Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Tsongkhapa (1357–1419)"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " <poem> Tsongkhapa (1357–1419) is a well-known Tibetan religious philosopher. In his {{Wiki|iconic}} form, wearing a tall yellow hat, he is the...")
 
 
(5 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
+
<nomobile>{{DisplayImages|539|3799|2713|3585|1589|2766|1506|2059|4097|1403|4354|2389|2809|330|1543|1827|2141|1649|2906|1966|2125|4458|3054|3592|1510}}</nomobile>
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] (1357–1419) is a well-known [[Tibetan]] [[religious]] [[philosopher]].
 +
 
 +
In his {{Wiki|iconic}} [[form]], wearing a tall [[yellow hat]], he is the center of the [[Gelugpa]] (Tib. [[dge lugs pa]]) [[sect]] that ruled [[Tibet]] until the {{Wiki|Chinese}} takeover in 1951, and whose {{Wiki|de facto}} leader is the [[Dalai Lama]]. [
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] has been the [[subject]] of poor, misleading {{Wiki|scholarship}} — particularly in the 19th century when so-called “[[Orientalist]]” [[scholars]] (e.g., {{Wiki|Monier-Williams}},
 +
 
 +
1888: 268, 277) falsely [[imagined]] him as a “reformer” who founded, or rediscovered, the [[rational]] and [[ethical]] school of original [[Buddhism]].
 +
 
 +
The historical [[Tsongkhapa]] flourished in the period immediately following the final redaction of the [[Buddhist canon]] in [[Tibetan]] translation (Tib. [[bKa' 'gyur]], pronounced [[Kanjur]]).
 +
 
 +
He presents a [[Middle Way]] (Sk. [[madhyamaka]], Tib. [[dbu ma pa]]) [[philosophy]], based on the works of the [[Indian]] [[philosopher]] [[Nāgārjuna]] (third-fourth century),
 +
 
 +
and strongly influenced by the [[Indo-Tibetan]] [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|logico-epistemological}} [[tradition]] (Sk. [[pramāṇa]], Tib. [[tshad ma]]) founded by the [[Indian]] [[epistemologists]] [[Dignāga]] and [[Dharmakīrti]] (fifth to seventh century).
  
 +
In it he strikes a [[balance]] between [[knowledge]] and praxis.
  
 +
He unerringly characterizes all statements about [[ultimate truths]] (Sk. [[paramārtha-satya]]) framed in positive terms as false, but develops a {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} to retain the authority of correct [[moral]] statements on a covering (Sk. [[saṃvṛti]]) or [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] (Sk. [[vyavahāra]]) level.
  
  
 +
His most influential [[writing]] reconciles the [[philosophy of emptiness]] (Sk. [[śūnyatā]]) with the {{Wiki|imperative}} of praxis [[embodied]] in a [[universal]] [[altruistic principle]] (Sk. [[bodhicitta]]).
  
<poem>
+
He gives [[pride]] of place to apparently {{Wiki|antinomian}} [[tantric]] praxis without devaluing the centrality of ordinary [[moral]] [[life]], and develops a {{Wiki|distinctive}} analysis of [[dependent origination]] (Sk. [[pratītya-samutpāda]]).
[[Tsongkhapa]] (1357–1419) is a well-known [[Tibetan]] [[religious]] [[philosopher]]. In his {{Wiki|iconic}} [[form]], wearing a tall [[yellow hat]], he is the center of the [[Gelugpa]] (Tib. [[dge lugs pa]]) [[sect]] that ruled [[Tibet]] until the {{Wiki|Chinese}} takeover in 1951, and whose {{Wiki|de facto}} leader is the [[Dalai Lama]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] has been the [[subject]] of poor, misleading {{Wiki|scholarship}} — particularly in the 19th century when so-called “[[Orientalist]]” [[scholars]] (e.g., {{Wiki|Monier-Williams}}, 1888: 268, 277) falsely [[imagined]] him as a “reformer” who founded, or rediscovered, the [[rational]] and [[ethical]] school of original [[Buddhism]].
 
  
The historical [[Tsongkhapa]] flourished in the period immediately following the final redaction of the [[Buddhist canon]] in [[Tibetan]] translation (Tib. [[bKa' 'gyur]], pronounced [[Kanjur]]). He presents a [[Middle Way]] (Sk. [[madhyamaka]], Tib. [[dbu ma pa]]) [[philosophy]], based on the works of the [[Indian]] [[philosopher]] [[Nāgārjuna]] (third-fourth century), and strongly influenced by the Indo-Tibetan [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|logico-epistemological}} [[tradition]] (Sk. [[pramāṇa]], Tib. [[tshad ma]]) founded by the [[Indian]] [[epistemologists]] [[Dignāga]] and [[Dharmakīrti]] (fifth to seventh century). In it he strikes a [[balance]] between [[knowledge]] and praxis. He unerringly characterizes all statements about [[ultimate truths]] (Sk. [[paramārtha-satya]]) framed in positive terms as false, but develops a {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} to retain the authority of correct [[moral]] statements on a covering (Sk. [[saṃvṛti]]) or [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] (Sk. [[vyavahāra]]) level. His most influential [[writing]] reconciles the [[philosophy of emptiness]] (Sk. [[śūnyatā]]) with the {{Wiki|imperative}} of praxis [[embodied]] in a [[universal]] {{Wiki|altruistic}} [[principle]] (Sk. [[bodhicitta]]). He gives [[pride]] of place to apparently {{Wiki|antinomian}} [[tantric]] praxis without devaluing the centrality of ordinary [[moral]] [[life]], and develops a {{Wiki|distinctive}} analysis of [[dependent origination]] (Sk. [[pratītya-samutpāda]]).
 
  
    1. [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[Life]]
 
        1.1 Overview
 
        1.2 Detailed account
 
    2. Early Period
 
        2.1 [[Explanation of the Difficult Points]] ([[Kun gzhi dka' 'grel]])
 
        2.2 [[Golden Garland]] ([[Legs bshad gser phreng]])
 
    3. Mature Period
 
    4. {{Wiki|Hermeneutics}}
 
    5. [[Ethics]]
 
    6. [[Tantra]]
 
    Bibliography
 
        Primary Works
 
        Secondary Works
 
    {{Wiki|Academic}} Tools
 
    Other Internet Resources
 
    Related Entries
 
  
1. [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[Life]]
 
 
1.1 Overview
 
1.1 Overview
 +
  
 
Biographical [[information]] about [[Tsongkhapa]] comes from clues in his [[own]] [[writing]], and from the {{Wiki|hagiography}} written by his [[student]] [[Kedrup Pelzangpo]] ([[mKhas grub dpal bzang po]]) (1385–1438) called [[Stream of Faith]] ([[Dad pa'i 'jug ngog]]) (partial translation in Thurman 1982).[1]
 
Biographical [[information]] about [[Tsongkhapa]] comes from clues in his [[own]] [[writing]], and from the {{Wiki|hagiography}} written by his [[student]] [[Kedrup Pelzangpo]] ([[mKhas grub dpal bzang po]]) (1385–1438) called [[Stream of Faith]] ([[Dad pa'i 'jug ngog]]) (partial translation in Thurman 1982).[1]
  
[[Tsongkhapa's]] [[life]] falls roughly into an earlier and later period. The later period is defined by a series of publications, beginning in about 1400, which systematically {{Wiki|present}} his mature [[philosophy]]. [[Tsongkhapa]], influenced by the divisions used by the editors of the [[Kanjur]], treats non-tantric and [[tantric]] sources separately. His [[philosophical]] [[views]] on [[tantra]], and, to a certain extent his work on [[ethics]] fall naturally into separate categories. The later period of his [[life]] includes a period of institution building, possibly with an [[eye]] to the founding of a new school or [[sect]].
+
[[Tsongkhapa's]] [[life]] falls roughly into an earlier and later period.  
1.2 Detailed account
+
 
 +
The later period is defined by a series of publications, beginning in about 1400, which systematically {{Wiki|present}} his mature [[philosophy]].  
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]], influenced by the divisions used by the editors of the [[Kanjur]], treats non-tantric and [[tantric]] sources separately.  
 +
 
 +
His [[philosophical]] [[views]] on [[tantra]], and, to a certain extent his work on [[ethics]] fall naturally into separate categories.  
 +
 
 +
The later period of his [[life]] includes a period of institution building, possibly with an [[eye]] to the founding of a new school or [[sect]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
The [[name]] [[Tsongkhapa]] derives from [[Tsong kha]], an [[ancient]] [[name]] for a part of the [[A mdo]] region of Greater [[Tibet]] ([[Bod chen]]) now included in [[Qinghai]] Province of the [[People's Republic of China]], and the [[Tibetan]] suffix pa that works as an [[agentive]] nominalizing {{Wiki|particle}}.
 +
 
 +
His given [[name]] is [[Losang]] (sometimes written [[Lozang Drakpa]] ([[bLo bzang grags pa]]).
 +
 
 +
He is also known by the [[honorific title]] [[Je Rinpoche]] ([[rJe rin po che]]) (“[[Precious]] Lord”).
 +
 
 +
He was born, probably to semi-nomadic {{Wiki|farmers}}, in a settlement now incorporated into the outskirts of the {{Wiki|Chinese}} city of [[Xi ning]].
 +
 
 +
His birthplace is marked by the popular [[Kumbum]] ([[sKu 'bum]]) [[monastery]],
 +
 
 +
 
 +
In his teens (1372–73), [[Tsongkhapa]] travelled from [[Tsong kha]] to Central ([[dBus]]) [[Tibet]] ([[Bod]]) where he remained until his [[death]] in 1419.
 +
 
 +
He arrived as a young man in {{Wiki|Central Tibet}} at the end of a long flowering of [[intellectual]] [[activity]]
 +
 
 +
called “the later diffusion of [[Buddhism]]” (Tib. [[spyi dar]]) that began with [[translator]] [[Rin chen bzang po]] (958–1055) and the scholar-saint [[Dīpaṃkāra-śrījñāna Atiśa]] (980–1054), and ended with the most important editor of the [[Kanjur]], [[Butōn]] ([[Bu ston Rin chen grub]], 1290–1364).
 +
 
 +
 
 +
According to [[Kedrup]], on his arrival in {{Wiki|Central Tibet}} [[Tsongkhapa]] first studied [[Tibetan medicine]], then a [[traditional]] [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|curriculum}} of [[abhidharma]], [[tenet]] systems (Tib. [[grub mtha]]') focusing on the [[Middle Way]] and [[Mind Only]] (Sk. [[cittamātra]]
 +
 
 +
also called [[yogācāra]]) [[philosophy]], [[Buddhist ethics]] (Tib. [[sdom gsum]]), and epistemology (Sk. [[pramāṇa]]).
 +
 
 +
His early studies were pursued mainly in {{Wiki|institutions}} affiliated with the two dominant [[scholarly]] [[traditions]] (Tib. [[lugs]]) of the time:
 +
 
 +
the [[Sangphu tradition]] ([[gSang phu ne'u tog]])  founded by [[Ngok]] ([[rNgog bLo ldan shes rab]]) (1059–1109), and the [[Sakya]] ([[Sa skya]]) [[epistemological tradition]] based primarily on the works of the [[Sa skya paṇḍi ta]] (1182–1251).
 +
 
 +
He also studied and practiced [[tantric Buddhism]].
 +
 
 +
In his early years he wrote a number of {{Wiki|essays}} on topics in [[abhidharma]] (Apple 2008), a detailed [[investigation]] of the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] (Sk.) (“[[foundation, storehouse]], [[basis-of all consciousness]]”) ([[Sparham]] 1993), and an important treatise, [[Golden Garland]] ([[Legs bshad gser phreng]]), on the [[Perfection of Wisdom]] (Sk. [[prajñā-pāramitā]]) {{Wiki|literature}} based on the codification of its topics in the [[Ornament for the Chapters]] ([[Abhisamayālaṃkāra]]) ([[Sparham]] 2008–2010).
 +
 
 +
After completing his [[Golden Garland]] in 1388–89, [[Tsongkhapa]] spent a period of some ten years removed from the hub of [[intellectual]] [[activity]].
 +
 
 +
He engaged in [[meditation]] and [[ritual]] [[religious]] exercises in [[Wikipedia:South Tibet|Southern Tibet]] ([[Lho kha]]) where, as evidenced in his short autobiographical [[writing]] from this transitional period (Thurman 1982), and corroborated by [[traditional]] sources (Kaschewsky 1971, [[Vostrikov]] 1970), he resorted to a communion or {{Wiki|dialogue}} with [[Mañjuśrī]]––the iconographic [[representation of perfect knowledge]] in the [[Buddhist pantheon]].
 +
 
 +
Through the {{Wiki|voice}} of [[Mañjuśrī]] he articulated a hierarchical system of [[philosophies]] culminating in what he characterized as a pristine, [[Middle Way]], *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]] (Tib. [[dBu ma thal 'gyur pa]]) that avoided over-reification (of the [[absolute]]) and over-negation (of the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]).
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] framed his [[insights]] not as original contributions, but as a rediscovery of meanings already revealed by the [[Buddha]].
 +
 
 +
In all his works he characterizes his [[philosophy]] as [[identical]] to the [[Buddha's]].
 +
 
 +
Further, he says his [[philosophy]] is based on [[Nāgārjuna's]] and [[Nāgārjuna's]] follower [[Ārya-deva's]] (third-fourth century) explanation of what the [[Buddha]] said.
 +
 
 +
His [[philosophy]] gets its [[name]] [[Prāsaṅgika]] (“those who reveal the unwelcome {{Wiki|consequences}} [[inherent]] in other's assertions”) from the importance it gives to [[Buddhapalita's]] (late fifth century) explication of [[Nāgārjuna's]] work, and to [[Candrakīrti's]] (mid-sixth to mid-seventh century) defense of [[Buddhapalita's]] explanation, in the face of [[criticism]] by [[Bhavaviveka]] (sixth century).
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] presented his mature [[philosophy]] in a series of volumes during the later period of his [[life]], beginning with the publication of his most famous work, the [[Great Exposition of the Stages of the Path]] ([[Lam rim chen mo]]) in 1402, at the age of 46.  
  
The [[name]] [[Tsongkhapa]] derives from [[Tsong kha]], an [[ancient]] [[name]] for a part of the [[A mdo]] region of Greater [[Tibet]] (Bod [[chen]]) now included in [[Qinghai]] Province of the [[People's Republic of China]], and the [[Tibetan]] suffix pa that works as an [[agentive]] nominalizing {{Wiki|particle}}. His given [[name]] is [[Losang]] (sometimes written [[Lozang]]) [[Drakpa]] ([[bLo bzang grags pa]]). He is also known by the [[honorific title]] [[Je Rinpoche]] ([[rJe rin po che]]) (“[[Precious]] Lord”). He was born, probably to semi-nomadic {{Wiki|farmers}}, in a settlement now incorporated into the outskirts of the {{Wiki|Chinese}} city of Xi ning. His birthplace is marked by the popular [[Kumbum]] ([[sKu 'bum]]) [[monastery]],
+
This was followed by [[Essence of Eloquence]] ([[Legs bshad snying po]]) and [[Ocean of Reasoning]] ([[Rigs pa'i rgya mtsho]]) (1407–1408), the [[Medium-Length Exposition of the Stages of the Path]] ([[Lam rim 'bring]]) in 1415, and, in the last years of his [[life]], his [[Elucidation of the Intention]] ([[dGongs pa rab gsal]]).
  
In his teens (1372–73), [[Tsongkhapa]] travelled from [[Tsong kha]] to Central ([[dBus]]) [[Tibet]] (Bod) where he remained until his [[death]] in 1419. He arrived as a young man in {{Wiki|Central Tibet}} at the end of a long flowering of [[intellectual]] [[activity]] called “the later diffusion [of [[Buddhism]]]” (Tib. [[spyi dar]]) that began with [[translator]] [[Rin chen bzang po]] (958–1055) and the scholar-saint [[Dīpaṃkāra-śrījñāna Atiśa]] (980–1054), and ended with the most important editor of the [[Kanjur]], [[Butōn]] ([[Bu ston Rin chen grub]], 1290–1364).
+
Together, in this series of works written over a seventeen year period, he succeeded in setting the agenda for the following centuries, to a great extent, with later writers taking positions pro and con his arguments.  
  
According to [[Kedrup]], on his arrival in {{Wiki|Central Tibet}} [[Tsongkhapa]] first studied [[Tibetan medicine]], then a [[traditional]] [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|curriculum}} of [[abhidharma]], [[tenet]] systems (Tib. [[grub mtha]]') focusing on the [[Middle Way]] and [[Mind Only]] (Sk. [[cittamātra]] also called [[yogācāra]]) [[philosophy]], [[Buddhist ethics]] (Tib. [[sdom gsum]]), and epistemology (Sk. [[pramāṇa]]). His early studies were pursued mainly in {{Wiki|institutions}} affiliated with the two dominant [[scholarly]] [[traditions]] (Tib. [[lugs]]) of the time: the [[Sangphu]] ([[gSang phu ne'u tog]]) [[tradition]] founded by [[Ngok]] ([[rNgog bLo ldan shes rab]]) (1059–1109), and the [[Sakya]] ([[Sa skya]]) [[epistemological]] [[tradition]] based primarily on the works of the [[Sa skya paṇḍi ta]] (1182–1251). He also studied and practiced [[tantric Buddhism]].
+
As is so often the case, his stature pushed much of earlier [[Tibetan]] [[intellectual]] history into the shadows, until its rediscovery by the Eclectic {{Wiki|Movement}} (Tib. [[Ris med]]) in [[Derge]] ([[sDe dge]]) in the late 18th century.
  
In his early years he wrote a number of {{Wiki|essays}} on topics in [[abhidharma]] (Apple 2008), a detailed [[investigation]] of the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] (Sk.) (“[[foundation, storehouse]], [[basis-of all consciousness]]”) ([[Sparham]] 1993), and an important treatise, [[Golden Garland]] ([[Legs bshad gser phreng]]), on the [[Perfection of Wisdom]] (Sk. [[prajñā-pāramitā]]) {{Wiki|literature}} based on the codification of its topics in the Ornament for the Chapters ([[Abhisamayālaṃkāra]]) ([[Sparham]] 2008–2010).
 
  
After completing his [[Golden Garland]] in 1388–89, [[Tsongkhapa]] spent a period of some ten years removed from the hub of [[intellectual]] [[activity]]. He engaged in [[meditation]] and [[ritual]] [[religious]] exercises in [[Wikipedia:South Tibet|Southern Tibet]] ([[Lho kha]]) where, as evidenced in his short autobiographical [[writing]] from this transitional period (Thurman 1982), and corroborated by [[traditional]] sources (Kaschewsky 1971, [[Vostrikov]] 1970), he resorted to a communion or {{Wiki|dialogue}} with Mañjuśrī––the iconographic [[representation]] of [[perfect knowledge]] in the [[Buddhist pantheon]]. Through the {{Wiki|voice}} of [[Mañjuśrī]] he articulated a hierarchical system of [[philosophies]] culminating in what he characterized as a pristine, [[Middle Way]], *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]] (Tib. [[dBu ma thal 'gyur pa]]) that avoided over-reification (of the [[absolute]]) and over-negation (of the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]).
+
[[Tsongkhapa]] wrote his major works on [[tantra]] and [[ethics]] at the same time as his major [[philosophical works]]. Volumes 3–12 of his collected works in 18 or 19 volumes deal exclusively with topics based on [[tantric]] sources.  
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] framed his [[insights]] not as original contributions, but as a rediscovery of meanings already revealed by the [[Buddha]]. In all his works he characterizes his [[philosophy]] as [[identical]] to the [[Buddha's]]. Further, he says his [[philosophy]] is based on [[Nāgārjuna's]] and [[Nāgārjuna's]] follower [[Ārya-deva's]] (third-fourth century) explanation of what the [[Buddha]] said. His [[philosophy]] gets its [[name]] [[Prāsaṅgika]] (“those who reveal the unwelcome {{Wiki|consequences}} [[[inherent]] in other's assertions]”) from the importance it gives to [[Buddhapalita's]] (late fifth century) explication of [[Nāgārjuna's]] work, and to [[Candrakīrti's]] (mid-sixth to mid-seventh century) defense of [[Buddhapalita's]] explanation, in the face of [[criticism]] by [[Bhavaviveka]] (sixth century).
+
In 1405 he completed his [[Great Exposition]] of [[Tantra]] ([[sNgags rim chen mo]]), a companion volume to his [[Great Exposition]], where, in [[harmony]] with his [[philosophy]], he argued that [[tantra]] is defined neither by special [[insight]] (Sk. [[vipaśyana]]) or [[Mahāyāna]] [[altruism]] (Sk. [[bodhicitta]]), but solely by [[deity yoga]] (Tib. [[lha'i rnal 'byor]]) (Hopkins 1980).
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] presented his mature [[philosophy]] in a series of volumes during the later period of his [[life]], beginning with the publication of his most famous work, the [[Great Exposition of the Stages of the Path]] ([[Lam rim chen mo]]) in 1402, at the age of 46. This was followed by [[Essence of Eloquence]] ([[Legs bshad snying po]]) and [[Ocean of Reasoning]] ([[Rigs pa'i rgya mtsho]]) (1407–1408), the [[Medium-Length Exposition of the Stages of the Path]] ([[Lam rim 'bring]]) in 1415, and, in the last years of his [[life]], his [[Elucidation of the Intention]] ([[dGongs pa rab gsal]]).
 
  
Together, in this series of works written over a seventeen year period, he succeeded in setting the agenda for the following centuries, to a great extent, with later writers taking positions pro and con his arguments. As is so often the case, his stature pushed much of earlier [[Tibetan]] [[intellectual]] history into the shadows, until its rediscovery by the Eclectic {{Wiki|Movement}} (Tib. [[Ris med]]) in [[Derge]] ([[sDe dge]]) in the late 18th century.
+
In 1402, [[Tsongkhapa]], with his [[teacher]] [[Rendawa]] ([[Red mda' ba gzhon nu blo gros]], 1349–1412) and others, at the [[temple]] of [[Namstedeng]] ([[rNam rtsed ldeng/lding]]) convened a [[gathering]] of [[monks]] with the [[intention]] of reinvigorating the [[Buddhist order]].
 +
 
 +
From this came [[Tsongkhapa's]] short, but influential works on basic [[Buddhist morality]] (Sk. [[prātimokṣa]]) that in turn laid the foundation for the importance some [[Gelukpa]] [[monasteries]] would place on a stricter adherence to the [[monastic code]].
 +
 
 +
In 1403 his influential works on [[ethical]] {{Wiki|codes}} for [[bodhisattvas]] ([[Byang chub gzhung lam]]) (Tatz 1987) and for [[tantric practitioners]] ([[rTsa ltung rnam bshad]]) ([[Sparham]] 2005) appeared.
 +
 
 +
His separate explanations of the three [[ethical]] {{Wiki|codes}} (Tib. [[sdom gsum]]) are {{Wiki|distinguished}} by the centrality they give to [[basic morality]], the importance the [[bodhisattva's]] code retains in [[tantra]], and,
 +
 
 +
in the {{Wiki|antinomian}} [[tantras]], the presence of a separate, [[prātimokṣa]]-like [[ordination ritual]] and a common code of [[ethical]] conduct.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
By 1409, at the age of 52, his place in [[Tibetan]] [[society]] was sufficiently established that he could garner the support and sponsorship necessary for a successful rejuvenation of the central [[temple]] in [[Lhasa]],  
 +
 
 +
for establishing a new-year [[prayer]] {{Wiki|festival}} ([[smon lam chen mo]]), and for completion of a large new [[monastery]], [[Ganden]] ([[dGa' ldan]]), where he lived for much of his subsequent [[life]] until his [[death]] there in 1419.  
 +
 
 +
He inspired two of his students [[Tashi Palden]] ([[bKra shis dpal ldan]]) (1379–1449) and [[Shakya Yeshey]] ([[Ye shes]]) (1354–1435) to found [[Drepung]] ('[[Bras spungs]]) [[monastery]] in 1416, and [[Sera Monastery]] in 1419, respectively.
 +
 
 +
These, with [[Ganden]], would later become the three largest and most powerful [[Gelukpa monasteries]], and indeed, the biggest [[monasteries]] in the [[world]].
 +
 
 +
In 1407 and 1413 the {{Wiki|Ming dynasty}} [[Yongle Emperor]] [[recognized]] [[Tsongkhapa's]] growing [[fame]] and importance by inviting him to the {{Wiki|Chinese}} court, as was the {{Wiki|custom}}.
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] wrote his major works on [[tantra]] and [[ethics]] at the same time as his major [[philosophical works]]. Volumes 3–12 of his collected works in 18 or 19 volumes deal exclusively with topics based on [[tantric]] sources. In 1405 he completed his [[Great Exposition]] of [[Tantra]] ([[sNgags rim chen mo]]), a companion volume to his [[Great Exposition]], where, in [[harmony]] with his [[philosophy]], he argued that [[tantra]] is defined neither by special [[insight]] (Sk. [[vipaśyana]]) or [[Mahāyāna]] [[altruism]] (Sk. [[bodhicitta]]), but solely by [[deity yoga]] (Tib. [[lha'i rnal 'byor]]) (Hopkins 1980).
 
  
In 1402, [[Tsongkhapa]], with his [[teacher]] [[Rendawa]] ([[Red mda' ba gzhon nu blo gros]], 1349–1412) and others, at the [[temple]] of [[Namstedeng]] ([[rNam rtsed ldeng/lding]]) convened a [[gathering]] of [[monks]] with the [[intention]] of reinvigorating the [[Buddhist order]]. From this came [[Tsongkhapa's]] short, but influential works on basic [[Buddhist morality]] (Sk. [[prātimokṣa]]) that in turn laid the foundation for the importance some [[Gelukpa]] [[monasteries]] would place on a stricter adherence to the [[monastic code]]. In 1403 his influential works on [[ethical]] {{Wiki|codes}} for [[bodhisattvas]] ([[Byang chub gzhung lam]]) (Tatz 1987) and for [[tantric practitioners]] ([[rTsa ltung rnam bshad]]) ([[Sparham]] 2005) appeared. His separate explanations of the three [[ethical]] {{Wiki|codes}} (Tib. [[sdom gsum]]) are {{Wiki|distinguished}} by the centrality they give to [[basic morality]], the importance the [[bodhisattva's]] code retains in [[tantra]], and, in the {{Wiki|antinomian}} [[tantras]], the presence of a separate, prātimokṣa-like [[ordination]] [[ritual]] and a common code of [[ethical]] conduct.
 
  
By 1409, at the age of 52, his place in [[Tibetan]] [[society]] was sufficiently established that he could garner the support and sponsorship necessary for a successful rejuvenation of the central [[temple]] in [[Lhasa]], for establishing a new-year [[prayer]] {{Wiki|festival}} ([[smon lam chen mo]]), and for completion of a large new [[monastery]], [[Ganden]] ([[dGa' ldan]]), where he lived for much of his subsequent [[life]] until his [[death]] there in 1419. He inspired two of his students [[Tashi Palden]] ([[bKra shis dpal ldan]]) (1379–1449) and [[Shakya Yeshey]] ([[Ye shes]]) (1354–1435) to found [[Drepung]] ('[[Bras spungs]]) [[monastery]] in 1416, and [[Sera Monastery]] in 1419, respectively. These, with [[Ganden]], would later become the three largest and most powerful [[Gelukpa]] [[monasteries]], and indeed, the biggest [[monasteries]] in the [[world]]. In 1407 and 1413 the {{Wiki|Ming dynasty}} [[Yongle Emperor]] [[recognized]] [[Tsongkhapa's]] growing [[fame]] and importance by inviting him to the {{Wiki|Chinese}} court, as was the {{Wiki|custom}}.
 
 
2. Early Period
 
2. Early Period
2.1 [[Explanation of the Difficult Points]] ([[Kun gzhi dka' 'grel]])
+
 
 +
===2.1 [[Explanation of the Difficult Points]] ([[Kun gzhi dka' 'grel]])===
 +
 
 +
 
  
 
[[Tsongkhapa's]] most important works from his early period are his [[Explanation of the Difficult Points]] ([[Kun gzhi dka' 'grel]]) and [[Golden Garland]] ([[Legs bshad gser phreng]]).
 
[[Tsongkhapa's]] most important works from his early period are his [[Explanation of the Difficult Points]] ([[Kun gzhi dka' 'grel]]) and [[Golden Garland]] ([[Legs bshad gser phreng]]).
  
In the former he gives a detailed explanation of the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] (“foundation consciousness”)––according to [[Tsongkhapa]] the {{Wiki|distinctive}} [[eighth consciousness]] in the [[eight-consciousness]] system of [[Asaṅga's]] (fourth century) [[Indian]] [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]].
+
In the former he gives a detailed explanation of the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] (“[[foundation consciousness]]”)––according to [[Tsongkhapa]] the {{Wiki|distinctive}} [[eighth consciousness]] in the [[eight-consciousness]] system of [[Asaṅga's]] (fourth century) [[Indian]] [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] opens his work with a brief [[discussion]] of the relationship between the [[views]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] and [[Asaṅga]].
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] then discovers in the different usages of the term [[ālaya-vijñāna]] and its near synonyms a negative connotation conveying the [[cause and effect]] [[nature]] of repeated [[suffering]] [[existences]] (Sk. [[saṃsāra]]).
 +
 
 +
He surveys the relevant {{Wiki|literature}}, limiting his [[discussion]] of [[gotra]] (“[[lineage]],” in the [[sense]] of the innate ability a [[person]] has to grow up into a [[fully enlightened being]]) to the presentation given in [[Asaṅga's]] [[Bodhisattva Levels]] ([[Bodhisattva-bhūmi]]).
 +
 
 +
There the “residual [[impression]] left by listening [to the [[correct exposition of the truth]]” (Sk. [[śruta-vāsanā]]) is the “seed” (Sk. [[bīja]]) that matures into [[enlightenment]].
 +
 
 +
It is little more than the innate [[clarity of mind]] when it is freed from limitation by habituation to a correct [[vision]] of [[reality]].
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] limits the sources for his explanation to non-tantric works, almost all by persons he will later describe as [[Indian]] [[Yogācāra]] writers,
 +
 
 +
demonstrating thereby the influence the categories used in the recently redacted [[Kanjur]] and [[Tenjur]] (Tib. [[bsTan 'gyur]], the [[name]] for the commentaries in [[Tibetan]] translation included in the [[canon]]) had on his [[thinking]].
 +
 
 +
When [[Tsongkhapa]] arrived in {{Wiki|Central Tibet}}, the pressing [[philosophical]] issue of the day was [[Dolpopa's]] ([[Dol po pa Shes rab rgyal mtshan]]) (1292–1361) [[Great Middle Way]] (Tib. [[dBu ma chen po]], Sk. *[[Mahā-madhayamaka]]) [[philosophy]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
It propounded a {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} based on the [[principle]] that a [[Buddha]] will always tell you clearly what he means. Based on a wide array of sources, and without making a clear {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[tantric]] and non-tantric works, its central [[tenet]] is that an [[absolute]], [[pure]], [[transcendental mind]] endowed with all good qualities [[exists]] radically other than the ordinary [[world]] of [[appearance]].
 +
 
 +
It is the archetypical [[Tibetan Buddhist]] [[gzhan stong]] (pronounced [[shentong]], “[[emptiness of other]]”) [[philosophy]].
 +
 
 +
[[Dolpopa]], stressing the {{Wiki|hermeneutic}} stated above, says [[Nāgārjuna]] and [[Asaṅga]], [[writing]] during the golden age, have the same [[philosophy]], the [[Great Middle Way]] clearly articulated by the [[Buddha]].
 +
 
 +
[[Dolpopa]] distinguishes a [[pure]], [[transcendental knowledge]] (Tib. [[kun gzhi ye shes]]) that is quite other than the {{Wiki|defiled}} [[foundation consciousness]] (Tib. [[kun gzhi rnam shes]]), and equates the former with his single [[absolute]], endowed with all the qualities of a [[Buddha]].
 +
 
 +
Later, in his mature period, as explained below, [[Tsongkhapa]] will be explicit.
 +
 
 +
He will [[state]] categorically that [[Asaṅga's]] [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]] is quite separate from, and in profundity {{Wiki|inferior}} to, [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[Middle Way school]], removing all references to a [[Great Middle Way]] school.
 +
 
 +
He will say the [[ālaya-vijñāna]], devoid of subject-object [[bifurcation]], provides the [[essential]] [[mind-stuff]] for [[defilement]] (=[[saṃsāra]]) and carries [[seeds]] for [[purification]] (=[[nirvāṇa]]) in a [[Yogācāra]] system that is fundamentally wrong, and at odds with the way things actually are.
 +
 
 +
He will give the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] only a {{Wiki|heuristic}} value, and say a [[correct view]] (the *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]] view) of the workings of [[psycho-physical]] [[reality]] (the [[Buddhist]] [[skandhas]]) totally invalidates it.
 +
 
 +
As [[Jeffrey Hopkins]] (2002, 2006b) has shown conclusively, such statements constitute an explicit rejection of [[Dolpopa's]] view, a view [[Tsongkhapa]] is still formulating in early works like the [[Explanation of the Difficult Points]].
 +
 
 +
In his [[Explanation of the Difficult Points]], [[Tsongkhapa]] is certain he does not accept the view of [[Dolpopa]], but he is still unsure exactly what he will put in its place.
 +
 
 +
He ignores [[Dolpopa's]] [[pure]], [[transcendental knowledge]] called [[ālaya]], mentioning it obliquely, only in passing, during a final brief survey of [[views]] based on {{Wiki|Chinese}} sources;
 +
 
 +
he leaves unanswered the question of the final [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|status}} of the [[eighth consciousness]]; and he allows the [[views]] of [[Asaṅga]] set forth in the [[Bodhisattva-bhūmi]] to retain an authority he will later explicitly deny.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
===2.2 [[Golden Garland]] ([[Legs bshad gser phreng]])===
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa's]] [[Golden Garland]] is his most important early work.
 +
 
 +
It takes the [[form]] of a long explanation of the [[Perfection of Wisdom]] ([[Prajñā-pāramitā]]) [[sūtras]], given [[pride]] of place in the [[Kanjur]] as the foremost [[words of the Buddha]], after the [[Vinaya]] section (the codifications of [[ethical]] conduct).
 +
 
 +
It is a word-by-word commentary on the topics in the [[Ornament for the Chapters]] ([[Abhisamayālaṃkāra]]).
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] bases his explanation on two sub-commentaries by [[Ārya]] [[Vimuktiṣeṇa]] (sixth century?) and [[Hari Bhadra]] (end of the eighth century).
 +
 
 +
It propounds a [[philosophy]] that later [[Gelukpas]], following the taxonomy developed in the mature works of [[Tsongkhapa]] himself, call [[Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka]], in [[essence]] a [[Middle Way]] that incorporates many of the categories of [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]], yet does not have the authority of [[Candrakīrti's]] [[Prāsaṅgika]] [[interpretation]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
A great deal has been written on the difference between [[Prāsaṅgika]] and [[Svātantrika]] ([[Dreyfus]] and [[McClintock]] 2003).
 +
 
 +
Historically, the [[Gelukpa's]] [[Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka]] is another [[name]] for the {{Wiki|mainstream}} [[philosophical]] school that developed in [[Tibet]], based primarily on the [[teaching]] of [[Śāntarakṣita]] and his [[student]] [[Kamalaśīla]] (both fl. end of the eight century), the two most important [[Indian]] [[paṇḍitas]] in the dissemination of [[Buddhist]] [[ideas]] to [[Tibet]].
 +
 
 +
Later [[Gelukpa]] [[scholastics]], basing themselves on the mature works of [[Tsongkhapa]], are unequivocal that [[Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka]], like the [[Yogācāra philosophy]] of [[Asaṅga]], is wrong, and has only {{Wiki|heuristic}} value.
 +
 
 +
At the same time, they tacitly [[acknowledge]] its centrality by taking this “wrong” [[philosophy]] as the foundation of their studies.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
In the [[Golden Garland]], [[Tsongkhapa]], following [[Śāntarakṣita's]] school as it developed in [[Tibet]], asserts that all bases (Sk. [[vastu]]) (the [[psycho-physical]] factors locating the [[person]] as they begin their [[philosophical]] career), all [[mental states]] along the course of the [[path]] (Sk. [[mārga]]), and the final result, are [[illusory]], because they lack any [[essential nature]].
 +
 
 +
But it is not yet clear how the basis relates to the final outcome (the result).
 +
 
 +
As explained below, [[Tsongkhapa]] will solve the problem in his mature works by a clear, radical, [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] leap denying any [[essential nature]] whatsoever, anywhere, to anything,
 +
 
 +
thereby implicitly and explicitly devaluing (in [[absolutist]] terms) the [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|status}} of the final, [[pure]], unified [[state]], relegating it to just one more [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], dependently-originated thing.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
In the [[Golden Garland]], [[Tsongkhapa]] has not yet fully developed his mature, systematic [[philosophy]].
 +
 
 +
He is still content with discrediting [[Dolpopa]] and surveying different points of view.
 +
 
 +
He uses [[Yogācāra]] {{Wiki|terminology}} to {{Wiki|present}} his [[own]] opinion, and uses a [[language]] to describe [[enlightened]] (and [[enlightening]]) [[knowledge]] that retains for it a separateness (through its freedom from all [[mental]] construction) from all other [[mental states]].
 +
 
 +
The primary [[object]] of [[philosophical]] inquiry in the [[Golden Garland]] is the {{Wiki|unity}} of the perceiving [[subject]] in [[enlightenment]], a topic that reflects the [[language]] and concerns of the [[Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka]] school.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
The [[Golden Garland]] is driven in no small measure by an agenda dedicated to discrediting [[Dolpopa's]] [[Perfection of Wisdom]] commentaries ([[Wikipedia:Matthew Kapstein|Kapstein]] 1992/3).
 +
 
 +
 
 +
This is evident from a comparison of [[Dolpopa]] and [[Tsongkhapa's]] sources and [[views]].
 +
 
 +
[[Dolpopa]] excoriates [[Ārya Vimuktiṣeṇa]] and [[Hari Bhadra]] and says they belong to the [[degenerate age]], propounding [[doctrines]] harmful to golden age [[Buddhism]].  
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] opens his work with a brief [[discussion]] of the relationship between the [[views]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] and [[Asaṅga]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] then discovers in the different usages of the term [[ālaya-vijñāna]] and its near synonyms a negative connotation conveying the [[cause and effect]] [[nature]] of repeated [[suffering]] [[existences]] (Sk. [[saṃsāra]]). He surveys the relevant {{Wiki|literature}}, limiting his [[discussion]] of [[gotra]] (“[[lineage]],” in the [[sense]] of the innate ability a [[person]] has to grow up into a [[fully enlightened being]]) to the presentation given in [[Asaṅga's]] [[Bodhisattva Levels]] ([[Bodhisattva-bhūmi]]). There the “residual [[impression]] left by listening [to the [[correct exposition of the truth]]]” (Sk. [[śruta-vāsanā]]) is the “seed” (Sk. [[bīja]]) that matures into [[enlightenment]]. It is little more than the innate [[clarity of mind]] when it is freed from limitation by habituation to a correct [[vision]] of [[reality]].
+
The [[Golden Garland]], on the other hand, is based on commentaries by [[Ārya Vimuktiṣeṇa]] and [[Hari Bhadra]] privileged by the [[Sangphu tradition]].  
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] limits the sources for his explanation to non-tantric works, almost all by persons he will later describe as [[Indian]] [[Yogācāra]] writers, demonstrating thereby the influence the categories used in the recently redacted [[Kanjur]] and [[Tenjur]] (Tib. [[bsTan 'gyur]], the [[name]] for the commentaries in [[Tibetan]] translation included in the [[canon]]) had on his [[thinking]].
+
[[Dolpopa]] says the two Defenses of the [[Perfection of Wisdom ūtras]] (Tib. [[Gnod 'jom]]) by “the foremost, [[Great Middle Way]] [[master]] [[Vasubandhu]],” stand as the primary [[scriptural]] authority for the [[Great Middle Way]] [[doctrine]], {{Wiki|superior}} even to the partial [[truths]] revealed by [[Nāgārjuna]].  
  
When [[Tsongkhapa]] arrived in {{Wiki|Central Tibet}}, the pressing [[philosophical]] issue of the day was [[Dolpopa's]] ([[Dol po pa Shes rab rgyal mtshan]]) (1292–1361) [[Great Middle Way]] (Tib. [[dBu ma chen po]], Sk. *[[Mahā-madhayamaka]]) [[philosophy]]. It propounded a {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} based on the [[principle]] that a [[Buddha]] will always tell you clearly what he means. Based on a wide array of sources, and without making a clear {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[tantric]] and non-tantric works, its central [[tenet]] is that an [[absolute]], [[pure]], [[transcendental mind]] endowed with all good qualities [[exists]] radically other than the ordinary [[world]] of [[appearance]]. It is the archetypical [[Tibetan Buddhist]] [[gzhan stong]] (pronounced [[shentong]], “[[emptiness of other]]”) [[philosophy]].
+
The [[Golden Garland]] [[disputes]] that [[Vasubandhu]] is the author of the two Defenses, and says, regardless of their author, they are simply restatements of [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[Middle Way]].  
  
[[Dolpopa]], stressing the {{Wiki|hermeneutic}} stated above, says [[Nāgārjuna]] and [[Asaṅga]], [[writing]] during the golden age, have the same [[philosophy]], the [[Great Middle Way]] clearly articulated by the [[Buddha]]. [[Dolpopa]] distinguishes a [[pure]], [[transcendental knowledge]] (Tib. [[kun gzhi]] [[ye shes]]) that is quite other than the {{Wiki|defiled}} [[foundation consciousness]] (Tib. [[kun gzhi rnam shes]]), and equates the former with his single [[absolute]], endowed with all the qualities of a [[Buddha]].
+
Finally, [[Dolpopa]] propounds a [[doctrine]] that holds that the basis, [[path]], and result are eternally the same, and all else is thoroughly [[imaginary]], but the [[Golden Garland]] is certain that such a view is wrong, and directly cites a passage from [[Dolpopa's]] work, though without naming its author, saying, “since no other great path-breaker, [i.e., founder of an original [[philosophy]]] besides him has ever asserted what [[Dolpopa]] says], learned persons are right to cast out [what he says] like a gob of spit” ([[Sparham]] 2008, p. 425).
  
Later, in his mature period, as explained below, [[Tsongkhapa]] will be explicit. He will [[state]] categorically that [[Asaṅga's]] [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]] is quite separate from, and in profundity {{Wiki|inferior}} to, [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[Middle Way school]], removing all references to a [[Great Middle Way]] school. He will say the [[ālaya-vijñāna]], devoid of subject-object [[bifurcation]], provides the [[essential]] mind-stuff for [[defilement]] (=[[saṃsāra]]) and carries [[seeds]] for [[purification]] (=[[nirvāṇa]]) in a [[Yogācāra]] system that is fundamentally wrong, and at odds with the way things actually are. He will give the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] only a {{Wiki|heuristic}} value, and say a [[correct view]] (the *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]] view) of the workings of [[psycho-physical]] [[reality]] (the [[Buddhist]] [[skandhas]]) totally invalidates it. As [[Jeffrey Hopkins]] (2002, 2006b) has shown conclusively, such statements constitute an explicit rejection of [[Dolpopa's]] view, a view [[Tsongkhapa]] is still formulating in early works like the [[Explanation of the Difficult Points]].
 
  
In his [[Explanation of the Difficult Points]], [[Tsongkhapa]] is certain he does not accept the view of [[Dolpopa]], but he is still unsure exactly what he will put in its place. He ignores [[Dolpopa's]] [[pure]], [[transcendental knowledge]] called [[ālaya]], mentioning it obliquely, only in passing, during a final brief survey of [[views]] based on {{Wiki|Chinese}} sources; he leaves unanswered the question of the final [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|status}} of the [[eighth consciousness]]; and he allows the [[views]] of [[Asaṅga]] set forth in the [[Bodhisattva-bhūmi]] to retain an authority he will later explicitly deny.
+
===3. Mature Period===
2.2 [[Golden Garland]] ([[Legs bshad gser phreng]])
 
  
[[Tsongkhapa's]] [[Golden Garland]] is his most important early work. It takes the [[form]] of a long explanation of the [[Perfection of Wisdom]] ([[Prajñā-pāramitā]]) [[sūtras]], given [[pride]] of place in the [[Kanjur]] as the foremost [[words of the Buddha]], after the [[Vinaya]] section (the codifications of [[ethical]] conduct). It is a word-by-word commentary on the topics in the Ornament for the Chapters ([[Abhisamayālaṃkāra]]). [[Tsongkhapa]] bases his explanation on two sub-commentaries by [[Ārya]] [[Vimuktiṣeṇa]] (sixth century?) and [[Hari]] [[Bhadra]] (end of the eighth century). It propounds a [[philosophy]] that later [[Gelukpas]], following the taxonomy developed in the mature works of [[Tsongkhapa]] himself, call [[Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka]], in [[essence]] a [[Middle Way]] that incorporates many of the categories of [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]], yet does not have the authority of [[Candrakīrti's]] [[Prāsaṅgika]] [[interpretation]].
 
  
A great deal has been written on the difference between [[Prāsaṅgika]] and [[Svātantrika]] (Dreyfus and [[McClintock]] 2003). Historically, the [[Gelukpa's]] [[Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka]] is another [[name]] for the {{Wiki|mainstream}} [[philosophical]] school that developed in [[Tibet]], based primarily on the [[teaching]] of [[Śāntarakṣita]] and his [[student]] [[Kamalaśīla]] (both fl. end of the eight century), the two most important [[Indian]] [[paṇḍitas]] in the dissemination of [[Buddhist]] [[ideas]] to [[Tibet]]. Later [[Gelukpa]] [[scholastics]], basing themselves on the mature works of [[Tsongkhapa]], are unequivocal that [[Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka]], like the [[Yogācāra philosophy]] of [[Asaṅga]], is wrong, and has only {{Wiki|heuristic}} value. At the same time, they tacitly [[acknowledge]] its centrality by taking this “wrong” [[philosophy]] as the foundation of their studies.
 
  
In the [[Golden Garland]], [[Tsongkhapa]], following [[Śāntarakṣita's]] school as it developed in [[Tibet]], asserts that all bases (Sk. [[vastu]]) (the [[psycho-physical]] factors locating the [[person]] as they begin their [[philosophical]] career), all [[mental states]] along the course of the [[path]] (Sk. [[mārga]]), and the final result, are [[illusory]], because they lack any [[essential nature]]. But it is not yet clear how the basis relates to the final outcome (the result). As explained below, [[Tsongkhapa]] will solve the problem in his mature works by a clear, radical, [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] leap denying any [[essential nature]] whatsoever, anywhere, to anything, thereby implicitly and explicitly devaluing (in [[absolutist]] terms) the [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|status}} of the final, [[pure]], unified [[state]], relegating it to just one more [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], dependently-originated thing.
+
[[Tsongkhapa]] formulated clearly the [[philosophy]] for which he is best known some ten years after finishing the [[Golden Garland]].  
  
In the [[Golden Garland]], [[Tsongkhapa]] has not yet fully developed his mature, systematic [[philosophy]]. He is still content with discrediting [[Dolpopa]] and surveying different points of view. He uses [[Yogācāra]] {{Wiki|terminology}} to {{Wiki|present}} his [[own]] opinion, and uses a [[language]] to describe [[enlightened]] (and [[enlightening]]) [[knowledge]] that retains for it a separateness (through its freedom from all [[mental]] construction) from all other [[mental states]]. The primary [[object]] of [[philosophical]] inquiry in the [[Golden Garland]] is the {{Wiki|unity}} of the perceiving [[subject]] in [[enlightenment]], a topic that reflects the [[language]] and concerns of the [[Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka]] school.
+
He characterized the [[vision]] that led him to his [[philosophy]] as a pristine [[Middle Way]] *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]].  
  
The [[Golden Garland]] is driven in no small measure by an agenda dedicated to discrediting [[Dolpopa's]] [[Perfection of Wisdom]] commentaries ([[Wikipedia:Matthew Kapstein|Kapstein]] 1992/3). This is evident from a comparison of [[Dolpopa]] and [[Tsongkhapa's]] sources and [[views]]. [[Dolpopa]] excoriates [[Ārya]] [[Vimuktiṣeṇa]] and [[Hari]] [[Bhadra]] and says they belong to the [[degenerate age]], propounding [[doctrines]] harmful to golden age [[Buddhism]]. The [[Golden Garland]], on the other hand, is based on commentaries by [[Ārya]] [[Vimuktiṣeṇa]] and [[Hari]] [[Bhadra]] privileged by the [[Sangphu]] [[tradition]]. [[Dolpopa]] says the two Defenses of the [[Perfection of Wisdom]] [[Sūtras]] (Tib. [[Gnod 'jom]]) by “the foremost, [[Great Middle Way]] [[master]] [[Vasubandhu]],” stand as the primary [[scriptural]] authority for the [[Great Middle Way]] [[doctrine]], {{Wiki|superior}} even to the partial [[truths]] revealed by [[Nāgārjuna]]. The [[Golden Garland]] [[disputes]] that [[Vasubandhu]] is the author of the two Defenses, and says, regardless of their author, they are simply restatements of [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[Middle Way]]. Finally, [[Dolpopa]] propounds a [[doctrine]] that holds that the basis, [[path]], and result are eternally the same, and all else is thoroughly [[imaginary]], but the [[Golden Garland]] is certain that such a view is wrong, and directly cites a passage from [[Dolpopa's]] work, though without naming its author, saying, “since no other great path-breaker, [i.e., founder of an original [[philosophy]]] besides him has ever asserted [what [[Dolpopa]] says], learned persons are right to cast out [what he says] like a gob of spit” ([[Sparham]] 2008, p. 425).
+
Reflecting back on his [[insight]], he would write in his In [[Praise]] of [[Dependent Origination]] ([[brTen 'brel bstod pa]] trans. by [[Tupten Jinpa]],
3. Mature Period
 
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] formulated clearly the [[philosophy]] for which he is best known some ten years after finishing the [[Golden Garland]]. He characterized the [[vision]] that led him to his [[philosophy]] as a pristine [[Middle Way]] *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]]. Reflecting back on his [[insight]], he would write in his In Praise of [[Dependent Origination]] ([[brTen 'brel bstod pa]] trans. by Tupten [[Jinpa]],
 
  
 
     “Nonetheless, before the {{Wiki|stream}} of this [[life]]
 
     “Nonetheless, before the {{Wiki|stream}} of this [[life]]
Line 98: Line 265:
 
     Know this perfectly well, not others.”
 
     Know this perfectly well, not others.”
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] first sets forth this mature [[philosophy]] linking [[dependent origination and emptiness]] in a special section at the end of his [[Great Exposition]]. There, in the context of an [[investigation]] into the end-product of an [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]], [[intellectual]] [[investigation]] into the truly real (Sk. [[tattva]], Tib. [[de kho na]]), and into the way things finally are at their deepest level (Sk. [[tathatā]], Tib. [[de bzhin nyid]]),[2] he says you have to identify the [[object of negation]] (Tib. [[dgag bya]]), i.e., the last false projection to appear as [[reality]], by avoiding two errors: going too far (Tib. khyab che ba) and not going far enough (Tib. [[khyab chung ba]]).
 
  
That his project does not presuppose a privileged, soul-like, [[state of consciousness]] that surveys and categorizes [[phenomena]] is evident from his [[assertion]] that these two errors originate in a latent [[psychological]] tendency in [[philosophers]]: first, to hold on to vestiges of [[truth]] ([[reality]]) where there is in fact an absence of it, and second, to fall back on some version of [[truth]] ([[reality]]) in ordinary [[appearance]] after failing to avoid [[nihilism]] in a futile quest for meaning.
+
[[Tsongkhapa]] first sets forth this mature [[philosophy]] linking [[dependent origination and emptiness]] in a special section at the end of his [[Great Exposition]].
 +
 
 +
There, in the context of an [[investigation]] into the end-product of an [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]], [[intellectual]] [[investigation]] into the truly real (Sk. [[tattva]], Tib. [[de kho na]]), and into the way things finally are at their deepest level (Sk. [[tathatā]], Tib. [[de bzhin nyid]]),
 +
 
 +
[2] he says you have to identify the [[object of negation]] (Tib. [[dgag bya]]), i.e., the last false projection to appear as [[reality]],
 +
 
 +
 
 +
by avoiding two errors:
 +
 
 +
 
 +
going too far (Tib. [[khyab che ba]]) and
 +
 
 +
not going far enough (Tib. [[khyab chung ba]]).
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
That his project does not presuppose a privileged, soul-like, [[state of consciousness]] that surveys and categorizes [[phenomena]] is evident from his [[assertion]] that these two errors originate in a latent [[psychological]] tendency in [[philosophers]]:  
 +
 
 +
first, to hold on to vestiges of [[truth]] ([[reality]]) where there is in fact an absence of it, and second, to fall back on some version of [[truth]] ([[reality]]) in ordinary [[appearance]] after failing to avoid [[nihilism]] in a futile quest for meaning.
 +
 
 +
This section of [[Tsongkhapa's]] work is based on the opening verse of [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[Root Verses on the Middle Way]] ([[Mūla-madhyamaka-kārikā]]). [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[Ocean of Reasoning]] (Garfield and [[Samten]] 2006a) is a detailed {{Wiki|exegesis}} of this work.
 +
 
 +
In it, [[Nāgārjuna]] says nothing is produced because it is not produced from itself, other, both or neither.
 +
 
 +
In [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[Great Exposition]], the [[subject]] of [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[syllogism]] is primarily the [[embodied]] [[person]], {{Wiki|reflecting}} the trend that runs throughout [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|literature}}, in general, to [[stress]] the application of [[philosophical]] analysis to praxis.
 +
 
 +
Furthermore, for [[Tsongkhapa]], [[Nāgārjuna's]] statement is about a first [[moment]] in the {{Wiki|continuum}} of the investigating [[person]].
 +
 
 +
By implication, {{Wiki|reflecting}} the continuing influence of [[Śāntarakṣita]], it is the [[person]] engaged in the [[philosophical]] [[investigation]] in the immediate [[moment]].
 +
 
 +
It is axiomatic for [[Buddhist philosophers]] that there is no {{Wiki|independent}} [[subject]] ([[soul]]) other than the [[five heaps]] ([[skandhas]]), so the [[subject]] of the [[syllogism]] becomes the complex or {{Wiki|continuum}} of [[sense-faculties]] in the {{Wiki|present}} instant.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
Such a [[subject]] makes [[excellence]] [[sense]] of [[Tsongkhapa's]] otherwise confusing juxtaposition of [[Nāgārjuna's]] analysis with [[Dharmakīrti's]] epistemology,
 +
 
 +
in which it is axiomatic that direct [[sense perception]] is an authoritative means of [[knowledge]] (Sk. [[pramāṇa]]).
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Nāgārjuna's]] statement that such a [[person]] was never produced seems {{Wiki|paradoxical}}, to say the least, because it appears to undercut the [[reality]] of the very [[intellectual]] act in which the thinker is self-evidently engaged.
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] makes it abundantly clear that in his view not only is the [[intellectual]] act itself utterly devoid of any [[essential]] [[reality]],
 +
 
 +
even the [[sense-faculties]] (the complex [[eye]], {{Wiki|ear}} and so on) also lack any [[essential]] [[reality]], never [[mind]] the [[sense]] {{Wiki|data}} they convey to the [[knowing]] {{Wiki|individual}}.
 +
 
  
This section of [[Tsongkhapa's]] work is based on the opening verse of [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[Root Verses on the Middle Way]] ([[Mūla-madhyamaka-kārikā]]). [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[Ocean of Reasoning]] (Garfield and [[Samten]] 2006a) is a detailed {{Wiki|exegesis}} of this work. In it, [[Nāgārjuna]] says nothing is produced because it is not produced from itself, other, both or neither. In [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[Great Exposition]], the [[subject]] of [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[syllogism]] is primarily the [[embodied]] [[person]], {{Wiki|reflecting}} the trend that runs throughout [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|literature}}, in general, to [[stress]] the application of [[philosophical]] analysis to praxis. Furthermore, for [[Tsongkhapa]], [[Nāgārjuna's]] statement is about a first [[moment]] in the {{Wiki|continuum}} of the investigating [[person]]. By implication, {{Wiki|reflecting}} the continuing influence of [[Śāntarakṣita]], it is the [[person]] engaged in the [[philosophical]] [[investigation]] in the immediate [[moment]]. It is axiomatic for [[Buddhist philosophers]] that there is no {{Wiki|independent}} [[subject]] ([[soul]]) other than the [[five heaps]] ([[skandhas]]), so the [[subject]] of the [[syllogism]] becomes the complex or {{Wiki|continuum}} of [[sense-faculties]] in the {{Wiki|present}} instant. Such a [[subject]] makes [[excellence]] [[sense]] of [[Tsongkhapa's]] otherwise confusing juxtaposition of [[Nāgārjuna's]] analysis with [[Dharmakīrti's]] epistemology, in which it is axiomatic that direct [[sense perception]] is an authoritative means of [[knowledge]] (Sk. [[pramāṇa]]).
+
[[Tsongkhapa's]] choice of the opening line's of [[Nāgārjuna's]] work as a point of departure for his [[philosophy]] stems from his [[belief]] that he has gained a true [[insight]] into [[dependent origination]] ([[pratītya-samutpāda]]).  
  
[[Nāgārjuna's]] statement that such a [[person]] was never produced seems {{Wiki|paradoxical}}, to say the least, because it appears to undercut the [[reality]] of the very [[intellectual]] act in which the thinker is self-evidently engaged. [[Tsongkhapa]] makes it abundantly clear that in his view not only is the [[intellectual]] act itself utterly devoid of any [[essential]] [[reality]], even the [[sense-faculties]] (the complex [[eye]], {{Wiki|ear}} and so on) also lack any [[essential]] [[reality]], never [[mind]] the [[sense]] {{Wiki|data}} they convey to the [[knowing]] {{Wiki|individual}}.
+
This [[insight]], he believes, resolves the [[paradox]] between his apparent [[nihilism]] and his insistence on the {{Wiki|weight}} of authoritative statements and [[cognitions]].  
  
[[Tsongkhapa's]] choice of the opening line's of [[Nāgārjuna's]] work as a point of departure for his [[philosophy]] stems from his [[belief]] that he has gained a true [[insight]] into [[dependent origination]] ([[pratītya-samutpāda]]). This [[insight]], he believes, resolves the [[paradox]] between his apparent [[nihilism]] and his insistence on the {{Wiki|weight}} of authoritative statements and [[cognitions]]. Thus he says in his [[Great Exposition]],
+
Thus he says in his [[Great Exposition]],
  
    “Therefore, the {{Wiki|intelligent}} should develop an unshakeable {{Wiki|certainty}} that the very meaning of [[emptiness]] is [[dependent-arising]]… Specifically, this is the {{Wiki|subtle}} point that the [[noble]] [[Nāgārjuna]] and his [[spiritual]] son [[Āryadeva]] had in [[mind]] and upon which the [[master]] [[Buddhapālita]] and the glorious [[Candrakīrti]] gave fully comprehensive commentary. This is how [[dependent-arising]] bestows certain [[knowledge]] of the absence of [[intrinsic existence]]; this is how it dawns on you that it is things which are devoid of [[intrinsic existence]] that are [[causes]] and effects” ([[Lamrim Chenmo]] Translation Committee Vol. 3, 139).
 
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] set out the ramifications of his view in “eight points that are difficult to understand” (Tib. [[dka' gnas]] brgyad) first enumerated in notes (rjes [[byang]]) to one of his lectures by his contemporary and [[disciple]], [[Darma]] [[rin chen]] (also called [[rGyal tshab]] rje “the {{Wiki|regent}}”). [[Tillemans]] (1998) has nicely rendered the opening of the text as follows,
+
“Therefore, the {{Wiki|intelligent}} should develop an unshakeable {{Wiki|certainty}} that the very meaning of [[emptiness]] is [[dependent-arising]]… Specifically, this is the {{Wiki|subtle}} point that the [[noble]] [[Nāgārjuna]] and his [[spiritual]] son [[Āryadeva]] had in [[mind]] and upon which the [[master]] [[Buddhapālita]] and the glorious [[Candrakīrti]] gave fully comprehensive commentary.
  
    “Concerning the [[[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]]] bases, there are the following [three points]: (1) the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] nonacceptance of particulars and of (2) the [[storehouse consciousness]], and (3) the [[acceptance]] of external [[objects]]. Concerning the [[path]], there are the following [four points]: (4) the nonacceptance of autonomous reasonings as being means for [[understanding]] [[reality]] and (5) the nonacceptance of [[self-awareness]]; (6) the way in which the [[two obscurations]] [[exist]]; (7) how it is accepted that the [[Buddha's disciples]] and those who become [[awakened]] without a [[Buddha's]] help realize that things are without any [[own-nature]]. Concerning the result, there is: (8) the way in which the [[buddhas]] know [[[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]] things in their full extent. Thus, there are four accepted theses and four unaccepted theses.”
+
This is how [[dependent-arising]] bestows certain [[knowledge]] of the absence of [[intrinsic existence]]; this is how it dawns on you that it is things which are devoid of [[intrinsic existence]] that are [[causes]] and effects” ([[Lamrim Chenmo]] Translation Committee Vol. 3, 139).
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] set out the ramifications of his view in “eight points that are difficult to understand” (Tib. [[dka' gnas brgyad]]) first enumerated in notes (rjes [[byang]]) to one of his lectures by his contemporary and [[disciple]], [[Darma rin chen]] (also called [[rGyal tshab rje]] “the {{Wiki|regent}}”). [[Tillemans]] (1998) has nicely rendered the opening of the text as follows,
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
===[[Concerning the ontological bases, there are the following three points]]===
 +
 
 +
 
 +
<poem>
 +
(1) the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] nonacceptance of particulars and of  
 +
(2) the [[storehouse consciousness]], and  
 +
(3) the [[acceptance]] of external [[objects]]. Concerning the [[path]], there are the following [four points]:  
 +
(4) the nonacceptance of autonomous reasonings as being means for [[understanding]] [[reality]] and  
 +
(5) the nonacceptance of [[self-awareness]];  
 +
(6) the way in which the [[two obscurations]] [[exist]];
 +
 +
(7) how it is accepted that the [[Buddha's disciples]] and those who become [[awakened]] without a [[Buddha's]] help realize that things are without any [[own-nature]]. Concerning the result, there is:  
 +
 
 +
(8) the way in which the [[buddhas]] know [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] things in their full extent. Thus, there are four accepted theses and four unaccepted theses.”
 +
</poem>
  
 
They have been discussed by a number of writers (Ruegg 2002, [[Cabezon]] 1992, 397).
 
They have been discussed by a number of writers (Ruegg 2002, [[Cabezon]] 1992, 397).
  
I have surveyed [[Tsongkhapa's]] early work on the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] above. For [[Tsongkhapa]], until the [[correct view]] is understood, it is necessary to assert the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] in order to save [[cause and effect]], and avoid falling into [[nihilism]]. When the [[correct view]] is obtained, the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] stands invalidated (Tillemans's second point). For [[Tsongkhapa]], it is only possible to understand [[cause and effect]] (in particular, as [[experienced]] in the immediate [[moment]] by an [[embodied]] [[person]]), by correctly [[understanding]] that [[dependent origination]] precludes any [[essential]] [[existence]] whatsoever.
+
I have surveyed [[Tsongkhapa's]] early work on the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] above.  
 +
 
 +
For [[Tsongkhapa]], until the [[correct view]] is understood, it is necessary to assert the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] in order to save [[cause and effect]], and avoid falling into [[nihilism]].  
 +
 
 +
When the [[correct view]] is obtained, the [[ālaya-vijñāna]] stands invalidated (Tillemans's second point).  
 +
 
 +
For [[Tsongkhapa]], it is only possible to understand [[cause and effect]] (in particular, as [[experienced]] in the immediate [[moment]] by an [[embodied]] [[person]]), by correctly [[understanding]] that [[dependent origination]] precludes any [[essential]] [[existence]] whatsoever.
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] asserts that a specific mark (Sk. [[sva-lakṣaṇa]]), for instance a mark that makes blue blue, instead of [[red]] or any other {{Wiki|color}}, has not even a nominal [[existence]].
 +
 
 +
This is the first of Tillemans's [[eight difficult points]].
 +
 
 +
In his {{Wiki|monograph}} [[Essence of Eloquence]], [[Tsongkhapa]] employs a {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} that treats [[language]] and [[knowledge]] as equally {{Wiki|semiotic}} in [[nature]].
 +
 
 +
This is consistent with [[Tsongkhapa's]] view that any [[intellectual]] act is itself utterly devoid of any [[essential]] [[reality]], yet functions on a [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level through the natural workings of [[dependent origination]] (Sk. [[dharmatā]]).
 +
 
 +
This view allows him to conclude that [[Dignāga]] and [[Dharmakīrti's]] Logico-epistemological school is {{Wiki|equivalent}} to [[Asaṅga's]] [[Yogācāra school]] insofar as the former school asserts a specific mark, seen by direct [[sense perception]], that is necessary in order to retain the [[reality]] of the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[world]].
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] takes the strong position that no datum that appears to (or is there but unknown to) [[thought]] or [[sense perception]], has any [[essential]] [[reality]].  
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] asserts that a specific mark (Sk. sva-lakṣaṇa), for instance a mark that makes blue blue, instead of red or any other {{Wiki|color}}, has not even a nominal [[existence]]. This is the first of Tillemans's [[eight difficult points]].
+
All are, equally, simply labeled by [[thought]] construction (Tib. [[rtog pas btags tsam]]).  
  
In his {{Wiki|monograph}} [[Essence of Eloquence]], [[Tsongkhapa]] employs a {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} that treats [[language]] and [[knowledge]] as equally {{Wiki|semiotic}} in [[nature]]. This is consistent with [[Tsongkhapa's]] view that any [[intellectual]] act is itself utterly devoid of any [[essential]] [[reality]], yet functions on a [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level through the natural workings of [[dependent origination]] (Sk. [[dharmatā]]). This view allows him to conclude that [[Dignāga]] and [[Dharmakīrti's]] Logico-epistemological school is {{Wiki|equivalent}} to [[Asaṅga's]] [[Yogācāra school]] insofar as the former school asserts a specific mark, seen by direct [[sense perception]], that is necessary in order to retain the [[reality]] of the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[world]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] takes the strong position that no datum that appears to (or is there but unknown to) [[thought]] or [[sense perception]], has any [[essential]] [[reality]]. All are, equally, simply labeled by [[thought]] construction (Tib. rtog pas btags tsam). Only convention makes the actual [[sense-faculties]], for example, real, and [[success]] or failure [[experienced]] in a [[dream]], for example, false. This [[dependent origination]] (between a label and what is labeled) precludes the [[essential]] [[existence]] implicit in the Epistemologist's sva-lakṣaṇa.
+
Only convention makes the actual [[sense-faculties]], for example, real, and [[success]] or failure [[experienced]] in a [[dream]], for example, false.  
  
[[Tsongkhapa's]] strong rejection of [[Yogācāra]] [[idealism]] leads him to assert the [[existence]] of external [[objects]] (the third point). His (discredited) [[Yogācāra school]], based on either the works of [[Asaṅga]] or the [[Epistemologists]], explains the absence of subject-object [[bifurcation]] as [[non-dual]] with [[thought]] or [[mind]] (Sk. [[citta]]). [[Realizing]] this in a [[non-conceptual]], [[meditational]] [[state]] constitutes a liberating [[vision]]. Ultimately, therefore, external [[objects]] are {{Wiki|projections}} of a [[deluded mind]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] rejects this, though he suggests only those who have understood the [[emptiness]] of [[inherent existence]] through {{Wiki|reflecting}} on the natural workings of [[dependent origination]] can set it aside. As he says in his [[Ocean of Reasoning]],
+
This [[dependent origination]] (between a label and what is labeled) precludes the [[essential]] [[existence]] implicit in the [[Epistemologist's]] [[sva-lakṣaṇa]].
  
    “The meaning of the statement that the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] designation of [[subject]] and [[objects]] stops is that the designation of these two stops from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of [[meditative equipoise]], but it does not mean that the [[insight]] in [[meditative equipoise]] and [[the ultimate truth]] are rejected as [[subject]] and [[object]]. This is because their being [[subject]] and [[object]] is not posited from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of analytic [[insight]], but from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[understanding]]” (Garfield and [[Samten]] 2006a, p. 26).
+
[[Tsongkhapa's]] strong rejection of [[Yogācāra]] [[idealism]] leads him to assert the [[existence]] of external [[objects]] (the third point).
 +
 
 +
His (discredited) [[Yogācāra school]], based on either the works of [[Asaṅga]] or the [[Epistemologists]], explains the absence of subject-object [[bifurcation]] as [[non-dual]] with [[thought]] or [[mind]] (Sk. [[citta]]).
 +
 
 +
[[Realizing]] this in a [[non-conceptual]], [[meditational]] [[state]] constitutes a liberating [[vision]].
 +
 
 +
Ultimately, therefore, external [[objects]] are {{Wiki|projections}} of a [[deluded mind]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] rejects this, though he suggests only those who have understood the [[emptiness]] of [[inherent existence]] through {{Wiki|reflecting}} on the natural workings of [[dependent origination]] can set it aside. As he says in his [[Ocean of Reasoning]],
 +
 
 +
 
 +
“The meaning of the statement that the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] designation of [[subject]] and [[objects]] stops is that the designation of these two stops from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of [[meditative equipoise]],  
 +
 
 +
but it does not mean that the [[insight]] in [[meditative equipoise]] and [[the ultimate truth]] are rejected as [[subject]] and [[object]].  
 +
 
 +
This is because their being [[subject]] and [[object]] is not posited from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of analytic [[insight]], but from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[understanding]]” (Garfield and [[Samten]] 2006a, p. 26).
  
 
From the {{Wiki|perspective}} of ordinary convention there are external [[objects]], so it is sufficient, on that level, to assert that they are there.
 
From the {{Wiki|perspective}} of ordinary convention there are external [[objects]], so it is sufficient, on that level, to assert that they are there.
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] does not accept [[svātantra]] (“autonomous”) {{Wiki|reasoning}} (the fourth point). He asserts that it is enough, when proving that any given [[subject]] is [[empty]] of [[intrinsic existence]], to lead the interlocutor, through {{Wiki|reasoning}}, to the unwelcome {{Wiki|consequences}} ([[prasaṅga]]) in their [[own]] untenable position; it is not necessary to demonstrate the {{Wiki|thesis}} based on {{Wiki|reasoning}} that presupposes any sort of intrinsic (=autonomous) [[existence]]. This gives [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[philosophy]] its [[name]] *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]], i.e., a [[philosophy]] of a [[middle way]] (between [[nihilism]] and {{Wiki|eternalism}}) arrived at through demonstrating the unwelcome {{Wiki|consequences}} (in any given position that presupposes [[intrinsic existence]]).
+
[[Tsongkhapa]] does not accept [[svātantra]] (“autonomous”) {{Wiki|reasoning}} (the fourth point).  
 +
 
 +
He asserts that it is enough, when proving that any given [[subject]] is [[empty]] of [[intrinsic existence]], to lead the interlocutor, through {{Wiki|reasoning}}, to the unwelcome {{Wiki|consequences}} ([[prasaṅga]]) in their [[own]] untenable position; it is not necessary to demonstrate the {{Wiki|thesis}} based on {{Wiki|reasoning}} that presupposes any sort of intrinsic (=autonomous) [[existence]].  
 +
 
 +
This gives [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[philosophy]] its [[name]] *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]], i.e., a [[philosophy]] of a [[middle way]] (between [[nihilism]] and {{Wiki|eternalism}}) arrived at through demonstrating the unwelcome {{Wiki|consequences}} (in any given position that presupposes [[intrinsic existence]]).
 +
 
 +
 
 +
In the context of this [[assertion]], [[Tsongkhapa]] offers a {{Wiki|distinctive}} explanation of the well-known [[Nayāyika]] objection to [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[philosophy]], namely, if the statements he uses to prove his {{Wiki|thesis}} are themselves without any final [[intrinsic reality]], they will be ineffective as proofs.
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] says *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamakas]] do not simply find faults in all positions and reject all positions as their [[own]]. They only deny any {{Wiki|thesis}} that presupposes an [[intrinsic existence]].
 +
 
 +
They do hold a specific {{Wiki|thesis}}, to wit, that all [[phenomena]] lack an [[intrinsic existence]].
 +
 
 +
They use {{Wiki|reasoning}} and [[logic]] that lacks any [[essential]] [[reality]] to establish this {{Wiki|thesis}}.
 +
 
 +
Such {{Wiki|reasoning}} derives its efficacity on a [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level through the natural workings of [[dependent origination]].
 +
 
 +
This is one of the most contentious assertions of [[Tsongkhapa]].
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa's]] rejection of any [[form]] of self-referential [[consciousness]] (Sk. [[sva-saṃvitti]], [[sva-saṃvedana]]) (the fifth point) is in [[essence]] a rejection of [[Śāntarakṣita's]] position that such self-referential or [[reflexive awareness]] is necessary to explain the self-evidential [[nature]] of [[consciousness]], and to explain the privileged access the [[conscious]] [[person]] has to their [[own]] [[consciousness]] as immediate and veridical (Garfield 2006b).[3]
 +
 
 +
At issue is the {{Wiki|status}} of the [[knowing]] [[subject]] engaged in the [[intellectual]] pursuit of the truly real. [[Tsongkhapa]] holds that such a [[knowing]] [[subject]] has no [[essential]] [[reality]] at all.
 +
 
 +
Such a position requires of [[Tsongkhapa]] an explanation of [[memory]].
 +
 
 +
His {{Wiki|solution}} is to deny that when you remember [[seeing]] [[object]] X you also remember the [[conscious]] act of [[seeing]] it.
 +
 
 +
(Were you to do so, there would have to be an aspect of the earlier [[consciousness]] of the [[object]] that was equally [[conscious]] of itself, i.e., self-referential.)
 +
 
 +
Instead, [[Tsongkhapa]] argues, [[memory]] is simply the earlier [[consciousness]] of [[object]] X, now designated “{{Wiki|past}}.”
 +
 
 +
When designated {{Wiki|past}}, inexorably (or inferentially, as it were) the presence of a [[consciousness]] of the {{Wiki|past}} [[object]] X is required to make [[sense]] of the {{Wiki|present}} [[reality]].
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] characterizes basic [[ignorance]] (Sk. [[avidyā]]), the [[root cause]] of [[suffering]] in [[Buddhist philosophy]], not as a latent tendency, but as an active defiling agency (Sk. [[kleśāvaraṇa]]) that projects a [[reality]] onto [[objects]] that is in fact absent from them.
 +
 
 +
This [[ignorance]] affects even [[sense perception]] and explains the veridical aspect that is, in fact, just error.
 +
 
 +
The residual [[impressions]] left by [[distortion]] (literally “perfumings” Sk. [[vāsanā]]) explain the mere [[appearance]] of things as real.
 +
 
 +
Beyond that, he asserts that habituation to this [[distortion]] prevents [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] and [[ultimate reality]] from appearing united in an [[appearing object]].
 +
 
 +
This explanation of the {{Wiki|psychology}} of error differs markedly from earlier [[Tibetan]] explanations and constitutes the sixth difficult point.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
In [[Tsongkhapa's]] mature [[philosophy]] the [[Mahāyāna altruistic principle]] ([[bodhicitta]]) is the sole criterion for distinguishing [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[Mahāyāna]] [[views]] and practices from non-[[Mahāyāna]] ones.
 +
 
 +
By privileging the [[principle]] in this way he is able to assert that any [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[realization]] of [[truth]] is a [[realization]] of the way things are, namely, a [[realization]] of no [[sva-bhāva]] (Sk.) (“[[own-being]], [[own-nature]], intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]”).
 +
 
 +
For [[Tsongkhapa]], therefore, [[Hīnayānists]] (by which he intends followers of the basic [[Buddhist doctrine]] of the [[Four Noble Truths]] set forth in the earliest [[scriptures]]), necessarily have the same [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[knowledge of reality]].
 +
 
 +
Were they not to have such [[knowledge]], he argues, they could not have reached the goals they reached (the seventh point).
 +
 
 +
Finally, [[Tsongkhapa]] has a robust explanation of the difference between true and false on the covering or [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level.
 +
 
 +
He denies any difference between a false [[object]] (a [[dream]] lottery ticket, for example) and a real one; as [[appearances]], he asserts, both are equally false, only convention decides which is true.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
===[[All phenomena equally lack truth]]===
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
In [[Tsongkhapa's]] mature [[philosophy]], therefore, all [[appearance]] is false––to appear is to appear as being truly what the [[appearance]] is of, and the [[principle]] of [[dependent origination]] precludes such [[truth]] from according with the way things actually are.
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] holds that sentences and their content, on the one hand, and [[minds]] and what appears to them on the other, function in the same way.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
Saying
 +
 
 +
(1) of a set of “true” and “false” statements that they are all equally untrue, and
 +
 
 +
(2) saying of unmediated sense-based [[perception]] or mistaken [[ideas]] that they are equally untrue is to say the same thing.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
The [[truth]] in both is decided by convention, not by something inhering in the true statement (or its content), or the valid [[perception]] (or its [[object]]).
 +
 
 +
For [[Tsongkhapa]], therefore, since all [[appearance]] is false, the [[Buddha]] [[knows]], but without any [[appearance]] of [[truth]] (the eighth difficult point).
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
===4. {{Wiki|Hermeneutics}}===
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
A {{Wiki|distinctive}} feature of [[Tsongkhapa's]] mature [[philosophy]] is the centrality he accords {{Wiki|hermeneutics}}, and the particular stratification of [[philosophical]] systems it occasions.
 +
 
 +
His focus on {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} stems in no small measure from his [[acceptance]] of the [[Kanjur]] as a true record of [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] statements of the [[Buddha]], and also from his wish to discredit [[Dolpopa's]] [[views]].
 +
 
 +
According to [[Tsongkhapa]], and worked out in detail in his [[Essence of Eloquence]], the given record of the [[Buddha's]] diverse statements seems to contain contradictions, so a reader must decide on criteria for interpreting them.
 +
 
 +
No statement of the [[Buddha]] can serve as a primary {{Wiki|hermeneutic}} [[principle]], so that [[principle]] necessarily becomes [[human]] [[reason]] (Sk. [[yukti]], Tib. [[rigs pa]]).
 +
 
 +
 
 +
When [[human]] [[reason]] is brought to bear on the diverse statements of the [[Buddha]], it concludes that all statements that an [[essential]] or intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] [[exists]], or any statements that presupposes that, cannot be taken literally, at face value.
 +
 
 +
This is because [[human]] [[reason]], when it analyzes [[the ultimate truth]] of any [[object]] or statement, finds it [[empty]] of anything intrinsic to it that would make it true.
 +
 
 +
For [[Tsongkhapa]], the line of {{Wiki|reasoning}} that leads most clearly to this conclusion is [[dependent origination]].
 +
 
 +
Statements that require [[interpretation]] [[Tsongkhapa]] groups into those of different [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] schools: in ascending order, Listener (Sk. [[Śrāvaka]]) schools based on older [[Buddhist]] sources (the [[Vaibhāṣika]] and [[Sautrāntika]]),
 +
 
 +
[[Yogācāra]] schools following [[Asaṅga]] and Dignāga/Dharmakīrti, and non-[[Prāsaṅgika]] [[Madhyamaka]] schools following [[Bhavaviveka]] and [[Śāntarakṣita]].
 +
 
 +
The *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]] school of [[Candrakīrti]] alone captures the final [[intention]] of the [[Buddha]].
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] was certainly not the first doxographer, but his clear and definitive categories had immense influence on later writers, so much so they have anachronistically been read back into works that were written before his time.
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa's]] particular {{Wiki|hermeneutics}}, the primary means he employs to lead readers to his [[philosophical]] [[insight]], allows him to characterize particular, [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]], [[Buddhist]] [[philosophies]] as wrong (because they are wrong from a [[Prāsaṅgika]] {{Wiki|perspective}}), yet right from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of those particular systems.
 +
 
 +
They are right because the [[philosophies]] have particular roles to play in a larger, grander scheme.
 +
 
 +
This scheme is part of the larger [[philosophy]] of a {{Wiki|perfect}} [[person]] whose [[views]] are in {{Wiki|perfect}} accord (Sk. [[tathāgata]]) with the way things are, i.e., [[dependent origination]], and whose statements are motivated solely by the [[benefit]] they have to those who hear them.
 +
 
 +
In this way, [[Tsongkhapa's]] {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} lead to, or incorporate, a second [[principle]], namely, [[bodhicitta]] (Sk.).
 +
 
 +
The [[word]] [[bodhicitta]] has at least six different, but {{Wiki|interrelated}} meanings in different contexts ([[Wangchuk]] 2007).
 +
 
 +
In his [[philosophical works]] [[Tsongkhapa]] uses it to mean a [[universal]], {{Wiki|altruistic}} [[principle]] (not unlike the {{Wiki|logos}}) that explains, primarily,
 +
 
 +
the genesis of the [[Buddha's]] diverse statements, i.e., explains why a [[person]] with {{Wiki|perfect}} {{Wiki|intellect}} and [[powers]] of expression would make statements that seem to contain contradictions.
 +
 
 +
This [[principle]] plays a central role in [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[assertion]] that all [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[attainments]], without {{Wiki|distinction}},
 +
 
 +
are based on an [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[insight]] into [[emptiness]] (the seventh of the [[eight difficult points]] listed above), and it leads him to assert that the “origin” of the [[Mahāyāna]] is located in [[bodhicitta]], and [[bodhicitta]] alone
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
===5. [[Ethics]]===
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] is part of a long, shared, [[Indo-Tibetan]] [[Buddhist tradition]] that conceives of [[ethical]] conduct not in [[absolute]] terms, but in the context of different {{Wiki|individuals}} in different situations.
 +
 
 +
There is an unspoken presupposition that [[ethical]] statements are grounded in [[reality]], in the [[sense]] that [[suffering]] (Sk. [[duḥkha]]) comes from [[actions]] (Sk. [[karma]]) that are not in accord with the way things actually are (Tib. [[dngos po'i gnas lugs]]).
 +
 
 +
The [[person]] is ultimately not {{Wiki|present}} as an [[ethical]] [[subject]], but is so, on a [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] or covering level, through the natural working of [[dependent origination]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] groups such {{Wiki|individuals}} into three separate categories (those who privilege basic [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|codes}}, [[bodhisattvas]], and [[tāntrikas]]).
 +
 
 +
Each is governed by an [[ethical]] code (Tib. [[sdom gsum]]), each {{Wiki|superior}} code subsuming the points of the lesser.
 +
 
 +
Beyond these three, his [[Great Exposition]] suggests ordinary [[ethical]] conduct is codified as well, in the main, in the [[ten ethical points]] (Sk. daśa-kuśala-patha) basic to any [[Wikipedia:Human life|human life]] that rises above the mere [[animal]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
The first of the three specifically [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|codes}}, the basic code, primarily governs the {{Wiki|behavior}} of [[monks and nuns]].
 +
 
 +
Since for [[Tsongkhapa]] each higher code incorporates all the {{Wiki|rules}} in the lower code, he conceives of the seven (or even twelve) sub-codes making up the basic code as, in descending order, containing fewer and fewer of the {{Wiki|rules}} that constitute the full code.
 +
 
 +
Each of the sub-codes is designed for particular [[people]] in particular [[human]] situations.
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] does not expect a butcher to be governed by the {{Wiki|rule}} of not {{Wiki|killing}}, for example, and he does not expect a lawyer to be governed by the {{Wiki|rule}} of not {{Wiki|lying}}.
 +
 
 +
He avoids gross devaluation of the basic code by privileging [[spiritual]] elites. In this, he takes a {{Wiki|pragmatic}} approach to [[ethics]] in line with his non-absolutist stance.
 +
 
 +
For [[Tsongkhapa]], it is axiomatic that [[Wikipedia:Human life|human life]] is not ipso facto privileged above any other [[form]] of [[life]], but his detailed explanation gives greater “{{Wiki|weight}}” to the [[karmic retribution]] that comes from {{Wiki|killing}} [[humans]], and amongst [[humans]], [[noble persons]], for example, than less [[fortunate]] [[forms]] of [[life]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa's]] explanation of the [[bodhisattva]] [[moral]] code presented in the [[Bodhisattva-bhūmi]] (Tatz 1987) follows naturally from the importance he gives to the {{Wiki|altruistic}} [[principle]] ([[bodhicitta]]) in his other [[writing]].
 +
 
 +
He reconciles {{Wiki|rules}} in the [[bodhisattva]] code that enjoin {{Wiki|behavior}} contradicting the basic code by positing an {{Wiki|elite}} that, through a noblesse oblige of the [[spiritually]] advanced, are required to do things which would be {{Wiki|unethical}} in an [[ordinary person]].
 +
 
 +
Their not doing so constitutes an [[ethical]] lapse.
 +
 
 +
For example, the basic code prohibits [[actions]] that influence what [[food]] a {{Wiki|donor}} puts in the [[begging bowl]] (with a few exceptions for [[human]] flesh and so on), and prohibits eating after noon.
 +
 
 +
The [[bodhisattva]] code contradicts the basic code insofar as it prohibits eating meat, even though, by so doing, the {{Wiki|donor}} does not get the opportunity to make [[charity]].
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] argues that if a [[monk]] at the [[bodhisattva]] stage of [[development]] eats meat it clashes with the dictates of the {{Wiki|altruistic}} [[principle]] ([[bodhicitta]]).
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] accepts that the diverse [[body]] of {{Wiki|literature}}, [[including]] the historically latest [[Buddhist tantras]] (some of which are distinctly {{Wiki|antinomian}} in [[character]]), are the work of a [[fully awakened]] being (Sk. [[buddha]]).
 +
 
 +
The last of the three {{Wiki|codes}} systematizes the conduct espoused in these [[tantras]].
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa's]] presentation is {{Wiki|distinctive}} for finding a code complete with a [[full ordination]] {{Wiki|ceremony}}.
 +
 
 +
The {{Wiki|practical}} result of his presentation is to revalue the basic code for [[monks]], and devalue the [[ritual of tantric consecration]] as it pertains to [[ethical]] conduct.
 +
 
 +
It stresses [[ethical]] conduct even in the context of works that appear, in line with the [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] drift of [[Buddhist philosophy]], to count [[ethical]] {{Wiki|codes}} as a block to the [[highest]] [[spiritual]] and [[philosophical]] [[attainment]].
 +
 
 +
For [[Tsongkhapa]] the [[tantric]] code is only for the very [[highest]] [[spiritual]] {{Wiki|elite}}, mainly [[monks and nuns]].
 +
 
 +
[[Tsongkhapa]] divides [[tantras]] into two [[sections]], and says the lower section is governed exclusively by the [[bodhisattva]] code, supplemented by specific [[ritual]] injunctions (Sk. [[vrata]]).
 +
 
 +
He gives two interpretations of the {{Wiki|rules}} for the [[higher tantras]], reserving the truly {{Wiki|antinomian}} {{Wiki|behavior}} for a {{Wiki|theoretical}} {{Wiki|elite}} whose [[altruism]] is so strong, and whose [[understanding]] and {{Wiki|status}} is so ennobled, that they engage in what ordinarily would be condemned as gross immorality.
 +
 
 +
According to this code, it is an [[ethical]] lapse not to eat meat, perhaps even [[human]] flesh, the [[logic]] being that in certain specific and unusual circumstances, in a [[person]] at this stage of [[development]], such {{Wiki|behavior}} would constitute a [[skillful means]] to [[benefit]] others.
 +
 
 +
 
  
In the context of this [[assertion]], [[Tsongkhapa]] offers a {{Wiki|distinctive}} explanation of the well-known Nayāyika objection to [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[philosophy]], namely, if the statements he uses to prove his {{Wiki|thesis}} are themselves without any final [[intrinsic reality]], they will be ineffective as proofs. [[Tsongkhapa]] says *Prāsaṅgika-madhyamakas do not simply find faults in all positions and reject all positions as their [[own]]. They only deny any {{Wiki|thesis}} that presupposes an [[intrinsic existence]]. They do hold a specific {{Wiki|thesis}}, to wit, that all [[phenomena]] lack an [[intrinsic existence]]. They use {{Wiki|reasoning}} and [[logic]] that lacks any [[essential]] [[reality]] to establish this {{Wiki|thesis}}. Such {{Wiki|reasoning}} derives its efficacity on a [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level through the natural workings of [[dependent origination]]. This is one of the most contentious assertions of [[Tsongkhapa]].
+
===[[Tantra]]===
  
[[Tsongkhapa's]] rejection of any [[form]] of self-referential [[consciousness]] (Sk. sva-saṃvitti, sva-saṃvedana) (the fifth point) is in [[essence]] a rejection of [[Śāntarakṣita's]] position that such self-referential or [[reflexive awareness]] is necessary to explain the self-evidential [[nature]] of [[consciousness]], and to explain the privileged access the [[conscious]] [[person]] has to their [[own]] [[consciousness]] as immediate and veridical (Garfield 2006b).[3] At issue is the {{Wiki|status}} of the [[knowing]] [[subject]] engaged in the [[intellectual]] pursuit of the truly real. [[Tsongkhapa]] holds that such a [[knowing]] [[subject]] has no [[essential]] [[reality]] at all.
 
  
Such a position requires of [[Tsongkhapa]] an explanation of [[memory]]. His {{Wiki|solution}} is to deny that when you remember [[seeing]] [[object]] X you also remember the [[conscious]] act of [[seeing]] it. (Were you to do so, there would have to be an aspect of the earlier [[consciousness]] of the [[object]] that was equally [[conscious]] of itself, i.e., self-referential.) Instead, [[Tsongkhapa]] argues, [[memory]] is simply the earlier [[consciousness]] of [[object]] X, now designated “{{Wiki|past}}.” When designated {{Wiki|past}}, inexorably (or inferentially, as it were) the presence of a [[consciousness]] of the {{Wiki|past}} [[object]] X is required to make [[sense]] of the {{Wiki|present}} [[reality]].
 
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] characterizes basic [[ignorance]] (Sk. [[avidyā]]), the [[root cause]] of [[suffering]] in [[Buddhist philosophy]], not as a latent tendency, but as an active defiling agency (Sk. [[kleśāvaraṇa]]) that projects a [[reality]] onto [[objects]] that is in fact absent from them. This [[ignorance]] affects even [[sense perception]] and explains the veridical aspect that is, in fact, just error. The residual [[impressions]] left by [[distortion]] (literally “perfumings” Sk. [[vāsanā]]) explain the mere [[appearance]] of things as real. Beyond that, he asserts that habituation to this [[distortion]] prevents [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] and [[ultimate reality]] from appearing united in an [[appearing object]]. This explanation of the {{Wiki|psychology}} of error differs markedly from earlier [[Tibetan]] explanations and constitutes the sixth difficult point.
+
[[Tsongkhapa]] does not have a different [[tantric]] [[philosophy]].  
  
In [[Tsongkhapa's]] mature [[philosophy]] the [[Mahāyāna]] {{Wiki|altruistic}} [[principle]] ([[bodhicitta]]) is the sole criterion for distinguishing [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[Mahāyāna]] [[views]] and practices from non-Mahāyāna ones. By privileging the [[principle]] in this way he is able to assert that any [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[realization]] of [[truth]] is a [[realization]] of the way things are, namely, a [[realization]] of no sva-bhāva (Sk.) (“[[own-being]], [[own-nature]], intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]”). For [[Tsongkhapa]], therefore, [[Hīnayānists]] (by which he intends followers of the basic [[Buddhist doctrine]] of the [[Four Noble Truths]] set forth in the earliest [[scriptures]]), necessarily have the same [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[knowledge of reality]]. Were they not to have such [[knowledge]], he argues, they could not have reached the goals they reached (the seventh point).
+
His [[Prāsaṅgika]] [[Middle Way]] is the [[philosophical]] position he articulates in his works on [[tantra]].  
  
Finally, [[Tsongkhapa]] has a robust explanation of the difference between true and false on the covering or [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level. He denies any difference between a false [[object]] (a [[dream]] lottery ticket, for example) and a real one; as [[appearances]], he asserts, both are equally false, only convention decides which is true. All [[phenomena]] equally lack [[truth]]. In [[Tsongkhapa's]] mature [[philosophy]], therefore, all [[appearance]] is false––to appear is to appear as being truly what the [[appearance]] is of, and the [[principle]] of [[dependent origination]] precludes such [[truth]] from according with the way things actually are.
+
He does however, unlike in his non-tantric works, accept that those propounding Idealistic [[philosophies]] ([[Yogācāra]], [[Svātantrika]] [[Middle Way]]) can have [[success]] in their practice.  
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] holds that sentences and their content, on the one hand, and [[minds]] and what appears to them on the other, function in the same way. Saying (1) of a set of “true” and “false” statements that they are all equally untrue, and (2) saying of unmediated sense-based [[perception]] or mistaken [[ideas]] that they are equally untrue is to say the same thing. The [[truth]] in both is decided by convention, not by something inhering in the true statement (or its content), or the valid [[perception]] (or its [[object]]). For [[Tsongkhapa]], therefore, since all [[appearance]] is false, the [[Buddha]] [[knows]], but without any [[appearance]] of [[truth]] (the eighth difficult point).
+
In this he reveals again the importance of the central [[Tibetan philosophical tradition]] going back to [[Śāntarakṣita]].
4. {{Wiki|Hermeneutics}}
 
  
A {{Wiki|distinctive}} feature of [[Tsongkhapa's]] mature [[philosophy]] is the centrality he accords {{Wiki|hermeneutics}}, and the particular stratification of [[philosophical]] systems it occasions. His focus on {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} stems in no small measure from his [[acceptance]] of the [[Kanjur]] as a true record of [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] statements of the [[Buddha]], and also from his wish to discredit [[Dolpopa's]] [[views]]. According to [[Tsongkhapa]], and worked out in detail in his [[Essence of Eloquence]], the given record of the [[Buddha's]] diverse statements seems to contain contradictions, so a reader must decide on criteria for interpreting them. No statement of the [[Buddha]] can serve as a primary {{Wiki|hermeneutic}} [[principle]], so that [[principle]] necessarily becomes [[human]] [[reason]] (Sk. [[yukti]], Tib. [[rigs pa]]).
 
  
When [[human]] [[reason]] is brought to bear on the diverse statements of the [[Buddha]], it concludes that all statements that an [[essential]] or intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] [[exists]], or any statements that presupposes that, cannot be taken literally, at face value. This is because [[human]] [[reason]], when it analyzes [[the ultimate truth]] of any [[object]] or statement, finds it [[empty]] of anything intrinsic to it that would make it true. For [[Tsongkhapa]], the line of {{Wiki|reasoning}} that leads most clearly to this conclusion is [[dependent origination]].
+
[[Tsongkhapa]] conceives of [[tantra]] as a subset of the [[Mahāyāna]], and to that extent all [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[Buddhist tantric]] [[activities]] are, necessarily, authentically {{Wiki|altruistic}}.  
  
Statements that require [[interpretation]] [[Tsongkhapa]] groups into those of different [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] schools: in ascending order, Listener (Sk. [[Śrāvaka]]) schools based on older [[Buddhist]] sources (the [[Vaibhāṣika]] and [[Sautrāntika]]), [[Yogācāra]] schools following [[Asaṅga]] and Dignāga/Dharmakīrti, and non-Prāsaṅgika [[Madhyamaka]] schools following [[Bhavaviveka]] and [[Śāntarakṣita]]. The *[[Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka]] school of [[Candrakīrti]] alone captures the final [[intention]] of the [[Buddha]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] was certainly not the first doxographer, but his clear and definitive categories had immense influence on later writers, so much so they have anachronistically been read back into works that were written before his time.
+
What differentiates [[tantric]] [[activity]] from other ordinary [[Mahāyāna]] [[activities]] is [[deity yoga]] (Tib. [[lha'i rnal 'byor]]), i.e., whether or not, from a first [[person]] {{Wiki|perspective}}, the [[person]] is acting as a {{Wiki|perfect}}, [[divine]][[subject]] when engaging in (primarily [[ritual]]) {{Wiki|behavior}}.
  
[[Tsongkhapa's]] particular {{Wiki|hermeneutics}}, the primary means he employs to lead readers to his [[philosophical]] [[insight]], allows him to characterize particular, [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]], [[Buddhist]] [[philosophies]] as wrong (because they are wrong from a [[Prāsaṅgika]] {{Wiki|perspective}}), yet right from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of those particular systems. They are right because the [[philosophies]] have particular roles to play in a larger, grander scheme. This scheme is part of the larger [[philosophy]] of a {{Wiki|perfect}} [[person]] whose [[views]] are in {{Wiki|perfect}} accord (Sk. [[tathāgata]]) with the way things are, i.e., [[dependent origination]], and whose statements are motivated solely by the [[benefit]] they have to those who hear them.
 
  
In this way, [[Tsongkhapa's]] {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} lead to, or incorporate, a second [[principle]], namely, [[bodhicitta]] (Sk.). The [[word]] [[bodhicitta]] has at least six different, but {{Wiki|interrelated}} meanings in different contexts ([[Wangchuk]] 2007). In his [[philosophical works]] [[Tsongkhapa]] uses it to mean a [[universal]], {{Wiki|altruistic}} [[principle]] (not unlike the {{Wiki|logos}}) that explains, primarily, the genesis of the [[Buddha's]] diverse statements, i.e., explains why a [[person]] with {{Wiki|perfect}} {{Wiki|intellect}} and [[powers]] of expression would make statements that seem to contain contradictions.
 
  
This [[principle]] plays a central role in [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[assertion]] that all [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[attainments]], without {{Wiki|distinction}}, are based on an [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[insight]] into [[emptiness]] (the seventh of the [[eight difficult points]] listed above), and it leads him to assert that the “origin” of the [[Mahāyāna]] is located in [[bodhicitta]], and [[bodhicitta]] alone
+
[[Tsongkhapa]] wrote works on the [[Vajrabhairava]], [[Cakrasaṃvara]], and [[Kālacakra tantras]], but is best known for his [[exposition]] of the [[Guhyasamāja tantra]] based on [[Indian]] commentaries associated with the names of [[Nāgārjuna]] and [[Āryadeva]],  
5. [[Ethics]]
 
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] is part of a long, shared, Indo-Tibetan [[Buddhist tradition]] that conceives of [[ethical]] conduct not in [[absolute]] terms, but in the context of different {{Wiki|individuals}} in different situations. There is an unspoken presupposition that [[ethical]] statements are grounded in [[reality]], in the [[sense]] that [[suffering]] (Sk. [[duḥkha]]) comes from [[actions]] (Sk. [[karma]]) that are not in accord with the way things actually are (Tib. [[dngos po'i gnas lugs]]). The [[person]] is ultimately not {{Wiki|present}} as an [[ethical]] [[subject]], but is so, on a [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] or covering level, through the natural working of [[dependent origination]].
+
particularly his short but influential Commentary on the [[Jñāna-vajra-samuccaya]] ([[Ye shes rdo rje kun las ‘dus pa'i ṭī kā]]) (1410), and magisterial [[Clear Exposition of the Five Stages of Guhyasamāja]] ([[gSang ‘dus rim lnga gsal sgron]]) (1411).  
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] groups such {{Wiki|individuals}} into three separate categories (those who privilege basic [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|codes}}, [[bodhisattvas]], and [[tāntrikas]]). Each is governed by an [[ethical]] code (Tib. [[sdom gsum]]), each {{Wiki|superior}} code subsuming the points of the lesser. Beyond these three, his [[Great Exposition]] suggests ordinary [[ethical]] conduct is codified as well, in the main, in the ten [[ethical]] points (Sk. daśa-kuśala-patha) basic to any [[Wikipedia:Human life|human life]] that rises above the mere [[animal]].
+
He accords great importance to [[esoteric]] [[yoga]].  
  
The first of the three specifically [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|codes}}, the basic code, primarily governs the {{Wiki|behavior}} of [[monks and nuns]]. Since for [[Tsongkhapa]] each higher code incorporates all the {{Wiki|rules}} in the lower code, he conceives of the seven (or even twelve) sub-codes making up the basic code as, in descending order, containing fewer and fewer of the {{Wiki|rules}} that constitute the full code. Each of the sub-codes is designed for particular [[people]] in particular [[human]] situations. [[Tsongkhapa]] does not expect a butcher to be governed by the {{Wiki|rule}} of not {{Wiki|killing}}, for example, and he does not expect a lawyer to be governed by the {{Wiki|rule}} of not {{Wiki|lying}}. He avoids gross devaluation of the basic code by privileging [[spiritual]] elites. In this, he takes a {{Wiki|pragmatic}} approach to [[ethics]] in line with his non-absolutist stance. For [[Tsongkhapa]], it is axiomatic that [[Wikipedia:Human life|human life]] is not ipso facto privileged above any other [[form]] of [[life]], but his detailed explanation gives greater “{{Wiki|weight}}” to the [[karmic retribution]] that comes from {{Wiki|killing}} [[humans]], and amongst [[humans]], [[noble persons]], for example, than less [[fortunate]] [[forms]] of [[life]].
+
In this [[respect]], his work is firmly located in the {{Wiki|mainstream}} [[Tibetan tradition]], influenced in particular by the [[translator]] [[Mar pa]] ([[Mar pa Chos kyi blo gros]]) (1012–1097), who spread the [[Six Teachings of Nāropa]] ([[Nā ro chos drug]]), a later [[Indian]] {{Wiki|synthesis}} of diverse [[tantric practices]], in [[Tibet]].  
  
[[Tsongkhapa's]] explanation of the [[bodhisattva]] [[moral]] code presented in the [[Bodhisattva-bhūmi]] (Tatz 1987) follows naturally from the importance he gives to the {{Wiki|altruistic}} [[principle]] ([[bodhicitta]]) in his other [[writing]]. He reconciles {{Wiki|rules}} in the [[bodhisattva]] code that enjoin {{Wiki|behavior}} contradicting the basic code by positing an {{Wiki|elite}} that, through a noblesse oblige of the [[spiritually]] advanced, are required to do things which would be {{Wiki|unethical}} in an [[ordinary person]]. Their not doing so constitutes an [[ethical]] lapse. For example, the basic code prohibits [[actions]] that influence what [[food]] a {{Wiki|donor}} puts in the [[begging bowl]] (with a few exceptions for [[human]] flesh and so on), and prohibits eating after noon. The [[bodhisattva]] code contradicts the basic code insofar as it prohibits eating meat, even though, by so doing, the {{Wiki|donor}} does not get the opportunity to make [[charity]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] argues that if a [[monk]] at the [[bodhisattva]] stage of [[development]] eats meat it clashes with the dictates of the {{Wiki|altruistic}} [[principle]] ([[bodhicitta]]).
+
Based on this [[Tsongkhapa]] gives detailed explanations of the [[nāḍī]] ([[channels]] for the [[energy]] or [[feelings]] that run through the [[tantric]] practitioner's [[body]]),  
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] accepts that the diverse [[body]] of {{Wiki|literature}}, including the historically latest [[Buddhist tantras]] (some of which are distinctly {{Wiki|antinomian}} in [[character]]), are the work of a [[fully awakened]] being (Sk. [[buddha]]). The last of the three {{Wiki|codes}} systematizes the conduct espoused in these [[tantras]]. [[Tsongkhapa's]] presentation is {{Wiki|distinctive}} for finding a code complete with a full [[ordination]] {{Wiki|ceremony}}. The {{Wiki|practical}} result of his presentation is to revalue the basic code for [[monks]], and devalue the [[ritual]] of [[tantric]] [[consecration]] as it pertains to [[ethical]] conduct. It stresses [[ethical]] conduct even in the context of works that appear, in line with the [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] drift of [[Buddhist philosophy]], to count [[ethical]] {{Wiki|codes}} as a block to the [[highest]] [[spiritual]] and [[philosophical]] [[attainment]].
+
[[cakra]] (circles of [[channels]] in the [[heart]], {{Wiki|throat}}, and other central points up the center of the [[body]] from the bottom of the spine, or tip of the {{Wiki|sex}} {{Wiki|organ}},  
  
For [[Tsongkhapa]] the [[tantric]] code is only for the very [[highest]] [[spiritual]] {{Wiki|elite}}, mainly [[monks and nuns]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] divides [[tantras]] into two [[sections]], and says the lower section is governed exclusively by the [[bodhisattva]] code, supplemented by specific [[ritual]] injunctions (Sk. [[vrata]]). He gives two interpretations of the {{Wiki|rules}} for the [[higher tantras]], reserving the truly {{Wiki|antinomian}} {{Wiki|behavior}} for a {{Wiki|theoretical}} {{Wiki|elite}} whose [[altruism]] is so strong, and whose [[understanding]] and {{Wiki|status}} is so ennobled, that they engage in what ordinarily would be condemned as gross immorality. According to this code, it is an [[ethical]] lapse not to eat meat, perhaps even [[human]] flesh, the [[logic]] being that in certain specific and unusual circumstances, in a [[person]] at this stage of [[development]], such {{Wiki|behavior}} would constitute a [[skillful means]] to [[benefit]] others.
+
to the top of the head) and [[caṇḍalī]] (an intense [[pleasure]] [[experienced]] as heat that spreads through the [[channels]] and fills the [[body]]).  
6. [[Tantra]]
 
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] does not have a different [[tantric]] [[philosophy]]. His [[Prāsaṅgika]] [[Middle Way]] is the [[philosophical]] position he articulates in his works on [[tantra]]. He does however, unlike in his non-tantric works, accept that those propounding Idealistic [[philosophies]] ([[Yogācāra]], [[Svātantrika]] [[Middle Way]]) can have [[success]] in their practice. In this he reveals again the importance of the central [[Tibetan]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]] going back to [[Śāntarakṣita]].
+
[[Tsongkhapa]] is praised, in particular, for his explanation of {{Wiki|theory}} and praxis associated with the [[illusory body]] (Sk. [[māyā-kāya]], Tib. [[sgyu lus]]) and [[clear light]] (Sk. [[prabhāsvara]], Tib. [['od gsal]]), a [[skillful]] [[adaptation]] of his [[understanding]] of the [[two truths]] to [[yogic]] praxis.  
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] conceives of [[tantra]] as a subset of the [[Mahāyāna]], and to that extent all [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[Buddhist tantric]] [[activities]] are, necessarily, authentically {{Wiki|altruistic}}. What differentiates [[tantric]] [[activity]] from other ordinary [[Mahāyāna]] [[activities]] is [[deity yoga]] (Tib. [[lha'i rnal 'byor]]), i.e., whether or not, from a first [[person]] {{Wiki|perspective}}, the [[person]] is acting as a {{Wiki|perfect}}, “[[divine]][[subject]] when engaging in (primarily [[ritual]]) {{Wiki|behavior}}.
+
This is summed up nicely in the statement, “The [[Pañcakramasaṃgrahaprakāśa]] ([[Illumination of the Summary of the Five Steps]]), a short treatise attributed to [[Nāropa]] (956–1040), [[combining]] the Six Teachings with the ‘[[Five Steps]]([[pañcakrama]]) of the [[Ārya tradition]] provided [[Tsong kha pa]] with the basic [[ideas]] of his [[Tantric]] system” ([[Tillemans]] 1998).
  
[[Tsongkhapa]] wrote works on the [[Vajrabhairava]], [[Cakrasaṃvara]], and [[Kālacakra]] [[tantras]], but is best known for his [[exposition]] of the [[Guhyasamāja tantra]] based on [[Indian]] commentaries associated with the names of [[Nāgārjuna]] and [[Āryadeva]], particularly his short but influential Commentary on the [[Jñāna-vajra-samuccaya]] ([[Ye shes rdo rje kun las ‘dus pa'i ṭī kā]]) (1410), and magisterial Clear [[Exposition]] of the [[Five Stages]] of [[Guhyasamāja]] ([[gSang ‘dus rim lnga gsal sgron]]) (1411). He accords great importance to [[esoteric]] [[yoga]]. In this [[respect]], his work is firmly located in the {{Wiki|mainstream}} [[Tibetan tradition]], influenced in particular by the [[translator]] [[Mar pa]] ([[Mar pa Chos kyi blo gros]]) (1012–1097), who spread the Six Teachings of [[Nāropa]] (Nā ro [[chos drug]]), a later [[Indian]] {{Wiki|synthesis}} of diverse [[tantric practices]], in [[Tibet]]. Based on this [[Tsongkhapa]] gives detailed explanations of the [[nāḍī]] (channels for the [[energy]] or [[feelings]] that run through the [[tantric]] practitioner's [[body]]), [[cakra]] (circles of channels in the [[heart]], {{Wiki|throat}}, and other central points up the center of the [[body]] from the bottom of the spine, or tip of the {{Wiki|sex}} {{Wiki|organ}}, to the top of the head) and caṇḍalī (an intense [[pleasure]] [[experienced]] as heat that spreads through the channels and fills the [[body]]). [[Tsongkhapa]] is praised, in particular, for his explanation of {{Wiki|theory}} and praxis associated with the [[illusory body]] (Sk. [[māyā-kāya]], Tib. [[sgyu lus]]) and [[clear light]] (Sk. [[prabhāsvara]], Tib. [['od gsal]]), a [[skillful]] [[adaptation]] of his [[understanding]] of the [[two truths]] to [[yogic]] praxis. This is summed up nicely in the statement, “The [[Pañcakramasaṃgrahaprakāśa]] ([[Illumination]] of the Summary of the Five Steps), a short treatise attributed to [[Nāropa]] (956–1040), combining the Six Teachings with the ‘Five Steps’ ([[pañcakrama]]) of the [[Ārya tradition]] provided [[Tsong kha pa]] with the basic [[ideas]] of his [[Tantric]] system” ([[Tillemans]] 1998).
+
 
Bibliography
+
[[Bibliography]]
 +
 
 +
<poem>
 
Primary Works
 
Primary Works
  
     Three sets of Collected Works of [[Tsongkhapa]] (“the [[Kumbum]] Jampaling, [[Tashilhunpo]] Parnying, and [[Lhasa]] [[Sho]] printery editions”), [[Tibetan Buddhist]] Resource Center.
+
     Three sets of Collected Works of [[Tsongkhapa]] (“the [[Kumbum]] [[Jampaling]], [[Tashilhunpo]] Parnying, and [[Lhasa]] [[Sho]] printery editions”), [[Tibetan Buddhist]] Resource [[Center]].
     In Praise of [[Dependent Origination]] ([[Brten 'brel bstod pa]] trans. by Tupten [[Jinpa]] [Available online (pdf)].
+
 
 +
     In [[Praise]] of [[Dependent Origination]] ([[Brten 'brel bstod pa]] trans. by Tupten [[Jinpa]] [Available online (pdf)].
  
 
Secondary Works
 
Secondary Works
  
 
     Anonymous, 1890. “The {{Wiki|Literature}} of [[Tibet]].” Edinburgh Review, 126–134.
 
     Anonymous, 1890. “The {{Wiki|Literature}} of [[Tibet]].” Edinburgh Review, 126–134.
     [[Cabezon]], Jose Ignacio, 1994. A Dose of [[Emptiness]]: An Annotated Translation of the [[sTong thun chen mo]] of [[mKhas grub]] [[dGe legs dpal bzang]]. Albany: {{Wiki|State University of New York Press}}.
+
     [[Cabezon]], Jose Ignacio, 1994. A Dose of [[Emptiness]]: An Annotated Translation of the [[sTong thun chen mo]] of [[mKhas grub]] [[dGe legs dpal bzang]]. [[Albany]]: {{Wiki|State University of New York Press}}.
 +
 
 
     Das, S.C., 1970. “[[Life]] and [[Legend of Tsoṅ Khapa]] ([[Lo-ssaṅ-tagpa]]), The Great [[Buddhist]] Reformer of [[Tibet]].” Journal of the [[Asiatic Society of Bengal]], Vol. LI (vi), 1882. Reprinted in Contributions on the [[Religion]] and [[History of Tibet]]. {{Wiki|New Delhi}}: [[Mañjuśrī]] Publishing House.
 
     Das, S.C., 1970. “[[Life]] and [[Legend of Tsoṅ Khapa]] ([[Lo-ssaṅ-tagpa]]), The Great [[Buddhist]] Reformer of [[Tibet]].” Journal of the [[Asiatic Society of Bengal]], Vol. LI (vi), 1882. Reprinted in Contributions on the [[Religion]] and [[History of Tibet]]. {{Wiki|New Delhi}}: [[Mañjuśrī]] Publishing House.
     Dreyfus, Georges, 1997. [[Recognizing]] [[Reality]]: [[Dharmakīrti's]] [[Philosophy]] and its [[Tibetan]] Interpretations. Albany: {{Wiki|State University of New York Press}}.
+
 
 +
     Dreyfus, Georges, 1997. [[Recognizing]] [[Reality]]: [[Dharmakīrti's]] [[Philosophy]] and its [[Tibetan]] Interpretations. [[Albany]]: {{Wiki|State University of New York Press}}.
 +
 
 
     Garfield, Jay L., and [[Geshe Ngawang Samten]], 2006a. [[Ocean of Reasoning]]. {{Wiki|Oxford}}: [[Oxford University Press]].
 
     Garfield, Jay L., and [[Geshe Ngawang Samten]], 2006a. [[Ocean of Reasoning]]. {{Wiki|Oxford}}: [[Oxford University Press]].
     –––, 2006b. “The [[Conventional]] {{Wiki|Status}} of Reflexive [[Awareness]]: What's at Stake in a [[Tibetan]] [[Debate]]?” [[Philosophy]] [[East]] and [[West]], 56(2), 201–228.
+
     –––, 2006b. “The [[Conventional]] {{Wiki|Status}} of Reflexive [[Awareness]]: What's at [[Stake]] in a [[Tibetan]] [[Debate]]?” [[Philosophy]] [[East]] and [[West]], 56(2), 201–228.
 +
 
 
     Hopkins, Jeffrey, 1980. [[Tantra]] in [[Tibet]]: The [[Great Exposition]] of Secret Mantra–Volume 1. {{Wiki|London}}: Allen and Unwin, pp. 83–169.
 
     Hopkins, Jeffrey, 1980. [[Tantra]] in [[Tibet]]: The [[Great Exposition]] of Secret Mantra–Volume 1. {{Wiki|London}}: Allen and Unwin, pp. 83–169.
 
     –––, 1999. [[Emptiness]] in the [[Mind-Only School]] of [[Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|Berkeley}}, CA.: {{Wiki|University of California Press}}.
 
     –––, 1999. [[Emptiness]] in the [[Mind-Only School]] of [[Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|Berkeley}}, CA.: {{Wiki|University of California Press}}.
 +
 
     –––, 2002. Reflections on [[Reality]]: The [[Three Natures]] and Non-Natures in the [[Mind-Only School]]: Dynamic Responses to [[Dzong-ka-ba's]] The [[Essence of Eloquence]]. {{Wiki|London}}: {{Wiki|University of California Press}}.
 
     –––, 2002. Reflections on [[Reality]]: The [[Three Natures]] and Non-Natures in the [[Mind-Only School]]: Dynamic Responses to [[Dzong-ka-ba's]] The [[Essence of Eloquence]]. {{Wiki|London}}: {{Wiki|University of California Press}}.
     –––, 2006a. [[Absorption]] in No [[External World]]: 170 Issues in [[Mind Only]] [[Buddhism]] (Dynamic Responses to [[Dzong-ka-ba's]] The [[Essence of Eloquence]]). Ithaca, N.Y.: [[Snow Lion Publications]].
+
 
     –––, 2008. [[Tsong-kha-pa's]] [[Final Exposition of Wisdom]]. Ithaca, N.Y.: [[Snow Lion Publications]].
+
     –––, 2006a. [[Absorption]] in No [[External World]]: 170 Issues in [[Mind Only]] [[Buddhism]] (Dynamic Responses to [[Dzong-ka-ba's]] The [[Essence of Eloquence]]). [[Ithaca]], N.Y.: [[Snow Lion Publications]].
 +
 
 +
     –––, 2008. [[Tsong-kha-pa's]] [[Final Exposition of Wisdom]]. [[Ithaca]], N.Y.: [[Snow Lion Publications]].
 
     [[Jinpa, Thupten]], 2002. [[Self]], [[Reality]], and [[Reason]] in [[Tibetan Philosophy]]. {{Wiki|London}}: RoutledgeCurzon.
 
     [[Jinpa, Thupten]], 2002. [[Self]], [[Reality]], and [[Reason]] in [[Tibetan Philosophy]]. {{Wiki|London}}: RoutledgeCurzon.
 +
 
     Kay, David, 2004. [[Tibetan]] and [[Zen Buddhism]] in {{Wiki|Britain}}. {{Wiki|London}}: RoutledgeCurzon.
 
     Kay, David, 2004. [[Tibetan]] and [[Zen Buddhism]] in {{Wiki|Britain}}. {{Wiki|London}}: RoutledgeCurzon.
     [[Lamrim Chenmo]] Translation Committee, Joshua W.C. Cutler (ed.), 2000–2004. The [[Great Treatise]] on the States of the [[Path]] to [[Enlightenment]]. Vols. 1–3. Ithaca, N.Y.: [[Snow Lion Publications]].
+
     [[Lamrim Chenmo]] Translation Committee, Joshua W.C. Cutler (ed.), 2000–2004. The [[Great Treatise]] on the States of the [[Path]] to [[Enlightenment]]. Vols. 1–3. [[Ithaca]], N.Y.: [[Snow Lion Publications]].
 +
 
 
     [[Matsumoto]], S., 1948. “The [[Mādhyamika]] [[philosophy]] of [[Tsong-kha-pa]].” In Memoirs of the Research Department of the [[Toyo Bunko]], 48, 17–47.
 
     [[Matsumoto]], S., 1948. “The [[Mādhyamika]] [[philosophy]] of [[Tsong-kha-pa]].” In Memoirs of the Research Department of the [[Toyo Bunko]], 48, 17–47.
 
     {{Wiki|Monier-Williams}}, M., 1888. [[Buddhism]] (Duff Lectures, {{Wiki|University of Edinburgh}}), [[Varanasi]]: Chowkhamba [[Sanskrit]] Series Office, 1964, second edition.
 
     {{Wiki|Monier-Williams}}, M., 1888. [[Buddhism]] (Duff Lectures, {{Wiki|University of Edinburgh}}), [[Varanasi]]: Chowkhamba [[Sanskrit]] Series Office, 1964, second edition.
     Napper, Elizabeth, 1989. Dependent-Arising and [[Emptiness]]. [[Boston]]: [[Wisdom Publications]].
+
 
     Ruegg, David Seyfort, 2000. “On Epistemological-Logical ([[pramāṇa]]) {{Wiki|Theory}} and the Ontic in [[Tsoṅ kha pa's]] [[Madhyamaka Philosophy]].” [[Three Studies]] in the History of [[Indian]] and [[Tibetan Madhyamaka]] [[Philosophy]]. Wiener Studien zur Tibetologie und Buddhismuskund 50. Wien: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien.
+
     Napper, [[Elizabeth]], 1989. Dependent-Arising and [[Emptiness]]. [[Boston]]: [[Wisdom Publications]].
     –––, 2002. Two {{Wiki|Prolegomena}} to [[Madhyamaka Philosophy]]: [[Chadrakīrti's]] [[Prasannapadā Madhyamakavṛtti]] on [[Madhyamakakārikā]], I.1 and [[Tsoṅ kha pa blo bzaṅ grags pa/rGyal tshab dar ma rin chen's dka‘ gnad brgyad kyi zin bris]]. Wien: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien.
+
     Ruegg, David Seyfort, 2000. “On Epistemological-Logical ([[pramāṇa]]) {{Wiki|Theory}} and the Ontic in [[Tsoṅ kha pa's]] [[Madhyamaka Philosophy]].” [[Three Studies]] in the History of [[Indian]] and [[Tibetan Madhyamaka]] [[Philosophy]]. Wiener Studien zur Tibetologie und Buddhismuskund 50. [[Wien]]: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien.
 +
 
 +
     –––, 2002. Two {{Wiki|Prolegomena}} to [[Madhyamaka Philosophy]]: [[Chadrakīrti's]] [[Prasannapadā Madhyamakavṛtti]] on [[Madhyamakakārikā]], I.1 and [[Tsoṅ kha pa blo bzaṅ grags pa/rGyal tshab dar ma rin chen's dka‘ gnad brgyad kyi zin bris]]. [[Wien]]: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien.
 +
 
 
     –––, 2004. “[[Indian]] and the [[Indic]] in [[Tibetan]] {{Wiki|Cultural}} History and [[Tsoṅ Kha Pa's]] [[Achievement]] as a [[Scholar]] and Thinker: An Essay on the Concepts of [[Buddhism in Tibet]] and [[Tibetan Buddhism]].“ [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]], 2004, 32.4, 321–343.
 
     –––, 2004. “[[Indian]] and the [[Indic]] in [[Tibetan]] {{Wiki|Cultural}} History and [[Tsoṅ Kha Pa's]] [[Achievement]] as a [[Scholar]] and Thinker: An Essay on the Concepts of [[Buddhism in Tibet]] and [[Tibetan Buddhism]].“ [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]], 2004, 32.4, 321–343.
     [[Sparham]], Gareth, 1993. Ocean of [[Eloquence]]. Albany: {{Wiki|State University of New York Press}}.
+
 
 +
     [[Sparham]], Gareth, 1993. Ocean of [[Eloquence]]. [[Albany]]: {{Wiki|State University of New York Press}}.
 
     –––, 2005. [[Tantric Ethics]]. Somerville MA: [[Wisdom Publications]].
 
     –––, 2005. [[Tantric Ethics]]. Somerville MA: [[Wisdom Publications]].
 +
 
     –––, 2007 [[Golden Garland]] of Eloquence—Vol. 1–3 by [[Tsong kha pa]].
English Translation by {{Wiki|Gareth Sparham}} (2007–2009). Fremont, CA: [[Jain]] Publishing.
 
     –––, 2007 [[Golden Garland]] of Eloquence—Vol. 1–3 by [[Tsong kha pa]].
English Translation by {{Wiki|Gareth Sparham}} (2007–2009). Fremont, CA: [[Jain]] Publishing.
 
     [[Tatz, Mark]], 1986. [[Asaṅga's]] [[Chapter]] on [[Ethics]], With the Commentary of [[Tsong-Kha-pa]], the Basic [[Path]] to [[Awakening]], the Complete [[Bodhisattva]]. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press.
 
     [[Tatz, Mark]], 1986. [[Asaṅga's]] [[Chapter]] on [[Ethics]], With the Commentary of [[Tsong-Kha-pa]], the Basic [[Path]] to [[Awakening]], the Complete [[Bodhisattva]]. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press.
 +
 
     –––, 1990. “Who is [[Tsong-kha-pa]] Refuting in His Basic [[Path]] to [[Awakening]]?” In Lawrence Epstein and Richard F. Sherburne (Eds.), Reflections on [[Tibetan]] Culture––Essays in [[Memory]] of Turrell V. [[Wylie]]. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press, 149–163.
 
     –––, 1990. “Who is [[Tsong-kha-pa]] Refuting in His Basic [[Path]] to [[Awakening]]?” In Lawrence Epstein and Richard F. Sherburne (Eds.), Reflections on [[Tibetan]] Culture––Essays in [[Memory]] of Turrell V. [[Wylie]]. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press, 149–163.
     [[Tauscher]], H., 1995. [[Die]] Lehre von den zwei Wirklichkeiten in [[Tsoṅ kha pas]] Madhyamaka-Werken. Wien: Wiener Studien zur Tibetologie und Buddhismuskund 50. Wien: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien Universität Wien.
+
 
     [[Thurman, Robert]] A.F., 1984. [[Tsong Khapa's]] [[Speech of Gold in the Essence of True Eloquence]]. Princeton: {{Wiki|Princeton University Press}}.
+
     [[Tauscher]], H., 1995. [[Die]] Lehre von den zwei Wirklichkeiten in [[Tsoṅ kha pas]] [[Madhyamaka]]-Werken. [[Wien]]: Wiener Studien zur Tibetologie und Buddhismuskund 50. [[Wien]]: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien Universität [[Wien]].
 +
 
 +
     [[Thurman, Robert]] A.F., 1984. [[Tsong Khapa's]] [[Speech of Gold in the Essence of True Eloquence]]. [[Princeton]]: {{Wiki|Princeton University Press}}.
 
     [[Tillemans]], T., 1992. “[[Tsong kha pa]] et al. on the Bhavaviveka-Candrakrti [[Debate]].” In Shoren Ihara and ZuihoYamaguchi (Eds.), [[Tibetan Studies]]. Narita: [[Naritasan Shinshoji]], vol. 1, 316–26.
 
     [[Tillemans]], T., 1992. “[[Tsong kha pa]] et al. on the Bhavaviveka-Candrakrti [[Debate]].” In Shoren Ihara and ZuihoYamaguchi (Eds.), [[Tibetan Studies]]. Narita: [[Naritasan Shinshoji]], vol. 1, 316–26.
 +
 
     –––, 1998. “[[Tsong kha pa blo bzang grags pa]].” In Routledge {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Philosophy]]. Edited by E. Craig, 487–490. {{Wiki|London}}: Routledge Co.
 
     –––, 1998. “[[Tsong kha pa blo bzang grags pa]].” In Routledge {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Philosophy]]. Edited by E. Craig, 487–490. {{Wiki|London}}: Routledge Co.
 +
 
     [[van der Kuijp]], Leonard W.J., 1985. “Apropos of a Recent Contribution to the History of the Central Way [[Philosophy]] in [[Tibet]]: [[Tsong-kha-pa's]] {{Wiki|Speech}} of {{Wiki|Gold}}. Berliner Indologische Studien 1, 47–74.
 
     [[van der Kuijp]], Leonard W.J., 1985. “Apropos of a Recent Contribution to the History of the Central Way [[Philosophy]] in [[Tibet]]: [[Tsong-kha-pa's]] {{Wiki|Speech}} of {{Wiki|Gold}}. Berliner Indologische Studien 1, 47–74.
 +
 
     Vose, Kevin, 2009. Resurrecting [[Candrakirti]]: [[Disputes]] in the [[Tibetan]] Creation of [[Prasangika]]. Studies in [[Indian]] and [[Tibetan Buddhism]]. Somerville MA: [[Wisdom Publications]].
 
     Vose, Kevin, 2009. Resurrecting [[Candrakirti]]: [[Disputes]] in the [[Tibetan]] Creation of [[Prasangika]]. Studies in [[Indian]] and [[Tibetan Buddhism]]. Somerville MA: [[Wisdom Publications]].
 +
 
     [[Williams]], Paul, 1983. “A note on some aspects of Mi bskyod rdo rje's critique of [[dGe lugs pa]] [[Madhyamaka]].” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 11, 125–45.
 
     [[Williams]], Paul, 1983. “A note on some aspects of Mi bskyod rdo rje's critique of [[dGe lugs pa]] [[Madhyamaka]].” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 11, 125–45.
 
     –––, 1998a. The Reflexive [[Nature]] of [[Awareness]]: A [[Tibetan Madhyamaka]] Defense. Richmond, UK: Curzon.
 
     –––, 1998a. The Reflexive [[Nature]] of [[Awareness]]: A [[Tibetan Madhyamaka]] Defense. Richmond, UK: Curzon.
 
     –––, 1998b. [[Altruism]] and [[Reality]]. Richmond, UK: Curzon.
 
     –––, 1998b. [[Altruism]] and [[Reality]]. Richmond, UK: Curzon.
     [[Yoshimizu]], C., 1989. Descriptive Catalogue of the Naritasan Institute Collection of [[Tibetan]] Works, vol. 1, Narita: [[Naritasan shinshoji]].
+
 
 +
     [[Yoshimizu]], C., 1989. Descriptive Catalogue of the [[Naritasan]] Institute Collection of [[Tibetan]] Works, vol. 1, Narita: [[Naritasan shinshoji]].
 
     Yotsuya, [[Kodo]], 1999. The Critique of [[Svatantra]] {{Wiki|Reasoning}} by [[Candrakirti]] and [[Tsong-kha-pa]]. Franz Steiner Verlag.
 
     Yotsuya, [[Kodo]], 1999. The Critique of [[Svatantra]] {{Wiki|Reasoning}} by [[Candrakirti]] and [[Tsong-kha-pa]]. Franz Steiner Verlag.
  
Line 225: Line 691:
 
     sep man icon How to cite this entry.
 
     sep man icon How to cite this entry.
 
     sep man icon Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP [[Society]].
 
     sep man icon Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP [[Society]].
     inpho icon Look up this entry topic at the Indiana [[Philosophy]] {{Wiki|Ontology}} Project (InPhO).
+
     inpho icon Look up this entry topic at the [[Indiana]] [[Philosophy]] {{Wiki|Ontology}} Project (InPhO).
     phil papers icon Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
+
     phil papers icon Enhanced [[bibliography]] for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
  
Other Internet Resources
+
Other [[Internet]] Resources
 +
 
 +
    [[Tibetan Buddhist]] Resource [[Center]]. A repository of digitally preserved works in [[Tibetan]], [[including]] a number or editions of [[Tsongkhapa's]] collected works.
  
    [[Tibetan Buddhist]] Resource Center. A repository of digitally preserved works in [[Tibetan]], including a number or editions of [[Tsongkhapa's]] collected works.
 
 
     [[Tibetan]] and [[Himalayan]] Library, {{Wiki|University of Virginia}}. A hub resource for [[Tibetan studies]] in [[universities]] worldwide.
 
     [[Tibetan]] and [[Himalayan]] Library, {{Wiki|University of Virginia}}. A hub resource for [[Tibetan studies]] in [[universities]] worldwide.
 
     {{Wiki|Asian}} Classics Input Project. The ACE tool allows readers to browse and search a number of [[Tsongkhapa's]] texts.
 
     {{Wiki|Asian}} Classics Input Project. The ACE tool allows readers to browse and search a number of [[Tsongkhapa's]] texts.
 +
 
     The [[Tibet]] Album, Collections of photographs of [[Tibet]] ({{Wiki|British}} photography in {{Wiki|Central Tibet}} 1920-1950). {{Wiki|Excellent}} record of pre-1959 [[dGe lugs]] [[monasteries]] and other {{Wiki|institutions}} influenced by [[Tsongkhapa]]..
 
     The [[Tibet]] Album, Collections of photographs of [[Tibet]] ({{Wiki|British}} photography in {{Wiki|Central Tibet}} 1920-1950). {{Wiki|Excellent}} record of pre-1959 [[dGe lugs]] [[monasteries]] and other {{Wiki|institutions}} influenced by [[Tsongkhapa]]..
 +
 
     UMA Institute for [[Tibetan Studies]]. UMA = Union of the {{Wiki|Modern}} and the [[Ancient]] Institute for [[Tibetan Studies]]. Contains audio-files of explanations of works of [[Tsongkhapa]] by [[traditional]] [[Tibetan]] [[teachers]], translated by [[Jeffrey Hopkins]].
 
     UMA Institute for [[Tibetan Studies]]. UMA = Union of the {{Wiki|Modern}} and the [[Ancient]] Institute for [[Tibetan Studies]]. Contains audio-files of explanations of works of [[Tsongkhapa]] by [[traditional]] [[Tibetan]] [[teachers]], translated by [[Jeffrey Hopkins]].
 +
 
     The [[Berzin]] Archives. The [[Buddhist]] Archives of Dr. [[Alexander Berzin]]. A non-academic, but sometimes informative site for [[dGe lugs pa]] explanations of [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[ideas]] maintained by [[Alexander Berzin]]
 
     The [[Berzin]] Archives. The [[Buddhist]] Archives of Dr. [[Alexander Berzin]]. A non-academic, but sometimes informative site for [[dGe lugs pa]] explanations of [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[ideas]] maintained by [[Alexander Berzin]]
  
 
Related Entries
 
Related Entries
  
[[Gelukpa]] [[[dge lugs pa]]] | [[Nāgārjuna]] | [[Śāntarakṣita]] | [[Tibetan]] epistemology and [[philosophy]] of [[language]] | [[Tibetan]] {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} | [[two truths]] in [[Tibet]], {{Wiki|theory}} of
+
[[Gelukpa]] [[dge lugs pa]] | [[Nāgārjuna]] | [[Śāntarakṣita]] | [[Tibetan]] epistemology and [[philosophy]] of [[language]] | [[Tibetan]] {{Wiki|hermeneutics}} | [[two truths]] in [[Tibet]], {{Wiki|theory}} of
  
  
 
{{Wiki|Gareth Sparham}} <gsparham@umich.edu>
 
{{Wiki|Gareth Sparham}} <gsparham@umich.edu>
</poem>
+
 
 
{{R}}
 
{{R}}
 
[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tsongkhapa/]
 
[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tsongkhapa/]
 
[[Category:Je Tsongkhapa]]
 
[[Category:Je Tsongkhapa]]

Latest revision as of 09:09, 29 March 2016

Guru b.jpg
BeoD7vghjk.jpg
Nagarjuna tibet.jpg
Story 819b.jpg
AAA444dala-alus.jpg
Temfdple.gif
Ksitigarbha-es50.jpg
Bcbb1O.jpg
1958fghjyuo.jpg
18Pawo Rinpoche.jpg
10cfD.JPG
Mboo H.jpeg
218 arcchool.jpg
Yogi.jpg
Yogset.jpg
025b3b.jpg
3117120729.jpg
Guru-a11E.jpg
MYpyay02.jpg
17686 n.jpg
23.jpg
BfkiG.JPG
Guru Rinpoc.jpg
Tushita heaven.jpg
Mo 4bc9.jpg




Tsongkhapa (1357–1419) is a well-known Tibetan religious philosopher.

In his iconic form, wearing a tall yellow hat, he is the center of the Gelugpa (Tib. dge lugs pa) sect that ruled Tibet until the Chinese takeover in 1951, and whose de facto leader is the Dalai Lama. [

Tsongkhapa has been the subject of poor, misleading scholarship — particularly in the 19th century when so-called “Orientalistscholars (e.g., Monier-Williams,

1888: 268, 277) falsely imagined him as a “reformer” who founded, or rediscovered, the rational and ethical school of original Buddhism.

The historical Tsongkhapa flourished in the period immediately following the final redaction of the Buddhist canon in Tibetan translation (Tib. bKa' 'gyur, pronounced Kanjur).

He presents a Middle Way (Sk. madhyamaka, Tib. dbu ma pa) philosophy, based on the works of the Indian philosopher Nāgārjuna (third-fourth century),

and strongly influenced by the Indo-Tibetan Buddhist logico-epistemological tradition (Sk. pramāṇa, Tib. tshad ma) founded by the Indian epistemologists Dignāga and Dharmakīrti (fifth to seventh century).

In it he strikes a balance between knowledge and praxis.

He unerringly characterizes all statements about ultimate truths (Sk. paramārtha-satya) framed in positive terms as false, but develops a hermeneutics to retain the authority of correct moral statements on a covering (Sk. saṃvṛti) or conventional (Sk. vyavahāra) level.


His most influential writing reconciles the philosophy of emptiness (Sk. śūnyatā) with the imperative of praxis embodied in a universal altruistic principle (Sk. bodhicitta).

He gives pride of place to apparently antinomian tantric praxis without devaluing the centrality of ordinary moral life, and develops a distinctive analysis of dependent origination (Sk. pratītya-samutpāda).


1.1 Overview


Biographical information about Tsongkhapa comes from clues in his own writing, and from the hagiography written by his student Kedrup Pelzangpo (mKhas grub dpal bzang po) (1385–1438) called Stream of Faith (Dad pa'i 'jug ngog) (partial translation in Thurman 1982).[1]

Tsongkhapa's life falls roughly into an earlier and later period.

The later period is defined by a series of publications, beginning in about 1400, which systematically present his mature philosophy.

Tsongkhapa, influenced by the divisions used by the editors of the Kanjur, treats non-tantric and tantric sources separately.

His philosophical views on tantra, and, to a certain extent his work on ethics fall naturally into separate categories.

The later period of his life includes a period of institution building, possibly with an eye to the founding of a new school or sect.


The name Tsongkhapa derives from Tsong kha, an ancient name for a part of the A mdo region of Greater Tibet (Bod chen) now included in Qinghai Province of the People's Republic of China, and the Tibetan suffix pa that works as an agentive nominalizing particle.

His given name is Losang (sometimes written Lozang Drakpa (bLo bzang grags pa).

He is also known by the honorific title Je Rinpoche (rJe rin po che) (“Precious Lord”).

He was born, probably to semi-nomadic farmers, in a settlement now incorporated into the outskirts of the Chinese city of Xi ning.

His birthplace is marked by the popular Kumbum (sKu 'bum) monastery,


In his teens (1372–73), Tsongkhapa travelled from Tsong kha to Central (dBus) Tibet (Bod) where he remained until his death in 1419.

He arrived as a young man in Central Tibet at the end of a long flowering of intellectual activity

called “the later diffusion of Buddhism” (Tib. spyi dar) that began with translator Rin chen bzang po (958–1055) and the scholar-saint Dīpaṃkāra-śrījñāna Atiśa (980–1054), and ended with the most important editor of the Kanjur, Butōn (Bu ston Rin chen grub, 1290–1364).


According to Kedrup, on his arrival in Central Tibet Tsongkhapa first studied Tibetan medicine, then a traditional Buddhist curriculum of abhidharma, tenet systems (Tib. grub mtha') focusing on the Middle Way and Mind Only (Sk. cittamātra

also called yogācāra) philosophy, Buddhist ethics (Tib. sdom gsum), and epistemology (Sk. pramāṇa).

His early studies were pursued mainly in institutions affiliated with the two dominant scholarly traditions (Tib. lugs) of the time:

the Sangphu tradition (gSang phu ne'u tog) founded by Ngok (rNgog bLo ldan shes rab) (1059–1109), and the Sakya (Sa skya) epistemological tradition based primarily on the works of the Sa skya paṇḍi ta (1182–1251).

He also studied and practiced tantric Buddhism.

In his early years he wrote a number of essays on topics in abhidharma (Apple 2008), a detailed investigation of the ālaya-vijñāna (Sk.) (“foundation, storehouse, basis-of all consciousness”) (Sparham 1993), and an important treatise, Golden Garland (Legs bshad gser phreng), on the Perfection of Wisdom (Sk. prajñā-pāramitā) literature based on the codification of its topics in the Ornament for the Chapters (Abhisamayālaṃkāra) (Sparham 2008–2010).

After completing his Golden Garland in 1388–89, Tsongkhapa spent a period of some ten years removed from the hub of intellectual activity.

He engaged in meditation and ritual religious exercises in Southern Tibet (Lho kha) where, as evidenced in his short autobiographical writing from this transitional period (Thurman 1982), and corroborated by traditional sources (Kaschewsky 1971, Vostrikov 1970), he resorted to a communion or dialogue with Mañjuśrī––the iconographic representation of perfect knowledge in the Buddhist pantheon.

Through the voice of Mañjuśrī he articulated a hierarchical system of philosophies culminating in what he characterized as a pristine, Middle Way, *Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka (Tib. dBu ma thal 'gyur pa) that avoided over-reification (of the absolute) and over-negation (of the conventional).

Tsongkhapa framed his insights not as original contributions, but as a rediscovery of meanings already revealed by the Buddha.

In all his works he characterizes his philosophy as identical to the Buddha's.

Further, he says his philosophy is based on Nāgārjuna's and Nāgārjuna's follower Ārya-deva's (third-fourth century) explanation of what the Buddha said.

His philosophy gets its name Prāsaṅgika (“those who reveal the unwelcome consequences inherent in other's assertions”) from the importance it gives to Buddhapalita's (late fifth century) explication of Nāgārjuna's work, and to Candrakīrti's (mid-sixth to mid-seventh century) defense of Buddhapalita's explanation, in the face of criticism by Bhavaviveka (sixth century).

Tsongkhapa presented his mature philosophy in a series of volumes during the later period of his life, beginning with the publication of his most famous work, the Great Exposition of the Stages of the Path (Lam rim chen mo) in 1402, at the age of 46.

This was followed by Essence of Eloquence (Legs bshad snying po) and Ocean of Reasoning (Rigs pa'i rgya mtsho) (1407–1408), the Medium-Length Exposition of the Stages of the Path (Lam rim 'bring) in 1415, and, in the last years of his life, his Elucidation of the Intention (dGongs pa rab gsal).

Together, in this series of works written over a seventeen year period, he succeeded in setting the agenda for the following centuries, to a great extent, with later writers taking positions pro and con his arguments.

As is so often the case, his stature pushed much of earlier Tibetan intellectual history into the shadows, until its rediscovery by the Eclectic Movement (Tib. Ris med) in Derge (sDe dge) in the late 18th century.


Tsongkhapa wrote his major works on tantra and ethics at the same time as his major philosophical works. Volumes 3–12 of his collected works in 18 or 19 volumes deal exclusively with topics based on tantric sources.

In 1405 he completed his Great Exposition of Tantra (sNgags rim chen mo), a companion volume to his Great Exposition, where, in harmony with his philosophy, he argued that tantra is defined neither by special insight (Sk. vipaśyana) or Mahāyāna altruism (Sk. bodhicitta), but solely by deity yoga (Tib. lha'i rnal 'byor) (Hopkins 1980).


In 1402, Tsongkhapa, with his teacher Rendawa (Red mda' ba gzhon nu blo gros, 1349–1412) and others, at the temple of Namstedeng (rNam rtsed ldeng/lding) convened a gathering of monks with the intention of reinvigorating the Buddhist order.

From this came Tsongkhapa's short, but influential works on basic Buddhist morality (Sk. prātimokṣa) that in turn laid the foundation for the importance some Gelukpa monasteries would place on a stricter adherence to the monastic code.

In 1403 his influential works on ethical codes for bodhisattvas (Byang chub gzhung lam) (Tatz 1987) and for tantric practitioners (rTsa ltung rnam bshad) (Sparham 2005) appeared.

His separate explanations of the three ethical codes (Tib. sdom gsum) are distinguished by the centrality they give to basic morality, the importance the bodhisattva's code retains in tantra, and,

in the antinomian tantras, the presence of a separate, prātimokṣa-like ordination ritual and a common code of ethical conduct.


By 1409, at the age of 52, his place in Tibetan society was sufficiently established that he could garner the support and sponsorship necessary for a successful rejuvenation of the central temple in Lhasa,

for establishing a new-year prayer festival (smon lam chen mo), and for completion of a large new monastery, Ganden (dGa' ldan), where he lived for much of his subsequent life until his death there in 1419.

He inspired two of his students Tashi Palden (bKra shis dpal ldan) (1379–1449) and Shakya Yeshey (Ye shes) (1354–1435) to found Drepung ('Bras spungs) monastery in 1416, and Sera Monastery in 1419, respectively.

These, with Ganden, would later become the three largest and most powerful Gelukpa monasteries, and indeed, the biggest monasteries in the world.

In 1407 and 1413 the Ming dynasty Yongle Emperor recognized Tsongkhapa's growing fame and importance by inviting him to the Chinese court, as was the custom.


2. Early Period

2.1 Explanation of the Difficult Points (Kun gzhi dka' 'grel)

Tsongkhapa's most important works from his early period are his Explanation of the Difficult Points (Kun gzhi dka' 'grel) and Golden Garland (Legs bshad gser phreng).

In the former he gives a detailed explanation of the ālaya-vijñāna (“foundation consciousness”)––according to Tsongkhapa the distinctive eighth consciousness in the eight-consciousness system of Asaṅga's (fourth century) Indian Yogācāra Buddhism.


Tsongkhapa opens his work with a brief discussion of the relationship between the views of Nāgārjuna and Asaṅga.

Tsongkhapa then discovers in the different usages of the term ālaya-vijñāna and its near synonyms a negative connotation conveying the cause and effect nature of repeated suffering existences (Sk. saṃsāra).

He surveys the relevant literature, limiting his discussion of gotra (“lineage,” in the sense of the innate ability a person has to grow up into a fully enlightened being) to the presentation given in Asaṅga's Bodhisattva Levels (Bodhisattva-bhūmi).

There the “residual impression left by listening [to the correct exposition of the truth” (Sk. śruta-vāsanā) is the “seed” (Sk. bīja) that matures into enlightenment.

It is little more than the innate clarity of mind when it is freed from limitation by habituation to a correct vision of reality.

Tsongkhapa limits the sources for his explanation to non-tantric works, almost all by persons he will later describe as Indian Yogācāra writers,

demonstrating thereby the influence the categories used in the recently redacted Kanjur and Tenjur (Tib. bsTan 'gyur, the name for the commentaries in Tibetan translation included in the canon) had on his thinking.

When Tsongkhapa arrived in Central Tibet, the pressing philosophical issue of the day was Dolpopa's (Dol po pa Shes rab rgyal mtshan) (1292–1361) Great Middle Way (Tib. dBu ma chen po, Sk. *Mahā-madhayamaka) philosophy.


It propounded a hermeneutics based on the principle that a Buddha will always tell you clearly what he means. Based on a wide array of sources, and without making a clear distinction between tantric and non-tantric works, its central tenet is that an absolute, pure, transcendental mind endowed with all good qualities exists radically other than the ordinary world of appearance.

It is the archetypical Tibetan Buddhist gzhan stong (pronounced shentong, “emptiness of other”) philosophy.

Dolpopa, stressing the hermeneutic stated above, says Nāgārjuna and Asaṅga, writing during the golden age, have the same philosophy, the Great Middle Way clearly articulated by the Buddha.

Dolpopa distinguishes a pure, transcendental knowledge (Tib. kun gzhi ye shes) that is quite other than the defiled foundation consciousness (Tib. kun gzhi rnam shes), and equates the former with his single absolute, endowed with all the qualities of a Buddha.

Later, in his mature period, as explained below, Tsongkhapa will be explicit.

He will state categorically that Asaṅga's Yogācāra Buddhism is quite separate from, and in profundity inferior to, Nāgārjuna's Middle Way school, removing all references to a Great Middle Way school.

He will say the ālaya-vijñāna, devoid of subject-object bifurcation, provides the essential mind-stuff for defilement (=saṃsāra) and carries seeds for purification (=nirvāṇa) in a Yogācāra system that is fundamentally wrong, and at odds with the way things actually are.

He will give the ālaya-vijñāna only a heuristic value, and say a correct view (the *Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka view) of the workings of psycho-physical reality (the Buddhist skandhas) totally invalidates it.

As Jeffrey Hopkins (2002, 2006b) has shown conclusively, such statements constitute an explicit rejection of Dolpopa's view, a view Tsongkhapa is still formulating in early works like the Explanation of the Difficult Points.

In his Explanation of the Difficult Points, Tsongkhapa is certain he does not accept the view of Dolpopa, but he is still unsure exactly what he will put in its place.

He ignores Dolpopa's pure, transcendental knowledge called ālaya, mentioning it obliquely, only in passing, during a final brief survey of views based on Chinese sources;

he leaves unanswered the question of the final ontological status of the eighth consciousness; and he allows the views of Asaṅga set forth in the Bodhisattva-bhūmi to retain an authority he will later explicitly deny.



2.2 Golden Garland (Legs bshad gser phreng)

Tsongkhapa's Golden Garland is his most important early work.

It takes the form of a long explanation of the Perfection of Wisdom (Prajñā-pāramitā) sūtras, given pride of place in the Kanjur as the foremost words of the Buddha, after the Vinaya section (the codifications of ethical conduct).

It is a word-by-word commentary on the topics in the Ornament for the Chapters (Abhisamayālaṃkāra).

Tsongkhapa bases his explanation on two sub-commentaries by Ārya Vimuktiṣeṇa (sixth century?) and Hari Bhadra (end of the eighth century).

It propounds a philosophy that later Gelukpas, following the taxonomy developed in the mature works of Tsongkhapa himself, call Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka, in essence a Middle Way that incorporates many of the categories of Yogācāra Buddhism, yet does not have the authority of Candrakīrti's Prāsaṅgika interpretation.


A great deal has been written on the difference between Prāsaṅgika and Svātantrika (Dreyfus and McClintock 2003).

Historically, the Gelukpa's Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka is another name for the mainstream philosophical school that developed in Tibet, based primarily on the teaching of Śāntarakṣita and his student Kamalaśīla (both fl. end of the eight century), the two most important Indian paṇḍitas in the dissemination of Buddhist ideas to Tibet.

Later Gelukpa scholastics, basing themselves on the mature works of Tsongkhapa, are unequivocal that Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka, like the Yogācāra philosophy of Asaṅga, is wrong, and has only heuristic value.

At the same time, they tacitly acknowledge its centrality by taking this “wrong” philosophy as the foundation of their studies.


In the Golden Garland, Tsongkhapa, following Śāntarakṣita's school as it developed in Tibet, asserts that all bases (Sk. vastu) (the psycho-physical factors locating the person as they begin their philosophical career), all mental states along the course of the path (Sk. mārga), and the final result, are illusory, because they lack any essential nature.

But it is not yet clear how the basis relates to the final outcome (the result).

As explained below, Tsongkhapa will solve the problem in his mature works by a clear, radical, nihilistic leap denying any essential nature whatsoever, anywhere, to anything,

thereby implicitly and explicitly devaluing (in absolutist terms) the ontological status of the final, pure, unified state, relegating it to just one more conventional, dependently-originated thing.


In the Golden Garland, Tsongkhapa has not yet fully developed his mature, systematic philosophy.

He is still content with discrediting Dolpopa and surveying different points of view.

He uses Yogācāra terminology to present his own opinion, and uses a language to describe enlightened (and enlightening) knowledge that retains for it a separateness (through its freedom from all mental construction) from all other mental states.

The primary object of philosophical inquiry in the Golden Garland is the unity of the perceiving subject in enlightenment, a topic that reflects the language and concerns of the Yogācāra-svātantrika-madhyamaka school.


The Golden Garland is driven in no small measure by an agenda dedicated to discrediting Dolpopa's Perfection of Wisdom commentaries (Kapstein 1992/3).


This is evident from a comparison of Dolpopa and Tsongkhapa's sources and views.

Dolpopa excoriates Ārya Vimuktiṣeṇa and Hari Bhadra and says they belong to the degenerate age, propounding doctrines harmful to golden age Buddhism.

The Golden Garland, on the other hand, is based on commentaries by Ārya Vimuktiṣeṇa and Hari Bhadra privileged by the Sangphu tradition.

Dolpopa says the two Defenses of the Perfection of Wisdom ūtras (Tib. Gnod 'jom) by “the foremost, Great Middle Way master Vasubandhu,” stand as the primary scriptural authority for the Great Middle Way doctrine, superior even to the partial truths revealed by Nāgārjuna.

The Golden Garland disputes that Vasubandhu is the author of the two Defenses, and says, regardless of their author, they are simply restatements of Nāgārjuna's Middle Way.

Finally, Dolpopa propounds a doctrine that holds that the basis, path, and result are eternally the same, and all else is thoroughly imaginary, but the Golden Garland is certain that such a view is wrong, and directly cites a passage from Dolpopa's work, though without naming its author, saying, “since no other great path-breaker, [i.e., founder of an original philosophy] besides him has ever asserted what Dolpopa says], learned persons are right to cast out [what he says] like a gob of spit” (Sparham 2008, p. 425).


3. Mature Period

Tsongkhapa formulated clearly the philosophy for which he is best known some ten years after finishing the Golden Garland.

He characterized the vision that led him to his philosophy as a pristine Middle Way *Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka.

Reflecting back on his insight, he would write in his In Praise of Dependent Origination (brTen 'brel bstod pa trans. by Tupten Jinpa,


   “Nonetheless, before the stream of this life
   Flowing towards death has come to cease
   That I have found slight faith in you—
   Even this I think is fortunate.
   Among teachers, the teacher of dependent origination,
   Amongst wisdoms, the knowledge of dependent origination—
   You, who're most excellent like the kings in the worlds,
   Know this perfectly well, not others.”


Tsongkhapa first sets forth this mature philosophy linking dependent origination and emptiness in a special section at the end of his Great Exposition.

There, in the context of an investigation into the end-product of an authentic, intellectual investigation into the truly real (Sk. tattva, Tib. de kho na), and into the way things finally are at their deepest level (Sk. tathatā, Tib. de bzhin nyid),

[2] he says you have to identify the object of negation (Tib. dgag bya), i.e., the last false projection to appear as reality,


by avoiding two errors:


going too far (Tib. khyab che ba) and

not going far enough (Tib. khyab chung ba).


That his project does not presuppose a privileged, soul-like, state of consciousness that surveys and categorizes phenomena is evident from his assertion that these two errors originate in a latent psychological tendency in philosophers:

first, to hold on to vestiges of truth (reality) where there is in fact an absence of it, and second, to fall back on some version of truth (reality) in ordinary appearance after failing to avoid nihilism in a futile quest for meaning.

This section of Tsongkhapa's work is based on the opening verse of Nāgārjuna's Root Verses on the Middle Way (Mūla-madhyamaka-kārikā). Tsongkhapa's Ocean of Reasoning (Garfield and Samten 2006a) is a detailed exegesis of this work.

In it, Nāgārjuna says nothing is produced because it is not produced from itself, other, both or neither.

In Tsongkhapa's Great Exposition, the subject of Nāgārjuna's syllogism is primarily the embodied person, reflecting the trend that runs throughout Buddhist philosophical literature, in general, to stress the application of philosophical analysis to praxis.

Furthermore, for Tsongkhapa, Nāgārjuna's statement is about a first moment in the continuum of the investigating person.

By implication, reflecting the continuing influence of Śāntarakṣita, it is the person engaged in the philosophical investigation in the immediate moment.

It is axiomatic for Buddhist philosophers that there is no independent subject (soul) other than the five heaps (skandhas), so the subject of the syllogism becomes the complex or continuum of sense-faculties in the present instant.


Such a subject makes excellence sense of Tsongkhapa's otherwise confusing juxtaposition of Nāgārjuna's analysis with Dharmakīrti's epistemology,

in which it is axiomatic that direct sense perception is an authoritative means of knowledge (Sk. pramāṇa).


Nāgārjuna's statement that such a person was never produced seems paradoxical, to say the least, because it appears to undercut the reality of the very intellectual act in which the thinker is self-evidently engaged.

Tsongkhapa makes it abundantly clear that in his view not only is the intellectual act itself utterly devoid of any essential reality,

even the sense-faculties (the complex eye, ear and so on) also lack any essential reality, never mind the sense data they convey to the knowing individual.


Tsongkhapa's choice of the opening line's of Nāgārjuna's work as a point of departure for his philosophy stems from his belief that he has gained a true insight into dependent origination (pratītya-samutpāda).

This insight, he believes, resolves the paradox between his apparent nihilism and his insistence on the weight of authoritative statements and cognitions.

Thus he says in his Great Exposition,


“Therefore, the intelligent should develop an unshakeable certainty that the very meaning of emptiness is dependent-arising… Specifically, this is the subtle point that the noble Nāgārjuna and his spiritual son Āryadeva had in mind and upon which the master Buddhapālita and the glorious Candrakīrti gave fully comprehensive commentary.

This is how dependent-arising bestows certain knowledge of the absence of intrinsic existence; this is how it dawns on you that it is things which are devoid of intrinsic existence that are causes and effects” (Lamrim Chenmo Translation Committee Vol. 3, 139).

Tsongkhapa set out the ramifications of his view in “eight points that are difficult to understand” (Tib. dka' gnas brgyad) first enumerated in notes (rjes byang) to one of his lectures by his contemporary and disciple, Darma rin chen (also called rGyal tshab rje “the regent”). Tillemans (1998) has nicely rendered the opening of the text as follows,


Concerning the ontological bases, there are the following three points

(1) the conventional nonacceptance of particulars and of
(2) the storehouse consciousness, and
(3) the acceptance of external objects. Concerning the path, there are the following [four points]:
(4) the nonacceptance of autonomous reasonings as being means for understanding reality and
(5) the nonacceptance of self-awareness;
(6) the way in which the two obscurations exist;
 
(7) how it is accepted that the Buddha's disciples and those who become awakened without a Buddha's help realize that things are without any own-nature. Concerning the result, there is:

(8) the way in which the buddhas know conventional things in their full extent. Thus, there are four accepted theses and four unaccepted theses.”

They have been discussed by a number of writers (Ruegg 2002, Cabezon 1992, 397).

I have surveyed Tsongkhapa's early work on the ālaya-vijñāna above.

For Tsongkhapa, until the correct view is understood, it is necessary to assert the ālaya-vijñāna in order to save cause and effect, and avoid falling into nihilism.

When the correct view is obtained, the ālaya-vijñāna stands invalidated (Tillemans's second point).

For Tsongkhapa, it is only possible to understand cause and effect (in particular, as experienced in the immediate moment by an embodied person), by correctly understanding that dependent origination precludes any essential existence whatsoever.

Tsongkhapa asserts that a specific mark (Sk. sva-lakṣaṇa), for instance a mark that makes blue blue, instead of red or any other color, has not even a nominal existence.

This is the first of Tillemans's eight difficult points.

In his monograph Essence of Eloquence, Tsongkhapa employs a hermeneutics that treats language and knowledge as equally semiotic in nature.

This is consistent with Tsongkhapa's view that any intellectual act is itself utterly devoid of any essential reality, yet functions on a conventional level through the natural workings of dependent origination (Sk. dharmatā).

This view allows him to conclude that Dignāga and Dharmakīrti's Logico-epistemological school is equivalent to Asaṅga's Yogācāra school insofar as the former school asserts a specific mark, seen by direct sense perception, that is necessary in order to retain the reality of the conventional world.

Tsongkhapa takes the strong position that no datum that appears to (or is there but unknown to) thought or sense perception, has any essential reality.

All are, equally, simply labeled by thought construction (Tib. rtog pas btags tsam).

Only convention makes the actual sense-faculties, for example, real, and success or failure experienced in a dream, for example, false.

This dependent origination (between a label and what is labeled) precludes the essential existence implicit in the Epistemologist's sva-lakṣaṇa.

Tsongkhapa's strong rejection of Yogācāra idealism leads him to assert the existence of external objects (the third point).

His (discredited) Yogācāra school, based on either the works of Asaṅga or the Epistemologists, explains the absence of subject-object bifurcation as non-dual with thought or mind (Sk. citta).

Realizing this in a non-conceptual, meditational state constitutes a liberating vision.

Ultimately, therefore, external objects are projections of a deluded mind. Tsongkhapa rejects this, though he suggests only those who have understood the emptiness of inherent existence through reflecting on the natural workings of dependent origination can set it aside. As he says in his Ocean of Reasoning,


“The meaning of the statement that the conventional designation of subject and objects stops is that the designation of these two stops from the perspective of meditative equipoise,

but it does not mean that the insight in meditative equipoise and the ultimate truth are rejected as subject and object.

This is because their being subject and object is not posited from the perspective of analytic insight, but from the perspective of conventional understanding” (Garfield and Samten 2006a, p. 26).

From the perspective of ordinary convention there are external objects, so it is sufficient, on that level, to assert that they are there.

Tsongkhapa does not accept svātantra (“autonomous”) reasoning (the fourth point).

He asserts that it is enough, when proving that any given subject is empty of intrinsic existence, to lead the interlocutor, through reasoning, to the unwelcome consequences (prasaṅga) in their own untenable position; it is not necessary to demonstrate the thesis based on reasoning that presupposes any sort of intrinsic (=autonomous) existence.

This gives Tsongkhapa's philosophy its name *Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka, i.e., a philosophy of a middle way (between nihilism and eternalism) arrived at through demonstrating the unwelcome consequences (in any given position that presupposes intrinsic existence).


In the context of this assertion, Tsongkhapa offers a distinctive explanation of the well-known Nayāyika objection to Nāgārjuna's philosophy, namely, if the statements he uses to prove his thesis are themselves without any final intrinsic reality, they will be ineffective as proofs.

Tsongkhapa says *Prāsaṅgika-madhyamakas do not simply find faults in all positions and reject all positions as their own. They only deny any thesis that presupposes an intrinsic existence.

They do hold a specific thesis, to wit, that all phenomena lack an intrinsic existence.

They use reasoning and logic that lacks any essential reality to establish this thesis.

Such reasoning derives its efficacity on a conventional level through the natural workings of dependent origination.

This is one of the most contentious assertions of Tsongkhapa.

Tsongkhapa's rejection of any form of self-referential consciousness (Sk. sva-saṃvitti, sva-saṃvedana) (the fifth point) is in essence a rejection of Śāntarakṣita's position that such self-referential or reflexive awareness is necessary to explain the self-evidential nature of consciousness, and to explain the privileged access the conscious person has to their own consciousness as immediate and veridical (Garfield 2006b).[3]

At issue is the status of the knowing subject engaged in the intellectual pursuit of the truly real. Tsongkhapa holds that such a knowing subject has no essential reality at all.

Such a position requires of Tsongkhapa an explanation of memory.

His solution is to deny that when you remember seeing object X you also remember the conscious act of seeing it.

(Were you to do so, there would have to be an aspect of the earlier consciousness of the object that was equally conscious of itself, i.e., self-referential.)

Instead, Tsongkhapa argues, memory is simply the earlier consciousness of object X, now designated “past.”

When designated past, inexorably (or inferentially, as it were) the presence of a consciousness of the past object X is required to make sense of the present reality.

Tsongkhapa characterizes basic ignorance (Sk. avidyā), the root cause of suffering in Buddhist philosophy, not as a latent tendency, but as an active defiling agency (Sk. kleśāvaraṇa) that projects a reality onto objects that is in fact absent from them.

This ignorance affects even sense perception and explains the veridical aspect that is, in fact, just error.

The residual impressions left by distortion (literally “perfumings” Sk. vāsanā) explain the mere appearance of things as real.

Beyond that, he asserts that habituation to this distortion prevents conventional and ultimate reality from appearing united in an appearing object.

This explanation of the psychology of error differs markedly from earlier Tibetan explanations and constitutes the sixth difficult point.


In Tsongkhapa's mature philosophy the Mahāyāna altruistic principle (bodhicitta) is the sole criterion for distinguishing authentic Mahāyāna views and practices from non-Mahāyāna ones.

By privileging the principle in this way he is able to assert that any authentic realization of truth is a realization of the way things are, namely, a realization of no sva-bhāva (Sk.) (“own-being, own-nature, intrinsic identity”).

For Tsongkhapa, therefore, Hīnayānists (by which he intends followers of the basic Buddhist doctrine of the Four Noble Truths set forth in the earliest scriptures), necessarily have the same authentic knowledge of reality.

Were they not to have such knowledge, he argues, they could not have reached the goals they reached (the seventh point).

Finally, Tsongkhapa has a robust explanation of the difference between true and false on the covering or conventional level.

He denies any difference between a false object (a dream lottery ticket, for example) and a real one; as appearances, he asserts, both are equally false, only convention decides which is true.


All phenomena equally lack truth

In Tsongkhapa's mature philosophy, therefore, all appearance is false––to appear is to appear as being truly what the appearance is of, and the principle of dependent origination precludes such truth from according with the way things actually are.

Tsongkhapa holds that sentences and their content, on the one hand, and minds and what appears to them on the other, function in the same way.


Saying

(1) of a set of “true” and “false” statements that they are all equally untrue, and

(2) saying of unmediated sense-based perception or mistaken ideas that they are equally untrue is to say the same thing.


The truth in both is decided by convention, not by something inhering in the true statement (or its content), or the valid perception (or its object).

For Tsongkhapa, therefore, since all appearance is false, the Buddha knows, but without any appearance of truth (the eighth difficult point).


4. Hermeneutics

A distinctive feature of Tsongkhapa's mature philosophy is the centrality he accords hermeneutics, and the particular stratification of philosophical systems it occasions.

His focus on hermeneutics stems in no small measure from his acceptance of the Kanjur as a true record of authentic statements of the Buddha, and also from his wish to discredit Dolpopa's views.

According to Tsongkhapa, and worked out in detail in his Essence of Eloquence, the given record of the Buddha's diverse statements seems to contain contradictions, so a reader must decide on criteria for interpreting them.

No statement of the Buddha can serve as a primary hermeneutic principle, so that principle necessarily becomes human reason (Sk. yukti, Tib. rigs pa).


When human reason is brought to bear on the diverse statements of the Buddha, it concludes that all statements that an essential or intrinsic identity exists, or any statements that presupposes that, cannot be taken literally, at face value.

This is because human reason, when it analyzes the ultimate truth of any object or statement, finds it empty of anything intrinsic to it that would make it true.

For Tsongkhapa, the line of reasoning that leads most clearly to this conclusion is dependent origination.

Statements that require interpretation Tsongkhapa groups into those of different Buddhist philosophical schools: in ascending order, Listener (Sk. Śrāvaka) schools based on older Buddhist sources (the Vaibhāṣika and Sautrāntika),

Yogācāra schools following Asaṅga and Dignāga/Dharmakīrti, and non-Prāsaṅgika Madhyamaka schools following Bhavaviveka and Śāntarakṣita.

The *Prāsaṅgika-madhyamaka school of Candrakīrti alone captures the final intention of the Buddha.

Tsongkhapa was certainly not the first doxographer, but his clear and definitive categories had immense influence on later writers, so much so they have anachronistically been read back into works that were written before his time.

Tsongkhapa's particular hermeneutics, the primary means he employs to lead readers to his philosophical insight, allows him to characterize particular, authentic, Buddhist philosophies as wrong (because they are wrong from a Prāsaṅgika perspective), yet right from the perspective of those particular systems.

They are right because the philosophies have particular roles to play in a larger, grander scheme.

This scheme is part of the larger philosophy of a perfect person whose views are in perfect accord (Sk. tathāgata) with the way things are, i.e., dependent origination, and whose statements are motivated solely by the benefit they have to those who hear them.

In this way, Tsongkhapa's hermeneutics lead to, or incorporate, a second principle, namely, bodhicitta (Sk.).

The word bodhicitta has at least six different, but interrelated meanings in different contexts (Wangchuk 2007).

In his philosophical works Tsongkhapa uses it to mean a universal, altruistic principle (not unlike the logos) that explains, primarily,

the genesis of the Buddha's diverse statements, i.e., explains why a person with perfect intellect and powers of expression would make statements that seem to contain contradictions.

This principle plays a central role in Tsongkhapa's assertion that all authentic attainments, without distinction,

are based on an authentic insight into emptiness (the seventh of the eight difficult points listed above), and it leads him to assert that the “origin” of the Mahāyāna is located in bodhicitta, and bodhicitta alone


5. Ethics

Tsongkhapa is part of a long, shared, Indo-Tibetan Buddhist tradition that conceives of ethical conduct not in absolute terms, but in the context of different individuals in different situations.

There is an unspoken presupposition that ethical statements are grounded in reality, in the sense that suffering (Sk. duḥkha) comes from actions (Sk. karma) that are not in accord with the way things actually are (Tib. dngos po'i gnas lugs).

The person is ultimately not present as an ethical subject, but is so, on a conventional or covering level, through the natural working of dependent origination.


Tsongkhapa groups such individuals into three separate categories (those who privilege basic Buddhist codes, bodhisattvas, and tāntrikas).

Each is governed by an ethical code (Tib. sdom gsum), each superior code subsuming the points of the lesser.

Beyond these three, his Great Exposition suggests ordinary ethical conduct is codified as well, in the main, in the ten ethical points (Sk. daśa-kuśala-patha) basic to any human life that rises above the mere animal.


The first of the three specifically Buddhist codes, the basic code, primarily governs the behavior of monks and nuns.

Since for Tsongkhapa each higher code incorporates all the rules in the lower code, he conceives of the seven (or even twelve) sub-codes making up the basic code as, in descending order, containing fewer and fewer of the rules that constitute the full code.

Each of the sub-codes is designed for particular people in particular human situations.

Tsongkhapa does not expect a butcher to be governed by the rule of not killing, for example, and he does not expect a lawyer to be governed by the rule of not lying.

He avoids gross devaluation of the basic code by privileging spiritual elites. In this, he takes a pragmatic approach to ethics in line with his non-absolutist stance.

For Tsongkhapa, it is axiomatic that human life is not ipso facto privileged above any other form of life, but his detailed explanation gives greater “weight” to the karmic retribution that comes from killing humans, and amongst humans, noble persons, for example, than less fortunate forms of life.


Tsongkhapa's explanation of the bodhisattva moral code presented in the Bodhisattva-bhūmi (Tatz 1987) follows naturally from the importance he gives to the altruistic principle (bodhicitta) in his other writing.

He reconciles rules in the bodhisattva code that enjoin behavior contradicting the basic code by positing an elite that, through a noblesse oblige of the spiritually advanced, are required to do things which would be unethical in an ordinary person.

Their not doing so constitutes an ethical lapse.

For example, the basic code prohibits actions that influence what food a donor puts in the begging bowl (with a few exceptions for human flesh and so on), and prohibits eating after noon.

The bodhisattva code contradicts the basic code insofar as it prohibits eating meat, even though, by so doing, the donor does not get the opportunity to make charity.

Tsongkhapa argues that if a monk at the bodhisattva stage of development eats meat it clashes with the dictates of the altruistic principle (bodhicitta).


Tsongkhapa accepts that the diverse body of literature, including the historically latest Buddhist tantras (some of which are distinctly antinomian in character), are the work of a fully awakened being (Sk. buddha).

The last of the three codes systematizes the conduct espoused in these tantras.

Tsongkhapa's presentation is distinctive for finding a code complete with a full ordination ceremony.

The practical result of his presentation is to revalue the basic code for monks, and devalue the ritual of tantric consecration as it pertains to ethical conduct.

It stresses ethical conduct even in the context of works that appear, in line with the nihilistic drift of Buddhist philosophy, to count ethical codes as a block to the highest spiritual and philosophical attainment.

For Tsongkhapa the tantric code is only for the very highest spiritual elite, mainly monks and nuns.

Tsongkhapa divides tantras into two sections, and says the lower section is governed exclusively by the bodhisattva code, supplemented by specific ritual injunctions (Sk. vrata).

He gives two interpretations of the rules for the higher tantras, reserving the truly antinomian behavior for a theoretical elite whose altruism is so strong, and whose understanding and status is so ennobled, that they engage in what ordinarily would be condemned as gross immorality.

According to this code, it is an ethical lapse not to eat meat, perhaps even human flesh, the logic being that in certain specific and unusual circumstances, in a person at this stage of development, such behavior would constitute a skillful means to benefit others.


Tantra

Tsongkhapa does not have a different tantric philosophy.

His Prāsaṅgika Middle Way is the philosophical position he articulates in his works on tantra.

He does however, unlike in his non-tantric works, accept that those propounding Idealistic philosophies (Yogācāra, Svātantrika Middle Way) can have success in their practice.

In this he reveals again the importance of the central Tibetan philosophical tradition going back to Śāntarakṣita.


Tsongkhapa conceives of tantra as a subset of the Mahāyāna, and to that extent all authentic Buddhist tantric activities are, necessarily, authentically altruistic.

What differentiates tantric activity from other ordinary Mahāyāna activities is deity yoga (Tib. lha'i rnal 'byor), i.e., whether or not, from a first person perspective, the person is acting as a perfect, “divinesubject when engaging in (primarily ritual) behavior.


Tsongkhapa wrote works on the Vajrabhairava, Cakrasaṃvara, and Kālacakra tantras, but is best known for his exposition of the Guhyasamāja tantra based on Indian commentaries associated with the names of Nāgārjuna and Āryadeva,

particularly his short but influential Commentary on the Jñāna-vajra-samuccaya (Ye shes rdo rje kun las ‘dus pa'i ṭī kā) (1410), and magisterial Clear Exposition of the Five Stages of Guhyasamāja (gSang ‘dus rim lnga gsal sgron) (1411).

He accords great importance to esoteric yoga.

In this respect, his work is firmly located in the mainstream Tibetan tradition, influenced in particular by the translator Mar pa (Mar pa Chos kyi blo gros) (1012–1097), who spread the Six Teachings of Nāropa (Nā ro chos drug), a later Indian synthesis of diverse tantric practices, in Tibet.

Based on this Tsongkhapa gives detailed explanations of the nāḍī (channels for the energy or feelings that run through the tantric practitioner's body),

cakra (circles of channels in the heart, throat, and other central points up the center of the body from the bottom of the spine, or tip of the sex organ,

to the top of the head) and caṇḍalī (an intense pleasure experienced as heat that spreads through the channels and fills the body).

Tsongkhapa is praised, in particular, for his explanation of theory and praxis associated with the illusory body (Sk. māyā-kāya, Tib. sgyu lus) and clear light (Sk. prabhāsvara, Tib. 'od gsal), a skillful adaptation of his understanding of the two truths to yogic praxis.

This is summed up nicely in the statement, “The Pañcakramasaṃgrahaprakāśa (Illumination of the Summary of the Five Steps), a short treatise attributed to Nāropa (956–1040), combining the Six Teachings with the ‘Five Steps’ (pañcakrama) of the Ārya tradition provided Tsong kha pa with the basic ideas of his Tantric system” (Tillemans 1998).


Bibliography

<poem> Primary Works

   Three sets of Collected Works of Tsongkhapa (“the Kumbum Jampaling, Tashilhunpo Parnying, and Lhasa Sho printery editions”), Tibetan Buddhist Resource Center.
   In Praise of Dependent Origination (Brten 'brel bstod pa trans. by Tupten Jinpa [Available online (pdf)].

Secondary Works

   Anonymous, 1890. “The Literature of Tibet.” Edinburgh Review, 126–134.
   Cabezon, Jose Ignacio, 1994. A Dose of Emptiness: An Annotated Translation of the sTong thun chen mo of mKhas grub dGe legs dpal bzang. Albany: State University of New York Press.
   Das, S.C., 1970. “Life and Legend of Tsoṅ Khapa (Lo-ssaṅ-tagpa), The Great Buddhist Reformer of Tibet.” Journal of the Asiatic Society of Bengal, Vol. LI (vi), 1882. Reprinted in Contributions on the Religion and History of Tibet. New Delhi: Mañjuśrī Publishing House.
   Dreyfus, Georges, 1997. Recognizing Reality: Dharmakīrti's Philosophy and its Tibetan Interpretations. Albany: State University of New York Press.
   Garfield, Jay L., and Geshe Ngawang Samten, 2006a. Ocean of Reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
   –––, 2006b. “The Conventional Status of Reflexive Awareness: What's at Stake in a Tibetan Debate?” Philosophy East and West, 56(2), 201–228.
   Hopkins, Jeffrey, 1980. Tantra in Tibet: The Great Exposition of Secret Mantra–Volume 1. London: Allen and Unwin, pp. 83–169.
   –––, 1999. Emptiness in the Mind-Only School of Buddhism. Berkeley, CA.: University of California Press.
   –––, 2002. Reflections on Reality: The Three Natures and Non-Natures in the Mind-Only School: Dynamic Responses to Dzong-ka-ba's The Essence of Eloquence. London: University of California Press.
   –––, 2006a. Absorption in No External World: 170 Issues in Mind Only Buddhism (Dynamic Responses to Dzong-ka-ba's The Essence of Eloquence). Ithaca, N.Y.: Snow Lion Publications.
   –––, 2008. Tsong-kha-pa's Final Exposition of Wisdom. Ithaca, N.Y.: Snow Lion Publications.
   Jinpa, Thupten, 2002. Self, Reality, and Reason in Tibetan Philosophy. London: RoutledgeCurzon.
   Kay, David, 2004. Tibetan and Zen Buddhism in Britain. London: RoutledgeCurzon.
   Lamrim Chenmo Translation Committee, Joshua W.C. Cutler (ed.), 2000–2004. The Great Treatise on the States of the Path to Enlightenment. Vols. 1–3. Ithaca, N.Y.: Snow Lion Publications.
   Matsumoto, S., 1948. “The Mādhyamika philosophy of Tsong-kha-pa.” In Memoirs of the Research Department of the Toyo Bunko, 48, 17–47.
   Monier-Williams, M., 1888. Buddhism (Duff Lectures, University of Edinburgh), Varanasi: Chowkhamba Sanskrit Series Office, 1964, second edition.
   Napper, Elizabeth, 1989. Dependent-Arising and Emptiness. Boston: Wisdom Publications.
   Ruegg, David Seyfort, 2000. “On Epistemological-Logical (pramāṇa) Theory and the Ontic in Tsoṅ kha pa's Madhyamaka Philosophy.” Three Studies in the History of Indian and Tibetan Madhyamaka Philosophy. Wiener Studien zur Tibetologie und Buddhismuskund 50. Wien: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien.
   –––, 2002. Two Prolegomena to Madhyamaka Philosophy: Chadrakīrti's Prasannapadā Madhyamakavṛtti on Madhyamakakārikā, I.1 and Tsoṅ kha pa blo bzaṅ grags pa/rGyal tshab dar ma rin chen's dka‘ gnad brgyad kyi zin bris. Wien: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien.
   –––, 2004. “Indian and the Indic in Tibetan Cultural History and Tsoṅ Kha Pa's Achievement as a Scholar and Thinker: An Essay on the Concepts of Buddhism in Tibet and Tibetan Buddhism.“ Journal of Indian Philosophy, 2004, 32.4, 321–343.
   Sparham, Gareth, 1993. Ocean of Eloquence. Albany: State University of New York Press.
   –––, 2005. Tantric Ethics. Somerville MA: Wisdom Publications.
   –––, 2007 Golden Garland of Eloquence—Vol. 1–3 by Tsong kha pa.
English Translation by Gareth Sparham (2007–2009). Fremont, CA: Jain Publishing.
   Tatz, Mark, 1986. Asaṅga's Chapter on Ethics, With the Commentary of Tsong-Kha-pa, the Basic Path to Awakening, the Complete Bodhisattva. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press.
   –––, 1990. “Who is Tsong-kha-pa Refuting in His Basic Path to Awakening?” In Lawrence Epstein and Richard F. Sherburne (Eds.), Reflections on Tibetan Culture––Essays in Memory of Turrell V. Wylie. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press, 149–163.
   Tauscher, H., 1995. Die Lehre von den zwei Wirklichkeiten in Tsoṅ kha pas Madhyamaka-Werken. Wien: Wiener Studien zur Tibetologie und Buddhismuskund 50. Wien: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien Universität Wien.
   Thurman, Robert A.F., 1984. Tsong Khapa's Speech of Gold in the Essence of True Eloquence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
   Tillemans, T., 1992. “Tsong kha pa et al. on the Bhavaviveka-Candrakrti Debate.” In Shoren Ihara and ZuihoYamaguchi (Eds.), Tibetan Studies. Narita: Naritasan Shinshoji, vol. 1, 316–26.
   –––, 1998. “Tsong kha pa blo bzang grags pa.” In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by E. Craig, 487–490. London: Routledge Co.
   van der Kuijp, Leonard W.J., 1985. “Apropos of a Recent Contribution to the History of the Central Way Philosophy in Tibet: Tsong-kha-pa's Speech of Gold. Berliner Indologische Studien 1, 47–74.
   Vose, Kevin, 2009. Resurrecting Candrakirti: Disputes in the Tibetan Creation of Prasangika. Studies in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism. Somerville MA: Wisdom Publications.
   Williams, Paul, 1983. “A note on some aspects of Mi bskyod rdo rje's critique of dGe lugs pa Madhyamaka.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 11, 125–45.
   –––, 1998a. The Reflexive Nature of Awareness: A Tibetan Madhyamaka Defense. Richmond, UK: Curzon.
   –––, 1998b. Altruism and Reality. Richmond, UK: Curzon.
   Yoshimizu, C., 1989. Descriptive Catalogue of the Naritasan Institute Collection of Tibetan Works, vol. 1, Narita: Naritasan shinshoji.
   Yotsuya, Kodo, 1999. The Critique of Svatantra Reasoning by Candrakirti and Tsong-kha-pa. Franz Steiner Verlag.

Academic Tools

   sep man icon 	How to cite this entry.
   sep man icon 	Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society.
   inpho icon 	Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).
   phil papers icon 	Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

   Tibetan Buddhist Resource Center. A repository of digitally preserved works in Tibetan, including a number or editions of Tsongkhapa's collected works.
   Tibetan and Himalayan Library, University of Virginia. A hub resource for Tibetan studies in universities worldwide.
   Asian Classics Input Project. The ACE tool allows readers to browse and search a number of Tsongkhapa's texts.
   The Tibet Album, Collections of photographs of Tibet (British photography in Central Tibet 1920-1950). Excellent record of pre-1959 dGe lugs monasteries and other institutions influenced by Tsongkhapa..
   UMA Institute for Tibetan Studies. UMA = Union of the Modern and the Ancient Institute for Tibetan Studies. Contains audio-files of explanations of works of Tsongkhapa by traditional Tibetan teachers, translated by Jeffrey Hopkins.
   The Berzin Archives. The Buddhist Archives of Dr. Alexander Berzin. A non-academic, but sometimes informative site for dGe lugs pa explanations of Tsongkhapa's ideas maintained by Alexander Berzin

Related Entries

Gelukpa dge lugs pa | Nāgārjuna | Śāntarakṣita | Tibetan epistemology and philosophy of language | Tibetan hermeneutics | two truths in Tibet, theory of


Gareth Sparham <gsparham@umich.edu>

Source

[1]