Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Manual of Pramana - Reading Ten: The Concept of Time"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with "Selection from the collected topics: thumb|250px| The Concept of Time The following selections on the concept of time (Dus-gsum gyi rnam-bz...")
 
m (Text replacement - "]]]" to "]])")
 
(7 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
Selection from the collected topics:
+
Selection from the [[collected topics]]:
[[File:Buddhas.life.b.016.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
+
[[File:Buddhas.life.b.016.jpg|thumb|250px|]]{{DisplayImages|1406|1847|335|1949|4466|2746|3414|325|2038|2253|1343|3693|1607|2477|1549|3471|3775|2671|3196|3207|1017|2416|577|2122|2230|4031|2677|235|28|2633|4179|2008|2983|4484|3724|1809|1065|2767|1541|464|883|2431|870|1462|1741|3721|3419|581|3231|3815|986|2840|907|2631|496}}
The Concept of Time
+
The [[Concept of Time]]
  
 
   
 
   
  
The following selections on the concept of time (Dus-gsum gyi rnam-bzhag), are excerpted from The Collected Topics of Rato (Rva-stod bsdus-grva), by Master Chokhla U-ser, a great master of Rato Monastery who lived about 1500 AD. This particular book is considered the “grandfather” of what came to be a separate genre of literature in Tibet: the dura (bsdus-grva), or “selected topics from the Commentary on Valid Perception (Pramana Varttika, or Tsad-ma rnam-’grel) of Master Dharmakirti (circa 650 AD).
+
The following selections on the [[concept of time]] ([[Dus-gsum gyi rnam-bzhag]]), are excerpted from The [[Collected Topics]] of Rato ([[Rva-stod bsdus-grva]]), by [[Master]] [[Chokhla U-ser]], a [[great master]] of [[Rato Monastery]] who lived about 1500 AD. This particular [[book]] is considered the “grandfather” of what came to be a separate genre of {{Wiki|literature}} in [[Tibet]]: the [[dura]] ([[bsdus-grva]]), or “selected topics from the [[Commentary on Valid Perception]] ([[Pramana Varttika]], or [[Tsad-ma rnam-’grel]]) of [[Master]] [[Dharmakirti]] (circa 650 AD).
  
Please note that indented statements are usually those given by the opponent. Responses within brackets are those that are usually left unwritten in the Tibetan text, and are understood to be there because of the context following each.
+
Please note that indented statements are usually those given by the opponent. Responses within brackets are those that are usually left unwritten in the [[Tibetan]] text, and are understood to be there because of the context following each.
  
 
_______________
 
_______________
Line 13: Line 13:
 
Suppose someone comes again, and makes the following claim:
 
Suppose someone comes again, and makes the following claim:
  
The definition of the past is: “That which has begun and stopped.” The definition of the present is: “That which has begun and not yet stopped.” The definition of the future is: “That condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present.”
+
The [[definition]] of the {{Wiki|past}} is: “That which has begun and stopped.” The [[definition]] of the {{Wiki|present}} is: “That which has begun and not yet stopped.” The [[definition]] of the {{Wiki|future}} is: “That [[condition]] of having not yet begun, although the [[causes]] for beginning are {{Wiki|present}}.”
  
 
Respective examples would be the following. For the first, the example would be last year’s crops. For the second, it would be this year’s crops; and, for the third, crops soon to grow.
 
Respective examples would be the following. For the first, the example would be last year’s crops. For the second, it would be this year’s crops; and, for the third, crops soon to grow.
Line 19: Line 19:
 
Concerning the first of these, we answer as follows.
 
Concerning the first of these, we answer as follows.
  
Aren’t your definition and example for the past though incorrect?
+
Aren’t your [[definition]] and example for the {{Wiki|past}} though incorrect?
  
Because there is no definition for the past,
+
Because there is no [[definition]] for the {{Wiki|past}},
  
And this is because the past doesn’t even exist,
+
And this is because the {{Wiki|past}} doesn’t even [[exist]],
  
And this is because anything which can be established as existing is always something of the present.
+
And this is because anything which can be established as [[existing]] is always something of the {{Wiki|present}}.
  
 
On this point, someone may come and make the following claim:
 
On this point, someone may come and make the following claim:
  
But there must be things that are past,
+
But there must be things that are {{Wiki|past}},
  
Because past time exists;
+
Because {{Wiki|past}} [[time]] [[exists]];
  
And this is because all three—past time, and future time, and present time—exist.
+
And this is because all three—past [[time]], and {{Wiki|future}} [[time]], and {{Wiki|present}} time—exist.
  
And this is because the three times exist.
+
And this is because the three times [[exist]].
  
 
To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
 
To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
  
And we also ask this person,
+
And we also ask this [[person]],
  
So is the past the past?
+
So is the {{Wiki|past}} the {{Wiki|past}}?
  
Because the past exists.
+
Because the {{Wiki|past}} [[exists]].
  
You already agreed to the reason here.
+
You already agreed to the [[reason]] here.
  
[Then I agree to your original statement: the past is the past.]
+
[Then I agree to your original statement: the {{Wiki|past}} is the {{Wiki|past}}.]
  
 
Suppose you agree to our original statement.
 
Suppose you agree to our original statement.
  
Consider the past.
+
Consider the {{Wiki|past}}.
  
It is not so the past,
+
It is not so the {{Wiki|past}},
  
 
Because it is not something which has stopped;
 
Because it is not something which has stopped;
Line 63: Line 63:
 
But it does necessarily follow,
 
But it does necessarily follow,
  
Because “the past,” “that which has stopped,” and “that which has been destroyed” all refer to the same thing.
+
Because “the {{Wiki|past}},” “that which has stopped,” and “that which has been destroyed” all refer to the same thing.
  
And this is true because all three of them exist;
+
And this is true because all three of them [[exist]];
  
And this is true because the past exists.
+
And this is true because the {{Wiki|past}} [[exists]].
  
You already agreed that the reason is true.
+
You already agreed that the [[reason]] is true.
  
 
Suppose that, instead of “it doesn’t necessarily follow,” the opponent says “it’s incorrect.”
 
Suppose that, instead of “it doesn’t necessarily follow,” the opponent says “it’s incorrect.”
  
Consider the past.
+
Consider the {{Wiki|past}}.
  
 
It is not so something which has been destroyed,
 
It is not so something which has been destroyed,
Line 83: Line 83:
 
But it does necessarily follow,
 
But it does necessarily follow,
  
Because there exists no one thing which is both (1) something that has been destroyed but which is still (2) a working thing.
+
Because there [[exists]] no one thing which is both (1) something that has been destroyed but which is still (2) a working thing.
  
 
And this is true because the Golden Necklace of Good Explanation says,
 
And this is true because the Golden Necklace of Good Explanation says,
  
None of the schools that belong to the side that believe that things exist through some nature of their own accept the idea that something which has been destroyed could be a working thing.
+
None of the schools that belong to the side that believe that things [[exist]] through some [[nature]] of their [[own]] accept the [[idea]] that something which has been destroyed could be a working thing.
  
[The Golden Necklace is a famed commentary by Je Tsongkapa upon the Ornament of Realizations, spoken to the realized being Asanga by Lord Maitreya.]
+
[The Golden Necklace is a famed commentary by [[Je Tsongkapa]] upon the Ornament of Realizations, spoken to the [[realized]] being [[Asanga]] by [[Lord Maitreya]].]
  
 
[Then I disagree to your earlier statement.]
 
[Then I disagree to your earlier statement.]
Line 95: Line 95:
 
Suppose you say that the earlier one is not correct.
 
Suppose you say that the earlier one is not correct.
  
Consider the past.
+
Consider the {{Wiki|past}}.
  
 
It is so a working thing,
 
It is so a working thing,
Line 101: Line 101:
 
Because it is something made.
 
Because it is something made.
  
[It's not correct to say that the past is something made.]
+
[It's not correct to say that the {{Wiki|past}} is something made.]
  
 
Suppose you say that it’s not correct.
 
Suppose you say that it’s not correct.
Line 115: Line 115:
 
But it does necessarily follow,
 
But it does necessarily follow,
  
Because “something that started” is the definition of “something made.”
+
Because “something that started” is the [[definition]] of “something made.”
  
 
[The earlier point is not correct.]
 
[The earlier point is not correct.]
Line 121: Line 121:
 
Suppose you say that the earlier point is not correct.
 
Suppose you say that the earlier point is not correct.
  
Consider the past.
+
Consider the {{Wiki|past}}.
  
 
It is so something that started,
 
It is so something that started,
Line 127: Line 127:
 
Because it is something that started and then stopped.
 
Because it is something that started and then stopped.
  
And this is true because it’s the past.
+
And this is true because it’s the {{Wiki|past}}.
  
You’ve agreed both to the reason and to what we’re asserting must be so, and the necessity is something that does apply to the definition. It must moreover be true that that which has been destroyed is a working thing,
+
You’ve agreed both to the [[reason]] and to what we’re asserting must be so, and the necessity is something that does apply to the [[definition]]. It must moreover be true that that which has been destroyed is a working thing,
  
Because the past is a working thing.
+
Because the {{Wiki|past}} is a working thing.
  
We’ve already established that the reason is true.
+
We’ve already established that the [[reason]] is true.
  
 
Suppose you do agree.
 
Suppose you do agree.
Line 139: Line 139:
 
Is it then the case that a working thing which has been destroyed is still a working thing?
 
Is it then the case that a working thing which has been destroyed is still a working thing?
  
Because (1) there does exist a working thing which has been destroyed, and (2) that which has been destroyed is a working thing.
+
Because (1) there does [[exist]] a working thing which has been destroyed, and (2) that which has been destroyed is a working thing.
  
You’ve already agreed to the latter part of the reason.
+
You’ve already agreed to the [[latter]] part of the [[reason]].
  
 
Suppose now you say that the first part is not correct.
 
Suppose now you say that the first part is not correct.
Line 147: Line 147:
 
The first is too correct,
 
The first is too correct,
  
Because there does exist a working thing which is past.
+
Because there does [[exist]] a working thing which is {{Wiki|past}}.
  
[It's not correct to say that there does exist a working thing which is past.]
+
[It's not correct to say that there does [[exist]] a working thing which is {{Wiki|past}}.]
  
 
Suppose you say that it’s not correct.
 
Suppose you say that it’s not correct.
Line 155: Line 155:
 
Consider a working thing.
 
Consider a working thing.
  
There does too exist it past,
+
There does too [[exist]] it {{Wiki|past}},
  
 
Because it is something that has been produced.
 
Because it is something that has been produced.
Line 163: Line 163:
 
Suppose you agree to our second original statement.
 
Suppose you agree to our second original statement.
  
So is a tree that was already destroyed still a tree?
+
So is a [[tree]] that was already destroyed still a [[tree]]?
  
 
Because a working thing which has been destroyed is still a working thing.
 
Because a working thing which has been destroyed is still a working thing.
  
You’ve already accepted the reason.
+
You’ve already accepted the [[reason]].
  
[Then I agree to your original statement: a tree that was already destroyed is still a tree.]
+
[Then I agree to your original statement: a [[tree]] that was already destroyed is still a [[tree]].]
  
 
Suppose you agree to our original statement.
 
Suppose you agree to our original statement.
  
So is it then true that when a tree has been burned up by fire there is still a tree?
+
So is it then true that when a [[tree]] has been burned up by [[fire]] there is still a [[tree]]?
  
Because (1) a tree that was already destroyed is a tree; and (2) there exists a destroyed tree subsequent to the burning up of a tree by a fire.
+
Because (1) a [[tree]] that was already destroyed is a [[tree]]; and (2) there [[exists]] a destroyed [[tree]] subsequent to the burning up of a [[tree]] by a [[fire]].
  
And this is so because—when a tree has been burned up by fire—there is a tree destroyed.
+
And this is so because—when a [[tree]] has been burned up by fire—there is a [[tree]] destroyed.
  
 
[I agree to your statement above.]
 
[I agree to your statement above.]
Line 183: Line 183:
 
Suppose you agree to our statement above.
 
Suppose you agree to our statement above.
 
[[File:Imag36es.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Imag36es.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
Is it then the case that—subsequent to the burning up of a tree by a fire—you can still see a tree by using your visual consciousness?
+
Is it then the case that—subsequent to the burning up of a [[tree]] by a fire—you can still see a [[tree]] by using your [[visual consciousness]]?
  
Because there does exist a tree subsequent to that point.
+
Because there does [[exist]] a [[tree]] subsequent to that point.
  
You already agreed to the reason.
+
You already agreed to the [[reason]].
  
If the one is the case, then the other is necessarily so. [That is, if there does exist a tree subsequent to that point, then you must be able to see it by using your visual consciousness.]
+
If the one is the case, then the other is necessarily so. [That is, if there does [[exist]] a [[tree]] subsequent to that point, then you must be able to see it by using your [[visual consciousness]].]
  
 
And you cannot agree to this last statement;
 
And you cannot agree to this last statement;
  
Because the following quotation from the Commentary on Valid Perception was meant to point out—to those who asserted that something which was destroyed could ever be a working thing—what very absurd consequences their position entailed:
+
Because the following quotation from the Commentary on Valid [[Perception]] was meant to point out—to those who asserted that something which was destroyed could ever be a working thing—what very absurd {{Wiki|consequences}} their position entailed:
  
 
Because it has started, then the destruction
 
Because it has started, then the destruction
  
Must be destroyed; and then the tree
+
Must be destroyed; and then the [[tree]]
  
 
Would have to be seen once more.
 
Would have to be seen once more.
  
Concerning the second of the original definitions, [that the definition of the present is "that which has begun and not yet stopped,"] we pose the following:
+
Concerning the second of the original definitions, [that the [[definition]] of the {{Wiki|present}} is "that which has begun and not yet stopped,"] we pose the following:
  
 
Consider “knowable things.”
 
Consider “knowable things.”
Line 207: Line 207:
 
So is it something which has begun and not yet stopped?
 
So is it something which has begun and not yet stopped?
  
Because it is something of the present.
+
Because it is something of the {{Wiki|present}}.
  
 
[It doesn't necessarily follow.]
 
[It doesn't necessarily follow.]
Line 213: Line 213:
 
But you already agree that it does necessarily follow.
 
But you already agree that it does necessarily follow.
  
[It's not correct to say that "knowable things" is something of the present.]
+
[It's not correct to say that "knowable things" is something of the {{Wiki|present}}.]
  
 
It is so correct,
 
It is so correct,
  
Because it can be established as existing.
+
Because it can be established as [[existing]].
  
 
[Then I agree to your statement above: "knowable things" is something that has begun and not yet stopped.]
 
[Then I agree to your statement above: "knowable things" is something that has begun and not yet stopped.]
Line 229: Line 229:
 
Because it has begun and not yet stopped.
 
Because it has begun and not yet stopped.
  
You already agreed to the reason.
+
You already agreed to the [[reason]].
  
 
[Then I agree to your statement.]
 
[Then I agree to your statement.]
Line 239: Line 239:
 
It is not so, that it is something which ever began,
 
It is not so, that it is something which ever began,
  
Because it is an unchanging thing.
+
Because it is an [[unchanging]] thing.
  
If you agreed [that an unchanging thing could begin], then what we would answer to you is obvious.
+
If you agreed [that an [[unchanging]] thing could begin], then what we would answer to you is obvious.
  
Concerning the third of the original definitions, [that the definition of the future is: "that condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present,"] we pose the following:
+
Concerning the third of the original definitions, [that the [[definition]] of the {{Wiki|future}} is: "that [[condition]] of having not yet begun, although the [[causes]] for beginning are {{Wiki|present}},"] we pose the following:
  
So is it true then that the future exists?
+
So is it true then that the {{Wiki|future}} [[exists]]?
  
Because it is something which has a definition;
+
Because it is something which has a [[definition]];
  
Because “that condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present” is the definition of the future.
+
Because “that [[condition]] of having not yet begun, although the [[causes]] for beginning are {{Wiki|present}}” is the [[definition]] of the {{Wiki|future}}.
  
You already agreed that the reason was true.
+
You already agreed that the [[reason]] was true.
  
 
[Then I agree to your point above.]
 
[Then I agree to your point above.]
Line 257: Line 257:
 
Suppose you agree to the above.
 
Suppose you agree to the above.
  
So is it then the case that the future is itself?
+
So is it then the case that the {{Wiki|future}} is itself?
  
Because it does exist.
+
Because it does [[exist]].
  
[I agree to your statement: the future is itself.]
+
[I agree to your statement: the {{Wiki|future}} is itself.]
  
 
Suppose you agree to our original statement.
 
Suppose you agree to our original statement.
  
Consider the future.
+
Consider the {{Wiki|future}}.
  
So is it then a condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present?
+
So is it then a [[condition]] of having not yet begun, although the [[causes]] for beginning are {{Wiki|present}}?
  
Because it is the future.
+
Because it is the {{Wiki|future}}.
  
You already agreed to the reason,
+
You already agreed to the [[reason]],
  
And it is obvious that the necessity must apply to the definition.
+
And it is obvious that the necessity must apply to the [[definition]].
  
 
[Then I agree.]
 
[Then I agree.]
Line 279: Line 279:
 
Suppose you agree.
 
Suppose you agree.
  
Depending on how they read this definition [in the Tibetan], some people claim, “I agree that the future is the condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present (Tib: skye ba’i rgyu yod).” Others claim, “I agree that the object of our argument [the future] is the condition of having not yet begun, even though it has cause to begin from this same condition (Tib: skye ba’i rgyu yod).”
+
Depending on how they read this [[definition]] [in the [[Tibetan]]), some [[people]] claim, “I agree that the {{Wiki|future}} is the [[condition]] of having not yet begun, although the [[causes]] for beginning are {{Wiki|present}} (Tib: skye ba’i rgyu yod).” Others claim, “I agree that the [[object]] of our argument [the {{Wiki|future}}] is the [[condition]] of having not yet begun, even though it has [[cause]] to begin from this same [[condition]] (Tib: skye ba’i rgyu yod).”
  
 
Well suppose then that you read it the first way.
 
Well suppose then that you read it the first way.
  
So does there exist a cause that makes the future begin?
+
So does there [[exist]] a [[cause]] that makes the {{Wiki|future}} begin?
  
Because the future is the condition of having not yet begun, even though the causes for beginning are present.
+
Because the {{Wiki|future}} is the [[condition]] of having not yet begun, even though the [[causes]] for beginning are {{Wiki|present}}.
  
You’ve already accepted the reason.
+
You’ve already accepted the [[reason]].
  
[I agree that there does exist a cause that makes the future begin.]
+
[I agree that there does [[exist]] a [[cause]] that makes the {{Wiki|future}} begin.]
  
 
Suppose you agree.
 
Suppose you agree.
  
So is this cause that makes the future begin a working thing?
+
So is this [[cause]] that makes the {{Wiki|future}} begin a working thing?
  
Because it does exist.
+
Because it does [[exist]].
  
 
[I agree that it is.]
 
[I agree that it is.]
Line 301: Line 301:
 
Suppose you agree.
 
Suppose you agree.
  
Consider this cause that makes the future begin.
+
Consider this [[cause]] that makes the {{Wiki|future}} begin.
  
 
Is it something made?
 
Is it something made?
Line 317: Line 317:
 
Because it is something made.
 
Because it is something made.
  
You already agreed to the reason.
+
You already agreed to the [[reason]].
  
 
But you cannot agree,
 
But you cannot agree,
Line 323: Line 323:
 
Because it is something which has not yet begun;
 
Because it is something which has not yet begun;
  
Because it is the condition of having not yet begun;
+
Because it is the [[condition]] of having not yet begun;
  
Because it is a condition where, even though [its cause] exists, it has not yet begun.
+
Because it is a [[condition]] where, even though [its [[cause]]) [[exists]], it has not yet begun.
  
You’ve already agreed both to the reason and to what we’re asserting must be so.
+
You’ve already agreed both to the [[reason]] and to what we’re asserting must be so.
  
And the following problem applies to the latter way of reading the phrase.
+
And the following problem applies to the [[latter]] way of reading the [[phrase]].
  
Is it then the case that this cause that will make it begin is a working thing?
+
Is it then the case that this [[cause]] that will make it begin is a working thing?
  
Because the cause that will make the future begin exists.
+
Because the [[cause]] that will make the {{Wiki|future}} begin [[exists]].
  
[It's not correct to say that the cause that will make the future begin exists.]
+
[It's not correct to say that the [[cause]] that will make the {{Wiki|future}} begin [[exists]].]
  
 
Suppose you say that it’s not correct.
 
Suppose you say that it’s not correct.
  
Consider this cause that will make the future begin.
+
Consider this [[cause]] that will make the {{Wiki|future}} begin.
  
It does so exist,
+
It does so [[exist]],
  
Because [the future] is a condition where, even though [its cause exists], it has not yet begun.
+
Because [the {{Wiki|future}}] is a [[condition]] where, even though [its [[cause]] [[exists]]), it has not yet begun.
  
You’ve already agreed both to the reason and to what we’re asserting must be so.
+
You’ve already agreed both to the [[reason]] and to what we’re asserting must be so.
  
 
[It doesn't necessarily follow.]
 
[It doesn't necessarily follow.]
Line 355: Line 355:
 
Suppose you agree to our statement above.
 
Suppose you agree to our statement above.
  
Consider the cause that makes [the future] begin.
+
Consider the [[cause]] that makes [the {{Wiki|future}}] begin.
  
 
It must then be something which has begun,
 
It must then be something which has begun,
Line 361: Line 361:
 
Because it is a working thing.
 
Because it is a working thing.
  
[I agree that the cause that makes the future begin is something which has begun.]
+
[I agree that the [[cause]] that makes the {{Wiki|future}} begin is something which has begun.]
  
 
Suppose you agree.
 
Suppose you agree.
Line 371: Line 371:
 
Because it is a thing which has yet to begin,
 
Because it is a thing which has yet to begin,
  
Because it is a condition of not having yet begun.
+
Because it is a [[condition]] of not having yet begun.
  
[It's not correct to say that the cause which makes the future begin is a condition of not having yet begun.]
+
[It's not correct to say that the [[cause]] which makes the {{Wiki|future}} begin is a [[condition]] of not having yet begun.]
  
 
Suppose you say that it’s not correct.
 
Suppose you say that it’s not correct.
  
Consider this cause that makes the future begin.
+
Consider this [[cause]] that makes the {{Wiki|future}} begin.
  
It is so the condition of not having yet begun,
+
It is so the [[condition]] of not having yet begun,
  
Because it is the condition of having not yet begun, even though it exists.
+
Because it is the [[condition]] of having not yet begun, even though it [[exists]].
  
You’ve already both to the reason and to what we’re asserting must be so.
+
You’ve already both to the [[reason]] and to what we’re asserting must be so.
  
 
_______________
 
_______________
Line 389: Line 389:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
  
Does there exist a cause for something to begin or not?
+
Does there [[exist]] a [[cause]] for something to begin or not?
  
 
We answer that there does, and then someone comes and makes the following claim:
 
We answer that there does, and then someone comes and makes the following claim:
  
But isn’t it the case that no cause for something to begin exists?
+
But isn’t it the case that no [[cause]] for something to begin [[exists]]?
  
Because isn’t it the case that nothing beginning exists?
+
Because isn’t it the case that nothing beginning [[exists]]?
  
 
Because isn’t it the case that, if something is a working thing, it can never be beginning?
 
Because isn’t it the case that, if something is a working thing, it can never be beginning?
Line 409: Line 409:
 
So is it then the case that there are no beginnings at all?
 
So is it then the case that there are no beginnings at all?
  
Because none of the following exist: “something that’s going to begin,” “something that needs to begin,” “something that’s about to begin,” and “something that’s in the act of beginning.”
+
Because none of the following [[exist]]: “something that’s going to begin,” “something that needs to begin,” “something that’s about to begin,” and “something that’s in the act of beginning.”
  
 
To this we say, “It doesn’t necessarily follow,” and then we say:
 
To this we say, “It doesn’t necessarily follow,” and then we say:
  
It’s like this. The beginning or the birth of something does too exist,
+
It’s like this. The beginning or the [[birth]] of something does too [[exist]],
  
Because past and future births exist.
+
Because {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}} [[births]] [[exist]].
  
And this is true because there exists the practice of amassing the two collections over a great many births, past and future.
+
And this is true because there [[exists]] the [[practice]] of amassing the [[two collections]] over a great many [[births]], {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}}.
  
And this is true because there does exist the creation of an Infallible
+
And this is true because there does [[exist]] the creation of an Infallible
  
Being, who comes from the practice of amassing the two collections over a great many births, past and future.
+
Being, who comes from the [[practice]] of amassing the [[two collections]] over a great many [[births]], {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}}.
  
 
And this itself is true, because there is a point to the following two quotations:
 
And this itself is true, because there is a point to the following two quotations:
Line 431: Line 431:
 
And—
 
And—
  
The proof is that it comes from the practice
+
The [[proof]] is that it comes from the [[practice]]
  
Of the attitude of compassion.
+
Of the [[attitude]] of [[compassion]].
  
[Both quotations are from the Commentary on Valid Perception, and are used to establish that an Enlightened Being is produced from many eons spent amassing the two collections.]
+
[Both quotations are from the Commentary on Valid [[Perception]], and are used to establish that an [[Enlightened Being]] is produced from many [[eons]] spent amassing the [[two collections]].]
  
Are you saying, moreover, that it is proper to throw away the whole system of those Lords of Reasoning, the Father and his spiritual Sons, and go following the system of that non-Buddhist school, the Rejectionists (Lokayata)?
+
Are you saying, moreover, that it is proper to throw away the whole system of those [[Lords]] of {{Wiki|Reasoning}}, the Father and his [[spiritual]] Sons, and go following the system of that [[non-Buddhist]] school, the Rejectionists ([[Wikipedia:Cārvāka|Lokayata]])?
  
 
Because you would have to accept the other side as our side in the following verses:
 
Because you would have to accept the other side as our side in the following verses:
Line 445: Line 445:
 
Even things that are hidden, and there’s
 
Even things that are hidden, and there’s
  
No proof that shows he can;
+
No [[proof]] that shows he can;
  
 
Neither is there a way to try.”
 
Neither is there a way to try.”
Line 455: Line 455:
 
And—
 
And—
  
Because the mind is something
+
Because the [[mind]] is something
  
That depends upon the body,
+
That depends upon the [[body]],
  
 
There is nothing you can achieve
 
There is nothing you can achieve
  
Through practice [over many lifetimes].
+
Through [[practice]] [over many lifetimes].
  
And this is true because it would then be right for you to accept the position that it’s impossible for there to exist an enlightened realized being who has practiced assembling the two collections over a great many births, past and future.
+
And this is true because it would then be right for you to accept the position that it’s impossible for there to [[exist]] an [[enlightened]] [[realized]] being who has practiced assembling the [[two collections]] over a great many [[births]], {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}}.
  
 
_______________
 
_______________
Line 469: Line 469:
 
Suppose someone comes again and claims,
 
Suppose someone comes again and claims,
  
There must too exist a working thing which is about to begin,
+
There must too [[exist]] a working thing which is about to begin,
  
Because there exists a working thing which is about to take birth from their mother’s womb.
+
Because there [[exists]] a working thing which is about to take [[birth]] from their mother’s [[womb]].
  
So does there exist then a working thing which is in the act of beginning?
+
So does there [[exist]] then a working thing which is in the act of beginning?
  
Because there exists a working which is about to take birth from their mother’s womb.
+
Because there [[exists]] a working which is about to take [[birth]] from their mother’s [[womb]].
  
 
The fact that it follows is something you find acceptable.
 
The fact that it follows is something you find acceptable.
  
But you cannot agree, because the glorious Chandrakirti has stated, “Since something in the act of beginning is only approaching beginning, it is not something which exists.”
+
But you cannot agree, because the glorious [[Chandrakirti]] has stated, “Since something in the act of beginning is only approaching beginning, it is not something which [[exists]].”
  
And are you, furthermore, saying that there exists a working thing which hasn’t begun?
+
And are you, furthermore, saying that there [[exists]] a working thing which hasn’t begun?
  
Because there exists a working thing which hasn’t begun, from their mother’s womb.
+
Because there [[exists]] a working thing which hasn’t begun, from their mother’s [[womb]].
  
Suppose someone comes and says, “It’s incorrect [to say that there exists a working thing which hasn't begun, from their mother's womb].
+
Suppose someone comes and says, “It’s incorrect [to say that there [[exists]] a working thing which hasn't begun, from their mother's [[womb]]).
  
But it is correct, because (1) there does exist a person who is in the act of staying in their mother’s womb, and (2) there also exists a working thing which is born complete.
+
But it is correct, because (1) there does [[exist]] a [[person]] who is in the act of staying in their mother’s [[womb]], and (2) there also [[exists]] a working thing which is born complete.
  
 
Are you saying, moreover, that a working thing which has already begun begins again?
 
Are you saying, moreover, that a working thing which has already begun begins again?
  
Because there exists a living being who has already taken birth, and who has to take birth again.
+
Because there [[exists]] a [[living being]] who has already taken [[birth]], and who has to take [[birth]] again.
  
And this is true because there exists a living being who has already taken birth, and who has to take birth again in the circle of suffering life.
+
And this is true because there [[exists]] a [[living being]] who has already taken [[birth]], and who has to take [[birth]] again in the circle of [[suffering]] [[life]].
  
And this is true because (1) there exists a living being who has already taken birth as a human, and who has to take birth again as a human; and (2) there exists a living being who has already taken birth into the desire realm, and who has to take birth into the desire realm again.
+
And this is true because (1) there [[exists]] a [[living being]] who has already taken [[birth]] as a [[human]], and who has to take [[birth]] again as a [[human]]; and (2) there [[exists]] a [[living being]] who has already taken [[birth]] into the [[desire realm]], and who has to take [[birth]] into the [[desire realm]] again.
  
Each of the reasons given is correct, because there do exist those who come from a birth as a human and are born as a human; and there do exist those who come from a birth in the desire realm and are born into the desire realm. It’s easy to accept these reasons.
+
Each of the [[reasons]] given is correct, because there do [[exist]] those who come from a [[birth]] as a [[human]] and are born as a [[human]]; and there do [[exist]] those who come from a [[birth]] in the [[desire realm]] and are born into the [[desire realm]]. It’s easy to accept these [[reasons]].
  
And is it, moreover, the case that there exists nothing which is occurring?
+
And is it, moreover, the case that there [[exists]] nothing which is occurring?
  
 
Because nothing which is a working thing could ever be something which is occurring.
 
Because nothing which is a working thing could ever be something which is occurring.
Line 507: Line 507:
 
The fact that it follows is something you find acceptable.
 
The fact that it follows is something you find acceptable.
  
The reason we’ve stated is correct, because anything which is a working thing is something which has already occurred from its own causes.
+
The [[reason]] we’ve stated is correct, because anything which is a working thing is something which has already occurred from its [[own]] [[causes]].
  
And this is true because anything which is a working thing is something which has already begun from its own causes.
+
And this is true because anything which is a working thing is something which has already begun from its [[own]] [[causes]].
  
[Then I agree to your original statement: it is the case that there exists nothing which is occurring.]
+
[Then I agree to your original statement: it is the case that there [[exists]] nothing which is occurring.]
  
 
Suppose you agree to our original statement.
 
Suppose you agree to our original statement.
  
There does too exist something which is occurring,
+
There does too [[exist]] something which is occurring,
  
Because there exist the four great elements.
+
Because there [[exist]] the [[four great elements]].
  
And this is because there do exist the four of earth, water, fire, and wind.
+
And this is because there do [[exist]] the four of [[earth]], [[water]], [[fire]], and [[wind]].
  
[Translator's note: This argument depends upon the fact that the Tibetan words for "occurring" and for "element" have the same spelling ('byung ba).]
+
[Translator's note: This argument depends upon the fact that the [[Tibetan]] words for "occurring" and for "[[element]]" have the same spelling ('byung ba).]
  
 
[It doesn't necessarily follow.]
 
[It doesn't necessarily follow.]
  
It does necessarily follow, because that highest master, Vasubandhu, has stated that the great elements are four.
+
It does necessarily follow, because that [[highest]] [[master]], [[Vasubandhu]], has stated that the [[great elements]] are four.
  
And this is true because the Treasure House says,
+
And this is true because the [[Treasure]] House says,
  
The elements are the following:
+
The [[elements]] are the following:
  
The divisions of elements we call
+
The divisions of [[elements]] we call
  
Earth and water and fire and wind.
+
[[Earth]] and [[water]] and [[fire]] and [[wind]].
  
 
_______________
 
_______________
  
Suppose yet another person comes and claims:
+
Suppose yet another [[person]] comes and claims:
  
There must too exist a working thing which still has to start,
+
There must too [[exist]] a working thing which still has to start,
  
Because there does exist a working thing which is going to start.
+
Because there does [[exist]] a working thing which is going to start.
  
And this is because there does exist a working thing which is going to occur.
+
And this is because there does [[exist]] a working thing which is going to occur.
  
 
To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
 
To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
  
The reason in itself though does apply to the subject,
+
The [[reason]] in itself though does apply to the [[subject]],
  
Because the four of blue, yellow, white, and red and the like are all derivatives of the elements, and there also exist tangible objects which are derivatives of the elements.
+
Because the four of blue, yellow, white, and red and the like are all derivatives of the [[elements]], and there also [[exist]] {{Wiki|tangible}} [[objects]] which are derivatives of the [[elements]].
  
And this is true because all tangible objects can be divided into two types: those that are elements, and those that are derivatives of the elements.
+
And this is true because all {{Wiki|tangible}} [[objects]] can be divided into two types: those that are [[elements]], and those that are derivatives of the [[elements]].
  
[Translator's note: This argument depends on the fact that the Tibetan for "going to occur" and for "derivative of the elements" is the same ('byung-'gyur).]
+
[Translator's note: This argument depends on the fact that the [[Tibetan]] for "going to occur" and for "derivative of the [[elements]]" is the same ('byung-'gyur).]
  
And this is true because The Treasure House of Wisdom says,
+
And this is true because The [[Treasure]] House of [[Wisdom]] says,
  
Tangible objects are of two types…
+
{{Wiki|Tangible}} [[objects]] are of two types…
  
You can’t though agree to the original statement, [that there must exist a working thing which still has to start],
+
You can’t though agree to the original statement, [that there must [[exist]] a working thing which still has to start],
  
 
Because anything which is a working thing is something which must have already started.
 
Because anything which is a working thing is something which must have already started.
Line 565: Line 565:
 
On this point some may make the following claim:
 
On this point some may make the following claim:
  
It must so be the case that there exists no working thing which is going to occur,
+
It must so be the case that there [[exists]] no working thing which is going to occur,
  
 
Because anything which is a working thing must have already occurred.
 
Because anything which is a working thing must have already occurred.
  
This position though reflects a gross error of failing to examine things thoroughly. The expressions “going to start” and “still needs to start” are equivalent in meaning, exclusively, “going to start from the beginning” and “still needs to start from the beginning.”
+
This position though reflects a gross error of failing to examine things thoroughly. The {{Wiki|expressions}} “going to start” and “still needs to start” are {{Wiki|equivalent}} in meaning, exclusively, “going to start from the beginning” and “still needs to start from the beginning.”
  
But whereas “still needs to occur” means, exclusively, “still needs to occur from the beginning,” the [Tibetan phrase for] “going to occur” also applies to things which have already occurred, such as the color blue, or the tangible objects of heat or cold, and so on. And the mistake by the opponent here is that they have never heard the terms explained this way.
+
But whereas “still needs to occur” means, exclusively, “still needs to occur from the beginning,” the ([[Tibetan]] [[phrase]] for] “going to occur” also applies to things which have already occurred, such as the {{Wiki|color}} blue, or the {{Wiki|tangible}} [[objects]] of heat or cold, and so on. And the mistake by the opponent here is that they have never heard the terms explained this way.
  
 
_______________
 
_______________
Line 577: Line 577:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
  
The definition of something “past” relative to the time of a water pitcher is “that which has started and also stopped, in the time that the water pitcher is present.”
+
The [[definition]] of something “{{Wiki|past}}” [[relative]] to the [[time]] of a [[water]] pitcher is “that which has started and also stopped, in the [[time]] that the [[water]] pitcher is {{Wiki|present}}.”
  
The definition of something “future” relative to the time of a water pitcher is “that which is such that—although the causes for it to start are already present—it has yet to start, in the time that the water pitcher is present.”
+
The [[definition]] of something “{{Wiki|future}}” [[relative]] to the [[time]] of a [[water]] pitcher is “that which is such that—although the [[causes]] for it to start are already present—it has yet to start, in the [[time]] that the [[water]] pitcher is {{Wiki|present}}.”
  
The definition of something “present” relative to the time of a water pitcher is “that which has started and not yet stopped, in the time that the water pitcher is present.”
+
The [[definition]] of something “{{Wiki|present}}” [[relative]] to the [[time]] of a [[water]] pitcher is “that which has started and not yet stopped, in the [[time]] that the [[water]] pitcher is {{Wiki|present}}.”
  
 
Let us address the first of these definitions.
 
Let us address the first of these definitions.
  
Consider the cause of a water pitcher.
+
Consider the [[cause]] of a [[water]] pitcher.
  
Is this cause then something which has started and also stopped, in the time that the water pitcher is present?
+
Is this [[cause]] then something which has started and also stopped, in the [[time]] that the [[water]] pitcher is {{Wiki|present}}?
  
Because it is something which is past relative to the time of the water pitcher.
+
Because it is something which is {{Wiki|past}} [[relative]] to the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.
  
 
And this is because it is the example we’ve chosen here.
 
And this is because it is the example we’ve chosen here.
  
And suppose you agree to the previous statement. [That is, suppose you agree that the cause of a water pitcher is something which has started and also stopped in the time of the water pitcher.]
+
And suppose you agree to the previous statement. [That is, suppose you agree that the [[cause]] of a [[water]] pitcher is something which has started and also stopped in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.]
  
Consider again the cause of a water pitcher.
+
Consider again the [[cause]] of a [[water]] pitcher.
  
Is it then one thing which has both (1) started in the time of the water pitcher and (2) stopped in the time of the water pitcher?
+
Is it then one thing which has both (1) started in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher and (2) stopped in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher?
  
 
[Why do you say that?]
 
[Why do you say that?]
Line 603: Line 603:
 
Because you agreed.
 
Because you agreed.
  
[Then I agree that the cause of a water pitcher is one thing which has both (1) started in the time of the water pitcher and (2) stopped in the time of the water pitcher.]
+
[Then I agree that the [[cause]] of a [[water]] pitcher is one thing which has both (1) started in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher and (2) stopped in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.]
  
 
Suppose you agree then.
 
Suppose you agree then.
Line 609: Line 609:
 
Consider this same thing.
 
Consider this same thing.
  
Is it then something which has started in the time of the water pitcher?
+
Is it then something which has started in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher?
  
 
[Why do you say that?]
 
[Why do you say that?]
Line 615: Line 615:
 
Because you agreed above.
 
Because you agreed above.
  
And yet you can’t agree, because it is something which has not started in the time of the water pitcher.
+
And yet you can’t agree, because it is something which has not started in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.
  
And this is because it is something which has not been made in the time of the water pitcher.
+
And this is because it is something which has not been made in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.
  
[It's not necessarily the case that, because the cause of a pitcher is something which has not been made in the time of the water pitcher, it must be something which has not started in the time of the water pitcher.]
+
[It's not necessarily the case that, because the [[cause]] of a pitcher is something which has not been made in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher, it must be something which has not started in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.]
  
 
Suppose you say that it’s not necessarily the case.
 
Suppose you say that it’s not necessarily the case.
Line 625: Line 625:
 
It is though necessarily the case,
 
It is though necessarily the case,
  
Because the very definition of something’s not having been made in a certain time is “something’s not having started” in that same time.
+
Because the very [[definition]] of something’s not having been made in a certain [[time]] is “something’s not having started” in that same [[time]].
  
And this is true because (1) there is at that time something which hasn’t been made, and (2) the definition of “something that hasn’t been made” is “something that hasn’t started.”
+
And this is true because (1) there is at that [[time]] something which hasn’t been made, and (2) the [[definition]] of “something that hasn’t been made” is “something that hasn’t started.”
  
And this is true because “something that has started” is the definition of “something that has been made.”
+
And this is true because “something that has started” is the [[definition]] of “something that has been made.”
  
Now suppose that you were to answer “it’s not correct to say that” above, where you answered “it doesn’t’ necessarily follow.” [That is, suppose you say that it's not correct to say that the cause of a water pitcher is something which has not been made in the time of the water pitcher.]
+
Now suppose that you were to answer “it’s not correct to say that” above, where you answered “it doesn’t’ necessarily follow.” [That is, suppose you say that it's not correct to say that the [[cause]] of a [[water]] pitcher is something which has not been made in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.]
  
 
Consider this same thing.
 
Consider this same thing.
  
It is so true that it has not been made in that particular time,
+
It is so true that it has not been made in that particular [[time]],
  
Because it doesn’t even exist in that particular time.
+
Because it doesn’t even [[exist]] in that particular [[time]].
 
[[File:Ma-buddha.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Ma-buddha.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
And this is because it has stopped in that particular time.
+
And this is because it has stopped in that particular [[time]].
  
And this is because, in that particular time, it has started and also stopped.
+
And this is because, in that particular [[time]], it has started and also stopped.
  
And you’ve already agreed to what we stated as our reason.
+
And you’ve already agreed to what we stated as our [[reason]].
  
Consider, moreover, the cause of a water pitcher, once again.
+
Consider, moreover, the [[cause]] of a [[water]] pitcher, once again.
  
It is not so, that it is one thing which has both (1) started in the time of the water pitcher, and (2) stopped in this same time,
+
It is not so, that it is one thing which has both (1) started in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher, and (2) stopped in this same [[time]],
  
 
Because it is not something which has stopped.
 
Because it is not something which has stopped.
Line 657: Line 657:
 
_______________
 
_______________
  
Suppose yet another person comes, and makes this claim:
+
Suppose yet another [[person]] comes, and makes this claim:
  
Consider the cause of a water pitcher.
+
Consider the [[cause]] of a [[water]] pitcher.
  
It is too something which has started in the time of the water pitcher,
+
It is too something which has started in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher,
  
Because it has finished starting in the time of the water pitcher.
+
Because it has finished starting in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.
  
 
To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
 
To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
  
Therefore we have to express the situation as follows: Although the cause of the water pitcher, in the time of the water pitcher, has already begun, it is not something which has begun in the time of the water pitcher. This is for example like the case where the followers of the Independent group of the Middle-Way School and such say that “Cause and effect is true [Tib: bden-pa], but not real [Tib: bden-pa].” You have to be able to make the same kind of distinction here.
+
Therefore we have to express the situation as follows: Although the [[cause]] of the [[water]] pitcher, in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher, has already begun, it is not something which has begun in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher. This is for example like the case where the followers of the Independent group of the [[Middle-Way]] School and such say that “[[Cause and effect]] is true [Tib: bden-pa], but not real [Tib: bden-pa].” You have to be able to make the same kind of {{Wiki|distinction}} here.
  
 
____________
 
____________
Line 673: Line 673:
 
Suppose someone comes along and claims,
 
Suppose someone comes along and claims,
  
Even though omniscience perceives a water pitcher directly, it does not do so in the sense that the word “directly” has when we divide perception into the two of “direct” and “deductive.”
+
Even though [[omniscience]] [[perceives]] a [[water]] pitcher directly, it does not do so in the [[sense]] that the [[word]] “directly” has when we divide [[perception]] into the two of “direct” and “{{Wiki|deductive}}.”
  
 
To this we answer, “You are absolutely correct.”
 
To this we answer, “You are absolutely correct.”
  
If however someone were to come along in a debate and say that “Every state of direct perception is ‘direct’ in the sense that this word has when we divide perception into the two of ‘direct’ and ‘deductive’,” some logic would be required to prove the point just made.
+
If however someone were to come along in a [[debate]] and say that “Every [[state]] of direct [[perception]] is ‘direct’ in the [[sense]] that this [[word]] has when we divide [[perception]] into the two of ‘direct’ and ‘{{Wiki|deductive}}’,” some [[logic]] would be required to prove the point just made.
  
 
____________
 
____________
  
As for the second definition, [the definition of "the future" given above,] consider the result of a water pitcher.
+
As for the second [[definition]], [the [[definition]] of "the {{Wiki|future}}" given above,] consider the result of a [[water]] pitcher.
  
 
Is it then something that has not begun?
 
Is it then something that has not begun?
  
Because it is the condition of not having begun.
+
Because it is the [[condition]] of not having begun.
  
And this is because it is the condition of not having begun, even though the causes for its beginning exist in the time of the water pitcher.
+
And this is because it is the [[condition]] of not having begun, even though the [[causes]] for its beginning [[exist]] in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.
  
Now some may come along and claim, in response, that “it doesn’t necessarily follow.” This however would indicate that they had yet to grasp the meaning of the collected topics on logic and perception.
+
Now some may come along and claim, in response, that “it doesn’t necessarily follow.” This however would indicate that they had yet to [[grasp]] the meaning of the [[collected topics]] on [[logic]] and [[perception]].
  
Suppose someone else came and said, instead, that “Your reason is not correct.”
+
Suppose someone else came and said, instead, that “Your [[reason]] is not correct.”
  
Consider then this same thing: [the result of a water pitcher].
+
Consider then this same thing: [the result of a [[water]] pitcher].
  
Are you saying that it is the condition of not having begun, even though, in the time of the pitcher, the causes for its beginning are present? Because it is “the future” at this same time.
+
Are you saying that it is the [[condition]] of not having begun, even though, in the [[time]] of the pitcher, the [[causes]] for its beginning are {{Wiki|present}}? Because it is “the {{Wiki|future}}” at this same [[time]].
  
The correctness of our reason is easy to accept.
+
The correctness of our [[reason]] is easy to accept.
  
 
And you’ve already accepted the necessity.
 
And you’ve already accepted the necessity.
  
As for the third of the definitions above, [that of "the present,"] suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
+
As for the third of the definitions above, [that of "the {{Wiki|present}},"] suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
  
Consider the cause of a water pitcher.
+
Consider the [[cause]] of a [[water]] pitcher.
  
It is so something which is present-time in the time of the water pitcher,
+
It is so something which is present-time in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher,
  
Because it is something which, in the time of the water pitcher, has begun and not yet stopped.
+
Because it is something which, in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher, has begun and not yet stopped.
  
It is so, because it is both (1) something which has begun in the time of the water pitcher and (2) something which has not stopped in that time.
+
It is so, because it is both (1) something which has begun in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher and (2) something which has not stopped in that [[time]].
  
Our side would answer that the first part of this reason is not correct.
+
Our side would answer that the first part of this [[reason]] is not correct.
  
 
And then the other side would come back with,
 
And then the other side would come back with,
Line 717: Line 717:
 
Consider then this same thing.
 
Consider then this same thing.
  
It is too something which has begun in the time of the water pitcher,
+
It is too something which has begun in the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher,
  
Because it is something which has finished beginning in that time.
+
Because it is something which has finished beginning in that [[time]].
  
 
To this we’d answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
 
To this we’d answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
Line 725: Line 725:
 
***************
 
***************
  
Here next is an analysis of the question of whether the past and the future exist or not. Generally speaking there exist no definitions for “the past” or “the future,” because the past and future are not things which even exist. This is because, anything which can be established as existing must always be existing in the present [according to this school of Buddhism].
+
Here next is an analysis of the question of whether the {{Wiki|past}} and the {{Wiki|future}} [[exist]] or not. Generally {{Wiki|speaking}} there [[exist]] no definitions for “the {{Wiki|past}}” or “the {{Wiki|future}},” because the {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}} are not things which even [[exist]]. This is because, anything which can be established as [[existing]] must always be [[existing]] in the {{Wiki|present}} [according to this school of [[Buddhism]]).
  
If though we were to establish the meaning of “the past” relative to a specific point of reference, we could say that the definition of its past relative to the time of a specific water pitcher could be given as follows:
+
If though we were to establish the meaning of “the {{Wiki|past}}” [[relative]] to a specific point of reference, we could say that the [[definition]] of its {{Wiki|past}} [[relative]] to the [[time]] of a specific [[water]] pitcher could be given as follows:
  
Something which has, by the time of the water pitcher, already started; and which has, by the time of the water pitcher, already ended as well.
+
Something which has, by the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher, already started; and which has, by the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher, already ended as well.
  
 
This and “the pitcher just before the pitcher” amount to the same thing.
 
This and “the pitcher just before the pitcher” amount to the same thing.
  
The definition of its present relative to the time of a specific water pitcher then could be given as follows:
+
The [[definition]] of its {{Wiki|present}} [[relative]] to the [[time]] of a specific [[water]] pitcher then could be given as follows:
  
That one thing which is both (1) something which has already come into existence by the time of the water pitcher; and (2) which is simultaneous to the water pitcher.
+
That one thing which is both (1) something which has already come into [[existence]] by the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher; and (2) which is simultaneous to the [[water]] pitcher.
  
The definition of its future relative to the time of a specific water pitcher, finally, could be given as follows:
+
The [[definition]] of its {{Wiki|future}} [[relative]] to the [[time]] of a specific [[water]] pitcher, finally, could be given as follows:
  
That one thing which is both (1) in the act of starting at the time of the water pitcher; and (2) not yet started at the time of the water pitcher.
+
That one thing which is both (1) in the act of starting at the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher; and (2) not yet started at the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher.
  
 
The following all amount to the same thing:
 
The following all amount to the same thing:
  
the not-yet-coming of the water pitcher;
+
the not-yet-coming of the [[water]] pitcher;
  
the cause of the water pitcher;
+
the [[cause]] of the [[water]] pitcher;
  
its past at the time of the water pitcher; and
+
its {{Wiki|past}} at the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher; and
  
its past relative to the water pitcher.
+
its {{Wiki|past}} [[relative]] to the [[water]] pitcher.
  
[Translator's note: "Not-yet-coming" and "future" are the same word in Tibetan (ma- 'ongs-pa).]
+
[Translator's note: "Not-yet-coming" and "{{Wiki|future}}" are the same [[word]] in [[Tibetan]] (ma- 'ongs-pa).]
  
 
The following also all amount to the same thing:
 
The following also all amount to the same thing:
  
the passing of the water pitcher;
+
the passing of the [[water]] pitcher;
  
the result of the water pitcher;
+
the result of the [[water]] pitcher;
  
its future at the time of the water pitcher; and
+
its {{Wiki|future}} at the [[time]] of the [[water]] pitcher; and
  
its future relative to the water pitcher.
+
its {{Wiki|future}} [[relative]] to the [[water]] pitcher.
  
[Translator's note: "Passing" and "past" are the same word in Tibetan ('das-pa).]
+
[Translator's note: "Passing" and "{{Wiki|past}}" are the same [[word]] in [[Tibetan]] ('das-pa).]
  
Generally speaking, there is no such thing as something which has stopped.
+
Generally {{Wiki|speaking}}, there is no such thing as something which has stopped.
  
And there is nothing which is about to begin. Neither is there anything which is in the act of beginning, nor is there anything which is approaching the state of beginning.
+
And there is nothing which is about to begin. Neither is there anything which is in the act of beginning, nor is there anything which is approaching the [[state]] of beginning.
  
There does exist though the passing of the smoke; and the stopping of the smoke; and the smoke’s not yet coming, and the smoke’s being about to begin; and the smoke’s being in the act of beginning; and the smoke’s approaching the state of beginning.
+
There does [[exist]] though the passing of the smoke; and the stopping of the smoke; and the smoke’s not yet coming, and the smoke’s being about to begin; and the smoke’s being in the act of beginning; and the smoke’s approaching the [[state]] of beginning.
  
There is though no such thing as smoke which is approaching the state of beginning. Neither is there any smoke which is in the act of beginning; nor any smoke which is about to begin; nor smoke which has stopped; nor smoke which has been destroyed; nor smoke which is past; nor smoke which is future.
+
There is though no such thing as smoke which is approaching the [[state]] of beginning. Neither is there any smoke which is in the act of beginning; nor any smoke which is about to begin; nor smoke which has stopped; nor smoke which has been destroyed; nor smoke which is {{Wiki|past}}; nor smoke which is {{Wiki|future}}.
  
 
The following all amount to the same thing:
 
The following all amount to the same thing:
Line 783: Line 783:
 
a thing which is in the act of being destroyed;
 
a thing which is in the act of being destroyed;
  
a thing which is approaching the past;
+
a thing which is approaching the {{Wiki|past}};
 
[[File:Nanda devatas.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Nanda devatas.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
a thing which is approaching its destruction.
 
a thing which is approaching its destruction.
  
These assertions [about the nature of time] are all presented in accordance with the beliefs of the “Logician” group within the Sutrist School. They would not necessarily be acceptable to any other school of Buddhism. The Detailists, for example, do accept ideas such as past karma and future karma, while the Necessity group entertains unimaginably profound positions such as the one that states that the destruction of something is a working thing.
+
These assertions [about the [[nature]] of [[time]]) are all presented in accordance with the [[beliefs]] of the “[[Logician]]” group within the Sutrist School. They would not necessarily be acceptable to any other school of [[Buddhism]]. The Detailists, for example, do accept [[ideas]] such as {{Wiki|past}} [[karma]] and {{Wiki|future}} [[karma]], while the Necessity group entertains unimaginably profound positions such as the one that states that the destruction of something is a working thing.
  
 
***************
 
***************
Line 793: Line 793:
 
   
 
   
  
Formal logic subject:
+
{{Wiki|Formal logic}} [[subject]]:
  
A Discussion of Incorrect Logical Statements
+
A [[Discussion]] of Incorrect [[Logical]] Statements
  
 
   
 
   
  
The following presentation on incorrect “logical” statements is excerpted from An Explanation of the Art of Reasoning (rTags-rigs), by the Tutor of His Holiness the Thirteenth Dalai Lama, Purbuchok Jampa Tsultrim Gyatso (1825-1901).
+
The following presentation on incorrect “[[logical]]” statements is excerpted from An Explanation of the [[Art]] of {{Wiki|Reasoning}} ([[rTags-rigs]]), by the Tutor of [[His Holiness]] the [[Thirteenth Dalai Lama]], Purbuchok [[Jampa]] [[Tsultrim Gyatso]] (1825-1901).
  
 
_______________
 
_______________
  
Here is the second major division of our presentation, in which we explain the opposite of a correct reason: that is, incorrect reasons. We proceed in two steps: the definition of such reasons, and their various divisions.
+
Here is the second major [[division]] of our presentation, in which we explain the opposite of a correct [[reason]]: that is, incorrect [[reasons]]. We proceed in two steps: the [[definition]] of such [[reasons]], and their various divisions.
  
The first of these we’ll discuss in terms of disproving our opponent’s beliefs, and then establishing our own beliefs. Here is the first. Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim: “Any reason where the three relationships fail to hold” is the definition of an incorrect reason.
+
The first of these we’ll discuss in terms of disproving our opponent’s [[beliefs]], and then establishing our [[own]] [[beliefs]]. Here is the first. Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim: “Any [[reason]] where the three relationships fail to hold” is the [[definition]] of an incorrect [[reason]].
  
This though is mistaken, for there is no such thing as an incorrect reason: everything which exists is a correct reason [to prove something].
+
This though is mistaken, for there is no such thing as an incorrect [[reason]]: everything which [[exists]] is a correct [[reason]] [to prove something].
  
Here secondly is our own position. The definition of an incorrect reason for a particular proof is:
+
Here secondly is our [[own]] position. The [[definition]] of an incorrect [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]] is:
  
A reason for a particular proof where the three relationships fail to hold.
+
A [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]] where the three relationships fail to hold.
  
Here secondly are the various divisions of incorrect reasons. Although there is not, generally speaking, any such thing as an incorrect reason, we can say that there do exist the following types of incorrect reasons in specific contexts:
+
Here secondly are the various divisions of incorrect [[reasons]]. Although there is not, generally {{Wiki|speaking}}, any such thing as an incorrect [[reason]], we can say that there do [[exist]] the following types of incorrect [[reasons]] in specific contexts:
  
1) Contradictory reasons for specific proofs;
+
1) [[Contradictory]] [[reasons]] for specific proofs;
  
2) Indefinite reasons for specific proofs; and
+
2) Indefinite [[reasons]] for specific proofs; and
  
3) Wrong reasons for specific proofs.
+
3) Wrong [[reasons]] for specific proofs.
  
We will discuss the first of these in four steps: definition; divisions; classical examples; and supporting arguments.
+
We will discuss the first of these in four steps: [[definition]]; divisions; classical examples; and supporting arguments.
  
Here is the first. The definition of a contradictory reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing is:
+
Here is the first. The [[definition]] of a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing is:
  
That one thing for which (1) the relationship between the subject and the reason does hold for proving that sound is an unchanging thing; and (2) the positive necessity between the reason and the quality to be proven also holds for proving that sound is not an unchanging thing.
+
That one thing for which (1) the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] does hold for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing; and (2) the positive necessity between the [[reason]] and the quality to be proven also holds for proving that [[sound]] is not an [[unchanging]] thing.
  
[A classical example would be: Consider sound. It is an unchanging thing, because it is a made thing.]
+
[A classical example would be: Consider [[sound]]. It is an [[unchanging]] thing, because it is a made thing.]
  
 
Here secondly are the divisions.
 
Here secondly are the divisions.
  
Contradictory reasons can be divided into two kinds: those which have a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they cover it completely, and those which have a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they go both ways, [covering or not].
+
[[Contradictory]] [[reasons]] can be divided into two kinds: those which have a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they cover it completely, and those which have a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they go both ways, [covering or not].
  
Here thirdly are the classical examples. “Something that was made” is a contradictory reason which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they cover it completely, in a proof that sound is not a changing thing. “Something which is a particular example of the general type called ‘made things’” is a contradictory reason which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they go both ways, in proving the same thing.
+
Here thirdly are the classical examples. “Something that was made” is a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they cover it completely, in a [[proof]] that [[sound]] is not a changing thing. “Something which is a particular example of the general type called ‘made things’” is a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they go both ways, in proving the same thing.
  
 
Next is the fourth category: the supporting arguments.
 
Next is the fourth category: the supporting arguments.
Line 839: Line 839:
 
Consider “something that was made.”
 
Consider “something that was made.”
  
It is so a contradictory reason which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they cover it completely, in a proof that sound is not a changing thing,
+
It is so a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they cover it completely, in a [[proof]] that [[sound]] is not a changing thing,
  
Because it is both (1) a contradictory reason for proving this particular thing, and (2) anything which is changing is also it.
+
Because it is both (1) a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] for proving this particular thing, and (2) anything which is changing is also it.
  
 
And consider “something which is a particular example of the general type called ‘made things’.”
 
And consider “something which is a particular example of the general type called ‘made things’.”
  
It is so a contradictory reason which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they go both ways, in a proof that sound is not a changing thing,
+
It is so a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they go both ways, in a [[proof]] that [[sound]] is not a changing thing,
  
Because it is a contradictory reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing.
+
Because it is a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing.
  
And this is so because (1) the relationship between this reason and the subject of the particular proof holds; and (2) it is definitely the case that the positive necessity between it and the quality to be proven is diametrically false.
+
And this is so because (1) the relationship between this [[reason]] and the [[subject]] of the particular [[proof]] holds; and (2) it is definitely the case that the positive necessity between it and the quality to be proven is diametrically false.
  
 
Consider, moreover, this same example.
 
Consider, moreover, this same example.
  
It is so a contradictory reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing,
+
It is so a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing,
  
Because it is a correct reason for proving that sound is a changing thing.
+
Because it is a correct [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is a changing thing.
  
 
_______________
 
_______________
Line 861: Line 861:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
  
So does there exist then a contradictory reason for proving that sound is a changing thing?
+
So does there [[exist]] then a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is a changing thing?
  
Because there does exist a contradictory reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing.
+
Because there does [[exist]] a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing.
  
 
To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
 
To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
  
And you could never agree [that there did exist a contradictory reason for proving that sound is a changing thing],
+
And you could never agree [that there did [[exist]] a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is a changing thing],
  
Because anything which is an incorrect reason for proving that sound is a changing thing must be either (1) an indefinite reason for the particular proof or (2) a wrong reason for the particular proof.
+
Because anything which is an incorrect [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is a changing thing must be either (1) an indefinite [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]] or (2) a wrong [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]].
  
 
____________
 
____________
Line 875: Line 875:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
  
If there exist the three relationships for any particular proof, then there must exist a correct reason for the particular proof.
+
If there [[exist]] the three relationships for any particular [[proof]], then there must [[exist]] a correct [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]].
  
 
Consider all knowable things.
 
Consider all knowable things.
  
There must then exist a correct reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing,
+
There must then [[exist]] a correct [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing,
  
Because the three relationships do exist for proving that sound is an unchanging thing.
+
Because the three relationships do [[exist]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing.
  
 
You’ve already accepted that it necessarily follows.
 
You’ve already accepted that it necessarily follows.
  
Suppose then that you say that it’s not correct [that the three relationships do exist for proving that sound is an unchanging thing].
+
Suppose then that you say that it’s not correct [that the three relationships do [[exist]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing].
  
They do too exist, because (1) there exists a relationship between the reason and the subject for this particular proof, and (2) there exists the positive necessity for the proof, and there exists the reverse necessity for the proof.
+
They do too [[exist]], because (1) there [[exists]] a relationship between the [[reason]] and the [[subject]] for this particular [[proof]], and (2) there [[exists]] the positive necessity for the [[proof]], and there [[exists]] the reverse necessity for the [[proof]].
  
The first part of our reason here is correct, because the relationship between the reason and the subject holds when “something made” is used as the reason in a proof that sound is an unchanging thing.
+
The first part of our [[reason]] here is correct, because the relationship between the [[reason]] and the [[subject]] holds when “something made” is used as the [[reason]] in a [[proof]] that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing.
  
Suppose you say that it’s not correct [that the relationship between the reason and the subject holds when "something made" is used as the reason in a proof that sound is an unchanging thing].
+
Suppose you say that it’s not correct [that the relationship between the [[reason]] and the [[subject]] holds when "something made" is used as the [[reason]] in a [[proof]] that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing].
  
 
Consider this same thing [that is, "something made"].
 
Consider this same thing [that is, "something made"].
Line 897: Line 897:
 
The relationship does too hold with it,
 
The relationship does too hold with it,
  
Because it is a contradictory reason for the particular proof.
+
Because it is a [[contradictory]] [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]].
  
And that’s true because it is a correct reason for proving that sound is a changing thing.
+
And that’s true because it is a correct [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is a changing thing.
  
And the second reason is a correct one, because that one thing which is both an existing phenomenon and something which is not momentary satisfies the positive necessity in a proof that sound is an unchanging thing.
+
And the second [[reason]] is a correct one, because that one thing which is both an [[existing]] [[phenomenon]] and something which is not momentary satisfies the positive necessity in a [[proof]] that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing.
  
 
Suppose you say that this is not correct.
 
Suppose you say that this is not correct.
  
Consider this same thing [that one thing which is both an existing phenomenon and something which is not momentary].
+
Consider this same thing [that one thing which is both an [[existing]] [[phenomenon]] and something which is not momentary].
  
 
It does too [satisfy the relationship of positive necessity],
 
It does too [satisfy the relationship of positive necessity],
  
Because (1) there does exist a correct similar example which covers both the reason and the quality to be proven, in this particular proof where that “one thing” we mentioned is used as the reason; and (2) this “one thing” can be verified, through a valid perception, as something that fits only the group of similar cases, in the way it is stated, within a proof that sound is an unchanging thing.
+
Because (1) there does [[exist]] a correct similar example which covers both the [[reason]] and the quality to be proven, in this particular [[proof]] where that “one thing” we mentioned is used as the [[reason]]; and (2) this “one thing” can be verified, through a valid [[perception]], as something that fits only the group of similar cases, in the way it is stated, within a [[proof]] that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing.
  
Now the first part of our reason is correct, because “unproduced, empty space” would be a correct similar example which covers both the reason and the quality to be proven in this particular proof, where the “one thing” we mentioned is used as a reason.
+
Now the first part of our [[reason]] is correct, because “unproduced, [[empty]] [[space]]” would be a correct similar example which covers both the [[reason]] and the quality to be proven in this particular [[proof]], where the “one thing” we mentioned is used as a [[reason]].
  
And the second part of our reason is correct, because “that one thing which is both an existing phenomenon and something which is not momentary” is something that fits only the group of similar cases, in the way it is stated, within this particular proof.
+
And the second part of our [[reason]] is correct, because “that one thing which is both an [[existing]] [[phenomenon]] and something which is not momentary” is something that fits only the group of similar cases, in the way it is stated, within this particular [[proof]].
  
And this is because it is, in fact, the definition of something which is unchanging.
+
And this is because it is, in fact, the [[definition]] of something which is [[unchanging]].
  
The third part of our reason above, [that there exists the reverse necessity for the proof,] is also correct. This is because that one thing which is both (1) an existing phenomenon and (2) something which is not momentary fulfils that same necessity.
+
The third part of our [[reason]] above, [that there [[exists]] the reverse necessity for the [[proof]],] is also correct. This is because that one thing which is both (1) an [[existing]] [[phenomenon]] and (2) something which is not momentary fulfils that same necessity.
  
Now suppose you say that our last reason is not correct. Consider this same thing [that is, that one thing which is both (1) an existing phenomenon and (2) something which is not momentary].
+
Now suppose you say that our last [[reason]] is not correct. Consider this same thing [that is, that one thing which is both (1) an [[existing]] [[phenomenon]] and (2) something which is not momentary].
  
It does so fulfil the reverse necessity for the proof that sound is an unchanging thing,
+
It does so fulfil the reverse necessity for the [[proof]] that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing,
  
Because there does exist a correct dissimilar example for the proof in which it serves as the reason; that is, an example which possesses neither the reason nor the quality to be proven for the particular proof. And it can also be verified, through a valid perception, that it only does not fit the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.
+
Because there does [[exist]] a correct dissimilar example for the [[proof]] in which it serves as the [[reason]]; that is, an example which possesses neither the [[reason]] nor the quality to be proven for the particular [[proof]]. And it can also be verified, through a valid [[perception]], that it only does not fit the group of dissimilar cases for the [[proof]].
  
Suppose finally that you agree to the original statement: [that is, you agree that there must exist a correct reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing].
+
Suppose finally that you agree to the original statement: [that is, you agree that there must [[exist]] a correct [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing].
  
Consider then sound.
+
Consider then [[sound]].
  
It is rather so, that there exists no correct reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing;
+
It is rather so, that there [[exists]] no correct [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing;
  
Because it is not something which is unchanging.
+
Because it is not something which is [[unchanging]].
  
 
_______________
 
_______________
Line 937: Line 937:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
 
Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:
  
It must then be so, that there is something for which all three relationships hold, in proving that sound is an unchanging thing;
+
It must then be so, that there is something for which all three relationships hold, in proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing;
  
Because there is something which fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for this proof; and there is something which fulfils the positive necessity for the proof; and there is something which fulfils the reverse necessity for the proof.
+
Because there is something which fulfils the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] for this [[proof]]; and there is something which fulfils the positive necessity for the [[proof]]; and there is something which fulfils the reverse necessity for the [[proof]].
  
 
To this we reply, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
 
To this we reply, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”
Line 945: Line 945:
 
____________
 
____________
  
Here secondly is our explanation of an indefinite reason; we will proceed first with a definition, and then with the various divisions of this reason. Here is the first of these.
+
Here secondly is our explanation of an indefinite [[reason]]; we will proceed first with a [[definition]], and then with the various divisions of this [[reason]]. Here is the first of these.
  
The following is the definition of an indefinite reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing:
+
The following is the [[definition]] of an indefinite [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing:
  
That one thing for which (1) the relationship between the subject and the reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing does hold; (2) the reverse relationship between the reason and the subject for proving that sound is an unchanging thing does not hold; and (3) the reverse relationship between the reason and the subject for proving that sound is not an unchanging thing doesn’t hold either.
+
That one thing for which (1) the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing does hold; (2) the [[reverse relationship]] between the [[reason]] and the [[subject]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing does not hold; and (3) the [[reverse relationship]] between the [[reason]] and the [[subject]] for proving that [[sound]] is not an [[unchanging]] thing doesn’t hold either.
  
[A classical example would be: Consider sound. It is an unchanging thing, because there is no such thing as antlers on a rabbit's head.]
+
[A classical example would be: Consider [[sound]]. It is an [[unchanging]] thing, because there is no such thing as antlers on a rabbit's head.]
  
Here secondly are the divisions. This kind of reason can be divided into two: unique indefinite reasons for a particular proof, and common indefinite reasons for a particular proof. We will discuss the first of these two in two steps: its definition, and a classical example for it.
+
Here secondly are the divisions. This kind of [[reason]] can be divided into two: unique indefinite [[reasons]] for a particular [[proof]], and common indefinite [[reasons]] for a particular [[proof]]. We will discuss the first of these two in two steps: its [[definition]], and a classical example for it.
  
Here is the first. The definition of something which is a unique indefinite reason for a particular proof is:
+
Here is the first. The [[definition]] of something which is a unique indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]] is:
  
That one thing which is both (1) an indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has yet to verify either one of the following: that it fits the group of similar cases for the proof, or that it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.
+
That one thing which is both (1) an indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]]; and (2) such that a [[person]] who already [[recognizes]] that it fulfils the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]] has yet to verify either one of the following: that it fits the group of similar cases for the [[proof]], or that it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the [[proof]].
  
 
Here secondly are some classical examples.
 
Here secondly are some classical examples.
  
The following are all both unique indefinite reasons for proving that sound is an unchanging thing, and unique indefinite reasons for proving that sound is a changing thing:
+
The following are all both unique indefinite [[reasons]] for proving that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing, and unique indefinite [[reasons]] for proving that [[sound]] is a changing thing:
  
 
something you can hear;
 
something you can hear;
  
the reverse of all that is not sound; and
+
the reverse of all that is not [[sound]]; and
  
the reversal of sound.
+
the [[reversal]] of [[sound]].
  
We will discuss the second type, common indefinite reasons, in two steps as well: definition, and divisions. Here is the first.
+
We will discuss the second type, common indefinite [[reasons]], in two steps as well: [[definition]], and divisions. Here is the first.
  
The definition of a common indefinite reason is:
+
The [[definition]] of a common indefinite [[reason]] is:
  
That one thing which is both (1) an indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has either verified (a) that it fits the group of similar cases for the proof, or (b) that it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.
+
That one thing which is both (1) an indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]]; and (2) such that a [[person]] who already [[recognizes]] that it fulfils the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]] has either verified (a) that it fits the group of similar cases for the [[proof]], or (b) that it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the [[proof]].
  
Here is the second. These types of reasons may be divided into three: those which are direct indefinite reasons for a particular proof; those which are uncertain indefinite reasons for a particular proof; and those indefinite reasons which are neither of the first two. Again we will discuss the first of these in terms of its definition and its divisions.
+
Here is the second. These types of [[reasons]] may be divided into three: those which are direct indefinite [[reasons]] for a particular [[proof]]; those which are uncertain indefinite [[reasons]] for a particular [[proof]]; and those indefinite [[reasons]] which are neither of the first two. Again we will discuss the first of these in terms of its [[definition]] and its divisions.
  
Here is the first. The definition of something which is a direct indefinite reason is:
+
Here is the first. The [[definition]] of something which is a direct indefinite [[reason]] is:
 
[[File:Rahula ordination.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Rahula ordination.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
That one thing which is both (1) an indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has verified that it fits both the group of similar cases and the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.
+
That one thing which is both (1) an indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]]; and (2) such that a [[person]] who already [[recognizes]] that it fulfils the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]] has verified that it fits both the group of similar cases and the group of dissimilar cases for the [[proof]].
  
Here secondly are the divisions of this type of reason. They come in four different types:
+
Here secondly are the divisions of this type of [[reason]]. They come in four different types:
  
1) Those direct indefinite reasons that cover both the group of similar cases and the group of dissimilar cases for the particular proof;
+
1) Those direct indefinite [[reasons]] that cover both the group of similar cases and the group of dissimilar cases for the particular [[proof]];
  
2) Those same kinds of reasons that cover the group of similar cases for the particular proof, but which go both ways as far as its group of dissimilar cases;
+
2) Those same kinds of [[reasons]] that cover the group of similar cases for the particular [[proof]], but which go both ways as far as its group of dissimilar cases;
  
3) Those same kinds of reasons that cover the group of dissimilar cases for the particular proof, but which go both ways as far as its group of similar cases; and
+
3) Those same kinds of [[reasons]] that cover the group of dissimilar cases for the particular [[proof]], but which go both ways as far as its group of similar cases; and
  
4) Those same kinds of reasons that go both ways as far as both the group of dissimilar cases and the group of similar cases for the particular proof.
+
4) Those same kinds of [[reasons]] that go both ways as far as both the group of dissimilar cases and the group of similar cases for the particular [[proof]].
  
 
Here are respective classical examples for each of these types.
 
Here are respective classical examples for each of these types.
  
1) The fact that there are no such things as rabbit antlers would be a direct indefinite reason that covers both the group of similar cases in a proof that sound is an unchanging thing, and the group of dissimilar cases for this same proof.
+
1) The fact that there are no such things as {{Wiki|rabbit}} antlers would be a direct indefinite [[reason]] that covers both the group of similar cases in a [[proof]] that [[sound]] is an [[unchanging]] thing, and the group of dissimilar cases for this same [[proof]].
  
2) “Changing thing” would be a direct indefinite reason that covers the group of similar cases in a proof that the sound of a conch shell is something produced through a conscious effort, but which goes both ways as far as the group of dissimilar cases for this same proof.
+
2) “Changing thing” would be a direct indefinite [[reason]] that covers the group of similar cases in a [[proof]] that the [[sound]] of a [[conch shell]] is something produced through a [[conscious]] [[effort]], but which goes both ways as far as the group of dissimilar cases for this same [[proof]].
  
3) “Changing thing” would be a direct indefinite reason that covers the group of dissimilar cases in a proof that sound of a conch shell is not something produced through a conscious effort, but which goes both ways as far as its group of similar cases.
+
3) “Changing thing” would be a direct indefinite [[reason]] that covers the group of dissimilar cases in a [[proof]] that [[sound]] of a [[conch shell]] is not something produced through a [[conscious]] [[effort]], but which goes both ways as far as its group of similar cases.
  
4) “Sense consciousness” would be a direct indefinite reason that goes both ways as far as both the group of dissimilar cases and the group of similar cases in a proof that a sense consciousness which thinks there are two moons [where there is only one] is a direct [valid] perception.
+
4) “[[Sense]] [[consciousness]]” would be a direct indefinite [[reason]] that goes both ways as far as both the group of dissimilar cases and the group of similar cases in a [[proof]] that a [[sense]] [[consciousness]] which [[thinks]] there are two moons [where there is only one] is a direct [valid] [[perception]].
  
Here secondly is our discussion of uncertain indefinite reasons; we will repeat the two steps of their definition and their divisions. Here is the first.
+
Here secondly is our [[discussion]] of uncertain indefinite [[reasons]]; we will repeat the two steps of their [[definition]] and their divisions. Here is the first.
  
The definition of something’s being an uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof is the following:
+
The [[definition]] of something’s being an uncertain indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]] is the following:
  
That one thing which is both (1) a common indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has either (a) already verified that it fits the group of similar cases for the proof, but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof or not; or else (b) already verified that it does fit the group of dissimilar cases for the proof, but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of similar cases for the proof or not.
+
That one thing which is both (1) a common indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]]; and (2) such that a [[person]] who already [[recognizes]] that it fulfils the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]] has either (a) already verified that it fits the group of similar cases for the [[proof]], but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the [[proof]] or not; or else (b) already verified that it does fit the group of dissimilar cases for the [[proof]], but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of similar cases for the [[proof]] or not.
  
Here secondly are the divisions of this type of reason. There are two: correct uncertain indefinite reasons and contradictory uncertain indefinite reasons.
+
Here secondly are the divisions of this type of [[reason]]. There are two: correct uncertain indefinite [[reasons]] and [[contradictory]] uncertain indefinite [[reasons]].
  
The definition of something’s being a correct uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof is:
+
The [[definition]] of something’s being a correct uncertain indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]] is:
  
That one thing which is both (1) an uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has already verified that it fits the group of similar cases for the proof, but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof or not.
+
That one thing which is both (1) an uncertain indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]]; and (2) such that a [[person]] who already [[recognizes]] that it fulfils the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]] has already verified that it fits the group of similar cases for the [[proof]], but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the [[proof]] or not.
  
The definition of something’s being a contradictory uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof is:
+
The [[definition]] of something’s being a [[contradictory]] uncertain indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]] is:
  
That one thing which is both (1) an uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has already verified that it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof, but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of similar cases for the proof or not.
+
That one thing which is both (1) an uncertain indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]]; and (2) such that a [[person]] who already [[recognizes]] that it fulfils the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]] has already verified that it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the [[proof]], but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of similar cases for the [[proof]] or not.
  
Here are some examples, in the order we gave the definitions. An example of the first would be giving “because he is making pronouncements” as a reason for proving that John, who is making pronouncements, is not an omniscient being—and giving this reason to someone who doubts the existence of an omniscient being.
+
Here are some examples, in the order we gave the definitions. An example of the first would be giving “because he is making pronouncements” as a [[reason]] for proving that John, who is making pronouncements, is not an [[omniscient]] being—and giving this [[reason]] to someone who [[doubts]] the [[existence]] of an [[omniscient]] being.
  
The same reason presented to the same person to prove that John, who is making pronouncements, is an omniscient being would be an example of the second type.
+
The same [[reason]] presented to the same [[person]] to prove that John, who is making pronouncements, is an [[omniscient]] being would be an example of the second type.
  
Here thirdly we’ll explain those common indefinite reasons which are neither the direct nor uncertain types. Again we proceed in terms of definition and classical example.
+
Here thirdly we’ll explain those common indefinite [[reasons]] which are neither the direct nor uncertain types. Again we proceed in terms of [[definition]] and classical example.
  
Here is the first. The definition of something being a common indefinite reason which is neither the direct nor the uncertain types for a particular proof is:
+
Here is the first. The [[definition]] of something being a common indefinite [[reason]] which is neither the direct nor the uncertain types for a particular [[proof]] is:
  
That one thing which is both (1) a common indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has already verified either that it fits only the group of similar cases for the proof, or that it only doesn’t fit the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.
+
That one thing which is both (1) a common indefinite [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]]; and (2) such that a [[person]] who already [[recognizes]] that it fulfils the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] for the particular [[proof]] has already verified either that it fits only the group of similar cases for the [[proof]], or that it only doesn’t fit the group of dissimilar cases for the [[proof]].
  
Here secondly is our classical example. “[Because there is a] taste of sugar in the present time” is a common indefinite reason which is neither the direct nor the uncertain types in a proof that a lump of sugar in one’s mouth has the visible appearance of a lump of sugar in the present time.
+
Here secondly is our classical example. “[Because there is a] {{Wiki|taste}} of sugar in the {{Wiki|present}} [[time]]” is a common indefinite [[reason]] which is neither the direct nor the uncertain types in a [[proof]] that a lump of sugar in one’s {{Wiki|mouth}} has the [[visible]] [[appearance]] of a lump of sugar in the {{Wiki|present}} [[time]].
  
Here third is our presentation on wrong reasons. Again we proceed in two steps of definition and divisions. Here is the first.
+
Here third is our presentation on wrong [[reasons]]. Again we proceed in two steps of [[definition]] and divisions. Here is the first.
  
The definition of a wrong reason for any particular proof is:
+
The [[definition]] of a wrong [[reason]] for any particular [[proof]] is:
  
That which (1) has been put forth as a reason for a particular proof, but (2) for which the relationship between the subject and the reason does not hold.
+
That which (1) has been put forth as a [[reason]] for a particular [[proof]], but (2) for which the relationship between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] does not hold.
  
Here secondly are the divisions of wrong reasons for particular proofs. There are three different types:
+
Here secondly are the divisions of wrong [[reasons]] for particular proofs. There are three different types:
  
1) Reasons which are wrong relative to meaning.
+
1) [[Reasons]] which are wrong [[relative]] to meaning.
  
2) Reasons which are wrong relative to a state of mind.
+
2) [[Reasons]] which are wrong [[relative]] to a [[state of mind]].
  
3) Reasons which are wrong relative to the particular opponent.
+
3) [[Reasons]] which are wrong [[relative]] to the particular opponent.
  
 
The first of these may itself be divided into seven different types:
 
The first of these may itself be divided into seven different types:
  
1) Reasons which are wrong because the very nature of the reason is non-existent.
+
1) [[Reasons]] which are wrong because the very [[nature]] of the [[reason]] is {{Wiki|non-existent}}.
  
2) Reasons which are wrong because the very nature of the subject is non-existent.
+
2) [[Reasons]] which are wrong because the very [[nature]] of the [[subject]] is {{Wiki|non-existent}}.
  
3) Reasons which are wrong because the reason and the quality to be proven are indistinguishable from one another.
+
3) [[Reasons]] which are wrong because the [[reason]] and the quality to be proven are indistinguishable from one another.
  
4) Reasons which are wrong because the subject and the reason are indistinguishable from one another.
+
4) [[Reasons]] which are wrong because the [[subject]] and the [[reason]] are indistinguishable from one another.
  
5) Reasons which are wrong because the subject and the quality to be proven are indistinguishable from one another.
+
5) [[Reasons]] which are wrong because the [[subject]] and the quality to be proven are indistinguishable from one another.
  
6) Reasons which are wrong because the reason does not pertain to the subject in the way it has been said to in the statement of the proof.
+
6) [[Reasons]] which are wrong because the [[reason]] does not pertain to the [[subject]] in the way it has been said to in the statement of the [[proof]].
  
7) Reasons which are wrong because some part of the reason fails to belong to the subject under consideration.
+
7) [[Reasons]] which are wrong because some part of the [[reason]] fails to belong to the [[subject]] under [[consideration]].
  
The following are respective examples of these types of reasons, in particular proofs:
+
The following are respective examples of these types of [[reasons]], in particular proofs:
  
 
1)
 
1)
  
Consider a particular person.
+
Consider a particular [[person]].
  
They are a suffering being,
+
They are a [[suffering]] being,
  
 
Because they have been impaled on a rabbit’s antlers.
 
Because they have been impaled on a rabbit’s antlers.
Line 1,071: Line 1,071:
 
2)
 
2)
  
Consider the antlers on the head of a rabbit.
+
Consider the antlers on the head of a {{Wiki|rabbit}}.
  
 
They are a changing thing,
 
They are a changing thing,
Line 1,079: Line 1,079:
 
3)
 
3)
  
Consider sound.
+
Consider [[sound]].
  
 
It is a changing thing,
 
It is a changing thing,
Line 1,087: Line 1,087:
 
4)
 
4)
  
Consider sound.
+
Consider [[sound]].
  
 
It is a changing thing,
 
It is a changing thing,
  
Because it is sound.
+
Because it is [[sound]].
  
 
5)
 
5)
  
Consider sound.
+
Consider [[sound]].
  
It is sound,
+
It is [[sound]],
  
 
Because it is something which was made.
 
Because it is something which was made.
Line 1,103: Line 1,103:
 
6)
 
6)
  
Consider sound.
+
Consider [[sound]].
  
 
It is a changing thing,
 
It is a changing thing,
  
Because it is something that you see with your eyes.
+
Because it is something that you see with your [[eyes]].
  
 
7)
 
7)
  
Consider a fruit tree.
+
Consider a fruit [[tree]].
  
It must be a conscious thing,
+
It must be a [[conscious]] thing,
  
Because its leaves curl up and night and seem to sleep.
+
Because its leaves curl up and night and seem to [[sleep]].
  
This brings us to the second kind of wrong reason: the one that is wrong relative to a state of mind. Here there are four different types:
+
This brings us to the second kind of wrong [[reason]]: the one that is wrong [[relative]] to a [[state of mind]]. Here there are four different types:
  
1) Reasons that are wrong because the opponent entertains doubt about the very nature of the reason.
+
1) [[Reasons]] that are wrong because the opponent entertains [[doubt]] about the very [[nature]] of the [[reason]].
  
2) Reasons that are wrong because the opponent entertains doubt about the very nature of the subject.
+
2) [[Reasons]] that are wrong because the opponent entertains [[doubt]] about the very [[nature]] of the [[subject]].
  
3) Reasons that are wrong because the opponent entertains doubt about the connection between the subject and the reason.
+
3) [[Reasons]] that are wrong because the opponent entertains [[doubt]] about the connection between the [[subject]] and the [[reason]].
  
4) Reasons that are wrong because there is nothing that the opponent has yet to understand.
+
4) [[Reasons]] that are wrong because there is nothing that the opponent has yet to understand.
  
 
The following are respective examples of these four, for particular proofs.
 
The following are respective examples of these four, for particular proofs.
  
1) The following proof, presented to a person who has yet to confirm to himself that “flesh-eaters” [a kind of ghost] actually exist:
+
1) The following [[proof]], presented to a [[person]] who has yet to confirm to himself that “flesh-eaters” [a kind of [[ghost]]) actually [[exist]]:
  
Consider sound.
+
Consider [[sound]].
  
 
It is a changing thing,
 
It is a changing thing,
  
Because flesh-eaters are something which can be cognized through valid perception.
+
Because flesh-eaters are something which can be [[Wikipedia:Cognition|cognized]] through valid [[perception]].
  
2) The following proof, presented to a person who has yet to confirm to himself that “smell-eaters” [spirits in the bardo or inbetween state] actually exist:
+
2) The following [[proof]], presented to a [[person]] who has yet to confirm to himself that “smell-eaters” ([[spirits]] in the [[bardo]] or inbetween [[state]]) actually [[exist]]:
  
 
Consider the song of the smell-eaters.
 
Consider the song of the smell-eaters.
Line 1,145: Line 1,145:
 
Because it is something that was made.
 
Because it is something that was made.
  
3) The following proof, presented to a person who doesn’t know where a particular peacock is:
+
3) The following [[proof]], presented to a [[person]] who doesn’t know where a particular [[peacock]] is:
  
 
Consider that mountain vale over there.
 
Consider that mountain vale over there.
  
There must be a peacock living there,
+
There must be a [[peacock]] living there,
  
Because we can hear a peacock crowing.
+
Because we can hear a [[peacock]] crowing.
  
4) The following proof, presented to the glorious Dharmakirti:
+
4) The following [[proof]], presented to the glorious [[Dharmakirti]]:
  
Consider sound.
+
Consider [[sound]].
  
 
It is a changing thing,
 
It is a changing thing,
Line 1,161: Line 1,161:
 
Because it is something that was made.
 
Because it is something that was made.
  
Here thirdly is our explanation of reasons which are wrong relative to the particular opponent. There are three different kinds of these reasons:
+
Here thirdly is our explanation of [[reasons]] which are wrong [[relative]] to the particular opponent. There are three different kinds of these [[reasons]]:
  
1) Reasons which are wrong relative to the proponent.
+
1) [[Reasons]] which are wrong [[relative]] to the proponent.
  
2) Reasons which are wrong relative to the opponent.
+
2) [[Reasons]] which are wrong [[relative]] to the opponent.
  
3) Reasons which are wrong relative to both the opponent and the proponent.
+
3) [[Reasons]] which are wrong [[relative]] to both the opponent and the proponent.
  
Here are respective examples for these three types of reasons, in particular proofs.
+
Here are respective examples for these three types of [[reasons]], in particular proofs.
  
1) The following proof, presented to a Buddhist by a Numerist [of member of the Sangkya, a non-Buddhist school of ancient India]:
+
1) The following [[proof]], presented to a [[Buddhist]] by a Numerist [of member of the Sangkya, a [[non-Buddhist]] school of {{Wiki|ancient India}}]:
  
Consider the intellect.
+
Consider the {{Wiki|intellect}}.
  
It is something devoid of mind,
+
It is something devoid of [[mind]],
  
 
Because it is something which starts and stops.
 
Because it is something which starts and stops.
  
2) The following proof, presented to a Buddhist by a member of the Unclothed
+
2) The following [[proof]], presented to a [[Buddhist]] by a member of the Unclothed
  
[or Jain school of ancient India]:
+
[or [[Jain]] school of {{Wiki|ancient India}}]:
  
Consider a fruit tree.
+
Consider a fruit [[tree]].
  
It must have a mind,
+
It must have a [[mind]],
  
Because it dies when you peel its bark.
+
Because it [[dies]] when you peel its bark.
  
3) The following proof, presented to a member of the Rejectionist [Lokayata] school by one of the Unclothed [Jain] school [both non-Buddhist groups of ancient India]:
+
3) The following [[proof]], presented to a member of the Rejectionist ([[Wikipedia:Cārvāka|Lokayata]]) school by one of the Unclothed ([[Jain]]) school [both [[non-Buddhist]] groups of {{Wiki|ancient India}}]:
  
Consider sound.
+
Consider [[sound]].
  
 
It is a changing thing,
 
It is a changing thing,
  
Because it is something you see with your eyes.
+
Because it is something you see with your [[eyes]].
  
 
***************
 
***************
Line 1,201: Line 1,201:
 
   
 
   
  
The forms of debate:
+
The [[forms]] of [[debate]]:
  
The traditional debate year
+
The [[traditional]] [[debate]] year
  
 
   
 
   
  
The following annual calendar for Sera Mey Tibetan Monastery gives a good picture of the schedule of study followed by all monks in the geshe program at the monastery. It is a traditional schedule which developed at the original Sera Mey in Lhasa, Tibet, over the centuries; since the rebuilding of Sera Mey in south India, the schedule has been reinstated—with a certain number of variations from the one used in Tibet—and is now followed closely, with some exceptions due to the need to work in the monastery cornfields and so on. Below is a translation of the annual calendar as it is currently posted on at the main temple of the monastery; the notes and some amendations to the calendar were completed with the help of Khen Rinpoche Geshe Lobsang Tharchin, a former abbot of the monastery.
+
The following annual [[calendar]] for [[Sera Mey]] [[Tibetan]] [[Monastery]] gives a good picture of the schedule of study followed by all [[monks]] in the [[geshe]] program at the [[monastery]]. It is a [[traditional]] schedule which developed at the original [[Sera Mey]] in [[Lhasa]], [[Tibet]], over the centuries; since the rebuilding of [[Sera Mey]] in [[south]] [[India]], the schedule has been reinstated—with a certain number of variations from the one used in Tibet—and is now followed closely, with some exceptions due to the need to work in the [[monastery]] cornfields and so on. Below is a translation of the annual [[calendar]] as it is currently posted on at the main [[temple]] of the [[monastery]]; the notes and some amendations to the [[calendar]] were completed with the help of [[Khen Rinpoche]] [[Geshe]] Lobsang [[Tharchin]], a former [[abbot]] of the [[monastery]].
  
 
_______________
 
_______________
Line 1,213: Line 1,213:
 
   
 
   
  
Annual Calendar of Debates, Examinations, and Other Special Events at Sera Mey Tibetan Monastery Bylakuppe, South India Schedule of Regular Dharma Sessions
+
Annual [[Calendar]] of [[Debates]], Examinations, and Other Special Events at [[Sera Mey]] [[Tibetan]] [[Monastery]] {{Wiki|Bylakuppe}}, {{Wiki|South India}} Schedule of Regular [[Dharma]] Sessions
  
 
   
 
   
  
The following are the eight traditional “dharma sessions” (chos-thog) that make up the standard periods of monastic study at Sera Mey Monastery. The first Tibetan month, by the way, normally falls in February or March of the western calendar. The dates below are the same for any given year, independent of the day of the week, and follow the waxing and waning of the moon.
+
The following are the eight [[traditional]] “[[dharma]] sessions” (chos-thog) that make up the standard periods of [[monastic]] study at [[Sera Mey Monastery]]. The first [[Tibetan]] month, by the way, normally falls in February or March of the {{Wiki|western}} [[calendar]]. The dates below are the same for any given year, {{Wiki|independent}} of the day of the week, and follow the waxing and waning of the [[moon]].
  
 
   
 
   
  
Session One: The Earlier Dharma Session of Spring (dPyid-chos dang-po)
+
Session One: The Earlier [[Dharma]] Session of Spring (dPyid-chos dang-po)
  
Starting assembly: 26th of the first Tibetan month
+
Starting assembly: 26th of the first [[Tibetan]] month
  
First firewood break: 27th and 28th of the first Tibetan month
+
First firewood break: 27th and 28th of the first [[Tibetan]] month
  
The “firewood break” (shing-slong), or literally “time for requesting firewood from sponsors” follows immediately after the starting assembly (yar-tsogs).
+
The “firewood break” (shing-slong), or literally “[[time]] for requesting firewood from sponsors” follows immediately after the starting assembly (yar-tsogs).
  
This assembly features prayers for the success of the session, and is attended by all monks who intend to participate for this period. It is also during this assembly that young monks who have been deemed ready by the abbot, the debate master, and their house teacher undergo the ceremony of intitiation into the debate park. These “newbies” are known as sarshuk (gsar-zhugs), or “newly entered.” They are expected to demonstrate their commitment to the debate session through perfect attendance, and especially serious study and debate, for the entire length of the session.
+
This assembly features [[prayers]] for the [[success]] of the session, and is attended by all [[monks]] who intend to participate for this period. It is also during this assembly that young [[monks]] who have been deemed ready by the [[abbot]], the [[debate]] [[master]], and their house [[teacher]] undergo the {{Wiki|ceremony}} of intitiation into the [[debate]] park. These “newbies” are known as sarshuk (gsar-zhugs), or “newly entered.” They are expected to demonstrate their commitment to the [[debate]] session through {{Wiki|perfect}} attendance, and especially serious study and [[debate]], for the entire length of the session.
  
In Lhasa, a head-count was taken during the starting assembly in order to determine the cooking and other needs. During the next two days, teams of monks would go out to help find firewood for the monastery kitchen, based on the head-count.
+
In [[Lhasa]], a head-count was taken during the starting assembly in order to determine the cooking and other needs. During the next two days, teams of [[monks]] would go out to help find firewood for the [[monastery]] kitchen, based on the head-count.
  
The first day of the firewood break was devoted to visiting lay communities in the countryside outside of Lhasa city to ask for firewood; families in these villages knew what day to expect the monks, and considered it an honor to prepare a good supply of wood in advance. On the second day the monks would travel to Lhasa city proper to request fuel. This supply of wood would have to last about two weeks, until the “mid-term firewood break” (rked-pa’i shing-slong).
+
The first day of the firewood break was devoted to visiting lay communities in the countryside outside of [[Lhasa]] city to ask for firewood; families in these villages knew what day to expect the [[monks]], and considered it an {{Wiki|honor}} to prepare a good supply of [[wood]] in advance. On the second day the [[monks]] would travel to [[Lhasa]] city proper to request fuel. This supply of [[wood]] would have to last about two weeks, until the “mid-term firewood break” (rked-pa’i shing-slong).
  
Great debate examinations: tsokrampa geshe examinations, 28th to the 30th of the first Tibetan month
+
Great [[debate]] examinations: tsokrampa [[geshe]] examinations, 28th to the 30th of the first [[Tibetan]] month
  
During specific sessions, intense debate examinations are held for candidates standing for various degrees at the monastery. The most well known of these degree titles is the geshe. The word “geshe” (kalyaNa mitra in Sanskrit, or dge-bshes in Tibetan) literally means “spiritual friend,” and is a term from the earliest days of Buddhism in India. Later, great masters among the first Tibetan Buddhists—the Kadampas—were called “geshe” out of respect for their learning and high level of practice.
+
During specific sessions, intense [[debate]] examinations are held for candidates [[standing]] for various degrees at the [[monastery]]. The most well known of these [[degree]] titles is the [[geshe]]. The [[word]] “[[geshe]]” (kalyaNa [[mitra]] in [[Sanskrit]], or [[dge-bshes]] in [[Tibetan]]) literally means “[[spiritual friend]],” and is a term from the earliest days of [[Buddhism]] in [[India]]. Later, great [[masters]] among the first [[Tibetan]] Buddhists—the Kadampas—were called “[[geshe]]” out of [[respect]] for their {{Wiki|learning}} and high level of [[practice]].
  
As monastic institutions began to form in Tibet, the word “geshe” came to be used as a title. It was originally used in the early “Big Three” monasteries of Sangpu (gSang-phu), Kyormo Lung (sKyor-mo lung), and Gadong (sGagdong). Sangpu, for example, was founded around the middle of the eleventh century.
+
As [[monastic]] {{Wiki|institutions}} began to [[form]] in [[Tibet]], the [[word]] “[[geshe]]” came to be used as a title. It was originally used in the early “Big Three” [[monasteries]] of [[Sangpu]] (gSang-phu), [[Kyormo Lung]] (sKyor-mo lung), and Gadong (sGagdong). [[Sangpu]], for example, was founded around the middle of the eleventh century.
  
Sangpu had two colleges within the confines (or gseb) of the monastery as a whole (known as the gling); early geshe candidates had to make their debate defense at a combined assembly of the two, and came to be known as lingse geshes, a corruption of the word lingsep (gling-gseb). The Great Dictionary of the Tibetan Language and other sources take the word lingse to mean gling-bsre, or a defense before the “combined” (bsre) assemblies of the two colleges in the monastery (gling). In either case, the point is the same.
+
[[Sangpu]] had two {{Wiki|colleges}} within the confines (or gseb) of the [[monastery]] as a whole (known as the gling); early [[geshe]] candidates had to make their [[debate]] defense at a combined assembly of the two, and came to be known as lingse [[geshes]], a corruption of the [[word]] [[lingsep]] (gling-gseb). The Great {{Wiki|Dictionary}} of the [[Tibetan Language]] and other sources take the [[word]] lingse to mean gling-bsre, or a defense before the “combined” (bsre) assemblies of the two {{Wiki|colleges}} in the [[monastery]] (gling). In either case, the point is the same.
  
At Sera Mey, there are typically four lingse geshe degrees conferred per year: these come in two pairs known as the “summer lingse” and the “winter lingse.” Geshes of this rank go through an examination process within their own monastery, as described in a previous reading for this course. During some of their defenses, these and other geshe candidates are required to provide an elaborate series of refreshments, involving some served to the entire assembly of their monastery. This ceremony is known as the “Thirteen-Course Tea and Broth” (Ja-thug bcu-gsum).
+
At [[Sera Mey]], there are typically four lingse [[geshe]] degrees conferred per year: these come in two pairs known as the “summer lingse” and the “winter lingse.” [[Geshes]] of this rank go through an {{Wiki|examination}} process within their [[own]] [[monastery]], as described in a previous reading for this course. During some of their defenses, these and other [[geshe]] candidates are required to provide an elaborate series of refreshments, involving some served to the entire assembly of their [[monastery]]. This {{Wiki|ceremony}} is known as the “Thirteen-Course Tea and Broth” (Ja-thug bcu-gsum).
  
During other defenses, lingse candidates need only provide a series of ten tea offerings on the day when they undergo a special part of their examination which involves reciting a great many pages of scripture from memory. This test is called a geshe shepa (dge-bshes bshad-pa); and since the major refreshments of tea and broth are not served to the entire assembly this time, the presentation is known as a “dry recitation” (skam-bshad).
+
During other defenses, lingse candidates need only provide a series of ten tea [[offerings]] on the day when they undergo a special part of their {{Wiki|examination}} which involves reciting a great many pages of [[scripture]] from [[memory]]. This test is called a [[geshe]] shepa ([[dge-bshes]] bshad-pa); and since the major refreshments of tea and broth are not served to the entire assembly this [[time]], the presentation is known as a “dry {{Wiki|recitation}}” (skam-bshad).
  
Below the rank of lingse geshe is the rikrampa (rigs rams-pa), and the next higher rank after the lingse is the tsokrampa (tsogs rams-pa). In both cases, the word rampa refers to the veritable myriad (rab-’byams, shortened to rams-pa) number of great Buddhist classics that a geshe must master. The word tsok in tsokrampa refers to the Session of the Great Assembly (Tsogschos), an annual meeting in Lhasa city of the six great colleges. Here there are two each for the “Great Three” monasteries of later times: Sera, Ganden, and Drepung, all founded around the opening of the fifteenth century. Representatives from Deyang (bDe-yangs) monastery would also attend this gathering, during which the candidates for the tsokrampa rank would have to defend their knowledge.
+
Below the rank of lingse [[geshe]] is the [[rikrampa]] ([[rigs]] rams-pa), and the next higher rank after the lingse is the tsokrampa ([[tsogs]] rams-pa). In both cases, the [[word]] rampa refers to the veritable {{Wiki|myriad}} (rab-’byams, shortened to rams-pa) number of great [[Buddhist]] classics that a [[geshe]] must [[master]]. The [[word]] [[tsok]] in tsokrampa refers to the Session of the [[Great Assembly]] (Tsogschos), an annual meeting in [[Lhasa]] city of the six great {{Wiki|colleges}}. Here there are two each for the “Great Three” [[monasteries]] of later times: [[Sera]], [[Ganden]], and [[Drepung]], all founded around the opening of the fifteenth century. Representatives from [[Deyang]] (bDe-yangs) [[monastery]] would also attend this [[gathering]], during which the candidates for the tsokrampa rank would have to defend their [[knowledge]].
 
[[File:Relig.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Relig.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
The Great Assembly traditionally began on the 20th of the second Tibetan month, and ended on the 30th. This is the time it would take to complete the examination of one or two tsokrampa candidates from each college per year. Candidates for the highest rank of geshe, the hlarampa (hla rams-pa), are examined during the Great Prayer Festival, or Munlam Chenmo. This festival was instituted by Je Tsongkapa in the 15th century as a great dharma celebration for the New Year. Since it was held in the capital city of Lhasa
+
The [[Great Assembly]] [[traditionally]] began on the 20th of the second [[Tibetan]] month, and ended on the 30th. This is the [[time]] it would take to complete the {{Wiki|examination}} of one or two tsokrampa candidates from each {{Wiki|college}} per year. Candidates for the [[highest]] rank of [[geshe]], the hlarampa ([[hla]] rams-pa), are examined during the [[Great Prayer Festival]], or Munlam Chenmo. This {{Wiki|festival}} was instituted by [[Je Tsongkapa]] in the 15th century as a great [[dharma]] celebration for the New Year. Since it was held in the {{Wiki|capital city}} of [[Lhasa]]
  
(Hla-sa), these geshes became known as hlarampa. Each of the six colleges normally nominates two candidates per year for the rank of hlarampa, although on some occasions it may be as many as four.
+
([[Hla-sa]]), these [[geshes]] became known as hlarampa. Each of the six {{Wiki|colleges}} normally nominates two candidates per year for the rank of hlarampa, although on some occasions it may be as many as four.
  
First actual debate session: begins 1st of the second Tibetan month
+
First actual [[debate]] session: begins 1st of the second [[Tibetan]] month
  
Mid-term firewood break: 5th and 6th of the second Tibetan month
+
Mid-term firewood break: 5th and 6th of the second [[Tibetan]] month
  
Second actual debate session: begins 7th of the second Tibetan month
+
Second actual [[debate]] session: begins 7th of the second [[Tibetan]] month
  
Auspicious conclusion: 18th of the second Tibetan month
+
[[Auspicious]] conclusion: 18th of the second [[Tibetan]] month
  
The “Auspicious Conclusion” (Shis-brjod) is a day of prayer and celebration for the successful end of another dharma session; it is marked by special recitations known as “pronouncing” (brjod) the “auspiciousness” (bkra-shis, the “trashi” in “trashi delek”). These prayers are done in a unique melody or yang (dbyangs). On this day too, the abbot of the monastery will often deliver a special dharma teaching.
+
The “[[Auspicious]] Conclusion” (Shis-brjod) is a day of [[prayer]] and celebration for the successful end of another [[dharma]] session; it is marked by special recitations known as “pronouncing” (brjod) the “auspiciousness” (bkra-shis, the “trashi” in “trashi delek”). These [[prayers]] are done in a unique melody or [[yang]] (dbyangs). On this day too, the [[abbot]] of the [[monastery]] will often deliver a special [[dharma]] [[teaching]].
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,267: Line 1,267:
 
Intersession break (Chos-mtsams):
 
Intersession break (Chos-mtsams):
  
19th of the second Tibetan month to the 7th of the third Tibetan month
+
19th of the second [[Tibetan]] month to the 7th of the third [[Tibetan]] month
  
Session Two: The Great Dharma Session of Spring (dPyid-chos chen-mo)
+
Session Two: The Great [[Dharma]] Session of Spring (dPyid-chos chen-mo)
  
Starting assembly: 8th of the third Tibetan month
+
Starting assembly: 8th of the third [[Tibetan]] month
  
First firewood break: 9th and 10th of the third Tibetan month
+
First firewood break: 9th and 10th of the third [[Tibetan]] month
  
Great debate examinations: summer lingse geshes, 11th to the 12th of the third Tibetan month
+
Great [[debate]] examinations: summer lingse [[geshes]], 11th to the 12th of the third [[Tibetan]] month
  
First actual debate session: begins 13th of the third Tibetan month
+
First actual [[debate]] session: begins 13th of the third [[Tibetan]] month
  
Mid-term firewood break: 22nd and 23rd of the third Tibetan month
+
Mid-term firewood break: 22nd and 23rd of the third [[Tibetan]] month
  
Second actual debate session: begins 24th of the third Tibetan month
+
Second actual [[debate]] session: begins 24th of the third [[Tibetan]] month
  
Auspicious conclusion: 7th of the fourth Tibetan month
+
[[Auspicious]] conclusion: 7th of the fourth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,289: Line 1,289:
 
Intersession break:
 
Intersession break:
  
8th of the fourth Tibetan month to the 16th of the fourth
+
8th of the fourth [[Tibetan]] month to the 16th of the fourth
  
Tibetan month
+
[[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
  
Session Three: The Earlier Summer Dharma Session (dByar-chos dang-po)
+
Session Three: The Earlier Summer [[Dharma]] Session (dByar-chos dang-po)
  
Starting assembly: 17th of the fourth Tibetan month
+
Starting assembly: 17th of the fourth [[Tibetan]] month
  
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the fourth Tibetan month
+
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the fourth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Great debate examinations: (no geshe debates)
+
Great [[debate]] examinations: (no [[geshe]] [[debates]])
  
First actual debate session: begins 20th of the fourth Tibetan month
+
First actual [[debate]] session: begins 20th of the fourth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
Mid-term firewood break: (none)
 
Mid-term firewood break: (none)
  
Second actual debate session: (none)
+
Second actual [[debate]] session: (none)
  
Auspicious conclusion: 1st of the fifth Tibetan month
+
[[Auspicious]] conclusion: 1st of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
  
Intersession break: 2nd of the fifth Tibetan month to the 16th of the fifth Tibetan month
+
Intersession break: 2nd of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month to the 16th of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
  
Session Four: The Great Dharma Session of Summer (dByar-chos chen-mo)
+
Session Four: The Great [[Dharma]] Session of Summer (dByar-chos chen-mo)
  
Starting assembly: 17th of the fifth Tibetan month
+
Starting assembly: 17th of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month
  
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the fifth Tibetan month
+
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Great debate examinations: summer lingse geshes (“dry recitation”) and rikram
+
Great [[debate]] examinations: summer lingse [[geshes]] (“dry {{Wiki|recitation}}”) and [[rikram]]
  
geshes; 20th to the 23rd of the fifth Tibetan month
+
[[geshes]]; 20th to the 23rd of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month
  
First actual debate session: begins 24th of the fifth Tibetan month
+
First actual [[debate]] session: begins 24th of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Mid-term firewood break: 2nd and 3rd of the sixth Tibetan month
+
Mid-term firewood break: 2nd and 3rd of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Second actual debate session: begins 4th of the sixth Tibetan month
+
Second actual [[debate]] session: begins 4th of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Auspicious conclusion: 15th of the sixth Tibetan month
+
[[Auspicious]] conclusion: 15th of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,339: Line 1,339:
 
Intersession break:
 
Intersession break:
  
16th of the sixth Tibetan month to the 16th of the seventh Tibetan month; includes rikram geshe exams, summer lingse geshe exams, rikchung pre-geshe exams, and rikdra inter-monastic debates
+
16th of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month to the 16th of the seventh [[Tibetan]] month; includes [[rikram]] [[geshe]] exams, summer lingse [[geshe]] exams, rikchung pre-geshe exams, and rikdra inter-monastic [[debates]]
  
The rikdra (rigs-grva) inter-monastic debates begin on the last day of the sixth Tibetan month and last until the 15th day of the seventh Tibetan month. During this time, thirty debaters from Sera Mey debate with thirty counterparts from the sister monastery of Sera Jey in the main assembly hall (tsogs-chen) shared by both monasteries for major events such as the biweekly monks’ purification ceremony, or sojong (gso-sbyong).
+
The rikdra (rigs-grva) inter-monastic [[debates]] begin on the last day of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month and last until the 15th day of the seventh [[Tibetan]] month. During this [[time]], thirty [[debaters]] from [[Sera Mey]] [[debate]] with thirty counterparts from the sister [[monastery]] of [[Sera Jey]] in the main assembly hall (tsogs-chen) shared by both [[monasteries]] for major events such as the biweekly [[monks]]’ [[purification]] {{Wiki|ceremony}}, or [[sojong]] (gso-sbyong).
  
During this time, pairs of debaters match off twice a day, once in the morning and once in the evening, for fifteen days. In a typical session, the proponent (snga-rgol) will be responsible for a lengthy recitation of scripture from memory, after which his opponent (phyi-rgol) is charged with posing a difficult series of formalized debate questions. In Tibet, the combined monasteries of Sera Mey and Sera Jey had joint holdings of property, and the income from these would be used during this session to supply all the monks attending with gifts of Tibetan pastries (kabse) and roasted barley flour, or tsampa.
+
During this [[time]], pairs of [[debaters]] match off twice a day, once in the morning and once in the evening, for fifteen days. In a typical session, the proponent (snga-rgol) will be responsible for a lengthy {{Wiki|recitation}} of [[scripture]] from [[memory]], after which his opponent (phyi-rgol) is charged with posing a difficult series of formalized [[debate]] questions. [[In Tibet]], the combined [[monasteries]] of [[Sera Mey]] and [[Sera Jey]] had joint holdings of property, and the income from these would be used during this session to supply all the [[monks]] attending with gifts of [[Tibetan]] pastries (kabse) and roasted {{Wiki|barley}} flour, or [[tsampa]].
  
It is also during this time that the rikchen (rigs-chen), or advanced pre-geshe debates, are held. Here a student who intends to take a higher geshe degree engages in a difficult and highly formalized debate against a similar candidate from the sister monastery. Other students in the monastery during this time are engaged in special examinations, administered by the abbot and debate master of their home monastery, during which they are required to recite, from memory, about 100 pages of scripture.
+
It is also during this [[time]] that the rikchen (rigs-chen), or advanced pre-geshe [[debates]], are held. Here a [[student]] who intends to take a higher [[geshe]] [[degree]] engages in a difficult and highly formalized [[debate]] against a similar candidate from the sister [[monastery]]. Other students in the [[monastery]] during this [[time]] are engaged in special examinations, administered by the [[abbot]] and [[debate]] [[master]] of their home [[monastery]], during which they are required to recite, from [[memory]], about 100 pages of [[scripture]].
  
 
   
 
   
  
Session Five: The Water Dharma Session (Chab-zhugs chos-thog)
+
Session Five: The [[Water]] [[Dharma]] Session (Chab-zhugs chos-thog)
  
Starting assembly: 17th of the seventh Tibetan month
+
Starting assembly: 17th of the seventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the seventh Tibetan month
+
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the seventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
Great debate examinations: (no geshe debates)
+
Great [[debate]] examinations: (no [[geshe]] [[debates]])
  
First actual debate session: begins 20th of the seventh Tibetan month
+
First actual [[debate]] session: begins 20th of the seventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
Mid-term firewood break: (none)
 
Mid-term firewood break: (none)
  
Second actual debate session: (none)
+
Second actual [[debate]] session: (none)
  
Auspicious conclusion: 30th of the seventh Tibetan month
+
[[Auspicious]] conclusion: 30th of the seventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
The “Water” Session (Chab-zhugs) is possibly given this name due to the fact that, during the period following the especially intense Great Session of Summer, students in the geshe program finally have enough time to relax and “enter the water” (chabzhugs), or take a nice slow bath. The rikchung and rikchen (preliminary and advanced pre-geshe debates) have been completed, as have the grueling rikdra intermonastic debates, and memorization exams. Students would be allowed take breaks in special parks throughout out the monastery, and traditional folk-dance troupes would come there at times, to perform the “goddess” plays (lha-mo).
+
The “[[Water]]” Session (Chab-zhugs) is possibly given this [[name]] due to the fact that, during the period following the especially intense Great Session of Summer, students in the [[geshe]] program finally have enough [[time]] to [[relax]] and “enter the [[water]]” (chabzhugs), or take a nice slow bath. The rikchung and rikchen (preliminary and advanced pre-geshe [[debates]]) have been completed, as have the grueling rikdra intermonastic [[debates]], and [[memorization]] exams. Students would be allowed take breaks in special parks throughout out the [[monastery]], and [[traditional]] folk-dance troupes would come there at times, to perform the “[[goddess]]” plays ([[lha-mo]]).
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,371: Line 1,371:
 
Intersession break:
 
Intersession break:
  
1st of the eighth Tibetan month to the 7th of the eighth
+
1st of the eighth [[Tibetan]] month to the 7th of the eighth
  
Tibetan month; this is the main “water break”
+
[[Tibetan]] month; this is the main “[[water]] break”
  
 
   
 
   
  
Session Six: The Dharma Session of Medicine Buddha (sMan-bla chos-thog)
+
Session Six: The [[Dharma]] Session of [[Medicine Buddha]] (sMan-bla chos-thog)
  
Starting assembly: 8th of the eighth Tibetan month
+
Starting assembly: 8th of the eighth [[Tibetan]] month
  
First firewood break: 9th and 10th of the eighth Tibetan month
+
First firewood break: 9th and 10th of the eighth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Great debate examinations: (no geshe debates)
+
Great [[debate]] examinations: (no [[geshe]] [[debates]])
  
First actual debate session: begins 11th of the eighth Tibetan month
+
First actual [[debate]] session: begins 11th of the eighth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Mid-term firewood break: 22nd and 23rd of the eighth Tibetan month
+
Mid-term firewood break: 22nd and 23rd of the eighth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Second actual debate session: begins 24th of the eighth Tibetan month
+
Second actual [[debate]] session: begins 24th of the eighth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Auspicious conclusion: 7th of the ninth Tibetan month
+
[[Auspicious]] conclusion: 7th of the ninth [[Tibetan]] month
  
This session takes its name from the fact that an extensive Medicine Buddha rite is held on the 11th of the eighth month.
+
This session takes its [[name]] from the fact that an extensive [[Medicine Buddha]] [[rite]] is held on the 11th of the eighth month.
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,399: Line 1,399:
 
Intersession break:
 
Intersession break:
  
8th of the ninth Tibetan month to the 16th of the ninth Tibetan month
+
8th of the ninth [[Tibetan]] month to the 16th of the ninth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
  
Session Seven: The Great Dharma Session of Autumn (sTon-chos chen-mo)
+
Session Seven: The Great [[Dharma]] Session of Autumn (sTon-chos chen-mo)
  
Starting assembly: 17th of the ninth Tibetan month
+
Starting assembly: 17th of the ninth [[Tibetan]] month
  
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the ninth Tibetan month
+
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the ninth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Great debate examinations: winter lingse geshe examinations, 20th and 21st of the ninth Tibetan month
+
Great [[debate]] examinations: winter lingse [[geshe]] examinations, 20th and 21st of the ninth [[Tibetan]] month
  
First actual debate session: begins 22nd of the ninth Tibetan month
+
First actual [[debate]] session: begins 22nd of the ninth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Mid-term firewood break: 2nd and 3rd of the tenth Tibetan month
+
Mid-term firewood break: 2nd and 3rd of the tenth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Second actual debate session: begins 4th of the tenth Tibetan month
+
Second actual [[debate]] session: begins 4th of the tenth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Auspicious conclusion: 16th of the tenth Tibetan month
+
[[Auspicious]] conclusion: 16th of the tenth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,423: Line 1,423:
 
Intersession break:
 
Intersession break:
  
17th of the tenth Tibetan month to the 16th of the eleventh Tibetan month
+
17th of the tenth [[Tibetan]] month to the 16th of the eleventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
  
Session Eight: The Great Dharma Session of Winter (dGun-chos chen-mo)
+
Session Eight: The Great [[Dharma]] Session of Winter (dGun-chos chen-mo)
  
Starting assembly: 17th of the eleventh Tibetan month
+
Starting assembly: 17th of the eleventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the eleventh Tibetan month
+
First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the eleventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
The great examinations: 20th to the 23rd of the eleventh Tibetan month; debate examinations for the winter lingse geshes and hlarampa geshes, the former presenting their “dry recitation”
+
The great examinations: 20th to the 23rd of the eleventh [[Tibetan]] month; [[debate]] examinations for the winter lingse [[geshes]] and hlarampa [[geshes]], the former presenting their “dry {{Wiki|recitation}}”
  
First actual debate session: begins 24th of the eleventh Tibetan month
+
First actual [[debate]] session: begins 24th of the eleventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
Mid-term firewood break: 12th and 13th of the twelfth Tibetan month
+
Mid-term firewood break: 12th and 13th of the twelfth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Second actual debate session: begins 14th of the twelfth Tibetan month
+
Second actual [[debate]] session: begins 14th of the twelfth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Auspicious conclusion: 16th of the twelfth Tibetan month
+
[[Auspicious]] conclusion: 16th of the twelfth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,447: Line 1,447:
 
Intersession break
 
Intersession break
  
This break features further examination of winter lingse geshes, the Tibetan New Year, and the Great Prayer Festival; it begins on the 17th of the twelfth Tibetan month and ends on the 25th of the first Tibetan month.
+
This break features further {{Wiki|examination}} of winter lingse [[geshes]], the [[Tibetan New Year]], and the [[Great Prayer Festival]]; it begins on the 17th of the twelfth [[Tibetan]] month and ends on the 25th of the first [[Tibetan]] month.
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,453: Line 1,453:
 
Annual Special Events
 
Annual Special Events
  
Passing On of Kedrup Tenpa Dargye (mKhas-grub dgongs-rdzogs)
+
Passing On of [[Kedrup Tenpa Dargye]] ([[mKhas-grub]] dgongs-rdzogs)
  
14th day of the fifth Tibetan month
+
14th day of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Kedrup Tenpa Dargye (1493-1568) was an illustrious scholar from Sera Mey who wrote many of the monastery’s textbooks. On special days like this, the monastery will be covered at night in strings of brightly colored electric lights that look like our Christmas-tree lights.
+
[[Kedrup Tenpa Dargye]] (1493-1568) was an illustrious [[scholar]] from [[Sera Mey]] who wrote many of the [[monastery’s]] textbooks. On special days like this, the [[monastery]] will be covered at night in strings of brightly colored electric lights that look like our Christmas-tree lights.
  
 
   
 
   
  
Summer Offering to the Two Dharma Protectors (Chos-skyong rnam-gnyis kyi dbyar-gsol)
+
Summer [[Offering]] to the Two [[Dharma Protectors]] ([[Chos-skyong]] rnam-gnyis kyi dbyar-gsol)
  
15th day of the fifth Tibetan month
+
15th day of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month
  
This particular day every year is known throughout Tibet as the “Day of Auspiciousness throughout the World” (‘Dzam-gling spyi-bzang). At Sera Mey, the occasion is used as an opportunity to thank the dharma protectors of the monastery for their help, and to request that they continue their sacred deeds. The two protectors here are Chamsing (lCam-sring) and Taok (Tha-’og). The protector Chamsing is shared with other monasteries, while Taok is a unique protector for Sera Mey. Please note that these two protectors have nothing to do with the current dharma protector controversy.
+
This particular day every year is known throughout [[Tibet]] as the “Day of Auspiciousness throughout the [[World]]” (‘Dzam-gling spyi-bzang). At [[Sera Mey]], the [[occasion]] is used as an opportunity to thank the [[dharma protectors]] of the [[monastery]] for their help, and to request that they continue their [[sacred]] [[deeds]]. The two [[protectors]] here are Chamsing (lCam-sring) and Taok (Tha-’og). The [[protector]] Chamsing is shared with other [[monasteries]], while Taok is a unique [[protector]] for [[Sera Mey]]. Please note that these two [[protectors]] have nothing to do with the current [[dharma protector]] [[controversy]].
  
 
   
 
   
  
Rikchung (Pre-Geshe Degree) Debates
+
Rikchung (Pre-Geshe [[Degree]]) [[Debates]]
  
25th to the 28th of the sixth Tibetan month
+
25th to the 28th of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,477: Line 1,477:
 
First team
 
First team
  
Proponent takes the subject “Turning of the Wheel,” opponent takes “Book of Maitreya”: 25th of the sixth Tibetan month
+
Proponent takes the [[subject]] “Turning of the [[Wheel]],” opponent takes “[[Book]] of [[Maitreya]]”: 25th of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month
  
Each of the subjects mentioned here are important topics from the Ornament of Realizations, spoken to the realized being Asanga by Lord Maitreya around 350 AD.
+
Each of the [[subjects]] mentioned here are important topics from the Ornament of Realizations, spoken to the [[realized]] being [[Asanga]] by [[Lord Maitreya]] around 350 AD.
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,485: Line 1,485:
 
Second team
 
Second team
  
Proponent takes “Sutra and Commentary,” opponent takes “Final End”: 26th of the sixth Tibetan month
+
Proponent takes “[[Sutra]] and Commentary,” opponent takes “Final End”: 26th of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,491: Line 1,491:
 
Third team
 
Third team
  
Proponent takes “Wish for Enlightenment,” opponent takes “Path of Preparation”: 27th of the sixth Tibetan month
+
Proponent takes “Wish for [[Enlightenment]],” opponent takes “[[Path]] of Preparation”: 27th of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,497: Line 1,497:
 
Fourth team
 
Fourth team
  
Proponent takes “Three Refuges,” opponent takes “Buddha Nature”: 28th of the sixth Tibetan month
+
Proponent takes “[[Three Refuges]],” opponent takes “[[Buddha Nature]]”: 28th of the sixth [[Tibetan]] month
 
[[File:Rice2.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Rice2.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
   
 
   
Line 1,503: Line 1,503:
 
Summer Examinations
 
Summer Examinations
  
8th of the seventh Tibetan month
+
8th of the seventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
  
Extensive Medicine Buddha Rite
+
Extensive [[Medicine Buddha]] [[Rite]]
  
11th of the eighth Tibetan month
+
11th of the eighth [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,515: Line 1,515:
 
Great Winter Examinations
 
Great Winter Examinations
  
8th of the eleventh Tibetan month
+
8th of the eleventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
 
   
 
   
  
Assembly of the Great Offering Ceremony for the Prayer of Maitreya
+
Assembly of the Great [[Offering]] {{Wiki|Ceremony}} for the [[Prayer]] of [[Maitreya]]
  
(Byams-smon sgrub-mchod chen-mo yar-tsogs) 25th of the eleventh Tibetan month
+
(Byams-smon sgrub-mchod chen-mo yar-tsogs) 25th of the eleventh [[Tibetan]] month
  
Khen Rinpoche notes that, in Tibet, this entire ceremony took nearly a month. The 17th of the eleventh month marks the opening ceremony for the session, and is followed by two days of a firewood break. The 20th and 21st are marked by the “dry recitations” for the winter lingshe geshes, and then the next three days are examinations for the hlarampa candidates. Finally, on the 25th, the actual prayer begins: all of the monks together recite the entire relevant work by the Buddha from memory. At Sera Jey, the recitation for this period is the Prayer of the Deeds of Samanta Bhadra (bZang-spyod smon-lam), also by Lord Buddha. The Prayer of Maitreya continues until the 13th of the twelfth Tibetan month.
+
[[Khen Rinpoche]] notes that, in [[Tibet]], this entire {{Wiki|ceremony}} took nearly a month. The 17th of the eleventh month marks the opening {{Wiki|ceremony}} for the session, and is followed by two days of a firewood break. The 20th and 21st are marked by the “dry recitations” for the winter lingshe [[geshes]], and then the next three days are examinations for the hlarampa candidates. Finally, on the 25th, the actual [[prayer]] begins: all of the [[monks]] together recite the entire relevant work by the [[Buddha]] from [[memory]]. At [[Sera Jey]], the {{Wiki|recitation}} for this period is the [[Prayer]] of the [[Deeds]] of [[Samanta Bhadra]] (bZang-spyod [[smon-lam]]), also by [[Lord Buddha]]. The [[Prayer]] of [[Maitreya]] continues until the 13th of the twelfth [[Tibetan]] month.
  
 
   
 
   
  
Great Torma Offering of the Twenty-Ninth (dGu-gtor chen-mo)
+
Great [[Torma Offering]] of the Twenty-Ninth (dGu-gtor chen-mo)
  
29th of the twelfth Tibetan month
+
29th of the twelfth [[Tibetan]] month
  
This is one of the year’s biggest prayer ceremonies; the next day is the last day of the year, the new (black) moon (gnam-gang).
+
This is one of the year’s biggest [[prayer]] {{Wiki|ceremonies}}; the next day is the last day of the year, the new (black) [[moon]] (gnam-gang).
  
 
   
 
   
  
Presentation of the Debate Ground Schedule (Chos-grvar tsogs-gtam ‘bulyun)
+
Presentation of the [[Debate]] Ground Schedule (Chos-grvar tsogs-gtam ‘bulyun)
  
16th of the third Tibetan month; 26th of the fifth Tibetan month; 16th of the eighth Tibetan month; and 26th of the ninth Tibetan month
+
16th of the third [[Tibetan]] month; 26th of the fifth [[Tibetan]] month; 16th of the eighth [[Tibetan]] month; and 26th of the ninth [[Tibetan]] month
  
On these four dates of the year, the debate master (dge-bskos) stands in the assembly of the debate park to announce the schedule for the coming period. He also outlines the duties that different members of the monastery will be expected to fulfill during this time, and reviews the general rule of behavior for the monastery from the monastery constitution (rtza-khrims, also known as a bca’-yig). This document for Sera Mey was written by His Holiness the Eighth Dalai Lama, Jampel Gyatso (1758- 1804); copies were very rare following the invasion of Tibet. A complete carving was located and supplied to Sera Mey several years ago by Asian Classics Input Project staff at the Oriental Library of the Russian Academy of Sciences in St Petersburg, Russia.
+
On these four dates of the year, the [[debate]] [[master]] (dge-bskos) stands in the assembly of the [[debate]] park to announce the schedule for the coming period. He also outlines the duties that different members of the [[monastery]] will be expected to fulfill during this [[time]], and reviews the general {{Wiki|rule}} of {{Wiki|behavior}} for the [[monastery]] from the [[monastery]] constitution (rtza-khrims, also known as a bca’-yig). This document for [[Sera Mey]] was written by [[His Holiness]] the [[Eighth Dalai Lama]], [[Jampel Gyatso]] (1758- 1804); copies were very rare following the [[Wikipedia:Invasion of Tibet (1950–1951)|invasion of Tibet]]. A complete carving was located and supplied to [[Sera Mey]] several years ago by {{Wiki|Asian}} Classics Input Project [[staff]] at the {{Wiki|Oriental}} Library of the {{Wiki|Russian Academy of Sciences}} in {{Wiki|St Petersburg}}, {{Wiki|Russia}}.
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,547: Line 1,547:
 
Rikpay Drotang
 
Rikpay Drotang
  
Debating Format, Part Three
+
[[Debating]] Format, Part Three
  
 
   
 
   
Line 1,553: Line 1,553:
 
Korwa la ta yupay chir
 
Korwa la ta yupay chir
  
A: Because the cycle of pain does have an end.
+
A: Because the cycle of [[pain]] does have an end.
  
 
Tak madrub
 
Tak madrub
Line 1,561: Line 1,561:
 
Korwa la ta mepar tel
 
Korwa la ta mepar tel
  
A: Are you telling me the cycle of pain doesn’t have an end?
+
A: Are you telling me the cycle of [[pain]] doesn’t have an end?
  
 
354
 
354
Line 1,575: Line 1,575:
 
Korwa la ngun gyi ta mepay chir
 
Korwa la ngun gyi ta mepay chir
  
B: Because the cycle of pain has no front end.
+
B: Because the cycle of [[pain]] has no front end.
  
Kyappa ma jung
+
Kyappa ma {{Wiki|jung}}
  
 
A: That doesn’t mean it can’t have an end!
 
A: That doesn’t mean it can’t have an end!
Line 1,583: Line 1,583:
 
Korwa la ta yu par tel
 
Korwa la ta yu par tel
  
B: Are you telling me the cycle of pain does have an end?
+
B: Are you telling me the cycle of [[pain]] does have an end?
  
 
Du
 
Du
Line 1,595: Line 1,595:
 
Korwa la chiy ta yupay chir
 
Korwa la chiy ta yupay chir
  
A: Because the cycle of pain has a back end.
+
A: Because the cycle of [[pain]] has a back end.
  
 
Yude
 
Yude
Line 1,603: Line 1,603:
 
Dakdzin gyi nyenpo top den yupay chir
 
Dakdzin gyi nyenpo top den yupay chir
  
A: Because there is a powerful antidote that will smash our habit of seeing things as self-existent.
+
A: Because there is a powerful antidote that will smash our [[Wikipedia:Habit (psychology)|habit]] of [[seeing]] things as [[self-existent]].
  
 
==See also==
 
==See also==

Latest revision as of 02:47, 5 April 2016

Selection from the collected topics:

Buddhas.life.b.016.jpg
6hx89Pz.jpg
1karmadakini.jpg
Ima3273ges.jpg
Forty m.jpg
Bq2x.JPG
Budfgtion.jpg
Uzba.jpg
0-4.jpg
Bairge.jpg
D Koh Yo Bu.JPG
Vaishravana401.jpg
189ghjgk.jpg
Clip-image0021.jpg
S-double1.jpg
Guru-Rinpoche-mandala.jpg
Stuupa matsirannas.jpg
Art 34x462.jpg
4662 n.jpg
LoB12.jpg
Url222.jpg
Tat-wale-baba-2.jpg
Mural-robes.jpg
Zaya Pandita.jpg
21 17-AFP1.jpg
Buddhist child Thailand.jpg
10bnm43 n.jpg
7340272 n.jpg
White-Tara-mandala.jpg
Goddesses-dzt.jpg
Uni 213.jpg
58tyuu.jpg
3D-brh68k.jpg
Zed-200.jpg
E2es.JPG
2bnpng.jpg
Ma66pg.jpg
Ne-the-dream.JPG
1r9zgseo1 500.jpg
Index0.jpg
Yuthog12.jpg
70560.jpg
Nk life 011.jpg
Galax114.jpg
TRooniTagneGradient.JPG
Lord shiva.jpg
29ccCopy.jpg
2.jpg
Memory min.jpg
Urlhjj.jpg
BeoJU0rCMAAdf.jpg
Shakdgsni500.jpg
Buddhist Nuns Myanma.jpg
Scape 020.jpg
Train ongolia.jpg
SimantiniDevi.jpg

The Concept of Time


The following selections on the concept of time (Dus-gsum gyi rnam-bzhag), are excerpted from The Collected Topics of Rato (Rva-stod bsdus-grva), by Master Chokhla U-ser, a great master of Rato Monastery who lived about 1500 AD. This particular book is considered the “grandfather” of what came to be a separate genre of literature in Tibet: the dura (bsdus-grva), or “selected topics from the Commentary on Valid Perception (Pramana Varttika, or Tsad-ma rnam-’grel) of Master Dharmakirti (circa 650 AD).

Please note that indented statements are usually those given by the opponent. Responses within brackets are those that are usually left unwritten in the Tibetan text, and are understood to be there because of the context following each.

_______________

Suppose someone comes again, and makes the following claim:

The definition of the past is: “That which has begun and stopped.” The definition of the present is: “That which has begun and not yet stopped.” The definition of the future is: “That condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present.”

Respective examples would be the following. For the first, the example would be last year’s crops. For the second, it would be this year’s crops; and, for the third, crops soon to grow.

Concerning the first of these, we answer as follows.

Aren’t your definition and example for the past though incorrect?

Because there is no definition for the past,

And this is because the past doesn’t even exist,

And this is because anything which can be established as existing is always something of the present.

On this point, someone may come and make the following claim:

But there must be things that are past,

Because past time exists;

And this is because all three—past time, and future time, and present time—exist.

And this is because the three times exist.

To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”

And we also ask this person,

So is the past the past?

Because the past exists.

You already agreed to the reason here.

[Then I agree to your original statement: the past is the past.]

Suppose you agree to our original statement.

Consider the past.

It is not so the past,

Because it is not something which has stopped;

And this is true because it is not something which has been destroyed.

[It doesn't necessarily follow.]

But it does necessarily follow,

Because “the past,” “that which has stopped,” and “that which has been destroyed” all refer to the same thing.

And this is true because all three of them exist;

And this is true because the past exists.

You already agreed that the reason is true.

Suppose that, instead of “it doesn’t necessarily follow,” the opponent says “it’s incorrect.”

Consider the past.

It is not so something which has been destroyed,

Because it is a working thing.

[It doesn't necessarily follow.]

But it does necessarily follow,

Because there exists no one thing which is both (1) something that has been destroyed but which is still (2) a working thing.

And this is true because the Golden Necklace of Good Explanation says,

None of the schools that belong to the side that believe that things exist through some nature of their own accept the idea that something which has been destroyed could be a working thing.

[The Golden Necklace is a famed commentary by Je Tsongkapa upon the Ornament of Realizations, spoken to the realized being Asanga by Lord Maitreya.]

[Then I disagree to your earlier statement.]

Suppose you say that the earlier one is not correct.

Consider the past.

It is so a working thing,

Because it is something made.

[It's not correct to say that the past is something made.]

Suppose you say that it’s not correct.

Consider this same thing.

It is so,

Because it’s something that started.

[It doesn't necessarily follow.]

But it does necessarily follow,

Because “something that started” is the definition of “something made.”

[The earlier point is not correct.]

Suppose you say that the earlier point is not correct.

Consider the past.

It is so something that started,

Because it is something that started and then stopped.

And this is true because it’s the past.

You’ve agreed both to the reason and to what we’re asserting must be so, and the necessity is something that does apply to the definition. It must moreover be true that that which has been destroyed is a working thing,

Because the past is a working thing.

We’ve already established that the reason is true.

Suppose you do agree.

Is it then the case that a working thing which has been destroyed is still a working thing?

Because (1) there does exist a working thing which has been destroyed, and (2) that which has been destroyed is a working thing.

You’ve already agreed to the latter part of the reason.

Suppose now you say that the first part is not correct.

The first is too correct,

Because there does exist a working thing which is past.

[It's not correct to say that there does exist a working thing which is past.]

Suppose you say that it’s not correct.

Consider a working thing.

There does too exist it past,

Because it is something that has been produced.

[Then I agree to your second original statement: it is the case that a working thing which has been destroyed is still a working thing.]

Suppose you agree to our second original statement.

So is a tree that was already destroyed still a tree?

Because a working thing which has been destroyed is still a working thing.

You’ve already accepted the reason.

[Then I agree to your original statement: a tree that was already destroyed is still a tree.]

Suppose you agree to our original statement.

So is it then true that when a tree has been burned up by fire there is still a tree?

Because (1) a tree that was already destroyed is a tree; and (2) there exists a destroyed tree subsequent to the burning up of a tree by a fire.

And this is so because—when a tree has been burned up by fire—there is a tree destroyed.

[I agree to your statement above.]

Suppose you agree to our statement above.

Imag36es.jpg

Is it then the case that—subsequent to the burning up of a tree by a fire—you can still see a tree by using your visual consciousness?

Because there does exist a tree subsequent to that point.

You already agreed to the reason.

If the one is the case, then the other is necessarily so. [That is, if there does exist a tree subsequent to that point, then you must be able to see it by using your visual consciousness.]

And you cannot agree to this last statement;

Because the following quotation from the Commentary on Valid Perception was meant to point out—to those who asserted that something which was destroyed could ever be a working thing—what very absurd consequences their position entailed:

Because it has started, then the destruction

Must be destroyed; and then the tree

Would have to be seen once more.

Concerning the second of the original definitions, [that the definition of the present is "that which has begun and not yet stopped,"] we pose the following:

Consider “knowable things.”

So is it something which has begun and not yet stopped?

Because it is something of the present.

[It doesn't necessarily follow.]

But you already agree that it does necessarily follow.

[It's not correct to say that "knowable things" is something of the present.]

It is so correct,

Because it can be established as existing.

[Then I agree to your statement above: "knowable things" is something that has begun and not yet stopped.]

Suppose you agree to our statement above.

Consider “knowable things.”

So is it something which ever began?

Because it has begun and not yet stopped.

You already agreed to the reason.

[Then I agree to your statement.]

Suppose you agree to our statement.

Consider this same thing..

It is not so, that it is something which ever began,

Because it is an unchanging thing.

If you agreed [that an unchanging thing could begin], then what we would answer to you is obvious.

Concerning the third of the original definitions, [that the definition of the future is: "that condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present,"] we pose the following:

So is it true then that the future exists?

Because it is something which has a definition;

Because “that condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present” is the definition of the future.

You already agreed that the reason was true.

[Then I agree to your point above.]

Suppose you agree to the above.

So is it then the case that the future is itself?

Because it does exist.

[I agree to your statement: the future is itself.]

Suppose you agree to our original statement.

Consider the future.

So is it then a condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present?

Because it is the future.

You already agreed to the reason,

And it is obvious that the necessity must apply to the definition.

[Then I agree.]

Suppose you agree.

Depending on how they read this definition [in the Tibetan), some people claim, “I agree that the future is the condition of having not yet begun, although the causes for beginning are present (Tib: skye ba’i rgyu yod).” Others claim, “I agree that the object of our argument [the future] is the condition of having not yet begun, even though it has cause to begin from this same condition (Tib: skye ba’i rgyu yod).”

Well suppose then that you read it the first way.

So does there exist a cause that makes the future begin?

Because the future is the condition of having not yet begun, even though the causes for beginning are present.

You’ve already accepted the reason.

[I agree that there does exist a cause that makes the future begin.]

Suppose you agree.

So is this cause that makes the future begin a working thing?

Because it does exist.

[I agree that it is.]

Suppose you agree.

Consider this cause that makes the future begin.

Is it something made?

Because it is a working thing.

[I agree that it is a working thing.]

Suppose you agree.

Consider this same thing.

Is it then something which has begun?

Because it is something made.

You already agreed to the reason.

But you cannot agree,

Because it is something which has not yet begun;

Because it is the condition of having not yet begun;

Because it is a condition where, even though [its cause) exists, it has not yet begun.

You’ve already agreed both to the reason and to what we’re asserting must be so.

And the following problem applies to the latter way of reading the phrase.

Is it then the case that this cause that will make it begin is a working thing?

Because the cause that will make the future begin exists.

[It's not correct to say that the cause that will make the future begin exists.]

Suppose you say that it’s not correct.

Consider this cause that will make the future begin.

It does so exist,

Because [the future] is a condition where, even though [its cause exists), it has not yet begun.

You’ve already agreed both to the reason and to what we’re asserting must be so.

[It doesn't necessarily follow.]

If you say it doesn’t necessarily follow, then your whole presentation collapses.

[Then I agree to your statement above.]

Suppose you agree to our statement above.

Consider the cause that makes [the future] begin.

It must then be something which has begun,

Because it is a working thing.

[I agree that the cause that makes the future begin is something which has begun.]

Suppose you agree.

Consider then this same thing.

It is not the case that it has already begun,

Because it is a thing which has yet to begin,

Because it is a condition of not having yet begun.

[It's not correct to say that the cause which makes the future begin is a condition of not having yet begun.]

Suppose you say that it’s not correct.

Consider this cause that makes the future begin.

It is so the condition of not having yet begun,

Because it is the condition of having not yet begun, even though it exists.

You’ve already both to the reason and to what we’re asserting must be so.

_______________

Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:

Does there exist a cause for something to begin or not?

We answer that there does, and then someone comes and makes the following claim:

But isn’t it the case that no cause for something to begin exists?

Because isn’t it the case that nothing beginning exists?

Because isn’t it the case that, if something is a working thing, it can never be beginning?

Because (1) isn’t it the case that, if something is a working thing, it must be something that began already; and (2) isn’t it the case that, if a working thing has begun already, it cannot start all over again?

To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”

_______________

Suppose someone comes again and claims,

So is it then the case that there are no beginnings at all?

Because none of the following exist: “something that’s going to begin,” “something that needs to begin,” “something that’s about to begin,” and “something that’s in the act of beginning.”

To this we say, “It doesn’t necessarily follow,” and then we say:

It’s like this. The beginning or the birth of something does too exist,

Because past and future births exist.

And this is true because there exists the practice of amassing the two collections over a great many births, past and future.

And this is true because there does exist the creation of an Infallible

Being, who comes from the practice of amassing the two collections over a great many births, past and future.

And this itself is true, because there is a point to the following two quotations:

By relying on the various proofs

Image022.jpg

It’s right to say “infallible.”

And—

The proof is that it comes from the practice

Of the attitude of compassion.

[Both quotations are from the Commentary on Valid Perception, and are used to establish that an Enlightened Being is produced from many eons spent amassing the two collections.]

Are you saying, moreover, that it is proper to throw away the whole system of those Lords of Reasoning, the Father and his spiritual Sons, and go following the system of that non-Buddhist school, the Rejectionists (Lokayata)?

Because you would have to accept the other side as our side in the following verses:

“An Infallible One would have to know

Even things that are hidden, and there’s

No proof that shows he can;

Neither is there a way to try.”

Thus do a number of them

Make their presentation.

And—

Because the mind is something

That depends upon the body,

There is nothing you can achieve

Through practice [over many lifetimes].

And this is true because it would then be right for you to accept the position that it’s impossible for there to exist an enlightened realized being who has practiced assembling the two collections over a great many births, past and future.

_______________

Suppose someone comes again and claims,

There must too exist a working thing which is about to begin,

Because there exists a working thing which is about to take birth from their mother’s womb.

So does there exist then a working thing which is in the act of beginning?

Because there exists a working which is about to take birth from their mother’s womb.

The fact that it follows is something you find acceptable.

But you cannot agree, because the glorious Chandrakirti has stated, “Since something in the act of beginning is only approaching beginning, it is not something which exists.”

And are you, furthermore, saying that there exists a working thing which hasn’t begun?

Because there exists a working thing which hasn’t begun, from their mother’s womb.

Suppose someone comes and says, “It’s incorrect [to say that there exists a working thing which hasn't begun, from their mother's womb).

But it is correct, because (1) there does exist a person who is in the act of staying in their mother’s womb, and (2) there also exists a working thing which is born complete.

Are you saying, moreover, that a working thing which has already begun begins again?

Because there exists a living being who has already taken birth, and who has to take birth again.

And this is true because there exists a living being who has already taken birth, and who has to take birth again in the circle of suffering life.

And this is true because (1) there exists a living being who has already taken birth as a human, and who has to take birth again as a human; and (2) there exists a living being who has already taken birth into the desire realm, and who has to take birth into the desire realm again.

Each of the reasons given is correct, because there do exist those who come from a birth as a human and are born as a human; and there do exist those who come from a birth in the desire realm and are born into the desire realm. It’s easy to accept these reasons.

And is it, moreover, the case that there exists nothing which is occurring?

Because nothing which is a working thing could ever be something which is occurring.

And this is because anything which is a working thing is something which has already occurred.

The fact that it follows is something you find acceptable.

The reason we’ve stated is correct, because anything which is a working thing is something which has already occurred from its own causes.

And this is true because anything which is a working thing is something which has already begun from its own causes.

[Then I agree to your original statement: it is the case that there exists nothing which is occurring.]

Suppose you agree to our original statement.

There does too exist something which is occurring,

Because there exist the four great elements.

And this is because there do exist the four of earth, water, fire, and wind.

[Translator's note: This argument depends upon the fact that the Tibetan words for "occurring" and for "element" have the same spelling ('byung ba).]

[It doesn't necessarily follow.]

It does necessarily follow, because that highest master, Vasubandhu, has stated that the great elements are four.

And this is true because the Treasure House says,

The elements are the following:

The divisions of elements we call

Earth and water and fire and wind.

_______________

Suppose yet another person comes and claims:

There must too exist a working thing which still has to start,

Because there does exist a working thing which is going to start.

And this is because there does exist a working thing which is going to occur.

To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”

The reason in itself though does apply to the subject,

Because the four of blue, yellow, white, and red and the like are all derivatives of the elements, and there also exist tangible objects which are derivatives of the elements.

And this is true because all tangible objects can be divided into two types: those that are elements, and those that are derivatives of the elements.

[Translator's note: This argument depends on the fact that the Tibetan for "going to occur" and for "derivative of the elements" is the same ('byung-'gyur).]

And this is true because The Treasure House of Wisdom says,

Tangible objects are of two types…

You can’t though agree to the original statement, [that there must exist a working thing which still has to start],

Because anything which is a working thing is something which must have already started.

On this point some may make the following claim:

It must so be the case that there exists no working thing which is going to occur,

Because anything which is a working thing must have already occurred.

This position though reflects a gross error of failing to examine things thoroughly. The expressions “going to start” and “still needs to start” are equivalent in meaning, exclusively, “going to start from the beginning” and “still needs to start from the beginning.”

But whereas “still needs to occur” means, exclusively, “still needs to occur from the beginning,” the (Tibetan phrase for] “going to occur” also applies to things which have already occurred, such as the color blue, or the tangible objects of heat or cold, and so on. And the mistake by the opponent here is that they have never heard the terms explained this way.

_______________

Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:

The definition of something “pastrelative to the time of a water pitcher is “that which has started and also stopped, in the time that the water pitcher is present.”

The definition of something “futurerelative to the time of a water pitcher is “that which is such that—although the causes for it to start are already present—it has yet to start, in the time that the water pitcher is present.”

The definition of something “presentrelative to the time of a water pitcher is “that which has started and not yet stopped, in the time that the water pitcher is present.”

Let us address the first of these definitions.

Consider the cause of a water pitcher.

Is this cause then something which has started and also stopped, in the time that the water pitcher is present?

Because it is something which is past relative to the time of the water pitcher.

And this is because it is the example we’ve chosen here.

And suppose you agree to the previous statement. [That is, suppose you agree that the cause of a water pitcher is something which has started and also stopped in the time of the water pitcher.]

Consider again the cause of a water pitcher.

Is it then one thing which has both (1) started in the time of the water pitcher and (2) stopped in the time of the water pitcher?

[Why do you say that?]

Because you agreed.

[Then I agree that the cause of a water pitcher is one thing which has both (1) started in the time of the water pitcher and (2) stopped in the time of the water pitcher.]

Suppose you agree then.

Consider this same thing.

Is it then something which has started in the time of the water pitcher?

[Why do you say that?]

Because you agreed above.

And yet you can’t agree, because it is something which has not started in the time of the water pitcher.

And this is because it is something which has not been made in the time of the water pitcher.

[It's not necessarily the case that, because the cause of a pitcher is something which has not been made in the time of the water pitcher, it must be something which has not started in the time of the water pitcher.]

Suppose you say that it’s not necessarily the case.

It is though necessarily the case,

Because the very definition of something’s not having been made in a certain time is “something’s not having started” in that same time.

And this is true because (1) there is at that time something which hasn’t been made, and (2) the definition of “something that hasn’t been made” is “something that hasn’t started.”

And this is true because “something that has started” is the definition of “something that has been made.”

Now suppose that you were to answer “it’s not correct to say that” above, where you answered “it doesn’t’ necessarily follow.” [That is, suppose you say that it's not correct to say that the cause of a water pitcher is something which has not been made in the time of the water pitcher.]

Consider this same thing.

It is so true that it has not been made in that particular time,

Because it doesn’t even exist in that particular time.

Ma-buddha.jpg

And this is because it has stopped in that particular time.

And this is because, in that particular time, it has started and also stopped.

And you’ve already agreed to what we stated as our reason.

Consider, moreover, the cause of a water pitcher, once again.

It is not so, that it is one thing which has both (1) started in the time of the water pitcher, and (2) stopped in this same time,

Because it is not something which has stopped.

And this is true because it hasn’t stopped.

And this is true because it is a produced thing.

_______________

Suppose yet another person comes, and makes this claim:

Consider the cause of a water pitcher.

It is too something which has started in the time of the water pitcher,

Because it has finished starting in the time of the water pitcher.

To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”

Therefore we have to express the situation as follows: Although the cause of the water pitcher, in the time of the water pitcher, has already begun, it is not something which has begun in the time of the water pitcher. This is for example like the case where the followers of the Independent group of the Middle-Way School and such say that “Cause and effect is true [Tib: bden-pa], but not real [Tib: bden-pa].” You have to be able to make the same kind of distinction here.

____________

Suppose someone comes along and claims,

Even though omniscience perceives a water pitcher directly, it does not do so in the sense that the word “directly” has when we divide perception into the two of “direct” and “deductive.”

To this we answer, “You are absolutely correct.”

If however someone were to come along in a debate and say that “Every state of direct perception is ‘direct’ in the sense that this word has when we divide perception into the two of ‘direct’ and ‘deductive’,” some logic would be required to prove the point just made.

____________

As for the second definition, [the definition of "the future" given above,] consider the result of a water pitcher.

Is it then something that has not begun?

Because it is the condition of not having begun.

And this is because it is the condition of not having begun, even though the causes for its beginning exist in the time of the water pitcher.

Now some may come along and claim, in response, that “it doesn’t necessarily follow.” This however would indicate that they had yet to grasp the meaning of the collected topics on logic and perception.

Suppose someone else came and said, instead, that “Your reason is not correct.”

Consider then this same thing: [the result of a water pitcher].

Are you saying that it is the condition of not having begun, even though, in the time of the pitcher, the causes for its beginning are present? Because it is “the future” at this same time.

The correctness of our reason is easy to accept.

And you’ve already accepted the necessity.

As for the third of the definitions above, [that of "the present,"] suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:

Consider the cause of a water pitcher.

It is so something which is present-time in the time of the water pitcher,

Because it is something which, in the time of the water pitcher, has begun and not yet stopped.

It is so, because it is both (1) something which has begun in the time of the water pitcher and (2) something which has not stopped in that time.

Our side would answer that the first part of this reason is not correct.

And then the other side would come back with,

Consider then this same thing.

It is too something which has begun in the time of the water pitcher,

Because it is something which has finished beginning in that time.

To this we’d answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”

Here next is an analysis of the question of whether the past and the future exist or not. Generally speaking there exist no definitions for “the past” or “the future,” because the past and future are not things which even exist. This is because, anything which can be established as existing must always be existing in the present [according to this school of Buddhism).

If though we were to establish the meaning of “the pastrelative to a specific point of reference, we could say that the definition of its past relative to the time of a specific water pitcher could be given as follows:

Something which has, by the time of the water pitcher, already started; and which has, by the time of the water pitcher, already ended as well.

This and “the pitcher just before the pitcher” amount to the same thing.

The definition of its present relative to the time of a specific water pitcher then could be given as follows:

That one thing which is both (1) something which has already come into existence by the time of the water pitcher; and (2) which is simultaneous to the water pitcher.

The definition of its future relative to the time of a specific water pitcher, finally, could be given as follows:

That one thing which is both (1) in the act of starting at the time of the water pitcher; and (2) not yet started at the time of the water pitcher.

The following all amount to the same thing:

the not-yet-coming of the water pitcher;

the cause of the water pitcher;

its past at the time of the water pitcher; and

its past relative to the water pitcher.

[Translator's note: "Not-yet-coming" and "future" are the same word in Tibetan (ma- 'ongs-pa).]

The following also all amount to the same thing:

the passing of the water pitcher;

the result of the water pitcher;

its future at the time of the water pitcher; and

its future relative to the water pitcher.

[Translator's note: "Passing" and "past" are the same word in Tibetan ('das-pa).]

Generally speaking, there is no such thing as something which has stopped.

And there is nothing which is about to begin. Neither is there anything which is in the act of beginning, nor is there anything which is approaching the state of beginning.

There does exist though the passing of the smoke; and the stopping of the smoke; and the smoke’s not yet coming, and the smoke’s being about to begin; and the smoke’s being in the act of beginning; and the smoke’s approaching the state of beginning.

There is though no such thing as smoke which is approaching the state of beginning. Neither is there any smoke which is in the act of beginning; nor any smoke which is about to begin; nor smoke which has stopped; nor smoke which has been destroyed; nor smoke which is past; nor smoke which is future.

The following all amount to the same thing:

a working thing;

a changing thing;

a momentary thing;

a thing which is in the act of being destroyed;

a thing which is approaching the past;

Nanda devatas.JPG

a thing which is approaching its destruction.

These assertions [about the nature of time) are all presented in accordance with the beliefs of the “Logician” group within the Sutrist School. They would not necessarily be acceptable to any other school of Buddhism. The Detailists, for example, do accept ideas such as past karma and future karma, while the Necessity group entertains unimaginably profound positions such as the one that states that the destruction of something is a working thing.


Formal logic subject:

A Discussion of Incorrect Logical Statements


The following presentation on incorrect “logical” statements is excerpted from An Explanation of the Art of Reasoning (rTags-rigs), by the Tutor of His Holiness the Thirteenth Dalai Lama, Purbuchok Jampa Tsultrim Gyatso (1825-1901).

_______________

Here is the second major division of our presentation, in which we explain the opposite of a correct reason: that is, incorrect reasons. We proceed in two steps: the definition of such reasons, and their various divisions.

The first of these we’ll discuss in terms of disproving our opponent’s beliefs, and then establishing our own beliefs. Here is the first. Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim: “Any reason where the three relationships fail to hold” is the definition of an incorrect reason.

This though is mistaken, for there is no such thing as an incorrect reason: everything which exists is a correct reason [to prove something].

Here secondly is our own position. The definition of an incorrect reason for a particular proof is:

A reason for a particular proof where the three relationships fail to hold.

Here secondly are the various divisions of incorrect reasons. Although there is not, generally speaking, any such thing as an incorrect reason, we can say that there do exist the following types of incorrect reasons in specific contexts:

1) Contradictory reasons for specific proofs;

2) Indefinite reasons for specific proofs; and

3) Wrong reasons for specific proofs.

We will discuss the first of these in four steps: definition; divisions; classical examples; and supporting arguments.

Here is the first. The definition of a contradictory reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing is:

That one thing for which (1) the relationship between the subject and the reason does hold for proving that sound is an unchanging thing; and (2) the positive necessity between the reason and the quality to be proven also holds for proving that sound is not an unchanging thing.

[A classical example would be: Consider sound. It is an unchanging thing, because it is a made thing.]

Here secondly are the divisions.

Contradictory reasons can be divided into two kinds: those which have a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they cover it completely, and those which have a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they go both ways, [covering or not].

Here thirdly are the classical examples. “Something that was made” is a contradictory reason which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they cover it completely, in a proof that sound is not a changing thing. “Something which is a particular example of the general type called ‘made things’” is a contradictory reason which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they go both ways, in proving the same thing.

Next is the fourth category: the supporting arguments.

Consider “something that was made.”

It is so a contradictory reason which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they cover it completely, in a proof that sound is not a changing thing,

Because it is both (1) a contradictory reason for proving this particular thing, and (2) anything which is changing is also it.

And consider “something which is a particular example of the general type called ‘made things’.”

It is so a contradictory reason which has a relationship with the group of dissimilar cases where they go both ways, in a proof that sound is not a changing thing,

Because it is a contradictory reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing.

And this is so because (1) the relationship between this reason and the subject of the particular proof holds; and (2) it is definitely the case that the positive necessity between it and the quality to be proven is diametrically false.

Consider, moreover, this same example.

It is so a contradictory reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing,

Because it is a correct reason for proving that sound is a changing thing.

_______________

Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:

So does there exist then a contradictory reason for proving that sound is a changing thing?

Because there does exist a contradictory reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing.

To this we answer, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”

And you could never agree [that there did exist a contradictory reason for proving that sound is a changing thing],

Because anything which is an incorrect reason for proving that sound is a changing thing must be either (1) an indefinite reason for the particular proof or (2) a wrong reason for the particular proof.

____________

Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:

If there exist the three relationships for any particular proof, then there must exist a correct reason for the particular proof.

Consider all knowable things.

There must then exist a correct reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing,

Because the three relationships do exist for proving that sound is an unchanging thing.

You’ve already accepted that it necessarily follows.

Suppose then that you say that it’s not correct [that the three relationships do exist for proving that sound is an unchanging thing].

They do too exist, because (1) there exists a relationship between the reason and the subject for this particular proof, and (2) there exists the positive necessity for the proof, and there exists the reverse necessity for the proof.

The first part of our reason here is correct, because the relationship between the reason and the subject holds when “something made” is used as the reason in a proof that sound is an unchanging thing.

Suppose you say that it’s not correct [that the relationship between the reason and the subject holds when "something made" is used as the reason in a proof that sound is an unchanging thing].

Consider this same thing [that is, "something made"].

The relationship does too hold with it,

Because it is a contradictory reason for the particular proof.

And that’s true because it is a correct reason for proving that sound is a changing thing.

And the second reason is a correct one, because that one thing which is both an existing phenomenon and something which is not momentary satisfies the positive necessity in a proof that sound is an unchanging thing.

Suppose you say that this is not correct.

Consider this same thing [that one thing which is both an existing phenomenon and something which is not momentary].

It does too [satisfy the relationship of positive necessity],

Because (1) there does exist a correct similar example which covers both the reason and the quality to be proven, in this particular proof where that “one thing” we mentioned is used as the reason; and (2) this “one thing” can be verified, through a valid perception, as something that fits only the group of similar cases, in the way it is stated, within a proof that sound is an unchanging thing.

Now the first part of our reason is correct, because “unproduced, empty space” would be a correct similar example which covers both the reason and the quality to be proven in this particular proof, where the “one thing” we mentioned is used as a reason.

And the second part of our reason is correct, because “that one thing which is both an existing phenomenon and something which is not momentary” is something that fits only the group of similar cases, in the way it is stated, within this particular proof.

And this is because it is, in fact, the definition of something which is unchanging.

The third part of our reason above, [that there exists the reverse necessity for the proof,] is also correct. This is because that one thing which is both (1) an existing phenomenon and (2) something which is not momentary fulfils that same necessity.

Now suppose you say that our last reason is not correct. Consider this same thing [that is, that one thing which is both (1) an existing phenomenon and (2) something which is not momentary].

It does so fulfil the reverse necessity for the proof that sound is an unchanging thing,

Because there does exist a correct dissimilar example for the proof in which it serves as the reason; that is, an example which possesses neither the reason nor the quality to be proven for the particular proof. And it can also be verified, through a valid perception, that it only does not fit the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.

Suppose finally that you agree to the original statement: [that is, you agree that there must exist a correct reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing].

Consider then sound.

It is rather so, that there exists no correct reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing;

Because it is not something which is unchanging.

_______________

Suppose someone comes and makes the following claim:

It must then be so, that there is something for which all three relationships hold, in proving that sound is an unchanging thing;

Because there is something which fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for this proof; and there is something which fulfils the positive necessity for the proof; and there is something which fulfils the reverse necessity for the proof.

To this we reply, “It doesn’t necessarily follow.”

____________

Here secondly is our explanation of an indefinite reason; we will proceed first with a definition, and then with the various divisions of this reason. Here is the first of these.

The following is the definition of an indefinite reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing:

That one thing for which (1) the relationship between the subject and the reason for proving that sound is an unchanging thing does hold; (2) the reverse relationship between the reason and the subject for proving that sound is an unchanging thing does not hold; and (3) the reverse relationship between the reason and the subject for proving that sound is not an unchanging thing doesn’t hold either.

[A classical example would be: Consider sound. It is an unchanging thing, because there is no such thing as antlers on a rabbit's head.]

Here secondly are the divisions. This kind of reason can be divided into two: unique indefinite reasons for a particular proof, and common indefinite reasons for a particular proof. We will discuss the first of these two in two steps: its definition, and a classical example for it.

Here is the first. The definition of something which is a unique indefinite reason for a particular proof is:

That one thing which is both (1) an indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has yet to verify either one of the following: that it fits the group of similar cases for the proof, or that it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.

Here secondly are some classical examples.

The following are all both unique indefinite reasons for proving that sound is an unchanging thing, and unique indefinite reasons for proving that sound is a changing thing:

something you can hear;

the reverse of all that is not sound; and

the reversal of sound.

We will discuss the second type, common indefinite reasons, in two steps as well: definition, and divisions. Here is the first.

The definition of a common indefinite reason is:

That one thing which is both (1) an indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has either verified (a) that it fits the group of similar cases for the proof, or (b) that it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.

Here is the second. These types of reasons may be divided into three: those which are direct indefinite reasons for a particular proof; those which are uncertain indefinite reasons for a particular proof; and those indefinite reasons which are neither of the first two. Again we will discuss the first of these in terms of its definition and its divisions.

Here is the first. The definition of something which is a direct indefinite reason is:

Rahula ordination.JPG

That one thing which is both (1) an indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has verified that it fits both the group of similar cases and the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.

Here secondly are the divisions of this type of reason. They come in four different types:

1) Those direct indefinite reasons that cover both the group of similar cases and the group of dissimilar cases for the particular proof;

2) Those same kinds of reasons that cover the group of similar cases for the particular proof, but which go both ways as far as its group of dissimilar cases;

3) Those same kinds of reasons that cover the group of dissimilar cases for the particular proof, but which go both ways as far as its group of similar cases; and

4) Those same kinds of reasons that go both ways as far as both the group of dissimilar cases and the group of similar cases for the particular proof.

Here are respective classical examples for each of these types.

1) The fact that there are no such things as rabbit antlers would be a direct indefinite reason that covers both the group of similar cases in a proof that sound is an unchanging thing, and the group of dissimilar cases for this same proof.

2) “Changing thing” would be a direct indefinite reason that covers the group of similar cases in a proof that the sound of a conch shell is something produced through a conscious effort, but which goes both ways as far as the group of dissimilar cases for this same proof.

3) “Changing thing” would be a direct indefinite reason that covers the group of dissimilar cases in a proof that sound of a conch shell is not something produced through a conscious effort, but which goes both ways as far as its group of similar cases.

4) “Sense consciousness” would be a direct indefinite reason that goes both ways as far as both the group of dissimilar cases and the group of similar cases in a proof that a sense consciousness which thinks there are two moons [where there is only one] is a direct [valid] perception.

Here secondly is our discussion of uncertain indefinite reasons; we will repeat the two steps of their definition and their divisions. Here is the first.

The definition of something’s being an uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof is the following:

That one thing which is both (1) a common indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has either (a) already verified that it fits the group of similar cases for the proof, but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof or not; or else (b) already verified that it does fit the group of dissimilar cases for the proof, but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of similar cases for the proof or not.

Here secondly are the divisions of this type of reason. There are two: correct uncertain indefinite reasons and contradictory uncertain indefinite reasons.

The definition of something’s being a correct uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof is:

That one thing which is both (1) an uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has already verified that it fits the group of similar cases for the proof, but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof or not.

The definition of something’s being a contradictory uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof is:

That one thing which is both (1) an uncertain indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has already verified that it fits the group of dissimilar cases for the proof, but is still uncertain whether it fits the group of similar cases for the proof or not.

Here are some examples, in the order we gave the definitions. An example of the first would be giving “because he is making pronouncements” as a reason for proving that John, who is making pronouncements, is not an omniscient being—and giving this reason to someone who doubts the existence of an omniscient being.

The same reason presented to the same person to prove that John, who is making pronouncements, is an omniscient being would be an example of the second type.

Here thirdly we’ll explain those common indefinite reasons which are neither the direct nor uncertain types. Again we proceed in terms of definition and classical example.

Here is the first. The definition of something being a common indefinite reason which is neither the direct nor the uncertain types for a particular proof is:

That one thing which is both (1) a common indefinite reason for a particular proof; and (2) such that a person who already recognizes that it fulfils the relationship between the subject and the reason for the particular proof has already verified either that it fits only the group of similar cases for the proof, or that it only doesn’t fit the group of dissimilar cases for the proof.

Here secondly is our classical example. “[Because there is a] taste of sugar in the present time” is a common indefinite reason which is neither the direct nor the uncertain types in a proof that a lump of sugar in one’s mouth has the visible appearance of a lump of sugar in the present time.

Here third is our presentation on wrong reasons. Again we proceed in two steps of definition and divisions. Here is the first.

The definition of a wrong reason for any particular proof is:

That which (1) has been put forth as a reason for a particular proof, but (2) for which the relationship between the subject and the reason does not hold.

Here secondly are the divisions of wrong reasons for particular proofs. There are three different types:

1) Reasons which are wrong relative to meaning.

2) Reasons which are wrong relative to a state of mind.

3) Reasons which are wrong relative to the particular opponent.

The first of these may itself be divided into seven different types:

1) Reasons which are wrong because the very nature of the reason is non-existent.

2) Reasons which are wrong because the very nature of the subject is non-existent.

3) Reasons which are wrong because the reason and the quality to be proven are indistinguishable from one another.

4) Reasons which are wrong because the subject and the reason are indistinguishable from one another.

5) Reasons which are wrong because the subject and the quality to be proven are indistinguishable from one another.

6) Reasons which are wrong because the reason does not pertain to the subject in the way it has been said to in the statement of the proof.

7) Reasons which are wrong because some part of the reason fails to belong to the subject under consideration.

The following are respective examples of these types of reasons, in particular proofs:

1)

Consider a particular person.

They are a suffering being,

Because they have been impaled on a rabbit’s antlers.

2)

Consider the antlers on the head of a rabbit.

They are a changing thing,

Because they were made.

3)

Consider sound.

It is a changing thing,

Because it is a changing thing.

4)

Consider sound.

It is a changing thing,

Because it is sound.

5)

Consider sound.

It is sound,

Because it is something which was made.

6)

Consider sound.

It is a changing thing,

Because it is something that you see with your eyes.

7)

Consider a fruit tree.

It must be a conscious thing,

Because its leaves curl up and night and seem to sleep.

This brings us to the second kind of wrong reason: the one that is wrong relative to a state of mind. Here there are four different types:

1) Reasons that are wrong because the opponent entertains doubt about the very nature of the reason.

2) Reasons that are wrong because the opponent entertains doubt about the very nature of the subject.

3) Reasons that are wrong because the opponent entertains doubt about the connection between the subject and the reason.

4) Reasons that are wrong because there is nothing that the opponent has yet to understand.

The following are respective examples of these four, for particular proofs.

1) The following proof, presented to a person who has yet to confirm to himself that “flesh-eaters” [a kind of ghost) actually exist:

Consider sound.

It is a changing thing,

Because flesh-eaters are something which can be cognized through valid perception.

2) The following proof, presented to a person who has yet to confirm to himself that “smell-eaters” (spirits in the bardo or inbetween state) actually exist:

Consider the song of the smell-eaters.

It is a changing thing,

Because it is something that was made.

3) The following proof, presented to a person who doesn’t know where a particular peacock is:

Consider that mountain vale over there.

There must be a peacock living there,

Because we can hear a peacock crowing.

4) The following proof, presented to the glorious Dharmakirti:

Consider sound.

It is a changing thing,

Because it is something that was made.

Here thirdly is our explanation of reasons which are wrong relative to the particular opponent. There are three different kinds of these reasons:

1) Reasons which are wrong relative to the proponent.

2) Reasons which are wrong relative to the opponent.

3) Reasons which are wrong relative to both the opponent and the proponent.

Here are respective examples for these three types of reasons, in particular proofs.

1) The following proof, presented to a Buddhist by a Numerist [of member of the Sangkya, a non-Buddhist school of ancient India]:

Consider the intellect.

It is something devoid of mind,

Because it is something which starts and stops.

2) The following proof, presented to a Buddhist by a member of the Unclothed

[or Jain school of ancient India]:

Consider a fruit tree.

It must have a mind,

Because it dies when you peel its bark.

3) The following proof, presented to a member of the Rejectionist (Lokayata) school by one of the Unclothed (Jain) school [both non-Buddhist groups of ancient India]:

Consider sound.

It is a changing thing,

Because it is something you see with your eyes.


The forms of debate:

The traditional debate year


The following annual calendar for Sera Mey Tibetan Monastery gives a good picture of the schedule of study followed by all monks in the geshe program at the monastery. It is a traditional schedule which developed at the original Sera Mey in Lhasa, Tibet, over the centuries; since the rebuilding of Sera Mey in south India, the schedule has been reinstated—with a certain number of variations from the one used in Tibet—and is now followed closely, with some exceptions due to the need to work in the monastery cornfields and so on. Below is a translation of the annual calendar as it is currently posted on at the main temple of the monastery; the notes and some amendations to the calendar were completed with the help of Khen Rinpoche Geshe Lobsang Tharchin, a former abbot of the monastery.

_______________


Annual Calendar of Debates, Examinations, and Other Special Events at Sera Mey Tibetan Monastery Bylakuppe, South India Schedule of Regular Dharma Sessions


The following are the eight traditionaldharma sessions” (chos-thog) that make up the standard periods of monastic study at Sera Mey Monastery. The first Tibetan month, by the way, normally falls in February or March of the western calendar. The dates below are the same for any given year, independent of the day of the week, and follow the waxing and waning of the moon.


Session One: The Earlier Dharma Session of Spring (dPyid-chos dang-po)

Starting assembly: 26th of the first Tibetan month

First firewood break: 27th and 28th of the first Tibetan month

The “firewood break” (shing-slong), or literally “time for requesting firewood from sponsors” follows immediately after the starting assembly (yar-tsogs).

This assembly features prayers for the success of the session, and is attended by all monks who intend to participate for this period. It is also during this assembly that young monks who have been deemed ready by the abbot, the debate master, and their house teacher undergo the ceremony of intitiation into the debate park. These “newbies” are known as sarshuk (gsar-zhugs), or “newly entered.” They are expected to demonstrate their commitment to the debate session through perfect attendance, and especially serious study and debate, for the entire length of the session.

In Lhasa, a head-count was taken during the starting assembly in order to determine the cooking and other needs. During the next two days, teams of monks would go out to help find firewood for the monastery kitchen, based on the head-count.

The first day of the firewood break was devoted to visiting lay communities in the countryside outside of Lhasa city to ask for firewood; families in these villages knew what day to expect the monks, and considered it an honor to prepare a good supply of wood in advance. On the second day the monks would travel to Lhasa city proper to request fuel. This supply of wood would have to last about two weeks, until the “mid-term firewood break” (rked-pa’i shing-slong).

Great debate examinations: tsokrampa geshe examinations, 28th to the 30th of the first Tibetan month

During specific sessions, intense debate examinations are held for candidates standing for various degrees at the monastery. The most well known of these degree titles is the geshe. The wordgeshe” (kalyaNa mitra in Sanskrit, or dge-bshes in Tibetan) literally means “spiritual friend,” and is a term from the earliest days of Buddhism in India. Later, great masters among the first Tibetan Buddhists—the Kadampas—were called “geshe” out of respect for their learning and high level of practice.

As monastic institutions began to form in Tibet, the wordgeshe” came to be used as a title. It was originally used in the early “Big Three” monasteries of Sangpu (gSang-phu), Kyormo Lung (sKyor-mo lung), and Gadong (sGagdong). Sangpu, for example, was founded around the middle of the eleventh century.

Sangpu had two colleges within the confines (or gseb) of the monastery as a whole (known as the gling); early geshe candidates had to make their debate defense at a combined assembly of the two, and came to be known as lingse geshes, a corruption of the word lingsep (gling-gseb). The Great Dictionary of the Tibetan Language and other sources take the word lingse to mean gling-bsre, or a defense before the “combined” (bsre) assemblies of the two colleges in the monastery (gling). In either case, the point is the same.

At Sera Mey, there are typically four lingse geshe degrees conferred per year: these come in two pairs known as the “summer lingse” and the “winter lingse.” Geshes of this rank go through an examination process within their own monastery, as described in a previous reading for this course. During some of their defenses, these and other geshe candidates are required to provide an elaborate series of refreshments, involving some served to the entire assembly of their monastery. This ceremony is known as the “Thirteen-Course Tea and Broth” (Ja-thug bcu-gsum).

During other defenses, lingse candidates need only provide a series of ten tea offerings on the day when they undergo a special part of their examination which involves reciting a great many pages of scripture from memory. This test is called a geshe shepa (dge-bshes bshad-pa); and since the major refreshments of tea and broth are not served to the entire assembly this time, the presentation is known as a “dry recitation” (skam-bshad).

Below the rank of lingse geshe is the rikrampa (rigs rams-pa), and the next higher rank after the lingse is the tsokrampa (tsogs rams-pa). In both cases, the word rampa refers to the veritable myriad (rab-’byams, shortened to rams-pa) number of great Buddhist classics that a geshe must master. The word tsok in tsokrampa refers to the Session of the Great Assembly (Tsogschos), an annual meeting in Lhasa city of the six great colleges. Here there are two each for the “Great Three” monasteries of later times: Sera, Ganden, and Drepung, all founded around the opening of the fifteenth century. Representatives from Deyang (bDe-yangs) monastery would also attend this gathering, during which the candidates for the tsokrampa rank would have to defend their knowledge.

Relig.jpg

The Great Assembly traditionally began on the 20th of the second Tibetan month, and ended on the 30th. This is the time it would take to complete the examination of one or two tsokrampa candidates from each college per year. Candidates for the highest rank of geshe, the hlarampa (hla rams-pa), are examined during the Great Prayer Festival, or Munlam Chenmo. This festival was instituted by Je Tsongkapa in the 15th century as a great dharma celebration for the New Year. Since it was held in the capital city of Lhasa

(Hla-sa), these geshes became known as hlarampa. Each of the six colleges normally nominates two candidates per year for the rank of hlarampa, although on some occasions it may be as many as four.

First actual debate session: begins 1st of the second Tibetan month

Mid-term firewood break: 5th and 6th of the second Tibetan month

Second actual debate session: begins 7th of the second Tibetan month

Auspicious conclusion: 18th of the second Tibetan month

The “Auspicious Conclusion” (Shis-brjod) is a day of prayer and celebration for the successful end of another dharma session; it is marked by special recitations known as “pronouncing” (brjod) the “auspiciousness” (bkra-shis, the “trashi” in “trashi delek”). These prayers are done in a unique melody or yang (dbyangs). On this day too, the abbot of the monastery will often deliver a special dharma teaching.


Intersession break (Chos-mtsams):

19th of the second Tibetan month to the 7th of the third Tibetan month

Session Two: The Great Dharma Session of Spring (dPyid-chos chen-mo)

Starting assembly: 8th of the third Tibetan month

First firewood break: 9th and 10th of the third Tibetan month

Great debate examinations: summer lingse geshes, 11th to the 12th of the third Tibetan month

First actual debate session: begins 13th of the third Tibetan month

Mid-term firewood break: 22nd and 23rd of the third Tibetan month

Second actual debate session: begins 24th of the third Tibetan month

Auspicious conclusion: 7th of the fourth Tibetan month


Intersession break:

8th of the fourth Tibetan month to the 16th of the fourth

Tibetan month


Session Three: The Earlier Summer Dharma Session (dByar-chos dang-po)

Starting assembly: 17th of the fourth Tibetan month

First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the fourth Tibetan month

Great debate examinations: (no geshe debates)

First actual debate session: begins 20th of the fourth Tibetan month

Mid-term firewood break: (none)

Second actual debate session: (none)

Auspicious conclusion: 1st of the fifth Tibetan month


Intersession break: 2nd of the fifth Tibetan month to the 16th of the fifth Tibetan month


Session Four: The Great Dharma Session of Summer (dByar-chos chen-mo)

Starting assembly: 17th of the fifth Tibetan month

First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the fifth Tibetan month

Great debate examinations: summer lingse geshes (“dry recitation”) and rikram

geshes; 20th to the 23rd of the fifth Tibetan month

First actual debate session: begins 24th of the fifth Tibetan month

Mid-term firewood break: 2nd and 3rd of the sixth Tibetan month

Second actual debate session: begins 4th of the sixth Tibetan month

Auspicious conclusion: 15th of the sixth Tibetan month


Intersession break:

16th of the sixth Tibetan month to the 16th of the seventh Tibetan month; includes rikram geshe exams, summer lingse geshe exams, rikchung pre-geshe exams, and rikdra inter-monastic debates

The rikdra (rigs-grva) inter-monastic debates begin on the last day of the sixth Tibetan month and last until the 15th day of the seventh Tibetan month. During this time, thirty debaters from Sera Mey debate with thirty counterparts from the sister monastery of Sera Jey in the main assembly hall (tsogs-chen) shared by both monasteries for major events such as the biweekly monkspurification ceremony, or sojong (gso-sbyong).

During this time, pairs of debaters match off twice a day, once in the morning and once in the evening, for fifteen days. In a typical session, the proponent (snga-rgol) will be responsible for a lengthy recitation of scripture from memory, after which his opponent (phyi-rgol) is charged with posing a difficult series of formalized debate questions. In Tibet, the combined monasteries of Sera Mey and Sera Jey had joint holdings of property, and the income from these would be used during this session to supply all the monks attending with gifts of Tibetan pastries (kabse) and roasted barley flour, or tsampa.

It is also during this time that the rikchen (rigs-chen), or advanced pre-geshe debates, are held. Here a student who intends to take a higher geshe degree engages in a difficult and highly formalized debate against a similar candidate from the sister monastery. Other students in the monastery during this time are engaged in special examinations, administered by the abbot and debate master of their home monastery, during which they are required to recite, from memory, about 100 pages of scripture.


Session Five: The Water Dharma Session (Chab-zhugs chos-thog)

Starting assembly: 17th of the seventh Tibetan month

First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the seventh Tibetan month

Great debate examinations: (no geshe debates)

First actual debate session: begins 20th of the seventh Tibetan month

Mid-term firewood break: (none)

Second actual debate session: (none)

Auspicious conclusion: 30th of the seventh Tibetan month

The “Water” Session (Chab-zhugs) is possibly given this name due to the fact that, during the period following the especially intense Great Session of Summer, students in the geshe program finally have enough time to relax and “enter the water” (chabzhugs), or take a nice slow bath. The rikchung and rikchen (preliminary and advanced pre-geshe debates) have been completed, as have the grueling rikdra intermonastic debates, and memorization exams. Students would be allowed take breaks in special parks throughout out the monastery, and traditional folk-dance troupes would come there at times, to perform the “goddess” plays (lha-mo).


Intersession break:

1st of the eighth Tibetan month to the 7th of the eighth

Tibetan month; this is the main “water break”


Session Six: The Dharma Session of Medicine Buddha (sMan-bla chos-thog)

Starting assembly: 8th of the eighth Tibetan month

First firewood break: 9th and 10th of the eighth Tibetan month

Great debate examinations: (no geshe debates)

First actual debate session: begins 11th of the eighth Tibetan month

Mid-term firewood break: 22nd and 23rd of the eighth Tibetan month

Second actual debate session: begins 24th of the eighth Tibetan month

Auspicious conclusion: 7th of the ninth Tibetan month

This session takes its name from the fact that an extensive Medicine Buddha rite is held on the 11th of the eighth month.


Intersession break:

8th of the ninth Tibetan month to the 16th of the ninth Tibetan month


Session Seven: The Great Dharma Session of Autumn (sTon-chos chen-mo)

Starting assembly: 17th of the ninth Tibetan month

First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the ninth Tibetan month

Great debate examinations: winter lingse geshe examinations, 20th and 21st of the ninth Tibetan month

First actual debate session: begins 22nd of the ninth Tibetan month

Mid-term firewood break: 2nd and 3rd of the tenth Tibetan month

Second actual debate session: begins 4th of the tenth Tibetan month

Auspicious conclusion: 16th of the tenth Tibetan month


Intersession break:

17th of the tenth Tibetan month to the 16th of the eleventh Tibetan month


Session Eight: The Great Dharma Session of Winter (dGun-chos chen-mo)

Starting assembly: 17th of the eleventh Tibetan month

First firewood break: 18th and 19th of the eleventh Tibetan month

The great examinations: 20th to the 23rd of the eleventh Tibetan month; debate examinations for the winter lingse geshes and hlarampa geshes, the former presenting their “dry recitation

First actual debate session: begins 24th of the eleventh Tibetan month

Mid-term firewood break: 12th and 13th of the twelfth Tibetan month

Second actual debate session: begins 14th of the twelfth Tibetan month

Auspicious conclusion: 16th of the twelfth Tibetan month


Intersession break

This break features further examination of winter lingse geshes, the Tibetan New Year, and the Great Prayer Festival; it begins on the 17th of the twelfth Tibetan month and ends on the 25th of the first Tibetan month.


Annual Special Events

Passing On of Kedrup Tenpa Dargye (mKhas-grub dgongs-rdzogs)

14th day of the fifth Tibetan month

Kedrup Tenpa Dargye (1493-1568) was an illustrious scholar from Sera Mey who wrote many of the monastery’s textbooks. On special days like this, the monastery will be covered at night in strings of brightly colored electric lights that look like our Christmas-tree lights.


Summer Offering to the Two Dharma Protectors (Chos-skyong rnam-gnyis kyi dbyar-gsol)

15th day of the fifth Tibetan month

This particular day every year is known throughout Tibet as the “Day of Auspiciousness throughout the World” (‘Dzam-gling spyi-bzang). At Sera Mey, the occasion is used as an opportunity to thank the dharma protectors of the monastery for their help, and to request that they continue their sacred deeds. The two protectors here are Chamsing (lCam-sring) and Taok (Tha-’og). The protector Chamsing is shared with other monasteries, while Taok is a unique protector for Sera Mey. Please note that these two protectors have nothing to do with the current dharma protector controversy.


Rikchung (Pre-Geshe Degree) Debates

25th to the 28th of the sixth Tibetan month


First team

Proponent takes the subject “Turning of the Wheel,” opponent takes “Book of Maitreya”: 25th of the sixth Tibetan month

Each of the subjects mentioned here are important topics from the Ornament of Realizations, spoken to the realized being Asanga by Lord Maitreya around 350 AD.


Second team

Proponent takes “Sutra and Commentary,” opponent takes “Final End”: 26th of the sixth Tibetan month


Third team

Proponent takes “Wish for Enlightenment,” opponent takes “Path of Preparation”: 27th of the sixth Tibetan month


Fourth team

Proponent takes “Three Refuges,” opponent takes “Buddha Nature”: 28th of the sixth Tibetan month

Rice2.jpg


Summer Examinations

8th of the seventh Tibetan month


Extensive Medicine Buddha Rite

11th of the eighth Tibetan month


Great Winter Examinations

8th of the eleventh Tibetan month


Assembly of the Great Offering Ceremony for the Prayer of Maitreya

(Byams-smon sgrub-mchod chen-mo yar-tsogs) 25th of the eleventh Tibetan month

Khen Rinpoche notes that, in Tibet, this entire ceremony took nearly a month. The 17th of the eleventh month marks the opening ceremony for the session, and is followed by two days of a firewood break. The 20th and 21st are marked by the “dry recitations” for the winter lingshe geshes, and then the next three days are examinations for the hlarampa candidates. Finally, on the 25th, the actual prayer begins: all of the monks together recite the entire relevant work by the Buddha from memory. At Sera Jey, the recitation for this period is the Prayer of the Deeds of Samanta Bhadra (bZang-spyod smon-lam), also by Lord Buddha. The Prayer of Maitreya continues until the 13th of the twelfth Tibetan month.


Great Torma Offering of the Twenty-Ninth (dGu-gtor chen-mo)

29th of the twelfth Tibetan month

This is one of the year’s biggest prayer ceremonies; the next day is the last day of the year, the new (black) moon (gnam-gang).


Presentation of the Debate Ground Schedule (Chos-grvar tsogs-gtam ‘bulyun)

16th of the third Tibetan month; 26th of the fifth Tibetan month; 16th of the eighth Tibetan month; and 26th of the ninth Tibetan month

On these four dates of the year, the debate master (dge-bskos) stands in the assembly of the debate park to announce the schedule for the coming period. He also outlines the duties that different members of the monastery will be expected to fulfill during this time, and reviews the general rule of behavior for the monastery from the monastery constitution (rtza-khrims, also known as a bca’-yig). This document for Sera Mey was written by His Holiness the Eighth Dalai Lama, Jampel Gyatso (1758- 1804); copies were very rare following the invasion of Tibet. A complete carving was located and supplied to Sera Mey several years ago by Asian Classics Input Project staff at the Oriental Library of the Russian Academy of Sciences in St Petersburg, Russia.


Supplement to Reading Ten

Rikpay Drotang

Debating Format, Part Three


Korwa la ta yupay chir

A: Because the cycle of pain does have an end.

Tak madrub

B: Wrong.

Korwa la ta mepar tel

A: Are you telling me the cycle of pain doesn’t have an end?

354

Du

B: Right.

Me de

A: Why not?

Korwa la ngun gyi ta mepay chir

B: Because the cycle of pain has no front end.

Kyappa ma jung

A: That doesn’t mean it can’t have an end!

Korwa la ta yu par tel

B: Are you telling me the cycle of pain does have an end?

Du

A: Right.

Yu de

B: Why so?

Korwa la chiy ta yupay chir

A: Because the cycle of pain has a back end.

Yude

B: Why so?

Dakdzin gyi nyenpo top den yupay chir

A: Because there is a powerful antidote that will smash our habit of seeing things as self-existent.

See also


Source

jetsongkapa.wordpress.com