratītya yad yad bhavati, tat tac śūntam [[svabhāvataḥ]]).[32] “[[Dependent co-arising]]” ([[pratityasamutpāda]]) was, to reiterate, the [[principle]] in terms of which the [[Buddha]] was able to explain the functioning of [[phenomena]] ([[dharma]]) without resorting to a {{Wiki|conception}} of [[permanent]] and [[eternal]] [[entity]] ([[nitya]] [[ātman]]). In this [[sense]], [[emptiness]] ([[śūnyatā]]) of [[Nāgārjuna]] is considered as significant reinterpretation of the [[Buddha’s]] [[dependent co-arising]] ([[pratityasamutpāda]]). So it says that he, who will not understand the [[Buddha’s]] [[dependent origination]], will not able to understand the [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]].  
+
[[Nāgārjuna]] represented this [[dependent origination]] [[formula]] of the [[Buddha]] to negate the [[conditions]] ([[pratyaya]]) [[interpretation]] of early [[Abhidharmikas]]. He says: “The [[self-nature]] of [[existence]] is not found in the [[condition]], etc.”[31] [[Nāgārjuna]] criticized the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[causation]] presented by the [[Sarvāstivādins]] and the [[Sautrāntika]]. He says: “whatever is [[subject]] to [[conditionality]], is by its very [[nature]] [[tranquil]] and [[empty]]” (Pratītya yad yad bhavati, tat tac śūntam [[svabhāvataḥ]]).[32] “[[Dependent co-arising]]” ([[pratityasamutpāda]]) was, to reiterate, the [[principle]] in terms of which the [[Buddha]] was able to explain the functioning of [[phenomena]] ([[dharma]]) without resorting to a {{Wiki|conception}} of [[permanent]] and [[eternal]] [[entity]] ([[nitya]] [[ātman]]). In this [[sense]], [[emptiness]] ([[śūnyatā]]) of [[Nāgārjuna]] is considered as significant reinterpretation of the [[Buddha’s]] [[dependent co-arising]] ([[pratityasamutpāda]]). So it says that he, who will not understand the [[Buddha’s]] [[dependent origination]], will not able to understand the [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]].  
  
  
 
[[Nāgārjuna]] [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] and [[Middle-way]]:
 
[[Nāgārjuna]] [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] and [[Middle-way]]:
  
According to Buddhadassa P.Kirthisinghe, “[[Voidness]] is not nothing, but rather no-thing; no thing that we know by our limited [[consciousness]]. What I [[realized]] in a transcendal state can only be described as no-thing or [[voidness]]”.[33] The main [[teaching]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is the [[doctrine]] of “[[emptiness]]” ([[śūnyatā]]) which is known as “[[Middle-way]]” (Mādhyamapratipada). [[Nāgārjuna]], in his [[Madhyamaka]] [[kārikā]] clearly states that the [[doctrine]] of “[[Śūnyatā]]” itself depends upon and falls under the [[middle way]] position.  
+
According to Buddhadassa P.Kirthisinghe, “[[Voidness]] is not nothing, but rather no-thing; no thing that we know by our limited [[consciousness]]. What I [[realized]] in a transcendal [[state]] can only be described as no-thing or [[voidness]]”.[33] The main [[teaching]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is the [[doctrine]] of “[[emptiness]]” ([[śūnyatā]]) which is known as “[[Middle-way]]” (Mādhyamapratipada). [[Nāgārjuna]], in his [[Madhyamaka]] [[kārikā]] clearly states that the [[doctrine]] of “[[Śūnyatā]]” itself depends upon and falls under the [[middle way]] position.  
  
  “We state that whatever is [[dependent-arising]] that is [[emptiness]]. That is [[dependent upon]] convention. That itself is the [[middle way]]” (Yaḥ pratītyasamutpādaḥ śūnyatām tām pracakṣmahe; yā [[prajñaptir upādāya]] pratipat {{Wiki|saiva}} madhyamā). [34]
+
  “We [[state]] that whatever is [[dependent-arising]] that is [[emptiness]]. That is [[dependent upon]] convention. That itself is the [[middle way]]” (Yaḥ pratītyasamutpādaḥ śūnyatām tām pracakṣmahe; yā [[prajñaptir upādāya]] pratipat {{Wiki|saiva}} [[madhyamā]]). [34]
  
In the [[Kaccāyana]] [[Gotta]] [[sutta]] of [[Samyutta Nikāya]] is clearly stated that the [[Buddha]] avoided two kinds of extreme [[views]], (i) [[existence]] (atthitā) and (ii) [[non-existence]] (natthitā) in thus;
+
In the [[Kaccāyana]] [[Gotta]] [[sutta]] of [[Samyutta Nikāya]] is clearly stated that the [[Buddha]] avoided two kinds of extreme [[views]], (i) [[existence]] ([[atthitā]]) and (ii) [[non-existence]] (natthitā) in thus;
"[[Kaccāyana]] the [[view]] that 'everything [[exists]]' is one extreme. ‘Everything doesn't [[exist]]': That is a second extreme. Avoiding these [[two extremes]], the [[Tathagata]] teaches the [[Dhamma]] via the middle: From [[ignorance]] as a requisite [[condition]] come fabrications…etc.”(Saban atthiti kho [[kaccāyana]] ayam eko anto, sabbam natthiti ayam dutiyo anto ete te ubho ante anupagamma majjhena tathāgato dhammam deseti. [[Avijja]] paccayā sankhārā……etc). [35]
+
"[[Kaccāyana]] the [[view]] that 'everything [[exists]]' is one extreme. ‘Everything doesn't [[exist]]': That is a second extreme. Avoiding these [[two extremes]], the [[Tathagata]] teaches the [[Dhamma]] via the middle: From [[ignorance]] as a requisite [[condition]] come fabrications…etc.”(Saban atthiti kho [[kaccāyana]] ayam eko anto, sabbam [[natthiti]] ayam dutiyo anto ete te ubho ante anupagamma majjhena [[tathāgato]] dhammam deseti. [[Avijja]] paccayā sankhārā……etc). [35]
  
 
[[Nāgārjuna]] recounts the same [[view]] in his Mādhyamikakārikā when he says:
 
[[Nāgārjuna]] recounts the same [[view]] in his Mādhyamikakārikā when he says:
 
“[[Exists]]” implies [[grasping]] {{Wiki|eternalism}} “Does not [[exist]]” implies the [[philosophy]] of {{Wiki|annihilation}}. Therefore a discerning [[person]] should not rely on either [[existence]] or [[non-existence]] (Astiti Sāsvata grāho nāstity [[uccheda]] darsanam, Tasmād astitva nastitve nasriyet vicaksanah). [36]
 
“[[Exists]]” implies [[grasping]] {{Wiki|eternalism}} “Does not [[exist]]” implies the [[philosophy]] of {{Wiki|annihilation}}. Therefore a discerning [[person]] should not rely on either [[existence]] or [[non-existence]] (Astiti Sāsvata grāho nāstity [[uccheda]] darsanam, Tasmād astitva nastitve nasriyet vicaksanah). [36]
  
{{Wiki|Eternalism}} (śasvatavāda) implies the [[existence]] of a transmigrating [[soul]] and [[Nihilism]] ([[ucchedavāda]]) is a [[metaphysical]] {{Wiki|materialistic}} [[views]]. The [[Buddha]] categorically rejected both the [[existence]] of a [[permanent]] [[entity]] called “[[soul]]” that propounded in the early [[Upanisads]] and the [[view]] of “[[nihilism]]” (everything doesn’t [[exists]]) that suggested by the {{Wiki|Materialists}}. Even in the Dhammacakkappavattana-sutta the [[Buddha]] rejected the [[two extremes]] of self-indulgence (kāmasukhallikānuyoga) and [[self-mortification]] (attakilomathānyoga) and followed the [[noble eight fold path]] ([[ariya]] aṭṭhangika maggo) as [[Middle-way]].  
+
{{Wiki|Eternalism}} (śasvatavāda) implies the [[existence]] of a transmigrating [[soul]] and [[Nihilism]] ([[ucchedavāda]]) is a [[metaphysical]] {{Wiki|materialistic}} [[views]]. The [[Buddha]] categorically rejected both the [[existence]] of a [[permanent]] [[entity]] called “[[soul]]” that propounded in the early [[Upanisads]] and the [[view]] of “[[nihilism]]” (everything doesn’t [[exists]]) that suggested by the {{Wiki|Materialists}}. Even in the [[Dhammacakkappavattana-sutta]] the [[Buddha]] rejected the [[two extremes]] of self-indulgence ([[kāmasukhallikānuyoga]]) and [[self-mortification]] ([[attakilomathānyoga]]) and followed the [[noble eight fold path]] ([[ariya]] aṭṭhangika [[maggo]]) as [[Middle-way]].  
  
"[[Bhikkhus]], these [[two extremes]] ought not to be cultivated by one gone forth from the house [[life]]. What are the two? There is [[devotion]] to {{Wiki|indulgence}} of [[pleasure]] in the [[objects]] of [[sensual desire]], which is {{Wiki|inferior}}, low, vulgar, ignoble, and leads to no good; and there is [[devotion]] to [[self]] torment, which is [[painful]], ignoble and leads to no good…"The [[middle way]] discovered by a [[Perfect One]] avoids both these [[extremes]]; it gives [[vision]], it gives [[knowledge]], and it leads to [[peace]], to direct acquaintance, to discovery, to [[nibbana]]. And what is that [[middle way]]? It is simply the [[noble eightfold path]]….,”[37]
+
"[[Bhikkhus]], these [[two extremes]] ought not to be cultivated by one gone forth from the house [[life]]. What are the two? There is [[devotion]] to {{Wiki|indulgence}} of [[pleasure]] in the [[objects]] of [[sensual desire]], which is {{Wiki|inferior}}, low, [[vulgar]], [[ignoble]], and leads to no good; and there is [[devotion]] to [[self]] torment, which is [[painful]], [[ignoble]] and leads to no good…"The [[middle way]] discovered by a [[Perfect One]] avoids both these [[extremes]]; it gives [[vision]], it gives [[knowledge]], and it leads to [[peace]], to direct acquaintance, to discovery, to [[nibbana]]. And what is that [[middle way]]? It is simply the [[noble eightfold path]]….,”[37]
[[Nāgārjuna]] significantly states the rejection of [[Sarvāstivādins]] interpretation of [[self-nature]] in thus;
+
[[Nāgārjuna]] significantly states the rejection of [[Sarvāstivādins]] [[interpretation]] of [[self-nature]] in thus;
 
“Those who see the [[own-nature]], other-nature, being, and [[non-being]] do not see the [[reality]] ([[tattva]]) in the [[Buddha’s teaching]].”[38]
 
“Those who see the [[own-nature]], other-nature, being, and [[non-being]] do not see the [[reality]] ([[tattva]]) in the [[Buddha’s teaching]].”[38]
  
Here he tried to make understand that the [[Buddha’s teaching]] means the [[path]] which leads to middle position. The {{Wiki|western}} [[scholars]] have been often misunderstood and misinterpreted the “[[Śūnyatā]]” [[doctrine]] of Nārārjuna as a [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] [[doctrine]]. [[Madhyamika]] [[Kārika]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] clearly reveals that his [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) is not [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] either, but is the [[Middle-way]] and it is the causal genesis ([[pratityasamutpada]]). The [[Middle-way]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]), implies on the state of [[empty]] from every thing where there is no [[Acceptance]] or {{Wiki|Negation}} and even neither [[Acceptance]] nor {{Wiki|Negation}} (acceptance—middle way—negation).
+
Here he tried to make understand that the [[Buddha’s teaching]] means the [[path]] which leads to middle position. The {{Wiki|western}} [[scholars]] have been often misunderstood and misinterpreted the “[[Śūnyatā]]” [[doctrine]] of Nārārjuna as a [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] [[doctrine]]. [[Madhyamika]] [[Kārika]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] clearly reveals that his [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) is not [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] either, but is the [[Middle-way]] and it is the causal genesis ([[pratityasamutpada]]). The [[Middle-way]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]), implies on the [[state]] of [[empty]] from every thing where there is no [[Acceptance]] or {{Wiki|Negation}} and even neither [[Acceptance]] nor {{Wiki|Negation}} (acceptance—middle way—negation).
  
  
 
Conclusion:
 
Conclusion:
  
Finally [[Nāgārjuna]] comes to conclude his [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) [[doctrine]] in [[logical]] way that the things are based on [[two truths]] in [[reality]]. According to his [[view]] the [[Buddha]] expounded [[two truths]] in thus: “The [[Buddha’s teaching]] rests on [[two truths]]: [[conventional truth]] ([[saṃvṛti]] [[satya]]), and [[truth]] in the [[highest]] [[sense]] ([[paramārtha satya]]). One who does not comprehend the distinction between these [[two truths]], does not comprehend the profound meaning of the [[Buddha’s teaching]].”[39] As it has discussed in above about the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[abhidharmikas]], who claim the [[entity]] ([[svabhāva]]) is ultimately real. But for [[Nāgārjuna]], an [[entity]] could have to depend on other entities. If the [[entity]] is found to be dependent, then {{Wiki|evidence}} will prove that it lacks of [[essence]] ([[svabhāva]]) and is thus not ultimately real. He points out that even [[emptiness]] ([[śūnyatā]]) lacks of [[self-nature]] ([[svabhāva]]) and is thus ultimately unreal. This [[emptiness]] is [[empty]] of really being [[emptiness]], thus, one avoids [[nihilism]]. In [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] he states that there is no differentiation between [[nirvāna]] and [[saṃsara]], because without experiencing the [[true nature]] of [[dukkha]] (un-satisfactoriness) in this [[saṃsara]], how could one realize the [[essentiality]] of [[nirvāna]]. [[Saṃvṛti]] [[Satya]] ([[conventional truth]]) conceals the [[true nature]] of [[reality]]. On the other hand the [[Paramārtha satya]] ([[highest truth]]), which always transcends [[conventional truth]], is beyond [[thought]] and [[language]]. This is why the [[Buddha]] always keep in “[[noble silence]]” when he was questioned on [[metaphysical]] matters, which cannot bring to be {{Wiki|liberated}} from [[Saṃsara]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] in [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] states that the [[Highest Truth]] cannot be understood without [[conventional truth]], thus said: “The [[highest truth]] cannot be taught without recourse to [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[language]]. [[Nirvāna]] cannot be [[realized]], if we do not realize the [[highest truth]].”[40] According to him, [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) is the [[ultimate reality]] as said: “It is [[empty]]” is not to be said, “It is non-empty,” nor “It is both ([[empty]] or non-empty), nor “It is neither”. They are only for the purpose of “[[verbal]] designation” (prajṇāpti).[41] This is the way in which he attempted to establish the [[non-substantiality]] of [[elements]] ([[dharma-nairātmya]]) and the [[non-substantiality]] of the [[human]] [[personality]] ([[pudgala-nairātmya]]).
+
Finally [[Nāgārjuna]] comes to conclude his [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) [[doctrine]] in [[logical]] way that the things are based on [[two truths]] in [[reality]]. According to his [[view]] the [[Buddha]] expounded [[two truths]] in thus: “The [[Buddha’s teaching]] rests on [[two truths]]: [[conventional truth]] ([[saṃvṛti]] [[satya]]), and [[truth]] in the [[highest]] [[sense]] ([[paramārtha satya]]). One who does not comprehend the {{Wiki|distinction}} between these [[two truths]], does not comprehend the [[profound meaning]] of the [[Buddha’s teaching]].”[39] As it has discussed in above about the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[abhidharmikas]], who claim the [[entity]] ([[svabhāva]]) is [[ultimately real]]. But for [[Nāgārjuna]], an [[entity]] could have to depend on other entities. If the [[entity]] is found to be dependent, then {{Wiki|evidence}} will prove that it lacks of [[essence]] ([[svabhāva]]) and is thus not [[ultimately real]]. He points out that even [[emptiness]] ([[śūnyatā]]) lacks of [[self-nature]] ([[svabhāva]]) and is thus ultimately unreal. This [[emptiness]] is [[empty]] of really being [[emptiness]], thus, one avoids [[nihilism]]. In [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] he states that there is no differentiation between [[nirvāna]] and [[saṃsara]], because without experiencing the [[true nature]] of [[dukkha]] (un-satisfactoriness) in this [[saṃsara]], how could one realize the [[essentiality]] of [[nirvāna]]. [[Saṃvṛti]] [[Satya]] ([[conventional truth]]) conceals the [[true nature]] of [[reality]]. On the other hand the [[Paramārtha satya]] ([[highest truth]]), which always {{Wiki|transcends}} [[conventional truth]], is beyond [[thought]] and [[language]]. This is why the [[Buddha]] always keep in “[[noble silence]]” when he was questioned on [[metaphysical]] matters, which cannot bring to be {{Wiki|liberated}} from [[Saṃsara]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] in [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] states that the [[Highest Truth]] cannot be understood without [[conventional truth]], thus said: “The [[highest truth]] cannot be [[taught]] without recourse to [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[language]]. [[Nirvāna]] cannot be [[realized]], if we do not realize the [[highest truth]].”[40] According to him, [[Śūnyatā]] ([[emptiness]]) is the [[ultimate reality]] as said: “It is [[empty]]” is not to be said, “It is [[non-empty]],” nor “It is both ([[empty]] or [[non-empty]]), nor “It is neither”. They are only for the {{Wiki|purpose}} of “[[verbal]] designation” (prajṇāpti).[41] This is the way in which he attempted to establish the [[non-substantiality]] of [[elements]] ([[dharma-nairātmya]]) and the [[non-substantiality]] of the [[human]] [[personality]] ([[pudgala-nairātmya]]).
  
 
To conclude this essay I can obviously assert that the [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is significant among other [[doctrines]] in [[Buddhism]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] did not accept any kind of {{Wiki|dogmatic}} [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], but clearly explained in [[logical]] way and showed to the [[people]] not to attach in [[attachment]] as the [[Buddha]] advised. The [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is the [[teaching]] of the [[Buddha]], which is par [[excellence]].
 
To conclude this essay I can obviously assert that the [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is significant among other [[doctrines]] in [[Buddhism]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] did not accept any kind of {{Wiki|dogmatic}} [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], but clearly explained in [[logical]] way and showed to the [[people]] not to attach in [[attachment]] as the [[Buddha]] advised. The [[Śūnyatā]] [[doctrine]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] is the [[teaching]] of the [[Buddha]], which is par [[excellence]].
Line 103: Line 137:
 
[8]          The [[Heart Sutra]], [[Prajna Paramita]] Hrydaya [[Sutra]], http://www.buddhanet.net/elearning/heartstr.htm; accessed date-25/10/08
 
[8]          The [[Heart Sutra]], [[Prajna Paramita]] Hrydaya [[Sutra]], http://www.buddhanet.net/elearning/heartstr.htm; accessed date-25/10/08
 
[9]          The Internet {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Philosophy]], [[Nāgārjuna]]; http://www.iep.utm.edu/n/nagarjun.htm; accessed date—25/10/08
 
[9]          The Internet {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Philosophy]], [[Nāgārjuna]]; http://www.iep.utm.edu/n/nagarjun.htm; accessed date—25/10/08
[10]            [[Sarvāstivāda]] [[Abhidharma]], [[Bhikkhu]] KL Dhammajoti, [[Sri Lanka]], 2004. p. 33
+
[10]            [[Sarvāstivāda]] [[Abhidharma]], [[Bhikkhu]] [[KL Dhammajoti]], [[Sri Lanka]], 2004. p. 33
 
[11]            Ibid—p.35
 
[11]            Ibid—p.35
 
[12]            {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Buddhism]], Vol-IV, Published by the Government of [[Sri Lanka]], 1979-1989, p.-460
 
[12]            {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Buddhism]], Vol-IV, Published by the Government of [[Sri Lanka]], 1979-1989, p.-460
 
[13]            AKB, 2: svalakṣaṇa-dhāranād dharmaḥ/ tad ayaṃ paramārtha-dharmaṃ vā nirvāṇaṃ dhama-lakṣaṇaṃ vā praty abhimukho [[dharma]] ity abhidharmaḥ
 
[13]            AKB, 2: svalakṣaṇa-dhāranād dharmaḥ/ tad ayaṃ paramārtha-dharmaṃ vā nirvāṇaṃ dhama-lakṣaṇaṃ vā praty abhimukho [[dharma]] ity abhidharmaḥ
[14]            Abhidharma-mahā-vibhāṣa-śastra; 777a, Cf Ny, 432b
+
[14]            [[Abhidharma-mahā-vibhāṣa-śastra]]; 777a, Cf Ny, 432b
 
[15]          The [[Essence]] of [[Scholasticism]], [[Abhidharmahṛdaya]]- T1550, Charles Willemen, {{Wiki|Delhi}}, 2006. p. 15
 
[15]          The [[Essence]] of [[Scholasticism]], [[Abhidharmahṛdaya]]- T1550, Charles Willemen, {{Wiki|Delhi}}, 2006. p. 15
 
[16]            Ibid—p.19
 
[16]            Ibid—p.19
 
[17]            [[Ātman]] is believed by [[Upanishadic]] thinkers as everlasting [[permanent]] [[entity]] of [[self]] who wanders throughout [[Samsara]].
 
[17]            [[Ātman]] is believed by [[Upanishadic]] thinkers as everlasting [[permanent]] [[entity]] of [[self]] who wanders throughout [[Samsara]].
 
[18]            [[Brahmajala sutta]], Digha-nikayā; http://web.ukonline.co.uk/theravada/brahma1.htm--accessed date;25/10/08
 
[18]            [[Brahmajala sutta]], Digha-nikayā; http://web.ukonline.co.uk/theravada/brahma1.htm--accessed date;25/10/08
[19]            The [[doctrine]] of the [[Upanisads]] and the [[Early Buddhism]], Hermann Oldenberg, Reprint: {{Wiki|Delhi}}, 1997. p.34
+
[19]            The [[doctrine]] of the [[Upanisads]] and the [[Early Buddhism]], {{Wiki|Hermann Oldenberg}}, Reprint: {{Wiki|Delhi}}, 1997. p.34
 
[20]            Ibid—p.35
 
[20]            Ibid—p.35
 
[21]            [[Anattalakkhana Sutta]], [[Samyutta Nikaya]] XXII, 59; http://acc6.its.brooklyn.cuny.edu/~phalsall/texts/anatta.txt; accessed date—25/10/08
 
[21]            [[Anattalakkhana Sutta]], [[Samyutta Nikaya]] XXII, 59; http://acc6.its.brooklyn.cuny.edu/~phalsall/texts/anatta.txt; accessed date—25/10/08
Line 120: Line 154:
 
[25]            Majjima [[Nikaya]], ([[Pali]] Text Soceity) Vol.-1, p.283, translated by [[Ñānamoli]] & [[Bhikkhu Bodhi]].
 
[25]            Majjima [[Nikaya]], ([[Pali]] Text Soceity) Vol.-1, p.283, translated by [[Ñānamoli]] & [[Bhikkhu Bodhi]].
 
[26]            [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] of [[Nāgārjuna]], David J.Kalupahana, p.15
 
[26]            [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] of [[Nāgārjuna]], David J.Kalupahana, p.15
[27]            [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]], chapter XXIV, verse-40
+
[27]            [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]], [[chapter]] XXIV, verse-40
 
[28]            Majjima [[Nikāya]] ([[Pali]] Text Soceity), p.655
 
[28]            Majjima [[Nikāya]] ([[Pali]] Text Soceity), p.655
 
[29]            [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]], Chapter-I, verse-1
 
[29]            [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]], Chapter-I, verse-1
Line 129: Line 163:
 
[34]            [[Madhyamika]] [[Kārikā]] XXIV, verse-18
 
[34]            [[Madhyamika]] [[Kārikā]] XXIV, verse-18
 
[35]            SN 12.15; Kaccayanagotta [[Sutta]]; http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn12/sn12.015.than.html; accessed date: 25/10/08
 
[35]            SN 12.15; Kaccayanagotta [[Sutta]]; http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn12/sn12.015.than.html; accessed date: 25/10/08
[36]            [[Madhyamika]] [[Kārikā]] XV, [[verse]] 10
+
[36]            [[Madhyamika]] [[Kārikā]] XV, verse 10
 
[37]          [[Dhammacakkappavattana Sutta]]; http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn56/sn56.011.nymo.html; accessed date—25/10/08
 
[37]          [[Dhammacakkappavattana Sutta]]; http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn56/sn56.011.nymo.html; accessed date—25/10/08
 
[38]            Mūlamadhyamikakārika, chapter-15, verse-6
 
[38]            Mūlamadhyamikakārika, chapter-15, verse-6
 
[39]            Mūlamadhyamaka [[Kārikā]], chapter-XXIV, verses; 8-9
 
[39]            Mūlamadhyamaka [[Kārikā]], chapter-XXIV, verses; 8-9
[40]            Mūlamadhyamaka [[Kārikā]], chapter-XXIV, [[verse]]: 10
+
[40]            Mūlamadhyamaka [[Kārikā]], chapter-XXIV, verse: 10
 
[41]            Mūlamadhyamaka [[Kārikā]], chapter-XXII, verses; 22
 
[41]            Mūlamadhyamaka [[Kārikā]], chapter-XXII, verses; 22
  
Line 140: Line 174:
  
 
Davids, T.W. Rhys -William Stede. [[Pali]]- English {{Wiki|Dictionary}}, {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}} Publication Private Limited.
 
Davids, T.W. Rhys -William Stede. [[Pali]]- English {{Wiki|Dictionary}}, {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}} Publication Private Limited.
Dhammajoti [[Bhikkhu]] KL.  [[Sarvāstivāda]] [[Abhidharma]], [[Sri Lanka]], 2004.
+
[[Dhammajoti]] [[Bhikkhu]] KL.  [[Sarvāstivāda]] [[Abhidharma]], [[Sri Lanka]], 2004.
 
Dr. Fa Qing, Lecture notes on [[Mahāyāna Buddhism]], IBC, 2008
 
Dr. Fa Qing, Lecture notes on [[Mahāyāna Buddhism]], IBC, 2008
 
{{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Buddhism]], Vol-IV, Published by the Government of [[Sri Lanka]], 1979-1989,
 
{{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Buddhism]], Vol-IV, Published by the Government of [[Sri Lanka]], 1979-1989,
Line 147: Line 181:
 
[[Murti]], T.R.V., The Central [[Philosophy]] of [[Buddhism]], Munshiram Manoharlala (Pvt) Ltd., {{Wiki|New Delhi}}, 1998.
 
[[Murti]], T.R.V., The Central [[Philosophy]] of [[Buddhism]], Munshiram Manoharlala (Pvt) Ltd., {{Wiki|New Delhi}}, 1998.
 
[[Ñānamoli]] & [[Bodhi]] [[Bhikkhu]]. Majjima [[Nikaya]], ([[Pali]] Text Soceity) Vol-1.
 
[[Ñānamoli]] & [[Bodhi]] [[Bhikkhu]]. Majjima [[Nikaya]], ([[Pali]] Text Soceity) Vol-1.
Oldenberg, Hermann. The [[doctrine]] of the [[Upanisads]] and the [[Early Buddhism]], Reprint: {{Wiki|Delhi}}, 1997.
+
[[Oldenberg]], Hermann. The [[doctrine]] of the [[Upanisads]] and the [[Early Buddhism]], Reprint: {{Wiki|Delhi}}, 1997.
 
Suzuki, D.T. Outlines of [[Mahayana Buddhism]], Munshiram Manoharlal, {{Wiki|New Delhi}}, 2000.  
 
Suzuki, D.T. Outlines of [[Mahayana Buddhism]], Munshiram Manoharlal, {{Wiki|New Delhi}}, 2000.  
 
[[Thera]] [[Narada]], The [[Dhammapada]], 4rd Edition 1993,
 
[[Thera]] [[Narada]], The [[Dhammapada]], 4rd Edition 1993,

Latest revision as of 06:03, 14 April 2015

Grenb 05.jpg
Buddhsd.jpg
Kuh0029.JPG
1296 he-hill.jpg
142256 n.jpg
Bcbvge.jpg
Teps one bow.jpg
Sakjamuni-Troonil-00.jpg
Ksitigarbha-es25.jpg
Buddha wer.jpg
12122..jpg
28825-1.jpg
Lord-Bu.jpg
Tthaya ruins.jpg
Z4ini(5)x.jpg

 by Jointu Chakma

Introduction:

Nāgārjuna is a great figure of Madhyamika school of Mahayana Buddhism who was lived between in the 1st and 2nd century CE.[1] He was born as a "Hindu," which in his time connoted religious allegiance to the Vedas, probably into an upper caste Brahmin family and probably in the southern Andhra region of India.[2] According to David J.Kalupahana, Nāgārjuna has been considered as the second Buddha and has occupied a second position in the line of patriarchs in almost all schools of Buddhism. Nāgārjuna represented an excellence doctrinal teaching against Śarvāstivādins and Puggalavādins dogmatic dharma-s doctrine which gained popularity among every society people. Nagarjuna wrote Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way (Mulamadhyamakakarika), by which after his passing away a school is emerged named as “Madhyamaka or Madhyamika” (middle-way). Nāgārjuna attempted to make understand about the world beyond neither believing on existence (atthita) nor non-existence (natthita) but everything is dependently co-arising (pratityasamutpāda) and empty of self-nature (svabhāva) of things. His doctrine of emptiness (Śūnyatā) rejects two extremes of existence and non-existence of things and follows middle way (madhyamapratipāda).

In this short writing I will briefly attempt to analyze the Śūnyatā (emptiness) doctrine of Nāgārjuna with comparison to early teaching of the Buddha. I have been attended that almost many of scholars roughly misunderstand the concept of emptiness as nihilistic doctrinal teaching. From my position I will summarize to make understand about the significance of Nāgārjuna Śūnyatā doctrine with historical background, why Nāgārjuna reinterpreted the doctrine of “Anatta” (no-self) and “Paticcasamuppada” (dependent co-arising) of the Buddha, is neither a doctrine of nihilism nor eternalism. The Śūnyatā doctrine of Nāgārjuna is the fundamental doctrine of the Buddha will be examined.

The meaning of the term “Śūnyatā”:

Śūnyatā is a Sanskrit term, which generally translated into English as ‘Emptiness’ or ‘Nothingness’ or ‘Voidness’, is a concept of central importance in the teaching of the Buddha.[3] In Pāli it is called Suññata which stands on the same meaning in English as ‘emptiness’ or ‘voidness’ and sometimes it has translated as un-substantiality, phenomenality, freedom from lust, ill-will and dullness.[4] The word Śūnyatā comes from adjective śūnya (in Sanskrit), suñña (in pāli), śūna (in vedic). These three words are translated as the same meaning of ‘empty’ or ‘void’.[5] Empty of something else or empty of permanent substance (svabhāva śūnya). Actually, this term “Śūnyatā” is the gradual development of Buddhist scholasticism.

In early Buddhist literatures “emptiness” (suññata) was described in the three perspectives, treating it

(1) as a meditative dwelling,

(2) as an attribute of objects, and

(3) as a type of awareness release.


For example, the Buddha at Samyutta Nikāya referring to ānāpānasatimindfulness by in and out breathing” says:
Monks, in this connection, a monk, going to the forest (araññagato) or going to the root of a tree (rukkha-mūlagato) or going to an empty place (suññagāra-gato), sitting cross-legged, holding the body straight, setting mindfulness in front of him, mindfully breathes out and in”.[6]
 
 Again in the Saṃyutta Nikāya the Buddha explained about the notion of emptiness when Ananda asked to the Buddha in thus;

Venerable Sir, it is said the world is empty, the world is empty. In what respect the world is empty?

The Buddha replied, “Insofar as it is empty of a self or of anything pertaining to a self (suññam idam attena vā attaniyena vā); thus it is said, Ananda, that the world is empty”.[7]

 The Buddha clearly explained that the self is so-called world, and it pertain non-self. Nāgārjuna too, explained the meaning of Śūnyatā in this way, as he denies about the existence of intrinsic self-nature.

The Heart Sutra of Mahāyāna Buddhism declares that the skandhas, which constitute our mental and physical existence, are empty in their nature or essence, i.e., empty of any such nature or essence.

 “Sariputra, the Characteristics of the emptiness of all dharmas are non-arising, non-ceasing, non-defiled, non-pure, non-increasing, non-decreasing."[8]

The wordŚūnyatā” has been interpreted and used for various purposes by the Buddha himself, and mainly in Nāgārjuna Śūnyatā doctrine it used to denote the empty of own self-nature (svalaksana).


The background of Nāgārjuna Śūnyatā doctrine:


The Śūnyatā (emptiness) doctrine of Nāgārjuna evolved during his life time, it is believed that he was a historical human being who lived sometime between 150 and 250 CE.[9] The main purpose of developing the Śūnyatā doctrine is due to Abhidharmikas interruption against the Buddha teaching.

Abhidharmikas developed a doctrine among many Buddhist schools that the all dharmas are exists in the three period of time. Therefore, Nāgārjuna invented the restatement of “anattadoctrine and “paticcasamuppada” of the Buddha to answer the dharma-theory of Abhidharmikas.

There are several Abhidharmika schools by which majority of people were influenced, such as Sarvāstivādins, Vaibhāsikas, Sautrantikas and Vātsiputriya. Sarvāstivāda was the most influential abhidharma school at that time which had developed probably by the middle of the 3rd Century B.C.[10]

This school opposed to Vibhajyavādins, and claimed that “all exists (sarvam asti)” in the sense of this manner is: the past dharma-s have existed; the future dharma-s will come into existence; the present dharma-s are existing”.

[11] All dharma-s in phenomenal existence are pratītya-samutpanna—dependently originated from an assemblage of conditions. According to Sarvāstivādins a dharma insist within which had in the past, in the present and in the future is real existence. Sarvastivadins forwarded the theory of “self nature” (svabhāva) and Sautrantikas introduced their conception of self or person (ātman, pudgala).On the other hand, the Vaibhāṣika eventually came to connote the orthodox Sarvāstivādins.

The Vaibhāṣikas maintain that everything exist for ever (sarvaṃ sarvadā asti) it means that all dharmas exist in the three periods of time, and the emphasis put on the reality (svabhāva) of dharmas is indicative of the conception that not only their present, but their past as well as future transition, too, represent something real.[12] In the Abhidharmakośabhāṣya of Vasubandhu explains about the term “dharma” as follows:


“A dharma is so called because it sustains its own characteristics. This dharma faces (abhi) toward the dharma in the highest senseNirvāṇa, or toward the characteristics of dharma-s, thus it is abhidharma”.[13]
 
In the Abhidharma-mahā-vibhāṣa-śastra it is said that dharmas have own-self character which can not be separated, explained in thus; “The entity itself is [its] characteristic, and the characteristic is the entity itself; for it is the case for all dharma-s that the characteristic cannot be predicated apart from the dharma itself”.[14] Vātsīputrīyas ideas define those who had in believing a pudgala or existing person.[15] Sarvāstivādins and Pudgalavādins were connected.

The Pudgalavādins also had connection with Mahāsaṃgikas, i.e. Prajñaptivādins.[16] On contrary of the Abhidharma-schools, Nāgājuna gave the doctrine of “emptiness or empty of self-nature or empty of existing dharmas” by which he recounts the “anattadoctrine of the Buddha. This is the main reason to maintain the Śūnyatā doctrine of Nāgārjuna against the dharma-theory of Abhidharmikas-schools.


NāgārjunaŚūnyatā” and the BuddhaAnattadoctrine


In this sub-topic I would like to analyze with comparison between the doctrine of Nāgārjuna “Śūnyata” (emptiness) and the BuddhaAnattā” (no-self). The concept of Ātman[17] (universal self) was the foremost central philosophical problematic doctrine among 62 views[18] in India during the time of the Buddha. The concept of Ātman (universal self) is the essence of the human existence developed in the Upaniṣads.[19] They believed that the Ātman, the self which had to be a Self of some creature needed for itself a certain definiteness in this bond with certain substratum. In the same time they developed the idea of ego, of Self to Brahma as Supreme Being with the one name. Hermann Oldenberg described in his book about the concept of Ātman and Brahman in thus, “When they wanted to describe Ātman, they said it was Brahman. If one asked for the Brahman, they explained it as Ātman.”[20] But the Buddha rejected such kind of dogmatic doctrine and formed a new pragmatic doctrine whereas he asserted in detail about “Atta” (self) and “Anattā” (no-self) in his Anattalakkhana sutta of Samyutta Nikayā as follows:

“The body, monks, is not self….'Feeling is not self.... Perception is not self.... Mental processes are not self....Consciousness is not self…..”“Any feeling whatsoever....Any perception whatsoever....Any mental processes whatsoever....Any consciousness whatsoever past, future, or present; internal or external; blatant or subtle, common or sublime, far or near: every consciousness is to be seen as it actually is with right discernment as: "This is not mine. This is not my self. This is not what I am."[21]

Nāgārjuna in his position sees the dharmas from an entirely different angle. He reinterprets the causal law (pratītyasamutpāda) to mean relativity (Śūnyatā) and, on the basis of that interpretation, undertakes a through examination of the dharma-theory[22] of the Abhidharma-schools. He criticizes to Abhidharma-schools while examining the dharma-theory in relation to anātma-doctrine. He rejects both the substance view (ātma-vāda) and the modal view (dharma-vāda). If there is no self, how character of own nature (svabhāva) could be ultimate reality? In Mūlamadhyamakakārikā he examines in thus;

In the absence of a self, how can there be something that belongs to the self? From the appeasement of the modes of self and self-hood, one abstains from creating the notions of “mine” and “I” (ātmany asati cātmīyam kta eva bhavisyati, nirmamo nirahamkārah samād ātmātmani-nayoh). [23]
 
Thus, Nāgārjuna rejects the dharma-theory of the Abhidharma-schools alike the Buddha rejects the “soul-theory” (ātman) of Upanisadic religious doctrine. According to many Buddhist scholars, the theme of Śūnyatā emerged from the Buddhist doctrines of Anattā. Of course Nāgārjuna did not use “Śūnyatādoctrine just only for reinterpreting “anattādoctrine, but meaningfully he tried to make clear vision on Abhidharmikas dogmatic views and recounts the Buddha teaching that “all dharma-s are without a self” (sabbe dharma anattā ti). [24]
Then how something do exist if there is neither-nor, is a common question was asked by Abhidharmikas. Nāgārjuna answered it by analyzing casual-law (pratityasamutpāda).


Nāgārjuna Śūnyatā and Pratityasamutpāda:

The Buddhist doctrine of Interdependent Origination implying as it does from the Madhyamaka standpoint, the continuity of cause (hetu) and effect (phala), the avoidance of alternative views and ultimately Emptiness (śūnyata). Madhyamaka is not nihilism (nāstivāda), but a clarification of dependent co-arising. Nāgārjuna reclaimed the doctrine of dependent co-arising as a doctrine of emptiness. The Buddha's teaching called Paticca-samuppada, usually translated as Dependent Origination, is fundamental to the Dhammā (Truth) awakened to by The Buddha on the night of His Enlightenment. The Buddha said:
 “One who sees the dependent origination (pratityasamutpāda) sees the Dhammā; one who sees the Dhammā sees dependent origination”.[25]

Here Dhammā (in the plural) meaning phenomena or things.[26] According to David J.Kalupahana, these are dependently arisen phenomena referred to earlier. They may also be described as elements of experience. Nāgārjuna in Mūlamadhyamakakārikā said:
“One who sees all things as arising in dependence, sees unregenerate existence and its origin, its cessation and the path to its cessation as they truly are.”[27]
 
The dependent origination describes the dependence of all phenomena upon cause (hetu) and condition (pratyaya), thus:
 “When this exists, that comes to be; with the arising of this, that arises. When this doest not exist, that does not come to be; with the cessation of this, that ceases” (Imasmim sati idam hoti, imassa upādā idam uppajjati. Imasmim asati idam na hoti, imassa nirodha idam nirujjhati).[28]

Nāgārjuna wrote in the causality verses of Mūlamadhyamakakārikā in thus:
“Nothing whatever arises. Not from itself, not from another, not from both itself and another, and not without a cause.”[29]

Nāgārjuna significantly justified and examined that the emptiness is only way to be seen as possibility of relational arising, indeed as that without which nothing is possible.
“Nothing fails to happen in this way, nothing is not empty.”[30]

Nāgārjuna represented this dependent origination formula of the Buddha to negate the conditions (pratyaya) interpretation of early Abhidharmikas. He says: “The self-nature of existence is not found in the condition, etc.”[31] Nāgārjuna criticized the theory of causation presented by the Sarvāstivādins and the Sautrāntika. He says: “whatever is subject to conditionality, is by its very nature tranquil and empty” (Pratītya yad yad bhavati, tat tac śūntam svabhāvataḥ).[32] “Dependent co-arising” (pratityasamutpāda) was, to reiterate, the principle in terms of which the Buddha was able to explain the functioning of phenomena (dharma) without resorting to a conception of permanent and eternal entity (nitya ātman). In this sense, emptiness (śūnyatā) of Nāgārjuna is considered as significant reinterpretation of the Buddha’s dependent co-arising (pratityasamutpāda). So it says that he, who will not understand the Buddha’s dependent origination, will not able to understand the Śūnyatā doctrine of Nāgārjuna.


Nāgārjuna Śūnyatā doctrine and Middle-way:

According to Buddhadassa P.Kirthisinghe, “Voidness is not nothing, but rather no-thing; no thing that we know by our limited consciousness. What I realized in a transcendal state can only be described as no-thing or voidness”.[33] The main teaching of Nāgārjuna is the doctrine of “emptiness” (śūnyatā) which is known as “Middle-way” (Mādhyamapratipada). Nāgārjuna, in his Madhyamaka kārikā clearly states that the doctrine of “Śūnyatā” itself depends upon and falls under the middle way position.

 “We state that whatever is dependent-arising that is emptiness. That is dependent upon convention. That itself is the middle way” (Yaḥ pratītyasamutpādaḥ śūnyatām tām pracakṣmahe; yā prajñaptir upādāya pratipat saiva madhyamā). [34]

In the Kaccāyana Gotta sutta of Samyutta Nikāya is clearly stated that the Buddha avoided two kinds of extreme views, (i) existence (atthitā) and (ii) non-existence (natthitā) in thus;
"Kaccāyana the view that 'everything exists' is one extreme. ‘Everything doesn't exist': That is a second extreme. Avoiding these two extremes, the Tathagata teaches the Dhamma via the middle: From ignorance as a requisite condition come fabrications…etc.”(Saban atthiti kho kaccāyana ayam eko anto, sabbam natthiti ayam dutiyo anto ete te ubho ante anupagamma majjhena tathāgato dhammam deseti. Avijja paccayā sankhārā……etc). [35]

Nāgārjuna recounts the same view in his Mādhyamikakārikā when he says:
Exists” implies grasping eternalism “Does not exist” implies the philosophy of annihilation. Therefore a discerning person should not rely on either existence or non-existence (Astiti Sāsvata grāho nāstity uccheda darsanam, Tasmād astitva nastitve nasriyet vicaksanah). [36]

Eternalism (śasvatavāda) implies the existence of a transmigrating soul and Nihilism (ucchedavāda) is a metaphysical materialistic views. The Buddha categorically rejected both the existence of a permanent entity called “soul” that propounded in the early Upanisads and the view of “nihilism” (everything doesn’t exists) that suggested by the Materialists. Even in the Dhammacakkappavattana-sutta the Buddha rejected the two extremes of self-indulgence (kāmasukhallikānuyoga) and self-mortification (attakilomathānyoga) and followed the noble eight fold path (ariya aṭṭhangika maggo) as Middle-way.

"Bhikkhus, these two extremes ought not to be cultivated by one gone forth from the house life. What are the two? There is devotion to indulgence of pleasure in the objects of sensual desire, which is inferior, low, vulgar, ignoble, and leads to no good; and there is devotion to self torment, which is painful, ignoble and leads to no good…"The middle way discovered by a Perfect One avoids both these extremes; it gives vision, it gives knowledge, and it leads to peace, to direct acquaintance, to discovery, to nibbana. And what is that middle way? It is simply the noble eightfold path….,”[37]
Nāgārjuna significantly states the rejection of Sarvāstivādins interpretation of self-nature in thus;
“Those who see the own-nature, other-nature, being, and non-being do not see the reality (tattva) in the Buddha’s teaching.”[38]

Here he tried to make understand that the Buddha’s teaching means the path which leads to middle position. The western scholars have been often misunderstood and misinterpreted the “Śūnyatādoctrine of Nārārjuna as a nihilistic doctrine. Madhyamika Kārika of Nāgārjuna clearly reveals that his Śūnyatā (emptiness) is not nihilistic either, but is the Middle-way and it is the causal genesis (pratityasamutpada). The Middle-way of Nāgārjuna is Śūnyatā (emptiness), implies on the state of empty from every thing where there is no Acceptance or Negation and even neither Acceptance nor Negation (acceptance—middle way—negation).


Conclusion:

Finally Nāgārjuna comes to conclude his Śūnyatā (emptiness) doctrine in logical way that the things are based on two truths in reality. According to his view the Buddha expounded two truths in thus: “The Buddha’s teaching rests on two truths: conventional truth (saṃvṛti satya), and truth in the highest sense (paramārtha satya). One who does not comprehend the distinction between these two truths, does not comprehend the profound meaning of the Buddha’s teaching.”[39] As it has discussed in above about the concept of abhidharmikas, who claim the entity (svabhāva) is ultimately real. But for Nāgārjuna, an entity could have to depend on other entities. If the entity is found to be dependent, then evidence will prove that it lacks of essence (svabhāva) and is thus not ultimately real. He points out that even emptiness (śūnyatā) lacks of self-nature (svabhāva) and is thus ultimately unreal. This emptiness is empty of really being emptiness, thus, one avoids nihilism. In Mūlamadhyamakakārikā he states that there is no differentiation between nirvāna and saṃsara, because without experiencing the true nature of dukkha (un-satisfactoriness) in this saṃsara, how could one realize the essentiality of nirvāna. Saṃvṛti Satya (conventional truth) conceals the true nature of reality. On the other hand the Paramārtha satya (highest truth), which always transcends conventional truth, is beyond thought and language. This is why the Buddha always keep in “noble silence” when he was questioned on metaphysical matters, which cannot bring to be liberated from Saṃsara. Nāgārjuna in Mūlamadhyamakakārikā states that the Highest Truth cannot be understood without conventional truth, thus said: “The highest truth cannot be taught without recourse to conventional language. Nirvāna cannot be realized, if we do not realize the highest truth.”[40] According to him, Śūnyatā (emptiness) is the ultimate reality as said: “It is empty” is not to be said, “It is non-empty,” nor “It is both (empty or non-empty), nor “It is neither”. They are only for the purpose of “verbal designation” (prajṇāpti).[41] This is the way in which he attempted to establish the non-substantiality of elements (dharma-nairātmya) and the non-substantiality of the human personality (pudgala-nairātmya).

To conclude this essay I can obviously assert that the Śūnyatā doctrine of Nāgārjuna is significant among other doctrines in Buddhism. Nāgārjuna did not accept any kind of dogmatic concepts, but clearly explained in logical way and showed to the people not to attach in attachment as the Buddha advised. The Śūnyatā doctrine of Nāgārjuna is the teaching of the Buddha, which is par excellence.
 _______________________________________________________________________________
 End Notes:
__________

[1] Nāgārjuna, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy; http://www.iep.utm.edu/n/nagarjun.htm, accessed date;25/10/08
[2] Ibid—
[3] Wikipedia; http://www.answers.com/topic/sunyata; accessed date: 25/10/08
[4] Pali- English Dictionary, T.W. Rhys Davids-William Stede—Motilal Banarsidass Publication Private Limited- P.717
[5] Ibid—
[6] The Notion of Emptiness in Early Buddhism, Choong Mun-keat, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi, 1999, p.8]
[7] Saṃyutta Nikayā, IV 35.85, p.54
[8] The Heart Sutra, Prajna Paramita Hrydaya Sutra, http://www.buddhanet.net/elearning/heartstr.htm; accessed date-25/10/08
[9] The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Nāgārjuna; http://www.iep.utm.edu/n/nagarjun.htm; accessed date—25/10/08
[10] Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma, Bhikkhu KL Dhammajoti, Sri Lanka, 2004. p. 33
[11] Ibid—p.35
[12] Encyclopedia of Buddhism, Vol-IV, Published by the Government of Sri Lanka, 1979-1989, p.-460
[13] AKB, 2: svalakṣaṇa-dhāranād dharmaḥ/ tad ayaṃ paramārtha-dharmaṃ vā nirvāṇaṃ dhama-lakṣaṇaṃ vā praty abhimukho dharma ity abhidharmaḥ
[14] Abhidharma-mahā-vibhāṣa-śastra; 777a, Cf Ny, 432b
[15] The Essence of Scholasticism, Abhidharmahṛdaya- T1550, Charles Willemen, Delhi, 2006. p. 15
[16] Ibid—p.19
[17] Ātman is believed by Upanishadic thinkers as everlasting permanent entity of self who wanders throughout Samsara.
[18] Brahmajala sutta, Digha-nikayā; http://web.ukonline.co.uk/theravada/brahma1.htm--accessed date;25/10/08
[19] The doctrine of the Upanisads and the Early Buddhism, Hermann Oldenberg, Reprint: Delhi, 1997. p.34
[20] Ibid—p.35
[21] Anattalakkhana Sutta, Samyutta Nikaya XXII, 59; http://acc6.its.brooklyn.cuny.edu/~phalsall/texts/anatta.txt; accessed date—25/10/08
[22] Abhidharmikas believe that the dharma or svabhāva is as reality and exits for all three period of time.
[23] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā of Nāgārjuna, David J. Kalupahana, Reprint: Delhi, 1996, 1999. p. 264
[24] Dhammapada (Pali version), verse;-279
[25] Majjima Nikaya, (Pali Text Soceity) Vol.-1, p.283, translated by Ñānamoli & Bhikkhu Bodhi.
[26] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā of Nāgārjuna, David J.Kalupahana, p.15
[27] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, chapter XXIV, verse-40
[28] Majjima Nikāya (Pali Text Soceity), p.655
[29] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, Chapter-I, verse-1
[30] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, XXIV, verse-19
[31] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā of Nāgārjuna, David J.Kalupahana, p. 32
[32] Outlines of Mahayana Buddhism, D.T.Suzuki, Munshiram Manoharlal, New Delhi, 2000. p.172
[33] Buddhism and Science, Buddhada Kirthisinghe, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi-1993, 1996. p.89
[34] Madhyamika Kārikā XXIV, verse-18
[35] SN 12.15; Kaccayanagotta Sutta; http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn12/sn12.015.than.html; accessed date: 25/10/08
[36] Madhyamika Kārikā XV, verse 10
[37] Dhammacakkappavattana Sutta; http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn56/sn56.011.nymo.html; accessed date—25/10/08
[38] Mūlamadhyamikakārika, chapter-15, verse-6
[39] Mūlamadhyamaka Kārikā, chapter-XXIV, verses; 8-9
[40] Mūlamadhyamaka Kārikā, chapter-XXIV, verse: 10
[41] Mūlamadhyamaka Kārikā, chapter-XXII, verses; 22

Bibliography
 ____________

Davids, T.W. Rhys -William Stede. Pali- English Dictionary, Motilal Banarsidass Publication Private Limited.
Dhammajoti Bhikkhu KL. Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma, Sri Lanka, 2004.
Dr. Fa Qing, Lecture notes on Mahāyāna Buddhism, IBC, 2008
Encyclopedia of Buddhism, Vol-IV, Published by the Government of Sri Lanka, 1979-1989,
JR.C.W. Huntington. The Emptiness of Emptiness, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi—2003. Kalupahana, David J. Mūlamadhyamakakārikā of Nāgārjuna, Reprint: Delhi, 1996, 1999.
Mun-keat, Choong. The Notion of Emptiness in Early Buddhism, Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi, 1999.
Murti, T.R.V., The Central Philosophy of Buddhism, Munshiram Manoharlala (Pvt) Ltd., New Delhi, 1998.
Ñānamoli & Bodhi Bhikkhu. Majjima Nikaya, (Pali Text Soceity) Vol-1.
Oldenberg, Hermann. The doctrine of the Upanisads and the Early Buddhism, Reprint: Delhi, 1997.
Suzuki, D.T. Outlines of Mahayana Buddhism, Munshiram Manoharlal, New Delhi, 2000.
Thera Narada, The Dhammapada, 4rd Edition 1993,
Willemen, Charles. The Essence of Scholasticism, Abhidharmahṛdaya- T1550, Delhi—2006.

Internet Sources:
Anattalakkhana Sutta, Samyutta Nikaya XXII, 59;
 http://acc6.its.brooklyn.cuny.edu/~phalsall/texts/anatta.txt
Brahmajala sutta, Digha-nikayā; http://web.ukonline.co.uk/theravada/brahma1.htm
Dhammacakkappavattana Sutta;
 http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn56/sn56.011.nymo.html
Nāgārjuna, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy; http://www.iep.utm.edu/n/nagarjun.htm
The Heart Sutra, Prajna Paramita Hrydaya Sutra,
 http://www.buddhanet.net/elearning/heartstr.htm;
The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Nāgārjuna; http://www.iep.utm.edu/n/nagarjun.htm
Wikipedia; http://www.answers.com/topic/sunyata

Source

joycht.blogspot.com.au