Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Marx and Buddhism by Monica"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with "{{DisplayImages|2208|1084|1363|2800|3174|2336|14|845}} ===Introduction=== Religious suffering is, at one and the same time, the expression of real suffering and a protest aga...")
 
 
(2 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{DisplayImages|2208|1084|1363|2800|3174|2336|14|845}}
+
{{DisplayImages|2208|1084|1363|2800|3174|14}}
 
===Introduction===
 
===Introduction===
  
Religious suffering is, at one and the same time, the expression of real suffering and a protest against real suffering.  Religion is the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart of a heartless world, and the soul of soulless conditions.  It is the opium of the people. (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
+
[[Religious]] [[suffering]] is, at one and the same [[time]], the expression of real [[suffering]] and a protest against real [[suffering]][[Religion]] is the sigh of the oppressed creature, the [[heart]] of a heartless [[world]], and the [[soul]] of soulless [[conditions]].  It is the {{Wiki|opium}} of the [[people]]. (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
  
The final line is the most famous condemnation of religion of the nineteenth century philosopher Karl Marx (1818-1883). (Wolff)  It was published in his essay “A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right” and has been used to justify the harsh suppression of religion by community regimes ever since.  This is, in part, because Marx ties the existence of ‘ancient’ and outdated religious institutions to the equally “ancien régime” of the political and economic powers (specifically, in Germany at that time).
+
The final line is the most famous condemnation of [[religion]] of the nineteenth century [[philosopher]] {{Wiki|Karl Marx}} (1818-1883). (Wolff)  It was published in his essay “A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s [[Philosophy]] of Right” and has been used to justify the harsh suppression of [[religion]] by {{Wiki|community}} regimes ever since.  This is, in part, because Marx ties the [[existence]] of ‘{{Wiki|ancient}}’ and outdated [[religious]] {{Wiki|institutions}} to the equally “ancien régime” of the {{Wiki|political}} and economic [[powers]] (specifically, in {{Wiki|Germany}} at that [[time]]).
  
In fact, his critique of religion itself is very short and evolves quickly into a concern with power and economics.  Unlike most contemporary Americans who unthinkingly accept the so-called separation of church and state, Marx saw religion and (economic) power as part of an inseparable social system created to preserve the status quo – a status quo detrimental to humanity and which must be thrown off.  Despite his seeming exaltation of humankind (in place of God), he is quick to make enemies through angry rhetoric calling for criticism to act as the “executioner” to that “criminal” by making “War on the German state of affairs!”(Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
+
In fact, his critique of [[religion]] itself is very short and evolves quickly into a [[concern]] with power and {{Wiki|economics}}.  Unlike most contemporary {{Wiki|Americans}} who unthinkingly accept the so-called separation of {{Wiki|church}} and state, Marx saw [[religion]] and (economic) power as part of an [[inseparable]] {{Wiki|social}} system created to preserve the {{Wiki|status}} quo – a {{Wiki|status}} quo detrimental to [[humanity]] and which must be thrown off.  Despite his seeming exaltation of humankind (in place of [[God]]), he is quick to make enemies through [[angry]] [[rhetoric]] calling for [[criticism]] to act as the “executioner” to that “criminal” by making “[[War]] on the {{Wiki|German}} state of affairs!”(Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
  
Sadly, under communist leadership this war extended itself into a war on organized religion, obscuring Marx’s perceptive, if naïve, critique of religion itself.  Thus most modern people know only that Marxism is hostile to religion, without knowing specifically how and why, therefore denying ourselves of these critical insights.  For Buddhists, this means overlooking the “ironic affinities” between Marxism and Buddhism, as well as failing to address the specific points of contention.  For example, Marxism and Buddhism both deny the existence of a creator God and immortal soul, see the world as dynamically interrelated, and are fundamentally concerned with human suffering.  However, they see the sources of this suffering, and therefore its cure, very differently and Buddhism does posit the existence of an ultimate Truth (buddhanature) which Marx denies, along with a few other metaphysical differences. (Brien, p. 35)  In this exploration let us start with Marx’s critique of religion, followed by some general responses, and end with a discussion of the relationship between Marx and Buddhism.
+
Sadly, under {{Wiki|communist}} [[leadership]] this [[war]] extended itself into a [[war]] on organized [[religion]], {{Wiki|obscuring}} Marx’s perceptive, if naïve, critique of [[religion]] itself.  Thus most {{Wiki|modern}} [[people]] know only that {{Wiki|Marxism}} is {{Wiki|hostile}} to [[religion]], without [[knowing]] specifically how and why, therefore denying ourselves of these critical [[insights]].  For [[Buddhists]], this means overlooking the “ironic affinities” between {{Wiki|Marxism}} and [[Buddhism]], as well as failing to address the specific points of contention.  For example, {{Wiki|Marxism}} and [[Buddhism]] both deny the [[existence]] of a creator [[God]] and [[immortal]] [[soul]], see the [[world]] as dynamically {{Wiki|interrelated}}, and are fundamentally concerned with [[human]] [[suffering]].  However, they see the sources of this [[suffering]], and therefore its cure, very differently and [[Buddhism]] does posit the [[existence]] of an [[ultimate Truth]] ([[buddhanature]]) which Marx denies, along with a few other [[metaphysical]] differences. (Brien, p. 35)  In this exploration let us start with Marx’s critique of [[religion]], followed by some general responses, and end with a [[discussion]] of the relationship between Marx and [[Buddhism]].
  
===Marx’s Critique of Religion===
+
===Marx’s Critique of [[Religion]]===
  
Rightly or wrongly, Marx saw religion as one of the many social structures contributing to humankind’s (then) present and much deplored state of affairs.  He was born into a post-Enlightenment world well in the grip of the Industrial Revolution, in which the rise of science and a Newtonian understanding of physics had let to many technical advances. (Reynolds, p. 63)  In some places, notably England and France, these technological advances had corresponded to revolutionary changes in government and social structure.  Meanwhile, Germany lagged behind.  Marx was roundly dissatisfied by this, even while criticizing the other revolutions as incomplete.
+
Rightly or wrongly, Marx saw [[religion]] as one of the many {{Wiki|social}} structures contributing to humankind’s (then) {{Wiki|present}} and much deplored state of affairs.  He was born into a post-Enlightenment [[world]] well in the [[grip]] of the Industrial {{Wiki|Revolution}}, in which the rise of [[science]] and a Newtonian [[understanding]] of [[physics]] had let to many technical advances. (Reynolds, p. 63)  In some places, notably {{Wiki|England}} and {{Wiki|France}}, these technological advances had corresponded to {{Wiki|revolutionary}} changes in government and {{Wiki|social}} structure.  Meanwhile, {{Wiki|Germany}} lagged behind.  Marx was roundly dissatisfied by this, even while criticizing the other revolutions as incomplete.
  
The young Marx fully bought into the Enlightenment notion of ‘progress,’ if not all the theoretical reasons behind it, and began publishing articles and essays during the early 1840’s, including “A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right” (henceforth “Critique”) and “On the Jewish Question” in 1844. (Wolff)  It is in the first of these essays that I am most interested.  In this essay Marx states unequivocally that “the criticism of religion is the prerequisite of all criticism.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
+
The young Marx fully bought into the [[Enlightenment]] notion of ‘progress,’ if not all the {{Wiki|theoretical}} [[reasons]] behind it, and began publishing articles and {{Wiki|essays}} during the early 1840’s, including “A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s [[Philosophy]] of Right” (henceforth “Critique”) and “On the {{Wiki|Jewish}} Question” in 1844. (Wolff)  It is in the first of these {{Wiki|essays}} that I am most [[interested]].  In this essay Marx states unequivocally that “the [[criticism]] of [[religion]] is the prerequisite of all [[criticism]].” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
  
:The foundation of irreligious criticism is: Man makes religion, religion does not make man. … Man is the world of man – state, society. … Religion is the general theory of this world, its encyclopaedic compendium, its logic in popular form, its spiritual point d’honneur, its consolation and justification.  It is the fantastic realization of the human essence since the human essence has not acquired any true reality. (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
+
:The foundation of irreligious [[criticism]] is: Man makes [[religion]], [[religion]] does not make man. … Man is the [[world]] of man – state, {{Wiki|society}}. … [[Religion]] is the general {{Wiki|theory}} of this [[world]], its encyclopaedic compendium, its [[logic]] in popular [[form]], its [[spiritual]] point d’honneur, its consolation and [[justification]].  It is the fantastic [[realization]] of the [[human]] [[essence]] since the [[human]] [[essence]] has not acquired any [[true reality]]. (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
  
Here he lays out his allegiance to both Hegel and Feuerbach, but also critiques them.  He accepted that God was made in humankind’s image and Feuerbach’s notion that “worshipping God diverted human beings from enjoying their own human powers,” while also asserting that Feuerbach missed the key force driving humans to do this: “alienation in material life” resulting from economic modes of production. (Wolff)
+
Here he lays out his allegiance to both [[Hegel]] and Feuerbach, but also critiques them.  He accepted that [[God]] was made in humankind’s image and Feuerbach’s notion that “worshipping [[God]] diverted [[human beings]] from enjoying their own [[human]] [[powers]],” while also asserting that Feuerbach missed the key force driving [[humans]] to do this: “alienation in material [[life]]” resulting from economic modes of production. (Wolff)
  
According to Jonathan Wolff (writing for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy), Marx was seeking to combine and transform the philosophies of materialism and idealism, specifically as part of the first of his “Theses on Feuerbach.”
+
According to Jonathan Wolff ([[writing]] for the {{Wiki|Stanford}} {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Philosophy]]), Marx was seeking to combine and [[transform]] the [[philosophies]] of {{Wiki|materialism}} and {{Wiki|idealism}}, specifically as part of the first of his “Theses on Feuerbach.”
  
:Materialism is complimented [by Marx] for understanding the physical reality of the world, but is criticized for ignoring the active role of the human subject in creating the world we perceive.  Idealism, at least as developed by Hegel, understands the active nature of the human subject, but confines it to thought or contemplation; the world is created through the categories we impose upon it.  Marx combines the insights of both traditions to propose a view in which human beings do indeed create – or at least transform – the world they find themselves in, but this transformation happens not in thought but through actual material activity…(Wolff)
+
:{{Wiki|Materialism}} is complimented [by Marx] for [[understanding]] the [[physical]] [[reality]] of the [[world]], but is criticized for ignoring the active role of the [[human]] [[subject]] in creating the [[world]] we {{Wiki|perceive}}{{Wiki|Idealism}}, at least as developed by [[Hegel]], [[understands]] the active [[nature]] of the [[human]] [[subject]], but confines it to [[thought]] or contemplation; the [[world]] is created through the categories we impose upon it.  Marx combines the [[insights]] of both [[traditions]] to propose a [[view]] in which [[human beings]] do indeed create – or at least [[transform]] – the [[world]] they find themselves in, but this [[transformation]] happens not in [[thought]] but through actual material activity…(Wolff)
  
This activity is called praxis or “the dynamic interaction through which the human being shapes the environment in some way, and in so doing shapes itself.” (Reynolds, p. 41)  In many ways, it is akin to social karma, which shall come up again later.
+
This [[activity]] is called praxis or “the dynamic interaction through which the [[human being]] shapes the environment in some way, and in so doing shapes itself.” (Reynolds, p. 41)  In many ways, it is akin to {{Wiki|social}} [[karma]], which shall come up again later.
  
As a materialist, Marx denied the existence of God, the soul, metaphysics in general, and any kind of ultimate truth or reality in particular.  Yet as an idealist and believer in progress, he felt that humanity’s destiny was still a hopeful one, that it was leading to something.  With God out of the picture, it was left to humankind to create that destiny, but humanity could only do that when the existing conservative forces, including religion, were swept away.
+
As a {{Wiki|materialist}}, Marx denied the [[existence]] of [[God]], the [[soul]], [[metaphysics]] in general, and any kind of [[ultimate truth]] or [[reality]] in particular.  Yet as an {{Wiki|idealist}} and believer in progress, he felt that humanity’s [[destiny]] was still a [[hopeful]] one, that it was leading to something.  With [[God]] out of the picture, it was left to humankind to create that [[destiny]], but [[humanity]] could only do that when the [[existing]] conservative forces, including [[religion]], were swept away.
  
Marx believed the proletariat revolution was the key – “a sphere, finally, which cannot emancipate itself without emancipating itself from all other spheres of society and thereby emancipating all other spheres of society.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive) This revolution would be political and economic, after which the conservative force of religion would die a natural death in the face of humanity’s renewed understanding of their own power.  In other words, we wouldn’t need God (or religion), that opiate, anymore.
+
Marx believed the proletariat {{Wiki|revolution}} was the key – “a [[sphere]], finally, which cannot emancipate itself without emancipating itself from all other spheres of {{Wiki|society}} and thereby emancipating all other spheres of {{Wiki|society}}.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive) This {{Wiki|revolution}} would be {{Wiki|political}} and economic, after which the conservative force of [[religion]] would [[die]] a natural [[death]] in the face of humanity’s renewed [[understanding]] of their own power.  In other words, we wouldn’t need [[God]] (or [[religion]]), that opiate, anymore.
  
 
===General Responses===
 
===General Responses===
  
Both the most damning and, perhaps, least critical assessment of Marx is that he failed.  Or rather, those following in his footsteps and calling themselves Marxists failed to pull off what they believed to be his ideal communist state.  As Huston Smith points out “All of Marx’s major predictions,” which he then lists, “turned out to be wrong…”  He then declares that “Modernity’s coming to see the gods it worshiped [i.e. rationalism, science, progress] for what they were – idols that failed – was the most important religious event of the twentieth century,” (Smith, p. 152-153) as though the continued vitality of religion in the face of critics like Marx is alone proof of religion’s efficacy.  I would counter that this critique is one-sided.  While rationalism, science (and scientism), and progress have failed to deliver on their utopian promises, so has religion (in this life).  Also, like religion, they stubbornly persist in modern thought even if we no longer shout their virtues from mountaintops.
+
Both the most damning and, perhaps, least critical assessment of Marx is that he failed.  Or rather, those following in his footsteps and calling themselves Marxists failed to pull off what they believed to be his {{Wiki|ideal}} {{Wiki|communist}} state.  As Huston Smith points out “All of Marx’s major predictions,” which he then lists, “turned out to be wrong…”  He then declares that “Modernity’s coming to see the [[gods]] it worshiped [i.e. [[rationalism]], [[science]], progress] for what they were – idols that failed – was the most important [[religious]] event of the twentieth century,” (Smith, p. 152-153) as though the continued [[vitality]] of [[religion]] in the face of critics like Marx is alone [[proof]] of religion’s efficacy.  I would counter that this critique is one-sided.  While [[rationalism]], [[science]] (and scientism), and progress have failed to deliver on their utopian promises, so has [[religion]] (in this [[life]]).  Also, like [[religion]], they stubbornly persist in {{Wiki|modern}} [[thought]] even if we no longer shout their [[virtues]] from mountaintops.
  
Smith praises “Marx’s compassion for the downtrodden” and call to social action but roundly criticizes “his faith in social engineering,” once again citing the failures of the communist regimes of the past century.  Marx was wrong to “circumvent the human heart” and believe that an external change can, or should, precede and internal revolution.  “Attempts to revolutionize the world to make it conform to a preconceived ideology can lead only to totalitarianism, for history is too unmanageable to conform to our conceptual designs.” (Smith, p. 165-167)  Yet I must ask, what is the Kingdom of Heaven (as in the Book of Revelation) if not a “preconceived idea?”  Are we off the hook if it is God’s “conceptual design” rather than our own?
+
Smith praises “Marx’s [[compassion]] for the downtrodden” and call to {{Wiki|social}} [[action]] but roundly criticizes “his [[faith]] in {{Wiki|social}} {{Wiki|engineering}},” once again citing the failures of the {{Wiki|communist}} regimes of the {{Wiki|past}} century.  Marx was wrong to “circumvent the [[human]] [[heart]]” and believe that an external change can, or should, precede and internal {{Wiki|revolution}}.  “Attempts to revolutionize the [[world]] to make it conform to a preconceived ideology can lead only to totalitarianism, for history is too unmanageable to conform to our {{Wiki|conceptual}} designs.” (Smith, p. 165-167)  Yet I must ask, what is the {{Wiki|Kingdom}} of [[Heaven]] (as in the [[Book]] of [[Revelation]]) if not a “preconceived [[idea]]?”  Are we off the hook if it is [[God’s]] “{{Wiki|conceptual}} design” rather than our own?
  
John Haught characterizes religion according to Marx as a distraction “from the real task of correcting the unjust conditions” ourselves. (Haught, p. 218)  Though Haught does not criticize Marx as directly as Smith does, it is clear he sees Marx’s reliance on human reason and human effort, without recourse to an ultimate truth of some kind, to be inadequate.  How can Marx attack religion on moral grounds, that it is “not moral enough,” while at the same time denying any ultimate ground on which to base morality?  “If there is no eternally established standards of right and wrong, then what is to keep us from a moral relativism where each person is left alone to decide what is good and evil?” (Haught, p. 242-243) If this is the case, how can we say that economic inequality, that human suffering itself, is a “bad” thing?
+
John Haught characterizes [[religion]] according to Marx as a {{Wiki|distraction}} “from the real task of correcting the unjust [[conditions]]” ourselves. (Haught, p. 218)  Though Haught does not criticize Marx as directly as Smith does, it is clear he sees Marx’s reliance on [[human]] [[reason]] and [[human]] [[effort]], without recourse to an [[ultimate truth]] of some kind, to be inadequate.  How can Marx attack [[religion]] on [[moral]] grounds, that it is “not [[moral]] enough,” while at the same [[time]] denying any [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] ground on which to base [[morality]]?  “If there is no eternally established standards of right and wrong, then what is to keep us from a [[moral]] {{Wiki|relativism}} where each [[person]] is left alone to decide what is [[good and evil]]?” (Haught, p. 242-243) If this is the case, how can we say that economic inequality, that [[human]] [[suffering]] itself, is a “bad” thing?
  
Wolff proposes that Marx himself may have been bothered by this very paradox.  He wonders if “Marx, like so many of us, did not have perfect knowledge of his own mind.”  Wolff points out that Marx never directly stated that capitalism was unjust or that communism would be just, in the moral sense of the word.  In the Communist Manifesto, Marx also states “communism abolishes … all religion and all morality, rather than constituting them on a new basis.”  Some have argued Marx believed a communist society would “transcend” justice.  In the end, all he can conclude is that Marx believed “Capitalism impedes human flourishing” and “Communism clearly advances human flourishing.” (Wolff)  Can either be labeled moral on those grounds?
+
Wolff proposes that Marx himself may have been bothered by this very [[paradox]].  He wonders if “Marx, like so many of us, did not have [[perfect knowledge]] of his own [[mind]].”  Wolff points out that Marx never directly stated that capitalism was unjust or that {{Wiki|communism}} would be just, in the [[moral]] [[sense]] of the [[word]].  In the {{Wiki|Communist}} Manifesto, Marx also states “{{Wiki|communism}} abolishes … all [[religion]] and all [[morality]], rather than constituting them on a new basis.”  Some have argued Marx believed a {{Wiki|communist}} {{Wiki|society}} would “transcend” justice.  In the end, all he can conclude is that Marx believed “Capitalism impedes [[human]] flourishing” and “{{Wiki|Communism}} clearly advances [[human]] flourishing.” (Wolff)  Can either be labeled [[moral]] on those grounds?
  
===Marx and Buddhism===
+
===Marx and [[Buddhism]]===
  
At this point, in typical Buddhist fashion, I seem to have raised more questions than I have answered.  Marx points out in his “Critique” that “The main stem of German morals and honesty, of the classes as well as of individuals, is rather that modest egoism which asserts its limitedness and allows it to be asserted against itself.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)  In the words of the Zen Buddhist truism: only don’t know.  Even on the point of human failure, Buddhism and Marx find ground for agreement.
+
At this point, in typical [[Buddhist fashion]], I seem to have raised more questions than I have answered.  Marx points out in his “Critique” that “The main stem of {{Wiki|German}} {{Wiki|morals}} and [[honesty]], of the classes as well as of {{Wiki|individuals}}, is rather that modest [[egoism]] which asserts its limitedness and allows it to be asserted against itself.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)  In the words of the [[Zen]] [[Buddhist]] truism: only don’t know.  Even on the point of [[human]] failure, [[Buddhism]] and Marx find ground for agreement.
  
In his article “Buddhism and Marxism: Ironic Affinities,” Kevin Brien calls out many more areas of accord, as well as several points of divergence.  Buddhism and Marxism are both “deeply concerned about human suffering,” “agree that there is no creator God, or eternal soul,” recognizes interdependence, and understand some form of karma, both individual and social for Buddhists, and at least social for Marxists. (Brien, p. 35)
+
In his article “[[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Marxism}}: Ironic Affinities,” Kevin Brien calls out many more areas of accord, as well as several points of divergence.  [[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Marxism}} are both “deeply concerned about [[human]] [[suffering]],” “agree that there is no creator [[God]], or [[eternal]] [[soul]],” [[recognizes]] [[interdependence]], and understand some [[form]] of [[karma]], both {{Wiki|individual}} and {{Wiki|social}} for [[Buddhists]], and at least {{Wiki|social}} for Marxists. (Brien, p. 35)
  
However, Buddhists diverge from Marx in their understanding of the causes of human suffering.  As Smith also pointed out, Marx proclaims external forces to be the cause of human suffering, while Buddhists and other religions cite mainly internal forces.  A Buddhist would claim that human suffering can be alleviated even in the face of monumental social and economic injustice and material inequality (though no Buddhist would claim this is easy or likely), while Marx would state such is flat-out impossible.  This difference results in a fundamental disagreement in means to the same end, alleviating human suffering.
+
However, [[Buddhists]] diverge from Marx in their [[understanding]] of the [[causes]] of [[human]] [[suffering]].  As Smith also pointed out, Marx proclaims external forces to be the [[cause]] of [[human]] [[suffering]], while [[Buddhists]] and other [[religions]] cite mainly internal forces.  A [[Buddhist]] would claim that [[human]] [[suffering]] can be alleviated even in the face of monumental {{Wiki|social}} and economic injustice and material inequality (though no [[Buddhist]] would claim this is easy or likely), while Marx would state such is flat-out impossible.  This difference results in a fundamental disagreement in means to the same end, alleviating [[human]] [[suffering]].
  
In many cases, it is Marx’s means that have been criticized more than his ends.  This has led Brien, among others, to introduce the concept of Humanistic-Marxism.  Humanism is not a new ingredient in Marxism, they argue, but rather a more complete understanding of Marx’s philosophy as “an integrated whole” rather than what they call orthodox-Marxism’s “gross distortion of Marx’s thought” caused by an artificial and “radical split between the early and late Marx.”  Brien points to Marx’s complaint to Engles about how his theories were being used even before his death: “All I know is that I am not a Marxist.” (Brien, p. 39-40)
+
In many cases, it is Marx’s means that have been criticized more than his ends.  This has led Brien, among others, to introduce the {{Wiki|concept}} of Humanistic-Marxism.  {{Wiki|Humanism}} is not a new ingredient in {{Wiki|Marxism}}, they argue, but rather a more complete [[understanding]] of Marx’s [[philosophy]] as “an integrated whole” rather than what they call orthodox-Marxism’s “gross distortion of Marx’s [[thought]]” [[caused]] by an artificial and “radical split between the early and late Marx.”  Brien points to Marx’s complaint to Engles about how his theories were being used even before his [[death]]: “All I know is that I am not a {{Wiki|Marxist}}.” (Brien, p. 39-40)
  
I believe Brien’s point about the “ironic affinities” between Buddhism and Marxism is well made, as are his pains to distinguish orthodox from humanistic-Marxism.  I see much that is humanistic in Marx’s “Critique,” which, admittedly, is the only essay of his I have read in full.  “To be radical is the grasp the root of the matter.  But, for man, the root is man himself.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
+
I believe Brien’s point about the “ironic affinities” between [[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Marxism}} is well made, as are his [[pains]] to distinguish {{Wiki|orthodox}} from humanistic-Marxism.  I see much that is [[humanistic]] in Marx’s “Critique,” which, admittedly, is the only essay of his I have read in full.  “To be radical is the [[grasp]] the [[root]] of the {{Wiki|matter}}.  But, for man, the [[root]] is man himself.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)
  
Smith and Haught’s criticisms seem to be based on their understanding of orthodox-Marxism rather than on the complete philosophy of Marx himself.  In this, they seem to be coming from the same place I started this essay at: Marx was clearly wrong, therefore we need not give him much consideration.  Moreover, he criticized religion and, seeing as we like religion, we naturally don’t like him.  However, most economists and philosophers will agree that Marx also got a great deal right.  Therefore, might he also have some valuable insights about religion as well?  Might we also be able to grant his the same benefit we grant Darwin and distinguish Marx from the Marxists?
+
Smith and Haught’s criticisms seem to be based on their [[understanding]] of orthodox-Marxism rather than on the complete [[philosophy]] of Marx himself.  In this, they seem to be coming from the same place I started this essay at: Marx was clearly wrong, therefore we need not give him much [[consideration]].  Moreover, he criticized [[religion]] and, [[seeing]] as we like [[religion]], we naturally don’t like him.  However, most economists and [[philosophers]] will agree that Marx also got a great deal right.  Therefore, might he also have some valuable [[insights]] about [[religion]] as well?  Might we also be able to grant his the same [[benefit]] we grant {{Wiki|Darwin}} and distinguish Marx from the Marxists?
  
Wolff attempts to walk a middle path by pointing out Marx’s ambiguous relationship with ideas of “justice.”  He cites Hume, who “argued that if there was enormous material abundance – if everyone could have whatever they wanted without invading another’s share – we would never have devised rules of justice.  And, of course, Marx often suggested that communism would be a society of such abundance.”  But while he suggested this would be so, “Marx also refused to speculate in detail about the nature of communism, arguing that it would arise through historical processes, and was not,” as Smith alleges (p. 166) “the realization of a pre-determined moral ideal.” (Wolff) In this way, communism would leave old notions of justice and morality behind.
+
Wolff attempts to walk a [[middle path]] by pointing out Marx’s {{Wiki|ambiguous}} relationship with [[ideas]] of “justice.”  He cites [[Hume]], who “argued that if there was enormous material abundance – if everyone could have whatever they wanted without invading another’s share – we would never have devised rules of justice.  And, of course, Marx often suggested that {{Wiki|communism}} would be a {{Wiki|society}} of such abundance.”  But while he suggested this would be so, “Marx also refused to speculate in detail about the [[nature]] of {{Wiki|communism}}, arguing that it would arise through historical {{Wiki|processes}}, and was not,” as Smith alleges (p. 166) “the [[realization]] of a pre-determined [[moral]] {{Wiki|ideal}}.” (Wolff) In this way, {{Wiki|communism}} would leave old notions of justice and [[morality]] behind.
  
However, Hume put forth a second way humanity could transcend justice: “…if there were complete fellow-feeling between all human beings.” (Wolff)  This, I believe, is also an essential part of the Buddhist path.  Through the cultivation of compassion and wisdom, we dissolve the delusion of separation between oneself and others.  We mend Marx’s alienation from the inside by realizing the ultimate truth he denies: buddhanature.
+
However, [[Hume]] put forth a second way [[humanity]] could transcend justice: “…if there were complete fellow-feeling between all [[human beings]].” (Wolff)  This, I believe, is also an [[essential]] part of the [[Buddhist path]].  Through the cultivation of [[compassion]] and [[wisdom]], we dissolve the [[delusion]] of separation between oneself and others.  We mend Marx’s alienation from the inside by [[realizing]] [[the ultimate truth]] he denies: [[buddhanature]].
  
Although I see the similarities between Marx and Buddhism, I do not believe the differences are reconcilable.  Marx would no doubt criticize Buddhism for its understanding of rebirth as being ridiculously metaphysical and for its separation of mind and brain.  However, as Reynolds points out, Marx’s understanding of materialism was based on the physics of his day, not modern quantum physics, which has been consistently unable to find “an ultimate substantial reality” that can be reliably labeled “matter” (or “energy”).  Likewise, scientific studies of consciousness demonstrate less and less reliability in the theory of mind as an epiphenomenon of the brain. (Reynolds, p. 63-64)  Yet, these two problems Marx would likely have with Buddhism pale in comparison to the first irreconcilable difference.
+
Although I see the similarities between Marx and [[Buddhism]], I do not believe the differences are reconcilable.  Marx would no [[doubt]] criticize [[Buddhism]] for its [[understanding]] of [[rebirth]] as being ridiculously [[metaphysical]] and for its separation of [[mind]] and {{Wiki|brain}}.  However, as Reynolds points out, Marx’s [[understanding]] of {{Wiki|materialism}} was based on the [[physics]] of his day, not {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|quantum physics}}, which has been consistently unable to find “an [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] substantial [[reality]]” that can be reliably labeled “{{Wiki|matter}}” (or “[[energy]]”).  Likewise, [[scientific]] studies of [[consciousness]] demonstrate less and less reliability in the {{Wiki|theory of mind}} as an epiphenomenon of the {{Wiki|brain}}. (Reynolds, p. 63-64)  Yet, these two problems Marx would likely have with [[Buddhism]] pale in comparison to the first irreconcilable difference.
  
Perhaps Marx, as other Westerners have done in recent years, would also criticism Buddhism for being too concerned with the internal – sitting on our hands meditating while the world is on fire.  However, Buddhism can easily criticize Marx for mistaking the finger for the moon.  Moreover, as the Dalai Lama has pointed out, “Because of a lack of genuine compassion their energy becomes much more destructive than constructive.” (Brien, quoting an interview with HHDL conducted by Andrew N. Woznicki, p. 38)  This is self-evident in Marx’s “Critique,” which utilizes a startling amount of violent rhetoric, definitely failing the Buddhist test for skillful means (upaya).  If  it had been evident to Marx that violent words would lead to violent deeds perhaps many of the atrocities of Marxists could have been avoided.  This is one reason I called Marx naïve at the outset.  That he underestimated the effectiveness and persistence of religion, as Smith notes, is the other reason.
+
Perhaps Marx, as other Westerners have done in recent years, would also [[criticism]] [[Buddhism]] for being too concerned with the internal – sitting on our hands [[meditating]] while the [[world]] is on [[fire]].  However, [[Buddhism]] can easily criticize Marx for mistaking the finger for the [[moon]].  Moreover, as the [[Dalai Lama]] has pointed out, “Because of a lack of genuine [[compassion]] their [[energy]] becomes much more {{Wiki|destructive}} than constructive.” (Brien, quoting an interview with HHDL conducted by Andrew N. Woznicki, p. 38)  This is [[self-evident]] in Marx’s “Critique,” which utilizes a startling amount of [[violent]] [[rhetoric]], definitely failing the [[Buddhist]] test for [[skillful means]] ([[upaya]]).  If  it had been evident to Marx that [[violent]] words would lead to [[violent]] [[deeds]] perhaps many of the atrocities of Marxists could have been avoided.  This is one [[reason]] I called Marx naïve at the outset.  That he underestimated the effectiveness and persistence of [[religion]], as Smith notes, is the other [[reason]].
  
I must conclude by saying that while I believe Buddhists and Marxists can get along (that one could even be both), we will never make for easy bedfellows.
+
I must conclude by saying that while I believe [[Buddhists]] and Marxists can get along (that one could even be both), we will never make for easy bedfellows.
  
 
==Bibliography==
 
==Bibliography==
  
Brien, Kevin M. “Buddhism and Marxism: Ironic Affinities,” Dialogue and Universalism, No. 1-2/2004, p. 35-59
+
Brien, Kevin M. “[[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Marxism}}: Ironic Affinities,” Dialogue and [[Universalism]], No. 1-2/2004, p. 35-59
  
Haught, John F.  What is Religion? An Introduction. New Jersey: Paulist Press, 1990.
+
Haught, John F.  What is [[Religion]]? An Introduction. {{Wiki|New Jersey}}: Paulist Press, 1990.
  
Marx, Karl, “A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,” Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbucher, 7 & 10 (February 1844), Paris.  Accessed at the Marxists’ Internet Archive on April 28, 2011, URL = < http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/critique-hpr/intro.htm&gt;
+
Marx, Karl, “A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s [[Philosophy]] of Right,” Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbucher, 7 & 10 (February 1844), {{Wiki|Paris}}.  Accessed at the Marxists’ Internet Archive on April 28, 2011, URL = < http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/critique-hpr/intro.htm&gt;
  
Reynolds, John Myrdhin, “Some Thoughts on a Buddhist-Marxist Dialogue,” Dialogue and Universalism, No. 1-2/2004, p. 61-65
+
Reynolds, [[John Myrdhin]], “Some [[Thoughts]] on a Buddhist-Marxist Dialogue,” Dialogue and [[Universalism]], No. 1-2/2004, p. 61-65
  
Smith, Huston. Why Religion Matters: The Fate of the Human Spirit in an Age of Disbelief. New York: Harper Collins, 2001.
+
Smith, Huston. Why [[Religion]] Matters: The [[Fate]] of the [[Human]] [[Spirit]] in an Age of Disbelief. {{Wiki|New York}}: Harper Collins, 2001.
  
Wolff, Jonathan, “Karl Marx”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/marx/&gt;.
+
Wolff, Jonathan, “{{Wiki|Karl Marx}}”, {{Wiki|The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}} (Spring 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/marx/&gt;.
  
 
{{R}}
 
{{R}}

Latest revision as of 16:41, 20 March 2014

Almsofferingrice.jpg
BuddhaNew126.jpg
Tonpa Shenrab Miwoche.jpg
161c99def2.jpg
7566.jpg
Mind-stillness.jpg

Introduction

Religious suffering is, at one and the same time, the expression of real suffering and a protest against real suffering. Religion is the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart of a heartless world, and the soul of soulless conditions. It is the opium of the people. (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)

The final line is the most famous condemnation of religion of the nineteenth century philosopher Karl Marx (1818-1883). (Wolff) It was published in his essay “A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right” and has been used to justify the harsh suppression of religion by community regimes ever since. This is, in part, because Marx ties the existence of ‘ancient’ and outdated religious institutions to the equally “ancien régime” of the political and economic powers (specifically, in Germany at that time).

In fact, his critique of religion itself is very short and evolves quickly into a concern with power and economics. Unlike most contemporary Americans who unthinkingly accept the so-called separation of church and state, Marx saw religion and (economic) power as part of an inseparable social system created to preserve the status quo – a status quo detrimental to humanity and which must be thrown off. Despite his seeming exaltation of humankind (in place of God), he is quick to make enemies through angry rhetoric calling for criticism to act as the “executioner” to that “criminal” by making “War on the German state of affairs!”(Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)

Sadly, under communist leadership this war extended itself into a war on organized religion, obscuring Marx’s perceptive, if naïve, critique of religion itself. Thus most modern people know only that Marxism is hostile to religion, without knowing specifically how and why, therefore denying ourselves of these critical insights. For Buddhists, this means overlooking the “ironic affinities” between Marxism and Buddhism, as well as failing to address the specific points of contention. For example, Marxism and Buddhism both deny the existence of a creator God and immortal soul, see the world as dynamically interrelated, and are fundamentally concerned with human suffering. However, they see the sources of this suffering, and therefore its cure, very differently and Buddhism does posit the existence of an ultimate Truth (buddhanature) which Marx denies, along with a few other metaphysical differences. (Brien, p. 35) In this exploration let us start with Marx’s critique of religion, followed by some general responses, and end with a discussion of the relationship between Marx and Buddhism.

Marx’s Critique of Religion

Rightly or wrongly, Marx saw religion as one of the many social structures contributing to humankind’s (then) present and much deplored state of affairs. He was born into a post-Enlightenment world well in the grip of the Industrial Revolution, in which the rise of science and a Newtonian understanding of physics had let to many technical advances. (Reynolds, p. 63) In some places, notably England and France, these technological advances had corresponded to revolutionary changes in government and social structure. Meanwhile, Germany lagged behind. Marx was roundly dissatisfied by this, even while criticizing the other revolutions as incomplete.

The young Marx fully bought into the Enlightenment notion of ‘progress,’ if not all the theoretical reasons behind it, and began publishing articles and essays during the early 1840’s, including “A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right” (henceforth “Critique”) and “On the Jewish Question” in 1844. (Wolff) It is in the first of these essays that I am most interested. In this essay Marx states unequivocally that “the criticism of religion is the prerequisite of all criticism.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)

The foundation of irreligious criticism is: Man makes religion, religion does not make man. … Man is the world of man – state, society. … Religion is the general theory of this world, its encyclopaedic compendium, its logic in popular form, its spiritual point d’honneur, its consolation and justification. It is the fantastic realization of the human essence since the human essence has not acquired any true reality. (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)

Here he lays out his allegiance to both Hegel and Feuerbach, but also critiques them. He accepted that God was made in humankind’s image and Feuerbach’s notion that “worshipping God diverted human beings from enjoying their own human powers,” while also asserting that Feuerbach missed the key force driving humans to do this: “alienation in material life” resulting from economic modes of production. (Wolff)

According to Jonathan Wolff (writing for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy), Marx was seeking to combine and transform the philosophies of materialism and idealism, specifically as part of the first of his “Theses on Feuerbach.”

Materialism is complimented [by Marx] for understanding the physical reality of the world, but is criticized for ignoring the active role of the human subject in creating the world we perceive. Idealism, at least as developed by Hegel, understands the active nature of the human subject, but confines it to thought or contemplation; the world is created through the categories we impose upon it. Marx combines the insights of both traditions to propose a view in which human beings do indeed create – or at least transform – the world they find themselves in, but this transformation happens not in thought but through actual material activity…(Wolff)

This activity is called praxis or “the dynamic interaction through which the human being shapes the environment in some way, and in so doing shapes itself.” (Reynolds, p. 41) In many ways, it is akin to social karma, which shall come up again later.

As a materialist, Marx denied the existence of God, the soul, metaphysics in general, and any kind of ultimate truth or reality in particular. Yet as an idealist and believer in progress, he felt that humanity’s destiny was still a hopeful one, that it was leading to something. With God out of the picture, it was left to humankind to create that destiny, but humanity could only do that when the existing conservative forces, including religion, were swept away.

Marx believed the proletariat revolution was the key – “a sphere, finally, which cannot emancipate itself without emancipating itself from all other spheres of society and thereby emancipating all other spheres of society.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive) This revolution would be political and economic, after which the conservative force of religion would die a natural death in the face of humanity’s renewed understanding of their own power. In other words, we wouldn’t need God (or religion), that opiate, anymore.

General Responses

Both the most damning and, perhaps, least critical assessment of Marx is that he failed. Or rather, those following in his footsteps and calling themselves Marxists failed to pull off what they believed to be his ideal communist state. As Huston Smith points out “All of Marx’s major predictions,” which he then lists, “turned out to be wrong…” He then declares that “Modernity’s coming to see the gods it worshiped [i.e. rationalism, science, progress] for what they were – idols that failed – was the most important religious event of the twentieth century,” (Smith, p. 152-153) as though the continued vitality of religion in the face of critics like Marx is alone proof of religion’s efficacy. I would counter that this critique is one-sided. While rationalism, science (and scientism), and progress have failed to deliver on their utopian promises, so has religion (in this life). Also, like religion, they stubbornly persist in modern thought even if we no longer shout their virtues from mountaintops.

Smith praises “Marx’s compassion for the downtrodden” and call to social action but roundly criticizes “his faith in social engineering,” once again citing the failures of the communist regimes of the past century. Marx was wrong to “circumvent the human heart” and believe that an external change can, or should, precede and internal revolution. “Attempts to revolutionize the world to make it conform to a preconceived ideology can lead only to totalitarianism, for history is too unmanageable to conform to our conceptual designs.” (Smith, p. 165-167) Yet I must ask, what is the Kingdom of Heaven (as in the Book of Revelation) if not a “preconceived idea?” Are we off the hook if it is God’sconceptual design” rather than our own?

John Haught characterizes religion according to Marx as a distraction “from the real task of correcting the unjust conditions” ourselves. (Haught, p. 218) Though Haught does not criticize Marx as directly as Smith does, it is clear he sees Marx’s reliance on human reason and human effort, without recourse to an ultimate truth of some kind, to be inadequate. How can Marx attack religion on moral grounds, that it is “not moral enough,” while at the same time denying any ultimate ground on which to base morality? “If there is no eternally established standards of right and wrong, then what is to keep us from a moral relativism where each person is left alone to decide what is good and evil?” (Haught, p. 242-243) If this is the case, how can we say that economic inequality, that human suffering itself, is a “bad” thing?

Wolff proposes that Marx himself may have been bothered by this very paradox. He wonders if “Marx, like so many of us, did not have perfect knowledge of his own mind.” Wolff points out that Marx never directly stated that capitalism was unjust or that communism would be just, in the moral sense of the word. In the Communist Manifesto, Marx also states “communism abolishes … all religion and all morality, rather than constituting them on a new basis.” Some have argued Marx believed a communist society would “transcend” justice. In the end, all he can conclude is that Marx believed “Capitalism impedes human flourishing” and “Communism clearly advances human flourishing.” (Wolff) Can either be labeled moral on those grounds?

Marx and Buddhism

At this point, in typical Buddhist fashion, I seem to have raised more questions than I have answered. Marx points out in his “Critique” that “The main stem of German morals and honesty, of the classes as well as of individuals, is rather that modest egoism which asserts its limitedness and allows it to be asserted against itself.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive) In the words of the Zen Buddhist truism: only don’t know. Even on the point of human failure, Buddhism and Marx find ground for agreement.

In his article “Buddhism and Marxism: Ironic Affinities,” Kevin Brien calls out many more areas of accord, as well as several points of divergence. Buddhism and Marxism are both “deeply concerned about human suffering,” “agree that there is no creator God, or eternal soul,” recognizes interdependence, and understand some form of karma, both individual and social for Buddhists, and at least social for Marxists. (Brien, p. 35)

However, Buddhists diverge from Marx in their understanding of the causes of human suffering. As Smith also pointed out, Marx proclaims external forces to be the cause of human suffering, while Buddhists and other religions cite mainly internal forces. A Buddhist would claim that human suffering can be alleviated even in the face of monumental social and economic injustice and material inequality (though no Buddhist would claim this is easy or likely), while Marx would state such is flat-out impossible. This difference results in a fundamental disagreement in means to the same end, alleviating human suffering.

In many cases, it is Marx’s means that have been criticized more than his ends. This has led Brien, among others, to introduce the concept of Humanistic-Marxism. Humanism is not a new ingredient in Marxism, they argue, but rather a more complete understanding of Marx’s philosophy as “an integrated whole” rather than what they call orthodox-Marxism’s “gross distortion of Marx’s thoughtcaused by an artificial and “radical split between the early and late Marx.” Brien points to Marx’s complaint to Engles about how his theories were being used even before his death: “All I know is that I am not a Marxist.” (Brien, p. 39-40)

I believe Brien’s point about the “ironic affinities” between Buddhism and Marxism is well made, as are his pains to distinguish orthodox from humanistic-Marxism. I see much that is humanistic in Marx’s “Critique,” which, admittedly, is the only essay of his I have read in full. “To be radical is the grasp the root of the matter. But, for man, the root is man himself.” (Marx via Marxists’ Internet Archive)

Smith and Haught’s criticisms seem to be based on their understanding of orthodox-Marxism rather than on the complete philosophy of Marx himself. In this, they seem to be coming from the same place I started this essay at: Marx was clearly wrong, therefore we need not give him much consideration. Moreover, he criticized religion and, seeing as we like religion, we naturally don’t like him. However, most economists and philosophers will agree that Marx also got a great deal right. Therefore, might he also have some valuable insights about religion as well? Might we also be able to grant his the same benefit we grant Darwin and distinguish Marx from the Marxists?

Wolff attempts to walk a middle path by pointing out Marx’s ambiguous relationship with ideas of “justice.” He cites Hume, who “argued that if there was enormous material abundance – if everyone could have whatever they wanted without invading another’s share – we would never have devised rules of justice. And, of course, Marx often suggested that communism would be a society of such abundance.” But while he suggested this would be so, “Marx also refused to speculate in detail about the nature of communism, arguing that it would arise through historical processes, and was not,” as Smith alleges (p. 166) “the realization of a pre-determined moral ideal.” (Wolff) In this way, communism would leave old notions of justice and morality behind.

However, Hume put forth a second way humanity could transcend justice: “…if there were complete fellow-feeling between all human beings.” (Wolff) This, I believe, is also an essential part of the Buddhist path. Through the cultivation of compassion and wisdom, we dissolve the delusion of separation between oneself and others. We mend Marx’s alienation from the inside by realizing the ultimate truth he denies: buddhanature.

Although I see the similarities between Marx and Buddhism, I do not believe the differences are reconcilable. Marx would no doubt criticize Buddhism for its understanding of rebirth as being ridiculously metaphysical and for its separation of mind and brain. However, as Reynolds points out, Marx’s understanding of materialism was based on the physics of his day, not modern quantum physics, which has been consistently unable to find “an ultimate substantial reality” that can be reliably labeled “matter” (or “energy”). Likewise, scientific studies of consciousness demonstrate less and less reliability in the theory of mind as an epiphenomenon of the brain. (Reynolds, p. 63-64) Yet, these two problems Marx would likely have with Buddhism pale in comparison to the first irreconcilable difference.

Perhaps Marx, as other Westerners have done in recent years, would also criticism Buddhism for being too concerned with the internal – sitting on our hands meditating while the world is on fire. However, Buddhism can easily criticize Marx for mistaking the finger for the moon. Moreover, as the Dalai Lama has pointed out, “Because of a lack of genuine compassion their energy becomes much more destructive than constructive.” (Brien, quoting an interview with HHDL conducted by Andrew N. Woznicki, p. 38) This is self-evident in Marx’s “Critique,” which utilizes a startling amount of violent rhetoric, definitely failing the Buddhist test for skillful means (upaya). If it had been evident to Marx that violent words would lead to violent deeds perhaps many of the atrocities of Marxists could have been avoided. This is one reason I called Marx naïve at the outset. That he underestimated the effectiveness and persistence of religion, as Smith notes, is the other reason.

I must conclude by saying that while I believe Buddhists and Marxists can get along (that one could even be both), we will never make for easy bedfellows.

Bibliography

Brien, Kevin M. “Buddhism and Marxism: Ironic Affinities,” Dialogue and Universalism, No. 1-2/2004, p. 35-59

Haught, John F. What is Religion? An Introduction. New Jersey: Paulist Press, 1990.

Marx, Karl, “A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,” Deutsch-Franzosische Jahrbucher, 7 & 10 (February 1844), Paris. Accessed at the Marxists’ Internet Archive on April 28, 2011, URL = < http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/critique-hpr/intro.htm>

Reynolds, John Myrdhin, “Some Thoughts on a Buddhist-Marxist Dialogue,” Dialogue and Universalism, No. 1-2/2004, p. 61-65

Smith, Huston. Why Religion Matters: The Fate of the Human Spirit in an Age of Disbelief. New York: Harper Collins, 2001.

Wolff, Jonathan, “Karl Marx”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/marx/>.

Source

dharmacowgirl.wordpress.com