Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Navya-Nyāya"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " The Navya-Nyāya or Neo-Logical darśana (view, system, or school) of Indian logic and Indian philosophy was founded in the 13th century CE by the philosoph...")
 
 
(2 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
{{DisplayImages|1944|4388}}
  
The [[Navya-Nyāya]] or Neo-Logical [[darśana]] (view, system, or school) of [[Indian logic]] and [[Indian philosophy]] was founded in the 13th century CE by the [[philosopher]] [[Gangeśa]] [[Upādhyāya]] of [[Mithila]].  
+
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
The [[Navya-Nyāya]] or [[Neo-Logical]] [[darśana]] (view, system, or school) of [[Indian logic]] and [[Indian philosophy]] was founded in the 13th century CE by the [[philosopher]] [[Gangeśa Upādhyāya]] of [[Mithila]].  
  
 
It was a [[development]] of the classical [[Nyāya darśana]].  
 
It was a [[development]] of the classical [[Nyāya darśana]].  
  
Other [[influences]] on [[Navya-Nyāya]] were the work of earlier [[philosophers]] [[Vācaspati Miśra]] (900–980 CE) and [[Udayana]] (late 10th century). It remained active in [[India]] through to the 18th century.
+
Other [[influences]] on [[Navya-Nyāya]] were the work of earlier [[philosophers]] [[Vācaspati Miśra]] (900–980 CE) and [[Udayana]] (late 10th century).  
 +
 
 +
It remained active in [[India]] through to the 18th century.
  
 
[[Gangeśa's]] [[book]] [[Tattvacintāmani]] ("[[Thought-Jewel of Reality]]") was written partly in response to [[Śrīharśa's]] [[Khandanakhandakhādya]], a defence of [[Advaita Vedānta]], which had [[offered]] a set of thorough {{Wiki|criticisms}} of [[Nyāya]] theories of [[thought]] and [[language]].  
 
[[Gangeśa's]] [[book]] [[Tattvacintāmani]] ("[[Thought-Jewel of Reality]]") was written partly in response to [[Śrīharśa's]] [[Khandanakhandakhādya]], a defence of [[Advaita Vedānta]], which had [[offered]] a set of thorough {{Wiki|criticisms}} of [[Nyāya]] theories of [[thought]] and [[language]].  
Line 10: Line 20:
 
In his [[book]], [[Gangeśa]] both addressed some of those {{Wiki|criticisms}} and – more important – critically examined the [[Nyāya darśana]] himself.  
 
In his [[book]], [[Gangeśa]] both addressed some of those {{Wiki|criticisms}} and – more important – critically examined the [[Nyāya darśana]] himself.  
  
He held that, while Śrīharśa had failed to successfully challenge the [[Nyāya]] realist {{Wiki|ontology}}, his and [[Gangeśa's]] [[own]] {{Wiki|criticisms}} brought out a need to improve and refine the [[logical]] and {{Wiki|linguistic}} tools of [[Nyāya]] [[thought]], to make them more rigorous and precise.
+
He held that, while [[Śrīharśa]] had failed to successfully challenge the [[Nyāya]] realist {{Wiki|ontology}}, his and [[Gangeśa's]] [[own]] {{Wiki|criticisms}} brought out a need to improve and refine the [[logical]] and {{Wiki|linguistic}} tools of [[Nyāya]] [[thought]], to make them more rigorous and precise.
  
 
[[Tattvacintāmani]] dealt with all the important aspects of [[Indian philosophy]], [[logic]], set {{Wiki|theory}}, and especially epistemology, which [[Gangeśa]] examined rigorously, developing and improving the [[Nyāya]] scheme, and [[offering]] examples.  
 
[[Tattvacintāmani]] dealt with all the important aspects of [[Indian philosophy]], [[logic]], set {{Wiki|theory}}, and especially epistemology, which [[Gangeśa]] examined rigorously, developing and improving the [[Nyāya]] scheme, and [[offering]] examples.  
Line 16: Line 26:
 
The results, especially his analysis of [[cognition]], were taken up and used by other [[darśanas]].
 
The results, especially his analysis of [[cognition]], were taken up and used by other [[darśanas]].
  
[[Navya-Nyāya]] developed a sophisticated [[language]] and {{Wiki|conceptual}} scheme that allowed it to raise, analyse, and solve problems in [[logic]] and epistemology.  
+
[[Navya-Nyāya]] developed a sophisticated [[language]] and {{Wiki|conceptual}} scheme that allowed it to raise, analyze, and solve problems in [[logic]] and epistemology.  
  
 
It systematised all the [[Nyāya]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] into four main categories (sense-)perception ([[pratyakşa]]), {{Wiki|inference}} ([[anumāna]]), comparison or similarity ([[upamāna]]), and testimony ([[sound]] or [[word]]; [[śabda]]).
 
It systematised all the [[Nyāya]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] into four main categories (sense-)perception ([[pratyakşa]]), {{Wiki|inference}} ([[anumāna]]), comparison or similarity ([[upamāna]]), and testimony ([[sound]] or [[word]]; [[śabda]]).
Line 24: Line 34:
 
This later school began around {{Wiki|eastern India}} and {{Wiki|Bengal}}, and developed theories resembling {{Wiki|modern}} [[logic]] by the 16th century, such as Gottlob Frege's "{{Wiki|distinction}} between [[sense]] and reference of proper names" and his "[[definition]] of number," as well as the [[Navya-Nyaya]] {{Wiki|theory}} of "restrictive [[conditions]] for universals" anticipating some of the developments in {{Wiki|modern}} set {{Wiki|theory}}.
 
This later school began around {{Wiki|eastern India}} and {{Wiki|Bengal}}, and developed theories resembling {{Wiki|modern}} [[logic]] by the 16th century, such as Gottlob Frege's "{{Wiki|distinction}} between [[sense]] and reference of proper names" and his "[[definition]] of number," as well as the [[Navya-Nyaya]] {{Wiki|theory}} of "restrictive [[conditions]] for universals" anticipating some of the developments in {{Wiki|modern}} set {{Wiki|theory}}.
  
[[Udayana]] in particular developed theories on "restrictive [[conditions]] for universals" and "[[infinite]] regress" that anticipated aspects of {{Wiki|modern}} set {{Wiki|theory}}. According to Kisor Kumar Chakrabarti:[2]
+
[[Udayana]] in particular developed theories on "restrictive [[conditions]] for universals" and "[[infinite]] regress" that anticipated aspects of {{Wiki|modern}} set {{Wiki|theory}}.  
 +
 
 +
According to Kisor [[Kumar]] Chakrabarti:  
 +
 
 +
:    In the third part we have shown how the study of the so-called 'restrictive [[conditions]] for universals' in [[Navya-Nyaya]] [[logic]] anticipated some of the developments of {{Wiki|modern}} set {{Wiki|theory}}. 
  
:    In the third part we have shown how the study of the so-called 'restrictive [[conditions]] for universals' in [[Navya-Nyaya]] [[logic]] anticipated some of the developments of {{Wiki|modern}} set {{Wiki|theory}}. [...]
+
In this section the [[discussion]] will center around some of the 'restrictive [[conditions]] for universals ([[jatibadhaka]]) proposed by [[Udayana]].  
  
In this section the [[discussion]] will center around some of the 'restrictive [[conditions]] for universals ([[jatibadhaka]]) proposed by [[Udayana]]. [...]
+
Another restrictive [[condition]] is [[anavastha]] or vicious [[infinite]] regress.  
  
Another restrictive [[condition]] is [[anavastha]] or vicious [[infinite]] regress. According to this restrictive [[condition]], no [[universal]] ([[jati]]) can be admitted to [[exist]], the admission of which would lead to a vicious [[infinite]] regress.  
+
According to this restrictive [[condition]], no [[universal]] ([[jati]]) can be admitted to [[exist]], the admission of which would lead to a vicious [[infinite]] regress.  
  
 
As an example [[Udayana]] says that there can be no [[universal]] of which every [[universal]] is a member; for if we had any such [[universal]], then, by {{Wiki|hypothesis}}, we have got a given {{Wiki|totality}} of all universals that [[exist]] and all of them belong to this big [[universal]].  
 
As an example [[Udayana]] says that there can be no [[universal]] of which every [[universal]] is a member; for if we had any such [[universal]], then, by {{Wiki|hypothesis}}, we have got a given {{Wiki|totality}} of all universals that [[exist]] and all of them belong to this big [[universal]].  
Line 36: Line 50:
 
But this [[universal]] is itself a [[universal]] and hence (since it cannot be a member of itself, because in [[Udayana's]] view no [[universal]] can be a member of itself) this [[universal]] too along with other universals must belong to a bigger [[universal]] and so on ad infinitum.  
 
But this [[universal]] is itself a [[universal]] and hence (since it cannot be a member of itself, because in [[Udayana's]] view no [[universal]] can be a member of itself) this [[universal]] too along with other universals must belong to a bigger [[universal]] and so on ad infinitum.  
  
What [[Udayana]] says here has [[interesting]] analogues in {{Wiki|modern}} set {{Wiki|theory}} in which it is held that a set of all sets (i.e., a set to which every set belongs) does not [[exist]].
+
What [[Udayana]] says here has [[interesting]] analogs in {{Wiki|modern}} set {{Wiki|theory}} in which it is held that a set of all sets (i.e., a set to which every set belongs) does not [[exist]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
{{W}}
 +
[[Category:Buddhist Terms]]
 +
[[Category:Buddhist Philosophy]]
 +
[[Category:Buddhism]]
 +
[[Category:Nyaya]]
 +
[[Category:India]]

Latest revision as of 18:45, 26 May 2023

GuruTroonil.jpg
1xxx2 1.jpg





The Navya-Nyāya or Neo-Logical darśana (view, system, or school) of Indian logic and Indian philosophy was founded in the 13th century CE by the philosopher Gangeśa Upādhyāya of Mithila.

It was a development of the classical Nyāya darśana.

Other influences on Navya-Nyāya were the work of earlier philosophers Vācaspati Miśra (900–980 CE) and Udayana (late 10th century).

It remained active in India through to the 18th century.

Gangeśa's book Tattvacintāmani ("Thought-Jewel of Reality") was written partly in response to Śrīharśa's Khandanakhandakhādya, a defence of Advaita Vedānta, which had offered a set of thorough criticisms of Nyāya theories of thought and language.

In his book, Gangeśa both addressed some of those criticisms and – more important – critically examined the Nyāya darśana himself.

He held that, while Śrīharśa had failed to successfully challenge the Nyāya realist ontology, his and Gangeśa's own criticisms brought out a need to improve and refine the logical and linguistic tools of Nyāya thought, to make them more rigorous and precise.

Tattvacintāmani dealt with all the important aspects of Indian philosophy, logic, set theory, and especially epistemology, which Gangeśa examined rigorously, developing and improving the Nyāya scheme, and offering examples.

The results, especially his analysis of cognition, were taken up and used by other darśanas.

Navya-Nyāya developed a sophisticated language and conceptual scheme that allowed it to raise, analyze, and solve problems in logic and epistemology.

It systematised all the Nyāya concepts into four main categories (sense-)perception (pratyakşa), inference (anumāna), comparison or similarity (upamāna), and testimony (sound or word; śabda).

Comparisons to modern logic

This later school began around eastern India and Bengal, and developed theories resembling modern logic by the 16th century, such as Gottlob Frege's "distinction between sense and reference of proper names" and his "definition of number," as well as the Navya-Nyaya theory of "restrictive conditions for universals" anticipating some of the developments in modern set theory.

Udayana in particular developed theories on "restrictive conditions for universals" and "infinite regress" that anticipated aspects of modern set theory.

According to Kisor Kumar Chakrabarti:

In the third part we have shown how the study of the so-called 'restrictive conditions for universals' in Navya-Nyaya logic anticipated some of the developments of modern set theory.

In this section the discussion will center around some of the 'restrictive conditions for universals (jatibadhaka) proposed by Udayana.

Another restrictive condition is anavastha or vicious infinite regress.

According to this restrictive condition, no universal (jati) can be admitted to exist, the admission of which would lead to a vicious infinite regress.

As an example Udayana says that there can be no universal of which every universal is a member; for if we had any such universal, then, by hypothesis, we have got a given totality of all universals that exist and all of them belong to this big universal.

But this universal is itself a universal and hence (since it cannot be a member of itself, because in Udayana's view no universal can be a member of itself) this universal too along with other universals must belong to a bigger universal and so on ad infinitum.

What Udayana says here has interesting analogs in modern set theory in which it is held that a set of all sets (i.e., a set to which every set belongs) does not exist.


Source

Wikipedia:Navya-Nyāya