Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Vijnaptimdtravijnaptimdtratdvibhdga: Translating Vijnaptimdtra and Vijnaptimdtratd in the Philosophy of Vasubandhu"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " Roberto Pinheiro Machado* This essay springs from a discussion that was carried out recently in a seminar on Buddhist philosophy. During a panel on Yogacara, I was...")
 
 
Line 11: Line 11:
  
  
This essay springs from a discussion that was carried out recently in a seminar on Buddhist philosophy. During a panel on Yogacara, I was met with considerable skepticism from my colleagues when I argued that Vasubandhu employed the terms “vijnaptimdtra” and “vijnaptimdtratd” with very different meanings.  
+
This essay springs from a [[discussion]] that was carried out recently in a seminar on [[Buddhist philosophy]]. During a panel on [[Yogacara]], I was met with considerable {{Wiki|skepticism}} from my [[colleagues]] when I argued that [[Vasubandhu]] employed the terms “vijnaptimdtra” and “vijnaptimdtratd” with very different meanings.  
  
My point was that Vasubandhu used the first in reference to what early Buddhist doctrine called “conventional reality,” and the second as a description of what the doctrine termed “ultimate reality.” Given the skeptical response, I decided to analyze a number of scholarly texts that mentioned the two concepts, and I noticed that although the difference that I was pointing out seemed obvious to me, it had in fact been largely overlooked by scholarship.  
+
My point was that [[Vasubandhu]] used the first in reference to what early [[Buddhist doctrine]] called “[[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[reality]],” and the second as a description of what the [[doctrine]] termed “[[ultimate reality]].” Given the skeptical response, I decided to analyze a number of [[scholarly]] texts that mentioned the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], and I noticed that although the difference that I was pointing out seemed obvious to me, it had in fact been largely overlooked by {{Wiki|scholarship}}.  
  
Above all, I realized that most English translations do not render the distinction with sufficient clarity.
+
Above all, I [[realized]] that most English translations do not render the {{Wiki|distinction}} with sufficient clarity.
  
In what follows I will thus approach the issue of translation and discuss the available English renderings of Vasubandhu's texts where the two concepts appear. I believe that the difference between vijnaptimatra from vijnaptimatrata is fundamental to the correct apprehension of the soteriological principles that underlie Vasubandhu's philosophy. The translations' shortcomings create the sort of difficulties that lead readers to overlook the main function of the two concepts in the philosopher's system.
+
In what follows I will thus approach the issue of translation and discuss the available English renderings of [[Vasubandhu's]] texts where the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] appear. I believe that the difference between [[vijnaptimatra]] from [[vijnaptimatrata]] is fundamental to the correct apprehension of the [[soteriological]] {{Wiki|principles}} that underlie [[Vasubandhu's]] [[philosophy]]. The translations' shortcomings create the sort of difficulties that lead readers to overlook the main function of the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] in the philosopher's system.
  
  
  
Department of Letters, Federal University of Rio Grande do Sul (Brazil). Email: robertopinheiromachado@live.comMy analysis will proceed through the following steps:
+
Department of Letters, Federal {{Wiki|University}} of Rio Grande do Sul ({{Wiki|Brazil}}). Email: robertopinheiromachado@live.comMy analysis will proceed through the following steps:
Firstly, I will point to the difficulties that arrive through the English translations of Vasubandhu by presenting the background in which the two concepts are developed, setting them in the context of the notion of “vijnapti,” as well as in that of the trisvabhava theory (as it appears in the Samlhinirmocana Sutra, the works of Asanga, and is discussed by Willis, Keenan, and Yamada).  
+
Firstly, I will point to the difficulties that arrive through the English translations of [[Vasubandhu]] by presenting the background in which the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] are developed, setting them in the context of the notion of “[[vijnapti]],” as well as in that of the [[trisvabhava]] {{Wiki|theory}} (as it appears in the Samlhinirmocana [[Sutra]], the works of [[Asanga]], and is discussed by Willis, Keenan, and Yamada).  
  
With such background in mind, I will work comparatively through eight translations of Vasubandhu and Asanga where the concepts are rendered primarily in an undifferentiated manner. Secondly, I will proceed to a close reading of Vasubandhu's Vimsatika, Vimsatikav®tti, and Trimsika in the original Sanskrit, pointing to the nuances in his employment of the two concepts.  
+
With such background in [[mind]], I will work comparatively through eight translations of [[Vasubandhu]] and [[Asanga]] where the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] are rendered primarily in an undifferentiated manner. Secondly, I will proceed to a close reading of [[Vasubandhu's]] [[Vimsatika]], Vimsatikav®tti, and [[Trimsika]] in the original [[Sanskrit]], pointing to the nuances in his employment of the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]].  
  
In this vein, an analysis of the five instances where the two concepts appear in the Vimsatika and Vimsatikav®tti will be approached in reference to the discussion of the role played by the suffix “ta” in the Sanskrit language (a discussion started in the Buddhist scholarly context by Takeuchi).
+
In this vein, an analysis of the five instances where the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] appear in the [[Vimsatika]] and Vimsatikav®tti will be approached in reference to the [[discussion]] of the role played by the suffix “ta” in the [[Sanskrit]] [[language]] (a [[discussion]] started in the [[Buddhist]] [[scholarly]] context by Takeuchi).
  
  
Thirdly, I will further develop my thesis by means of an inferential analysis where the usages of the two concepts will be seen in reference to the soteriological project that underlies Vasubandhu's philosophy. At this point I will refer to passages from selected sutras that are relevant to the Yogacara tradition in which the philosopher is inscribed, and which will corroborate with the demonstration of the distinct connotations of the two terms in question.
+
Thirdly, I will further develop my {{Wiki|thesis}} by means of an inferential analysis where the usages of the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] will be seen in reference to the [[soteriological]] project that underlies [[Vasubandhu's]] [[philosophy]]. At this point I will refer to passages from selected [[sutras]] that are relevant to the [[Yogacara tradition]] in which the [[philosopher]] is inscribed, and which will corroborate with the demonstration of the {{Wiki|distinct}} connotations of the two terms in question.
  
  
Finally, I will propose an alternative translation to the term “vijnaptimatrata” that will differentiate it more clearly from “vijnaptimatra.”
+
Finally, I will propose an alternative translation to the term “[[vijnaptimatrata]]” that will differentiate it more clearly from “[[vijnaptimatra]].”
  
Before we begin our inquiry, it is important to bear in mind that in the past decades Buddhist scholars have recurrently emphasized the need of more and better translations of original Sanskrit Buddhist texts (in this vein, Janice Willis and Bruce Cameron Hall present two instances where such necessity is discussed at considerable length). This essay follows such an emphasis in an attempt to stress, and hopefully help clarify, some of the difficulties involved in the task of rendering Buddhist philosophical ideas in English in a way that does not remove their soteriological implications from our sight.
+
Before we begin our inquiry, it is important to bear in [[mind]] that in the {{Wiki|past}} decades [[Buddhist scholars]] have recurrently emphasized the need of more and better translations of original [[Sanskrit]] [[Buddhist texts]] (in this vein, Janice Willis and Bruce Cameron Hall {{Wiki|present}} two instances where such necessity is discussed at considerable length). This essay follows such an {{Wiki|emphasis}} in an attempt to [[stress]], and hopefully help clarify, some of the difficulties involved in the task of rendering [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] [[ideas]] in English in a way that does not remove their [[soteriological]] implications from our [[sight]].
  
  
  
1. Background on vijnapti in relation with the trisvabhava theory and comparison of English translations
+
1. Background on [[vijnapti]] in [[relation]] with the [[trisvabhava]] {{Wiki|theory}} and comparison of English translations
  
1.1 The two truths and the three svabhavas
+
1.1 The [[two truths]] and the three [[svabhavas]]
  
  
In order to observe how vijhaptimatra and vijhaptimatrata operate in relation to conventional and ultimate reality (samvrti sat and paramartha sat, respectively), we need first have a clear understanding of the role played by the doctrine of two truths as it underlies nearly the entirety of Vasubandhu’s system of thought.  
+
In order to observe how vijhaptimatra and vijhaptimatrata operate in [[relation]] to [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] and [[ultimate reality]] ([[samvrti]] sat and [[paramartha]] sat, respectively), we need first have a [[clear understanding]] of the role played by the [[doctrine]] of [[two truths]] as it underlies nearly the entirety of [[Vasubandhu’s]] system of [[thought]].  
  
The necessity for clarifying such a role springs from the fact that instead of drawing directly on early Buddhist scripture and, in doing so, immediately embracing its twofold division of reality, the philosopher adopts the new doctrine of trisvabhava, a tripartite classification of the nature of phenomena that was first formulated by Asanga (following, primarily, the Mahayana Samdhinirmocana and Lahkavatara sutras). As Willis points out-
+
The necessity for clarifying such a role springs from the fact that instead of drawing directly on early [[Buddhist scripture]] and, in doing so, immediately embracing its twofold [[division]] of [[reality]], the [[philosopher]] adopts the [[new doctrine]] of [[trisvabhava]], a tripartite {{Wiki|classification}} of the [[nature]] of [[phenomena]] that was first formulated by [[Asanga]] (following, primarily, the [[Mahayana]] [[Samdhinirmocana]] and Lahkavatara [[sutras]]). As Willis points out-
  
  
For Asanga, the two-truths theory was insufficient. He therefore devised a schema which states that all phenomena have three natures: (1) a mentally constructed and therefore imaginary (parikalpita) nature; (2) a dependent, or relative (paratantra) nature; and (3) a perfected or absolute (parinispanna) nature. (Willis 1979: 18).
+
For [[Asanga]], the two-truths {{Wiki|theory}} was insufficient. He therefore devised a {{Wiki|schema}} which states that all [[phenomena]] have [[three natures]]: (1) a [[mentally]] [[constructed]] and therefore [[imaginary]] ([[parikalpita]]) [[nature]]; (2) a dependent, or [[relative]] ([[paratantra]]) [[nature]]; and (3) a perfected or [[absolute]] ([[parinispanna]]) [[nature]]. (Willis 1979: 18).
  
  
Such a tripartite classification was adopted and further developed by Vasubandhu, who, as I argue below, added to it the dimension of non-being (abhava). By asserting the presence of non-being together with that of being, Vasubandhu established the ground for the equation of being and non-being in ultimate reality nd with it supplied a new support to the primary goal of the trisvabhava theory as established by Asanga, that is, that of clarifying the Mahayana doctrine of sunyata and providing, in Willis’ words, “an insulation against nihilism.” (Willis 1979: 18).
+
Such a tripartite {{Wiki|classification}} was adopted and further developed by [[Vasubandhu]], who, as I argue below, added to it the [[dimension]] of [[non-being]] ([[abhava]]). By asserting the presence of [[non-being]] together with that of being, [[Vasubandhu]] established the ground for the equation of [[being and non-being]] in [[ultimate reality]] nd with it supplied a new support to the primary goal of the [[trisvabhava]] {{Wiki|theory}} as established by [[Asanga]], that is, that of clarifying the [[Mahayana doctrine]] of [[sunyata]] and providing, in Willis’ words, “an insulation against [[nihilism]].” (Willis 1979: 18).
  
  
Be that as it may, what interests us here is to observe that the trisvabhava theory, while in fact intended to further develop and extend the older Buddhist doctrine of two truths, was never meant to deny it. And it is in this sense that, as we will see, the older division of reality into samv®ti and paramdrtha sat still holds validity both in the trisvabhava theory, as well as in the whole of Vasubandhu's system.  
+
Be that as it may, what interests us here is to observe that the [[trisvabhava]] {{Wiki|theory}}, while in fact intended to further develop and extend the older [[Buddhist doctrine]] of [[two truths]], was never meant to deny it. And it is in this [[sense]] that, as we will see, the older [[division]] of [[reality]] into samv®ti and paramdrtha sat still holds validity both in the [[trisvabhava]] {{Wiki|theory}}, as well as in the whole of [[Vasubandhu's]] system.  
  
The point to be kept in mind here is that the purpose for the adoption of a new category of phenomena was primarily that of finding a middle ground that would account for the conversion from the first form of reality to the second. Such a middle category is, following Asanga's abovementioned formulation, the paratantra-svabhava or “dependent nature.”
+
The point to be kept in [[mind]] here is that the {{Wiki|purpose}} for the adoption of a new category of [[phenomena]] was primarily that of finding a middle ground that would account for the [[conversion]] from the first [[form]] of [[reality]] to the second. Such a middle category is, following [[Asanga's]] abovementioned formulation, the [[paratantra-svabhava]] or “[[dependent nature]].”
  
  
In order to further clarify the meaning of paratantra- svabhava in Asanga and Vasubandhu, we must look at the source of the trisvabhava theory in the Samlhinirmocana Sutra. It is in its sixth chapter that we find the tripartite analysis of being appearing in its most basic formulation.  
+
In order to further clarify the meaning of [[paratantra]]- [[svabhava]] in [[Asanga]] and [[Vasubandhu]], we must look at the source of the [[trisvabhava]] {{Wiki|theory}} in the Samlhinirmocana [[Sutra]]. It is in its sixth [[chapter]] that we find the tripartite analysis of being appearing in its most basic formulation.  
  
As the Buddha pronounces the following speech to the Bodhisattva Gunakara, the notion of the paratantra-svabhava is expounded as that which adheres to phenomena that, by arising under the rubric of co-dependent origination (prat¥tya-samutpada), are ultimately empty of self­nature:
+
As the [[Buddha]] pronounces the following {{Wiki|speech}} to the [[Bodhisattva]] [[Gunakara]], the notion of the [[paratantra-svabhava]] is expounded as that which adheres to [[phenomena]] that, by [[arising]] under the rubric of co-dependent origination (prat¥tya-samutpada), are ultimately [[empty]] of self­nature:
  
  
Gunakara, in dependence upon names that are connected with signs, the imputational [parikalpita-svabhava] character is known. In dependence upon strongly adhering to the other-dependent character as being the imputational character, the other-dependent character [paratantra- svabhava] is known. In dependence upon absence of strong adherence to the other-dependent character as being the imputational character, the thoroughly established character [parinispanna-svabhdva] is known. (Powers 1995: 87)
+
[[Gunakara]], in [[dependence]] upon names that are connected [[with signs]], the imputational [[[parikalpita-svabhava]]] [[character]] is known. In [[dependence]] upon strongly adhering to the [[other-dependent]] [[character]] as being the [[imputational character]], the [[other-dependent]] [[character]] [[[paratantra]]- [[svabhava]]] is known. In [[dependence]] upon absence of strong adherence to the [[other-dependent]] [[character]] as being the [[imputational character]], the thoroughly established [[character]] [parinispanna-svabhdva] is known. ([[Powers]] 1995: 87)
  
  
As that which adheres to the constructed nature of phenomena, the paratantra-svabhava stands as a middle category where ignorance abides and suffering originates. The equation that expresses the relation among ignorance, suffering, and co­dependent origination appears in the sutra as follows:
+
As that which adheres to the [[constructed]] [[nature]] of [[phenomena]], the [[paratantra-svabhava]] stands as a middle category where [[ignorance]] abides and [[suffering]] originates. The equation that expresses the [[relation]] among [[ignorance]], [[suffering]], and co­dependent origination appears in the [[sutra]] as follows:
  
  
Gunakara, what is the other-dependent character of phenomena? It is simply the dependent origination of phenomena. It is like this: Because this exists, that arises; because this is produced, that is produced. It ranges from: “Due to the condition of ignorance, compositional factors [arise],” up to: “In this way, the whole great assemblage of suffering arises.” (Powers 1995: 83).
+
[[Gunakara]], what is the [[other-dependent]] [[character]] of [[phenomena]]? It is simply the [[dependent origination]] of [[phenomena]]. It is like this: Because this [[exists]], that arises; because this is produced, that is produced. It ranges from: “Due to the [[condition]] of [[ignorance]], [[compositional factors]] [arise],” up to: “In this way, the whole great assemblage of [[suffering]] arises.” ([[Powers]] 1995: 83).
  
  
We thus understand that, in opposition to both parikalpita- svabhava, the category of the being of objects (vastu or grahya) that exist only by means of (illusory) thought-construction (vikalpa), and to parinispanna-svabhava, the one where reality is perfected and free of thought construction, paratantra-svabhdva stands as the category of the subject (grahaka), which, following the traditional Buddhist doctrine of anatman, is in fact ultimately non-existent, that is, is itself a mind construct.  
+
We thus understand that, in [[opposition]] to both [[parikalpita]]- [[svabhava]], the category of the being of [[objects]] ([[vastu]] or [[grahya]]) that [[exist]] only by means of ([[illusory]]) [[thought-construction]] ([[vikalpa]]), and to [[parinispanna-svabhava]], the one where [[reality]] is perfected and free of [[thought]] construction, paratantra-svabhdva stands as the category of the [[subject]] ([[grahaka]]), which, following the [[traditional]] [[Buddhist doctrine]] of [[anatman]], is in fact ultimately [[non-existent]], that is, is itself a [[mind]] construct.  
  
From this we can assume that when the sutra claims that the paratantra-svabhava is made known by the adherence of “the other dependent character as being the imputational character,” it is claiming precisely that the paratantra-svabhava is made known when that which grasps mentally constructed phenomena is taken to exist in the same mode as such grasped phenomena themselves, that is, as existing in and by themselves outside of consciousness.
+
From this we can assume that when the [[sutra]] claims that the [[paratantra-svabhava]] is made known by the adherence of “the other dependent [[character]] as being the [[imputational character]],” it is claiming precisely that the [[paratantra-svabhava]] is made known when that which [[grasps]] [[mentally]] [[constructed]] [[phenomena]] is taken to [[exist]] in the same mode as such grasped [[phenomena]] themselves, that is, as [[existing]] in and by themselves outside of [[consciousness]].
  
  
But what is most important to notice is that paratantra- svabhava, besides being the nature of the phenomenon whose very nature constructs parikalpita-svabhava, is also the one that permits the conversion from this same parikalpita-svabhava to parinispanna-svabhava. The conversion itself is worked out by Asanga and Vasubandhu under the name of “dsrayapardv®tti,” a term commonly translated as “revolution of the basis.” The point is thus that through asrayaparav®tti the paratantra-svabhava is converted in parinispanna-svabhava, and as such loses its “dependent” nature, that is, it ceases to depend on mentally constructed objects in order to exist, and as such ceases all grasping.  
+
But what is most important to notice is that [[paratantra]]- [[svabhava]], besides being the [[nature]] of the [[phenomenon]] whose very [[nature]] constructs [[parikalpita-svabhava]], is also the one that permits the [[conversion]] from this same [[parikalpita-svabhava]] to [[parinispanna-svabhava]]. The [[conversion]] itself is worked out by [[Asanga]] and [[Vasubandhu]] under the [[name]] of “dsrayapardv®tti,” a term commonly translated as “[[revolution of the basis]].” The point is thus that through asrayaparav®tti the [[paratantra-svabhava]] is converted in [[parinispanna-svabhava]], and as such loses its “dependent” [[nature]], that is, it ceases to depend on [[mentally]] [[constructed]] [[objects]] in order to [[exist]], and as such ceases all [[grasping]].  
  
Asrayapardv®tti is, then, the key soteriological aim for which the trisvabhava theory was built. As Keenan notes,
+
Asrayapardv®tti is, then, the key [[soteriological]] aim for which the [[trisvabhava]] {{Wiki|theory}} was built. As Keenan notes,
  
  
The theory of the three patterns (trisvabhdva) strove to show that the basic other-dependent pattern of consciousness accounts both for the genesis of imagined illusion and for the possibility of its transformation into perfect awakening and wisdom. (Keenan 1989: 50)
+
The {{Wiki|theory}} of the three patterns (trisvabhdva) strove to show that the basic [[other-dependent]] pattern of [[consciousness]] accounts both for the genesis of [[imagined]] [[illusion]] and for the possibility of its [[transformation]] into {{Wiki|perfect}} [[awakening]] and [[wisdom]]. (Keenan 1989: 50)
Such transformation, understood as the perfection of reality occurring in the paratantra-svabhdva as a revolution of its basis (dsrayapardv®tti), amounts, in traditional Buddhist terms, to the overcoming of conventional reality towards the achievement of ultimate truth.
+
Such [[transformation]], understood as the [[perfection]] of [[reality]] occurring in the paratantra-svabhdva as a {{Wiki|revolution}} of its basis (dsrayapardv®tti), amounts, in [[traditional]] [[Buddhist]] terms, to the [[overcoming]] of [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[reality]] towards the [[achievement]] of [[ultimate truth]].
  
  
1.2 Vijnapti, vijnaptimatra, and vijhapimatrata
+
1.2 [[Vijnapti]], [[vijnaptimatra]], and vijhapimatrata
  
  
  
Intrinsically related to the process of dsrayapardv®tti, it must be noted, is the notion of vijnapti, put forth by Vasubandhu to further characterize the being of paratantra-svabhdva. Here we arrive at our first major point in the attempt to understand the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd.  
+
Intrinsically related to the process of dsrayapardv®tti, it must be noted, is the notion of [[vijnapti]], put forth by [[Vasubandhu]] to further characterize the being of paratantra-svabhdva. Here we arrive at our first major point in the attempt to understand the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd.  
  
For, as will become clear, it is the very notion of vijnapti with its role in the transformation from parikalpita to parinispanna-svabhdva that will provide us with the basis for correctly apprehending the different functions assumed by vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd in Vasubandhu's philosophical system.  
+
For, as will become clear, it is the very notion of [[vijnapti]] with its role in the [[transformation]] from [[parikalpita]] to parinispanna-svabhdva that will provide us with the basis for correctly apprehending the different functions assumed by vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd in [[Vasubandhu's]] [[philosophical]] system.  
  
In order to demonstrate such distinct functions, I will proceed first to an examination of the concept of vijnapti itself, and then to an analysis of the meaning it acquires when supplemented by the term mdtra. The difficulties involved in correctly grasping the new concept, now “vijnaptimdtra,” will be observed through the disagreement on its basic meaning seen in the work of two scholars, Janice Willis and Bruce Cameron Hall.  
+
In order to demonstrate such {{Wiki|distinct}} functions, I will proceed first to an {{Wiki|examination}} of the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[vijnapti]] itself, and then to an analysis of the meaning it acquires when supplemented by the term mdtra. The difficulties involved in correctly [[grasping]] the new {{Wiki|concept}}, now “vijnaptimdtra,” will be observed through the disagreement on its basic meaning seen in the work of two [[scholars]], Janice Willis and Bruce Cameron Hall.  
  
After a brief analysis of their basic assumptions, I will look into the concept's appearance in the first verse of Vasubandhu's Vimsatikd, and call forth two translations that, while agreeing on its basic meaning, support Willis's understanding of the concept. Following this, I will then call forth passages in Vasubandhu's text where “vijnaptimdtra” appears accrued by the suffix “td,” forming now “vijnaptimdtratd,” and point to how in such instances not only does agreement in translation further slacken, but also the accretion of the suffix “td” is not, in most cases, properly taken into consideration by the translators.
+
After a brief analysis of their basic {{Wiki|assumptions}}, I will look into the concept's [[appearance]] in the first verse of [[Vasubandhu's]] Vimsatikd, and call forth two translations that, while agreeing on its basic meaning, support Willis's [[understanding]] of the {{Wiki|concept}}. Following this, I will then call forth passages in [[Vasubandhu's]] text where “vijnaptimdtra” appears accrued by the suffix “td,” forming now “vijnaptimdtratd,” and point to how in such instances not only does agreement in translation further slacken, but also the accretion of the suffix “td” is not, in most cases, properly taken into [[consideration]] by the [[translators]].
  
  
  
1.2.1. Vijnapti
+
1.2.1. [[Vijnapti]]
  
  
  
Going back to the concept of vijnapti, then, we should now observe how such foundational notion has been met with difficulties in scholarly interpretation, and how such difficulties gave rise to a wealth of translations that are for the most part unhelpful in arriving at a clear understanding of the concept. Yamada (1997: 163), for instance, explains vijhapti as follows:
+
Going back to the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[vijnapti]], then, we should now observe how such foundational notion has been met with difficulties in [[scholarly]] [[interpretation]], and how such difficulties gave rise to a [[wealth]] of translations that are for the most part unhelpful in arriving at a [[clear understanding]] of the {{Wiki|concept}}. Yamada (1997: 163), for instance, explains vijhapti as follows:
  
In our world of experience, “being conscious,” (vijhana) means that the three modes of transformation of vijhana (vijhana-parinama) have taken place. Moreover, “being conscious,” can take place only in the form of “being conscious of something.” Thus vijnana is inevitably double­faceted. Within consciousness there are two things present at one and the same time, one being being conscious (vijnana) of something and the other being something (vijneya) of which one is conscious. This double-faceted consciousness is called vijnapti, representation.
+
In our [[world]] of [[experience]], “being [[conscious]],” ([[vijhana]]) means that the three modes of [[transformation]] of [[vijhana]] (vijhana-parinama) have taken place. Moreover, “being [[conscious]],” can take place only in the [[form]] of “being [[conscious]] of something.” Thus [[vijnana]] is inevitably double­faceted. Within [[consciousness]] there are two things {{Wiki|present}} at one and the same time, one being being [[conscious]] ([[vijnana]]) of something and the other being something (vijneya) of which one is [[conscious]]. This double-faceted [[consciousness]] is called [[vijnapti]], [[representation]].
  
  
Here the concept of vijnapti appears in phenomenological terms as the reflexive consciousness that apprehends itself in the processes of apprehending the external world, creating thus a double perspective on reality. Such understanding of vijnapti, however, is unsatisfactory to the extent that it does not account for many of the nuances it assumes under Vasubandhu's usage.  
+
Here the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[vijnapti]] appears in {{Wiki|phenomenological}} terms as the reflexive [[consciousness]] that apprehends itself in the {{Wiki|processes}} of apprehending the [[external world]], creating thus a double {{Wiki|perspective}} on [[reality]]. Such [[understanding]] of [[vijnapti]], however, is unsatisfactory to the extent that it does not account for many of the nuances it assumes under [[Vasubandhu's]] usage.  
  
As we will see after looking closely into the philosopher's original words, and attempting a new translation for the concept, this limited understanding of vijnapti is very likely one of the causes of scholars' failure to properly differentiate vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata.  
+
As we will see after looking closely into the philosopher's original words, and attempting a [[new translation]] for the {{Wiki|concept}}, this limited [[understanding]] of [[vijnapti]] is very likely one of the [[causes]] of [[scholars]]' failure to properly differentiate [[vijnaptimatra]] and [[vijnaptimatrata]].  
  
At this point, however, we should notice that Yamada himself does seem to be aware that the above understanding of vijnapti is in fact not the only possible one. A clear indicator that such is the case is that throughout the abovementioned essay he translates the term vijnapti in as many as seven different ways: as “appearance” (p. 162); “internal mind” (p. 169); “mental function” (p. 169); “discursive mind” (p. 167); “relative subject” (p. 168); “empirical cognition” (p. 170); and “representation” (p. 163).
+
At this point, however, we should notice that Yamada himself does seem to be {{Wiki|aware}} that the above [[understanding]] of [[vijnapti]] is in fact not the only possible one. A clear indicator that such is the case is that throughout the abovementioned essay he translates the term [[vijnapti]] in as many as seven different ways: as “[[appearance]]” (p. 162); “internal [[mind]]” (p. 169); “[[mental function]]” (p. 169); “discursive [[mind]]” (p. 167); “[[relative]] [[subject]]” (p. 168); “[[empirical]] [[cognition]]” (p. 170); and “[[representation]]” (p. 163).
  
  
As a discussion of each of the above renderings would only lead us into a maze of confusion, we should keep in mind that the difficulty lies in the fact that nowhere in Vasubandhu can we find a clear specification that vijnapti necessarily implies a dualistic form of perception.  
+
As a [[discussion]] of each of the above renderings would only lead us into a maze of [[confusion]], we should keep in [[mind]] that the difficulty lies in the fact that nowhere in [[Vasubandhu]] can we find a clear specification that [[vijnapti]] necessarily implies a [[dualistic]] [[form]] of [[perception]].  
  
As a mental image, vijnapti can be understood both as a basic “perception” that does not assume anything about that which is perceived, as well as a “representation” that implies a subjective construction of what is found in the perceptive field. It must be noted, however, that the level of discussion at which vijnapti must perforce be understood as a “representation,” is solely that where all perceptions must be understood as such.  
+
As a [[mental]] image, [[vijnapti]] can be understood both as a basic “[[perception]]” that does not assume anything about that which is [[perceived]], as well as a “[[representation]]” that implies a [[subjective]] construction of what is found in the perceptive field. It must be noted, however, that the level of [[discussion]] at which [[vijnapti]] must perforce be understood as a “[[representation]],” is solely that where all [[perceptions]] must be understood as such.  
  
This level is the one where it is assumed that the object perceived has already changed by the time it is apprehended by the senses; at this level a vijnapti would naturally amount to a “representation,” but not necessarily to a “representation” as opposed to a “perception.”
+
This level is the one where it is assumed that the [[object]] [[perceived]] has already changed by the time it is apprehended by the [[senses]]; at this level a [[vijnapti]] would naturally amount to a “[[representation]],” but not necessarily to a “[[representation]]” as opposed to a “[[perception]].”
  
  
1.2.2 From vijnapti to vijnaptimdtra: Willis vs. Hall
+
1.2.2 From [[vijnapti]] to vijnaptimdtra: Willis vs. Hall
  
  
Be that as it may, from the variegated assortment of translations we see in Yamada—which manifest the flagrant difficulty in rendering the term vijnapti in a single and more precise way—we could expect further complications in scholarly translation when Vasubandhu adds first the word “matra,” and then the suffix “ta,” to “vijnapti.” Starting then our comparative approach to the translations, we should begin by observing Willis's understanding of vijnaptimatra:
+
Be that as it may, from the variegated assortment of translations we see in Yamada—which [[manifest]] the flagrant difficulty in rendering the term [[vijnapti]] in a single and more precise way—we could expect further complications in [[scholarly]] translation when [[Vasubandhu]] adds first the [[word]] “[[matra]],” and then the suffix “ta,” to “[[vijnapti]].” Starting then our comparative approach to the translations, we should begin by observing Willis's [[understanding]] of [[vijnaptimatra]]:
  
  
It is here that we find the Yogacara's important epistemological point that in every ordinary cognition, what is cognized is not an accurate portrayal of an object existing outside the mind but merely an object-like mental image (vijnaptimatra) of that; only a “conceptualized” object, one that is solely the product of constructive imagination. (Willis 1979: 26).
+
It is here that we find the Yogacara's important [[epistemological]] point that in every ordinary [[cognition]], what is [[Wikipedia:Cognition|cognized]] is not an accurate portrayal of an [[object]] [[existing]] outside the [[mind]] but merely an object-like [[mental]] image ([[vijnaptimatra]]) of that; only a “[[conceptualized]]” [[object]], one that is solely the product of constructive [[imagination]]. (Willis 1979: 26).
  
  
Here vijnaptimatra is defined as “merely an object-like mental image.” We should pay careful attention to the appearance of term “merely” in Willis's fragment. While the term vijnapti alone could be translated as “object-like mental image” (a notion close enough to Yamada's “representation”), “matra” has an adjectival function, qualifying vijnapti into what translates now as “merely an object-like mental image” [my italics].
+
Here [[vijnaptimatra]] is defined as “merely an object-like [[mental]] image.” We should pay careful [[attention]] to the [[appearance]] of term “merely” in Willis's fragment. While the term [[vijnapti]] alone could be translated as “object-like [[mental]] image” (a notion close enough to Yamada's “[[representation]]”), “[[matra]]” has an adjectival function, qualifying [[vijnapti]] into what translates now as “merely an object-like [[mental]] image” [my italics].
  
  
While the difference may seem slight, such understanding of matra as “merely” leads to a definition of vijnaptimatra that will provide the term with the capacity to describe what is expounded in traditional Buddhist thought as “conventional reality.”  
+
While the difference may seem slight, such [[understanding]] of [[matra]] as “merely” leads to a [[definition]] of [[vijnaptimatra]] that will provide the term with the capacity to describe what is expounded in [[traditional]] [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] as “[[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[reality]].”  
  
The point here is that in order to assert that every ordinary cognition, or every vijnapti, is not the cognition of an object that exists in itself—that is, of an object that, were it in fact to exist in itself, would consequently pertain to ultimate reality—Vasubandhu adjoins the term matra and by doing so qualifies vijnapti as a cognition or representation that is “merely” conventional.  
+
The point here is that in order to assert that every ordinary [[cognition]], or every [[vijnapti]], is not the [[cognition]] of an [[object]] that [[exists]] in itself—that is, of an [[object]] that, were it in fact to [[exist]] in itself, would consequently pertain to [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] reality—Vasubandhu adjoins the term [[matra]] and by doing so qualifies [[vijnapti]] as a [[cognition]] or [[representation]] that is “merely” [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]].  
  
In other words, such cognition is defined as a “mere” representation precisely to the extent that it is incapable of accounting for the object itself, or for ultimate reality in general. Needless to say, Willis's understanding of vijnaptimdtra as “merely and object like mental image” is valid.
+
In other words, such [[cognition]] is defined as a “mere” [[representation]] precisely to the extent that it is incapable of accounting for the [[object]] itself, or for [[ultimate reality]] in general. Needless to say, Willis's [[understanding]] of vijnaptimdtra as “merely and [[object]] like [[mental]] image” is valid.
  
  
  
Although all this may sound like common sense, such an interpretation of the term mdtra as functioning in the context of Vasubandhu's texts with a meaning akin to that of the English word “merely” is not unanimously agreed upon by scholars. For this reason, the work of one scholar deserves special attention.  
+
Although all this may [[sound]] like {{Wiki|common sense}}, such an [[interpretation]] of the term mdtra as functioning in the context of [[Vasubandhu's]] texts with a meaning akin to that of the English [[word]] “merely” is not unanimously agreed upon by [[scholars]]. For this [[reason]], the work of one [[scholar]] deserves special [[attention]].  
  
In “The Meaning of Vijnapti in Vasubandhu's Concept of Mind,” Bruce Cameron Hall (:1986) counters with considerable vehemence the notion that the concept mdtra functions in the context of Vasubandhu's philosophy with a meaning akin to that of the English “merely.”  
+
In “The Meaning of [[Vijnapti]] in [[Vasubandhu's]] {{Wiki|Concept}} of [[Mind]],” Bruce Cameron Hall (:1986) counters with considerable vehemence the notion that the {{Wiki|concept}} mdtra functions in the context of [[Vasubandhu's]] [[philosophy]] with a meaning akin to that of the English “merely.”  
  
Attempting an historical analysis of the concept of vijnapti, Hall starts his essay pointing to the shortcomings of the available English translations of the term vijnaptimdtra as “representation-only” (Hamilton:1938), “ideation-only” (Chan: 1957), and “perception-only” (Anacker: 1984), and then proposes an analysis of the term's usage in the original Sanskrit as the alternative to a new English translation of it.
+
Attempting an historical analysis of the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[vijnapti]], Hall starts his essay pointing to the shortcomings of the available English translations of the term vijnaptimdtra as “representation-only” (Hamilton:1938), “ideation-only” ([[Chan]]: 1957), and “[[perception-only]]” ([[Anacker]]: 1984), and then proposes an analysis of the term's usage in the original [[Sanskrit]] as the alternative to a new English translation of it.
  
  
Hall then proceeds to examine the concept's appearance in the Sarvastivadin Abhidharma, and stresses Vasubandhu's appropriation of the term and employment of it in a special sense.  
+
Hall then proceeds to examine the concept's [[appearance]] in the [[Sarvastivadin Abhidharma]], and stresses [[Vasubandhu's]] appropriation of the term and employment of it in a special [[sense]].  
  
Aptly citing the philosopher's Abhidharmakosa-bhdsya, Hall demonstrates how in that work the concept of vijnapti is intrinsically related to that of vijndna. There, he argues, vijnapti is understood as the very apprehension of consciousness with respect to the various sense objects (p. 12). Another important factor in understanding the term, Hall contends, relates to Vasubandhu's equation of it with other concepts used to define the notion of “mind,” a contention followed by a thorough analysis of such concepts as they mutually interact.
+
Aptly citing the philosopher's Abhidharmakosa-bhdsya, Hall demonstrates how in that work the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[vijnapti]] is intrinsically related to that of vijndna. There, he argues, [[vijnapti]] is understood as the very apprehension of [[consciousness]] with [[respect]] to the various [[sense objects]] (p. 12). Another important factor in [[understanding]] the term, Hall contends, relates to [[Vasubandhu's]] equation of it with other [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] used to define the notion of “[[mind]],” a contention followed by a thorough analysis of such [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] as they mutually interact.
  
  
In the second part of his essay, Hall inquires on the meaning of the concept “mdtra,” pointing to its various possible translations. One such translation, that is, that of mdtra as “mere,” is readily dismissed. Still, Hall recognizes that an important question remains, namely, why does Vasubandhu employ the term vijnaptimdtra in his works instead of remaining faithful to the earlier notion of “cittamdtra” that appears in several sutras, as well as in the works of Asanga.
+
In the second part of his essay, Hall inquires on the meaning of the {{Wiki|concept}} “mdtra,” pointing to its various possible translations. One such translation, that is, that of mdtra as “mere,” is readily dismissed. Still, Hall [[recognizes]] that an important question remains, namely, why does [[Vasubandhu]] employ the term vijnaptimdtra in his works instead of remaining [[faithful]] to the earlier notion of “cittamdtra” that appears in several [[sutras]], as well as in the works of [[Asanga]].
  
  
Hall then offers, somewhat against his originally stated purpose, what amounts to a translation of vijnaptimdtra, rendering the concept as “percept” and engaging it in an East/West comparative analysis where “vijnaptimatra” and “percept” are seen as equivalent. Hall's claim is that, just like a percept, a vijnapti is a representation that is independent on the existence of an external object.  
+
Hall then offers, somewhat against his originally stated {{Wiki|purpose}}, what amounts to a translation of vijnaptimdtra, rendering the {{Wiki|concept}} as “[[percept]]” and engaging it in an East/West comparative analysis where “[[vijnaptimatra]]” and “[[percept]]” are seen as {{Wiki|equivalent}}. Hall's claim is that, just like a [[percept]], a [[vijnapti]] is a [[representation]] that is {{Wiki|independent}} on the [[existence]] of an [[external object]].  
  
Such type of representation is understood by Hall as a purely mental product, and as such is equated with the notion of “mind-only.” In Hall's words, and within his attempt to justify his linking of “vijnaptimatra” and “percept,” “when vijnapti is qualified as ‘mind-only,' it cannot be meant as a representation of anything else, especially not of an external object.” (Hall 1986: 14).
+
Such type of [[representation]] is understood by Hall as a purely [[mental]] product, and as such is equated with the notion of “[[mind-only]].” In Hall's words, and within his attempt to justify his linking of “[[vijnaptimatra]]” and “[[percept]],” “when [[vijnapti]] is qualified as ‘[[mind-only]],' it cannot be meant as a [[representation]] of anything else, especially not of an [[external object]].” (Hall 1986: 14).
  
  
Equating the notion of vijnapti with “mind-only,” however, will lead us into serious difficulties if “mind-only” is to be understood not as a qualifier of external reality—that is, as an explanation that any object represented in consciousness does not exist outside of consciousness itself (and, in this particular sense is “mind-only”)—but as a state of being in which mind abides without being linked to the representation, or mental construction, of any object.  
+
Equating the notion of [[vijnapti]] with “[[mind-only]],” however, will lead us into serious difficulties if “[[mind-only]]” is to be understood not as a qualifier of external reality—that is, as an explanation that any [[object]] represented in [[consciousness]] does not [[exist]] outside of [[consciousness]] itself (and, in this particular [[sense]] is “mind-only”)—but as a [[state of being]] in which [[mind]] abides without being linked to the [[representation]], or [[mental]] construction, of any [[object]].  
  
We should be attentive, then, to these two possible understandings of “mind-only,” namely, one that is a description of the world in its quality of a mind-constructed entity, and another that describes the state of a pure mind that does not apprehend objects as external to itself. The point to be kept in mind here, however, is that when cross-analyzing the scholarship on Vasubandhu, such a distinction between the two possible understandings of “mind-only” is—as we soon will see—largely overlooked.
+
We should be attentive, then, to these two possible understandings of “[[mind-only]],” namely, one that is a description of the [[world]] in its [[quality]] of a mind-constructed [[entity]], and another that describes the [[state]] of a [[pure mind]] that does not apprehend [[objects]] as external to itself. The point to be kept in [[mind]] here, however, is that when cross-analyzing the {{Wiki|scholarship}} on [[Vasubandhu]], such a {{Wiki|distinction}} between the two possible understandings of “[[mind-only]]” is—as we soon will see—largely overlooked.
  
  
  
Be it as it may, as such double capacity of the concept of “mind-only” is based precisely on the perception of the dual nature of reality, and in this sense is fundamental to the correct grasping of Vasubandhu's soteriology, my contention at this point is that Hall, by mistakenly applying the second sense of “mind-only” to vijnaptimatra, blurs the doctrine of the two truths out of Vasubandhu's enterprise.
+
Be it as it may, as such double capacity of the {{Wiki|concept}} of “[[mind-only]]” is based precisely on the [[perception]] of the dual [[nature of reality]], and in this [[sense]] is fundamental to the correct [[grasping]] of [[Vasubandhu's]] {{Wiki|soteriology}}, my contention at this point is that Hall, by mistakenly applying the second [[sense]] of “[[mind-only]]” to [[vijnaptimatra]], blurs the [[doctrine of the two truths]] out of [[Vasubandhu's]] enterprise.
  
  
In the same vein, by losing sight of the aforementioned double sense of “mind-only,” Hall appears to overlook the fact that a vijnapti cannot be regarded simply as an objectless representation, or as something that “cannot be meant as the representation of anything else,” for even if the object represented in a vijnapti had no equivalent in external reality, such representation would still be not objectless to the extent that it would still exist as a mental object.  
+
In the same vein, by losing [[sight]] of the aforementioned double [[sense]] of “[[mind-only]],” Hall appears to overlook the fact that a [[vijnapti]] cannot be regarded simply as an objectless [[representation]], or as something that “cannot be meant as the [[representation]] of anything else,” for even if the [[object]] represented in a [[vijnapti]] had no {{Wiki|equivalent}} in [[external reality]], such [[representation]] would still be not objectless to the extent that it would still [[exist]] as a [[mental object]].  
  
In other words, regardless of whether or not such representation has a bearing on external reality, it still implies the presence of the very mental representation that it itself is.  
+
In other words, regardless of whether or not such [[representation]] has a bearing on [[external reality]], it still implies the presence of the very [[mental]] [[representation]] that it itself is.  
  
If we followed Hall's argument, then, vijnaptimatra would amount to something scarcely different then vijnapti: it would be a sort of “vijnapti-only” where the external object would, given its non-necessity, be ruled out. Such understanding of vijnaptimatra, however, is also unable carry the connotation, actually implied in Hall's analysis, of “mind-only” in the sense of “mind-itself,” or of a mind free from representation or thought construction.  
+
If we followed Hall's argument, then, [[vijnaptimatra]] would amount to something scarcely different then [[vijnapti]]: it would be a sort of “vijnapti-only” where the [[external object]] would, given its non-necessity, be ruled out. Such [[understanding]] of [[vijnaptimatra]], however, is also unable carry the connotation, actually implied in Hall's analysis, of “[[mind-only]]” in the [[sense]] of “[[mind-itself]],” or of a [[mind]] free from [[representation]] or [[thought]] construction.  
  
For such a free mind would not be the one that abides in a state of objectless representation, even if an “objectless representation” were in fact possible, but the one that would exist in the very absence of any representation. Such would be the mind in the state of what the Yogacara tradition calls nirvikalpa-jnana, or “non-discriminative perception.”
+
For such a free [[mind]] would not be the one that abides in a [[state]] of objectless [[representation]], even if an “objectless [[representation]]” were in fact possible, but the one that would [[exist]] in the very absence of any [[representation]]. Such would be the [[mind]] in the [[state]] of what the [[Yogacara tradition]] calls [[nirvikalpa-jnana]], or “non-discriminative [[perception]].”
  
  
This second understanding of “mind-only,” as a state of being, as opposed to an adjective that qualifies external reality, will in fact appear, as we will see, in Willis's translation of the term “vijnaptimatrata” as it occurs in Vasubandhu's Trimsika, verse 25.  
+
This second [[understanding]] of “[[mind-only]],” as a [[state of being]], as opposed to an {{Wiki|adjective}} that qualifies [[external reality]], will in fact appear, as we will see, in Willis's translation of the term “[[vijnaptimatrata]]” as it occurs in [[Vasubandhu's]] [[Trimsika]], verse 25.  
  
My point here, however, is not to assert that the term “mind-only” should be employed only in one of the two senses discussed above, but that, given the evident difficulties the term is prone to create, the employment of another term altogether might be a better option. At any rate, were the employment of the term to be insisted upon, we should expect that the above two senses would, at least, be clearly distinguished.
+
My point here, however, is not to assert that the term “[[mind-only]]” should be employed only in one of the two [[senses]] discussed above, but that, given the evident difficulties the term is prone to create, the employment of another term altogether might be a better option. At any rate, were the employment of the term to be insisted upon, we should expect that the above two [[senses]] would, at least, be clearly {{Wiki|distinguished}}.
  
  
Be that as it may, before we can move look into more translations of Vasubandhu's work, it is important to emphasize that what lies at the heart of Hall's misunderstanding of the meaning of vijnaptimatra, and of his dismissal of the obviously valid translation of the term matra as “mere,” is, besides his inattentiveness of the difference between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata, the perception of a positive connotation pertaining to the concept of vijnaptimatra as it appears in Vasubandhu's system.  
+
Be that as it may, before we can move look into more translations of [[Vasubandhu's]] work, it is important to {{Wiki|emphasize}} that what lies at the [[heart]] of Hall's {{Wiki|misunderstanding}} of the meaning of [[vijnaptimatra]], and of his dismissal of the obviously valid translation of the term [[matra]] as “mere,” is, besides his [[inattentiveness]] of the difference between [[vijnaptimatra]] and [[vijnaptimatrata]], the [[perception]] of a positive connotation pertaining to the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[vijnaptimatra]] as it appears in [[Vasubandhu's]] system.  
  
Linked to such perception is Hall's assertion that Vasubandhu's use of “vijnapti” in the compound vijnaptimatra instead of “vijnana” or “citta,” “seems to indicate an intent to avoid the idealist extreme.” (Hall 1986: 15).
+
Linked to such [[perception]] is Hall's [[assertion]] that [[Vasubandhu's]] use of “[[vijnapti]]” in the compound [[vijnaptimatra]] instead of “[[vijnana]]” or “[[citta]],” “seems to indicate an intent to avoid the {{Wiki|idealist}} extreme.” (Hall 1986: 15).
  
  
In spite of the fact that we can find no clear evidence that to “avoid the idealist extreme” is anything that Vasubandhu himself had in mind, such avoidance would seem, to Hall, to account for a positive quality inherent in vijnaptimatra, a quality that the negative adjectival function of the word “mere” would perforce downplay.  
+
In spite of the fact that we can find no clear {{Wiki|evidence}} that to “avoid the {{Wiki|idealist}} extreme” is anything that [[Vasubandhu]] himself had in [[mind]], such avoidance would seem, to Hall, to account for a positive [[quality]] [[inherent]] in [[vijnaptimatra]], a [[quality]] that the negative adjectival function of the [[word]] “mere” would perforce downplay.  
  
Nevertheless, were we to grant the positive quality claimed by Hall, vijnaptimatra would appear not as a critique of reality, that is, not as a warning that the world of objects in its entirety is nothing more than, or “merely a,” mind construct, but as something else that, on the contrary, should be striven for. And it is precisely here that Hall misses the soteriological principle that directs the whole of Vasubandhu's philosophy.  
+
Nevertheless, were we to grant the positive [[quality]] claimed by Hall, [[vijnaptimatra]] would appear not as a critique of [[reality]], that is, not as a warning that the [[world]] of [[objects]] in its entirety is nothing more than, or “merely a,” [[mind]] construct, but as something else that, on the contrary, should be striven for. And it is precisely here that Hall misses the [[soteriological]] [[principle]] that directs the whole of [[Vasubandhu's]] [[philosophy]].  
  
For the perception of a positive connotation to vijnaptimatra leads Hall (1986: 15) to assert that “mind itself is vijnaptimatra”, an assertion that not only Vasubandhu himself is not willing to make, but that also contradicts the simple logic that if vijnaptimatra can be understood as “representation only,” then “mind itself,” in the context of Vasubandhu's soteriology, cannot be such “representation only,” but, on the contrary, it must, again, be mind free from such representation.
+
For the [[perception]] of a positive connotation to [[vijnaptimatra]] leads Hall (1986: 15) to assert that “[[mind]] itself is [[vijnaptimatra]]”, an [[assertion]] that not only [[Vasubandhu]] himself is not willing to make, but that also contradicts the simple [[logic]] that if [[vijnaptimatra]] can be understood as “[[representation]] only,” then “[[mind]] itself,” in the context of [[Vasubandhu's]] {{Wiki|soteriology}}, cannot be such “[[representation]] only,” but, on the contrary, it must, again, be [[mind]] free from such [[representation]].
  
  
Another important point is that what appears to be lying at the heart of Hall's misunderstanding is a failure to effectively recognize the adjectival function assumed by the notion of vijnaptimatra in Vasubandhu's texts.  
+
Another important point is that what appears to be {{Wiki|lying}} at the [[heart]] of Hall's {{Wiki|misunderstanding}} is a failure to effectively [[recognize]] the adjectival function assumed by the notion of [[vijnaptimatra]] in [[Vasubandhu's]] texts.  
  
As we will see below, although the term is employed in different ways (as for instance, a “teaching,” as that which is “responsible for the false notion of the self,” and as that which “accounts for the perceptual arising of form”), its primary grammatical function in Vasubandhu's usage is that of an adjective, that is, as a description of reality.  
+
As we will see below, although the term is employed in different ways (as for instance, a “[[teaching]],” as that which is “responsible for the false notion of the [[self]],” and as that which “accounts for the {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[arising]] of [[form]]”), its primary {{Wiki|grammatical}} function in [[Vasubandhu's]] usage is that of an {{Wiki|adjective}}, that is, as a description of [[reality]].  
  
As we will see below, if we take the first paragraph of the Vimsatikav®tti as paradigmatic, we will notice that all Vasubandhu asserts at that point is that the trailokadhatu, or the external world in its tripartite conception, is vijnaptimatra, and not that “mind itself” is so.  
+
As we will see below, if we take the first paragraph of the Vimsatikav®tti as paradigmatic, we will notice that all [[Vasubandhu]] asserts at that point is that the trailokadhatu, or the [[external world]] in its tripartite {{Wiki|conception}}, is [[vijnaptimatra]], and not that “[[mind]] itself” is so.  
  
Paying close attention to the grammatical function of vijnaptimatra in the texts themselves, then, will lead us to see that the term qualifies the external world of objects in a negative way, that is, as something that is nothing but, or that is “merely,” a mind construct. The point to be kept in perspective is thus that since vijnaptimatra describes and qualifies the mentally constructed world, it can only describe and qualify conventional reality. And if this is correct, it then remains for us to learn what the concept would be that would describe and qualify ultimate reality.
+
Paying [[close attention]] to the {{Wiki|grammatical}} function of [[vijnaptimatra]] in the texts themselves, then, will lead us to see that the term qualifies the [[external world]] of [[objects]] in a negative way, that is, as something that is nothing but, or that is “merely,” a [[mind]] construct. The point to be kept in {{Wiki|perspective}} is thus that since [[vijnaptimatra]] describes and qualifies the [[mentally]] [[constructed]] [[world]], it can only describe and qualify [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[reality]]. And if this is correct, it then remains for us to learn what the {{Wiki|concept}} would be that would describe and qualify [[ultimate reality]].
  
  
In spite of the above misapprehensions, Hall (1986: 18) is in fact correct when, at the end of his essay, he points to the fact that “it is, after all, sainsara that is declared to be vijnaptimatra.” And, if this is so, then here again we should pose the question: if Vasubandhu uses the term vijnaptimatra to account for experience of sainsara, then what term does he use to account for nirvana?
+
In spite of the above misapprehensions, Hall (1986: 18) is in fact correct when, at the end of his essay, he points to the fact that “it is, after all, sainsara that is declared to be [[vijnaptimatra]].” And, if this is so, then here again we should pose the question: if [[Vasubandhu]] uses the term [[vijnaptimatra]] to account for [[experience]] of sainsara, then what term does he use to account for [[nirvana]]?
  
  
Line 214: Line 214:
  
  
In order to arrive at a clear understanding of the difference between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata, and of the rapport between the latter concept and that of paramartha sat, we must now look into Vasubandhu's actual texts and verify how his employment of “vijnaptimatra” is consistent with the translation of the term matra as “mere.”  
+
In order to arrive at a [[clear understanding]] of the difference between [[vijnaptimatra]] and [[vijnaptimatrata]], and of the rapport between the [[latter]] {{Wiki|concept}} and that of [[paramartha]] sat, we must now look into [[Vasubandhu's]] actual texts and verify how his employment of “[[vijnaptimatra]]” is consistent with the translation of the term [[matra]] as “mere.”  
  
After doing this, we will be in a position to look into the philosopher's usage of “vijnaptimatrata,” and to work comparatively between the two terms, with the double purpose of demonstrating their difference while at the same time showing that the blurring of their boundaries occurs, for the most part, at the level of translation.
+
After doing this, we will be in a position to look into the philosopher's usage of “[[vijnaptimatrata]],” and to work comparatively between the two terms, with the double {{Wiki|purpose}} of demonstrating their difference while at the same time showing that the blurring of their [[boundaries]] occurs, for the most part, at the level of translation.
  
  
In the first verse of the Vimsatika Vasubadhu writes:
+
In the first verse of the [[Vimsatika]] Vasubadhu writes:
  
vijnaptimatramevaitadasadarthavabhasanat| yatha taimirikasyasatkesacandradidarsanam ||1||
+
vijnaptimatramevaitadasadarthavabhasanat| [[yatha]] taimirikasyasatkesacandradidarsanam ||1||
Below we find Kochumuttom's translation of the passage. Notice that “vijnaptimatra” is correctly rendered by the word “mere”:
+
Below we find Kochumuttom's translation of the passage. Notice that “[[vijnaptimatra]]” is correctly rendered by the [[word]] “mere”:
  
It is all mere representation of consciousness,
+
It is all mere [[representation]] of [[consciousness]],
Because there is the appearance of non-existent objects;
+
Because there is the [[appearance]] of [[non-existent]] [[objects]];
  
 
Just as a man with a cataract
 
Just as a man with a cataract
 
Sees hairs, moons, etc.
 
Sees hairs, moons, etc.
Which do not exist in reality. (Kochumuttom 1982: 166)
+
Which do not [[exist]] in [[reality]]. ({{Wiki|Kochumuttom}} 1982: 166)
  
In the same vein, Anacker's translation of the term, albeit not inclusive of the word “mere,” does not get in the way of understanding the negative connotation of vijnaptimatra:
+
In the same vein, Anacker's translation of the term, albeit not inclusive of the [[word]] “mere,” does not get in the way of [[understanding]] the negative connotation of [[vijnaptimatra]]:
All this is perception only, because of the appearance
+
All this is [[perception]] only, because of the [[appearance]]
of non-existent objects,
+
of [[non-existent]] [[objects]],
  
just as there may be the seeing of non-existent nets of hair by someone afflicted with an optical disorder. (Anacker 1984: 161).
+
just as there may be the [[seeing]] of [[non-existent]] nets of [[hair]] by someone afflicted with an optical disorder. ([[Anacker]] 1984: 161).
  
  
Here the notion “perception only” works as a qualifier of reality that devalues its contents in view of assumed limitations in cognition. Such is the agreement on the basic meaning of vijnaptimdtra. When it comes to the term "vijnaptimatrata." however, there is less agreement as to translation. Before we can point out the discrepancies, however, it is important to notice that Anacker renders “vijnaptimdtratd" in a manner that does not differentiate it from "vijnaptimatra." Here is verse 25 of the Trimsikd. followed by his translation:
+
Here the notion “[[perception]] only” works as a qualifier of [[reality]] that devalues its contents in view of assumed limitations in [[cognition]]. Such is the agreement on the basic meaning of vijnaptimdtra. When it comes to the term "[[vijnaptimatrata]]." however, there is less agreement as to translation. Before we can point out the discrepancies, however, it is important to notice that [[Anacker]] renders “vijnaptimdtratd" in a manner that does not differentiate it from "[[vijnaptimatra]]." Here is verse 25 of the Trimsikd. followed by his translation:
  
  
dharmanam paramarthasca sa yatastathata’pi sah\ sarvakalam tathabhavat saiva vijnaptimdtratd ||25||
+
dharmanam paramarthasca sa yatastathata’pi sah\ [[sarvakalam]] tathabhavat {{Wiki|saiva}} vijnaptimdtratd ||25||
 
Anacker’s translation (1984: 188):
 
Anacker’s translation (1984: 188):
  
  
It is the ultimate truth of all events, and so it is “Suchness”, too, since it is just so all the time, and it’s just perception-only.
+
It is [[the ultimate truth]] of all events, and so it is “[[Suchness]]”, too, since it is just so all the time, and it’s just [[perception-only]].
As we can perceive, Anacker fails to distinguish “vijnaptimdtra" from “vijnaptimdtratd" in his translation, rendering both terms as “perception-only.” Kochumuttom’s translation (1982: 157) of Trimsikd 25, however, presents a development from Anacker’s:
+
As we can {{Wiki|perceive}}, [[Anacker]] fails to distinguish “vijnaptimdtra" from “vijnaptimdtratd" in his translation, rendering both terms as “[[perception-only]].” Kochumuttom’s translation (1982: 157) of Trimsikd 25, however, presents a [[development]] from Anacker’s:
  
That from which all elements have their ultimate reality,
+
That from which all [[elements]] have their [[ultimate reality]],
[Is the third naturelessness,] It is also called suclmess,
+
[Is the third [[naturelessness]],] It is also called suclmess,
 
Because it remains always as such;
 
Because it remains always as such;
  
That is itself the state [in which one realizes the meaning]
+
That is itself the [[state]] [in which one realizes the meaning]
Of mere representation of consciousness, too.
+
Of mere [[representation]] of [[consciousness]], too.
  
Here the word “state” indicates Kochumuttom’s perception of the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd. Going from the first as “mere representation of consciousness” to the second as “the state [in which one realizes the meaning] of mere representation of consciousness,” however, may not sufficiently emphasize the difference, obscuring it for the reader who does not have prior knowledge of Vasubandhu’s arguments, or that lacks access to the original Sanskrit text. At any rate, and as we will see in more detail below, Kochumuttom’s rendering is valid.
+
Here the [[word]] “[[state]]” indicates Kochumuttom’s [[perception]] of the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd. Going from the first as “mere [[representation]] of [[consciousness]]” to the second as “the [[state]] [in which one realizes the meaning] of mere [[representation]] of [[consciousness]],” however, may not sufficiently {{Wiki|emphasize}} the difference, {{Wiki|obscuring}} it for the reader who does not have prior [[knowledge]] of [[Vasubandhu’s]] arguments, or that lacks access to the original [[Sanskrit]] text. At any rate, and as we will see in more detail below, Kochumuttom’s rendering is valid.
  
  
Contrary to Anacker and Kochumuttom, Willis translates “vijnaptimatra” and “vijnaptimatrata” in a more clearly differentiated manner. Below, we find her translation of the same verse (Trimsikd, 25), which should be compared with the previously cited fragment where we observed her rendering of vijnaptimatra as “merely an object-like mental image”:
+
Contrary to [[Anacker]] and {{Wiki|Kochumuttom}}, Willis translates “[[vijnaptimatra]]” and “[[vijnaptimatrata]]” in a more clearly differentiated manner. Below, we find her translation of the same verse (Trimsikd, 25), which should be compared with the previously cited fragment where we observed her rendering of [[vijnaptimatra]] as “merely an object-like [[mental]] image”:
  
  
The supreme truth of all dharmas
+
The [[supreme truth]] of all [[dharmas]]
  
Is nothing other than the True Norm (suchness).
+
Is nothing other than the True Norm ([[suchness]]).
It is forever true to its nature,
+
It is forever true to its [[nature]],
Which is the true nature of mind-only.( Willis 1979: 34)
+
Which is the [[true nature]] of [[mind-only]].( Willis 1979: 34)
  
  
Willis thus goes from vijnaptimatra as “merely an object­like mental image” to vijnaptimatrata as “mind-only.” Recalling Hall's renderings of Vasubandhu's concepts, and now cross­examining it with Willis's, we observe that the former employs “mind-only” in reference to vijnaptimatra, and that the latter does so in regard to vijnaptimatrata. Such a double usage of “mind- only” hides from the reader the basic difference between the two Sanskrit terms.
+
Willis thus goes from [[vijnaptimatra]] as “merely an object­like [[mental]] image” to [[vijnaptimatrata]] as “[[mind-only]].” Recalling Hall's renderings of [[Vasubandhu's]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], and now cross­examining it with Willis's, we observe that the former employs “[[mind-only]]” in reference to [[vijnaptimatra]], and that the [[latter]] does so in regard to [[vijnaptimatrata]]. Such a double usage of “[[mind]]- only” hides from the reader the basic difference between the two [[Sanskrit]] terms.
  
  
  
With that in mind, we must now observe another translation of the passage. In the following fragment we will see that, as an alternative to the previously observed efforts of Willis, Anacker and Kochumuttom, Yamada opts for leaving the term “vijnaptimatrata” untranslated (notice that he joins verses 24 and 25 of the Trimsika in his translation):
+
With that in [[mind]], we must now observe another translation of the passage. In the following fragment we will see that, as an alternative to the previously observed efforts of Willis, [[Anacker]] and {{Wiki|Kochumuttom}}, Yamada opts for leaving the term “[[vijnaptimatrata]]” untranslated (notice that he joins verses 24 and 25 of the [[Trimsika]] in his translation):
  
  
 
Thus, there is the next non-being-ness (nihsvabhdvatd),
 
Thus, there is the next non-being-ness (nihsvabhdvatd),
for that [sa = nispnanna-svabhava] is the ultimate reality of all dharmas.
+
for that [sa = nispnanna-svabhava] is the [[ultimate reality]] of all [[dharmas]].
 
It is such-ness (tathatd), as it is such-being (tathdbhdva) at all times.
 
It is such-ness (tathatd), as it is such-being (tathdbhdva) at all times.
  
Line 282: Line 282:
 
This is, indeed, vijnaptimdtratd. (Yamada 1997: 168)
 
This is, indeed, vijnaptimdtratd. (Yamada 1997: 168)
  
If Yamada's rendering of Trimsikd 25 does not provide us with a translation of “vijnaptimdtratd,” at another point of the same essay where the above fragment appears he does seem to be attentive to the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd. By rendering the latter term as “Vijnapti-Only- ness” (Yamada 1997: 172), however, Yamada once again falls short of providing us with a complete translation.
+
If Yamada's rendering of Trimsikd 25 does not provide us with a translation of “vijnaptimdtratd,” at another point of the same essay where the above fragment appears he does seem to be attentive to the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd. By rendering the [[latter]] term as “Vijnapti-Only- ness” (Yamada 1997: 172), however, Yamada once again falls short of providing us with a complete translation.
  
  
We are thus provided with four translations of “vijnaptimdtratd”: Kochumuttom's “state in which one realizes the meaning of mere representation of consciousness,” Anacker's “perception-only,” Willis's “mind-only,” together with Yamada's renderings. Given that the four previous examples tend to obstruct our way into a clear distinction between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata in translation, we should now look at a fifth rendering of Trimsika 25. Richard H. Robinson's translation accomplishes a more clear differentiation between the two concepts:
+
We are thus provided with four translations of “vijnaptimdtratd”: Kochumuttom's “[[state]] in which one realizes the meaning of mere [[representation]] of [[consciousness]],” Anacker's “[[perception-only]],” Willis's “[[mind-only]],” together with Yamada's renderings. Given that the four previous examples tend to obstruct our way into a clear {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[vijnaptimatra]] and [[vijnaptimatrata]] in translation, we should now look at a fifth rendering of [[Trimsika]] 25. Richard H. Robinson's translation accomplishes a more clear differentiation between the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]:
  
  
Because it is the absoluteness of the elements and their suchness,
+
Because it is the [[absoluteness]] of the [[elements]] and their [[suchness]],
Because it is ‘so' forever. It alone is perception-only-ness. (Lusthaus 2002: 299)
+
Because it is ‘so' forever. It alone is perception-only-ness. ([[Lusthaus]] 2002: 299)
  
  
Here one sees the suffix “ta” added by Vasubandhu to “vijnaptimatra” being accounted for by the English particle “ness.” Such rendering allows for a more precise understanding of the concept than was possible with the previously cited translations. Robinson's version of the following verse 26 of the Trimsika provides us with another instance where a clearer understanding of vijnaptimatrata becomes evident:
+
Here one sees the suffix “ta” added by [[Vasubandhu]] to “[[vijnaptimatra]]” being accounted for by the English {{Wiki|particle}} “ness.” Such rendering allows for a more precise [[understanding]] of the {{Wiki|concept}} than was possible with the previously cited translations. Robinson's version of the following verse 26 of the [[Trimsika]] provides us with another instance where a clearer [[understanding]] of [[vijnaptimatrata]] becomes evident:
  
  
yavad vijnaptimatratve vijnanam navatisthatil grahadvayasyanusayastavanna vinivartate ||26||
+
yavad vijnaptimatratve [[vijnanam]] navatisthatil grahadvayasyanusayastavanna vinivartate ||26||
So long as consciousness does not remain in the state of representation-only,
+
So long as [[consciousness]] does not remain in the [[state]] of representation-only,
The residues of the twofold grasping will not cease to function. (Lusthaus 2002: 300)
+
The residues of the twofold [[grasping]] will not cease to function. ([[Lusthaus]] 2002: 300)
  
  
Noticing that the Sanskrit suffix “tva” (appearing in the verse in the locative form “vijnaptimatratve”), possesses a grammatical function analogous to that of “ta,” we find Robinson replacing the previous particle “ness” of verse 25 with the word “state.”  
+
Noticing that the [[Sanskrit]] suffix “tva” (appearing in the verse in the [[locative]] [[form]] “vijnaptimatratve”), possesses a {{Wiki|grammatical}} function analogous to that of “ta,” we find [[Robinson]] replacing the previous {{Wiki|particle}} “ness” of verse 25 with the [[word]] “[[state]].”  
  
Such qualification of “representation-only” as a state of being arrived at by consciousness gives us a clear awareness of the import of “vijnaptimatrata” as something other than a qualifier of external reality. Below are alternative renderings of verse of 26: Willis (1979: 35):
+
Such qualification of “representation-only” as a [[state of being]] arrived at by [[consciousness]] gives us a clear [[awareness]] of the import of “[[vijnaptimatrata]]” as something other than a qualifier of [[external reality]]. Below are alternative renderings of verse of 26: Willis (1979: 35):
  
  
Inasmuch as consciousness in its unawakened state
+
Inasmuch as [[consciousness]] in its unawakened [[state]]
Is not in the abode of the reality of mind-only,
+
Is not in the abode of the [[reality]] of [[mind-only]],
  
The six-sense organs, their objects, and the seeds of evil desires Cannot be controlled and extirpated.
+
The [[six-sense organs]], their [[objects]], and the [[seeds]] of [[evil]] [[desires]] Cannot be controlled and extirpated.
Anacker (1984: 188):
+
[[Anacker]] (1984: 188):
  
As long as consciousness is not situated within perception only, the residues of a “dual” apprehension will not come to an end.
+
As long as [[consciousness]] is not situated within [[perception]] only, the residues of a “dual” apprehension will not come to an end.
Kochumuttom (1982: 158):
+
{{Wiki|Kochumuttom}} (1982: 158):
  
As long as consciousness does not abide
+
As long as [[consciousness]] does not abide
In the realization [that the subject-object designations]
+
In the [[realization]] [that the subject-object designations]
Are mere representations of consciousness,
+
Are mere {{Wiki|representations}} of [[consciousness]],
The attachment to the twofold grasping
+
The [[attachment]] to the twofold [[grasping]]
 
Will not cease to operate.
 
Will not cease to operate.
  
  
Among the three translations, Kochumuttom's is again especially worthy of attention. If we agree with the notion that the term “vijnaptimatrata” refers to the state of being where the mind is free from conceptualization, and that such freedom occurs precisely as the “realization that the subject-object designations are mere representations of consciousness” then Kochumuttom's translation does in fact present us with a valid rendering of vijnaptimatrata, one that is, indeed, akin to that of Robinson.
+
Among the three translations, Kochumuttom's is again especially worthy of [[attention]]. If we agree with the notion that the term “[[vijnaptimatrata]]” refers to the [[state of being]] where the [[mind]] is free from [[conceptualization]], and that such freedom occurs precisely as the “[[realization]] that the subject-object designations are mere {{Wiki|representations}} of [[consciousness]]” then Kochumuttom's translation does in fact {{Wiki|present}} us with a valid rendering of [[vijnaptimatrata]], one that is, indeed, akin to that of [[Robinson]].
  
  
The above identification of the mind free from thought construction with the realization that the dualism implied in the subject-object distinction is merely mind constructed, however, leaves room for extensive doctrinal debate.  
+
The above identification of the [[mind]] free from [[thought]] construction with the [[realization]] that the [[dualism]] implied in the subject-object {{Wiki|distinction}} is merely [[mind]] [[constructed]], however, leaves room for extensive [[doctrinal]] [[debate]].  
  
Although we can assert with a high degree of certainty that, within the Buddhist reflection, the realization that all duality occurs primarily at the mental level is in fact a prerequisite for mind's abiding in non-conceptualization, such realization in and by itself, that is, in the sense of no more than a rational understanding, can hardly be equated with mind's freedom from thought construction.  
+
Although we can assert with a high [[degree]] of {{Wiki|certainty}} that, within the [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|reflection}}, the [[realization]] that all [[duality]] occurs primarily at the [[mental]] level is in fact a prerequisite for [[mind's]] abiding in non-conceptualization, such [[realization]] in and by itself, that is, in the [[sense]] of no more than a [[rational]] [[understanding]], can hardly be equated with [[mind's]] freedom from [[thought]] construction.  
  
To put in more clear terms, and always keeping in mind that we are dealing with problems at the level of translation, what we have at hand are two possible interpretations of the term “realization” that can give off two different meanings when applied in relation to vijnaptimatrata: the first, where “realization” is meant as an understanding that occurs primarily at the intellectual level, and the second where “realization” is intended as “actualization,” that is, as the coming into effect of something.
+
To put in more clear terms, and always keeping in [[mind]] that we are dealing with problems at the level of translation, what we have at hand are two possible interpretations of the term “[[realization]]” that can give off two different meanings when applied in [[relation]] to [[vijnaptimatrata]]: the first, where “[[realization]]” is meant as an [[understanding]] that occurs primarily at the [[intellectual]] level, and the second where “[[realization]]” is intended as “actualization,” that is, as the coming into effect of something.
  
  
In the phrase “As long as consciousness does not abide in the realization [that the subject-object designations] are mere representations of consciousness the attachment to the twofold grasping will not cease to operate,” Kochumuttom appears to be inattentive to the nuances of the term “realization,” and therefore employs it in the first sense described, that is, as a rational “realization” of a given idea.
+
In the [[phrase]] “As long as [[consciousness]] does not abide in the [[realization]] [that the subject-object designations] are mere {{Wiki|representations}} of [[consciousness]] the [[attachment]] to the twofold [[grasping]] will not cease to operate,” {{Wiki|Kochumuttom}} appears to be inattentive to the nuances of the term “[[realization]],” and therefore employs it in the first [[sense]] described, that is, as a [[rational]] “[[realization]]” of a given [[idea]].
  
  
Be that as it may, Kochumuttom's implication of the term “realization” with vijnaptimatrata is useful to our inquiry in that it helps us clarify our own aims. Our task here is first to demonstrate that vijnaptimatrata indeed implies “realization” in the second sense described above, that is, as “actualization,” and second to arrive at a translation of the Sanskrit term where such “realization” would be rendered in the clearest way possible.
+
Be that as it may, Kochumuttom's implication of the term “[[realization]]” with [[vijnaptimatrata]] is useful to our inquiry in that it helps us clarify our [[own]] aims. Our task here is first to demonstrate that [[vijnaptimatrata]] indeed implies “[[realization]]” in the second [[sense]] described above, that is, as “actualization,” and second to arrive at a translation of the [[Sanskrit]] term where such “[[realization]]” would be rendered in the clearest way possible.
  
  
Accomplishing the first task would thus imply a depiction of vijnaptimatrata as a realization that occurs not simply as a rational understanding of something, but as the actualization of a given element. As the element that is to be actualized is consciousness itself, the “realization” proposed would imply a transformation of consciousness, that is, its coming into a state where a change in its very nature has occurred.  
+
Accomplishing the first task would thus imply a depiction of [[vijnaptimatrata]] as a [[realization]] that occurs not simply as a [[rational]] [[understanding]] of something, but as the actualization of a given [[element]]. As the [[element]] that is to be actualized is [[consciousness]] itself, the “[[realization]]” proposed would imply a [[transformation of consciousness]], that is, its coming into a [[state]] where a change in its very [[nature]] has occurred.  
  
Such discussion, however, will inevitably fall under the doctrinal debate about the way in which such “transformation of consciousness” should be in fact described. As we will see, this debate is, in turn, inextricably linked to the inquiries into the meaning of asraya-parav®tti, and on the role played by meditative practices in the development of Buddhist philosophical concepts.  
+
Such [[discussion]], however, will inevitably fall under the [[doctrinal]] [[debate]] about the way in which such “[[transformation of consciousness]]” should be in fact described. As we will see, this [[debate]] is, in turn, inextricably linked to the inquiries into the meaning of asraya-parav®tti, and on the role played by [[meditative practices]] in the [[development]] of [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]].  
  
But before we can discuss the relation between vijnaptimatrata and asraya-parav®tti, we must first look at yet another translation that will provide us with the basis to further clarify the role played by the suffix “ta” in the formation of the compound “vijnaptimatrata.” Only after we clearly understand the grammatical elements integrated in the Sanskrit term, will we be in a position to inquire on its doctrinal and philosophical implications.
+
But before we can discuss the [[relation]] between [[vijnaptimatrata]] and asraya-parav®tti, we must first look at yet another translation that will provide us with the basis to further clarify the role played by the suffix “ta” in the formation of the compound “[[vijnaptimatrata]].” Only after we clearly understand the {{Wiki|grammatical}} [[elements]] integrated in the [[Sanskrit]] term, will we be in a position to inquire on its [[doctrinal]] and [[philosophical]] implications.
  
  
Turning to Xuanzang's Chinese translation of the Trimsika, Dan Lusthaus offers us yet another rendering of “vijnaptimatrata,” presenting it now as “psychosophical-closure-hood (Lusthaus 2002: 299).” In spite of the obvious difficulty in arriving at what “psychosophical-closure” could possibly mean, we do find in Lusthaus the same sort of consistency seen in Robinson where the suffix “ta” (or “tva”) is taken into account in the formation of Vasubandhu's compound. Rendering the particle “ta” as “hood” provides Lusthaus' translation of vijnaptimatrata with the abstract quality that removes it from the adjectival function of vijnaptimdtra.
+
Turning to [[Xuanzang's]] {{Wiki|Chinese}} translation of the [[Trimsika]], [[Dan Lusthaus]] offers us yet another rendering of “[[vijnaptimatrata]],” presenting it now as “psychosophical-closure-hood ([[Lusthaus]] 2002: 299).” In spite of the obvious difficulty in arriving at what “psychosophical-closure” could possibly mean, we do find in [[Lusthaus]] the same sort of consistency seen in [[Robinson]] where the suffix “ta” (or “tva”) is taken into account in the formation of [[Vasubandhu's]] compound. Rendering the {{Wiki|particle}} “ta” as “hood” provides [[Lusthaus]]' translation of [[vijnaptimatrata]] with the abstract [[quality]] that removes it from the adjectival function of vijnaptimdtra.
  
  
Here we must note that the question of the precise meaning of the suffix “td” in Sanskrit Buddhist texts has been discussed at length by Shoko Takeuchi in her essay “Phenomena and Reality in Vijnaptimatra Thought (I): On the usages of the suffix ‘ta' in Maitreya's Treatises.” Although in this work Takeuchi does not approach the question of the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd, her explanation of how the suffix “td” came to be understood as having a meaning of its own within Buddhist scholarship will certainly be illuminating for our discussion.
+
Here we must note that the question of the precise meaning of the suffix “td” in [[Sanskrit]] [[Buddhist texts]] has been discussed at length by [[Shoko]] Takeuchi in her essay “[[Phenomena]] and [[Reality]] in [[Vijnaptimatra]] [[Thought]] (I): On the usages of the suffix ‘ta' in [[Maitreya's]] Treatises.” Although in this work Takeuchi does not approach the question of the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd, her explanation of how the suffix “td” came to be understood as having a meaning of its [[own]] within [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|scholarship}} will certainly be [[illuminating]] for our [[discussion]].
  
  
After explaining how the suffix is employed in Sanskrit to form an abstract noun, and as such does not possess an independent meaning, Takeuchi shows how the Chinese Faxiang School understood the term “tathatd” to mean “absolute reality” by virtue of the suffix “td” appended to it. In Takeuchi's words (1977: 259),
+
After explaining how the suffix is employed in [[Sanskrit]] to [[form]] an abstract {{Wiki|noun}}, and as such does not possess an {{Wiki|independent}} meaning, Takeuchi shows how the {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Faxiang School]] understood the term “tathatd” to mean “[[absolute reality]]” by [[virtue]] of the suffix “td” appended to it. In Takeuchi's words (1977: 259),
  
  
Originally the relationship between ‘phenomena' and ‘reality' was explained as ‘neither identical nor different' simply by adding the suffix “td” to a word, e.g., dharma and dharmatd, tathd and tathatd, and so on. But the unique way in which the Fa-hsiang School explained this relationship originated in its interpretation that the suffix td has an independent meaning of its own.
+
Originally the relationship between ‘[[phenomena]]' and ‘[[reality]]' was explained as ‘neither [[identical]] nor different' simply by adding the suffix “td” to a [[word]], e.g., [[dharma]] and dharmatd, tathd and tathatd, and so on. But the unique way in which the [[Fa-hsiang School]] explained this relationship originated in its [[interpretation]] that the suffix td has an {{Wiki|independent}} meaning of its [[own]].
  
  
From the above we can derive two inferences that are closely related to our inquiry. The first, connected to our search for the clarification of the meaning of “vijnaptimdtratd,” would be that the interpretation of the Faxiang School regarding the usage of the suffix “td” in Maitreya's treatises might be valid, and as such might hold true to Vasubandhu's works as well.  
+
From the above we can derive two inferences that are closely related to our inquiry. The first, connected to our search for the clarification of the meaning of “vijnaptimdtratd,” would be that the [[interpretation]] of the [[Faxiang School]] regarding the usage of the suffix “td” in [[Maitreya's]] treatises might be valid, and as such might hold true to [[Vasubandhu's]] works as well.  
  
In such a case, that is, by possessing an independent meaning of its own, the suffix “td” might be prone to conferring a completely new meaning to vijnaptimdtratd, distinguishing it thus very clearly from vijnaptimdtra. The second inference, this one moving along the lines of inquiring on a possible explanation for the shortcomings of the English translations, would surmise that the absence of direct contact with that specific Chinese interpretation referred to by Takeuchi may have lead Western scholars to overlook the change in meaning provided by accretion of the suffix “td” to Sanskrit Buddhist concepts.  
+
In such a case, that is, by possessing an {{Wiki|independent}} meaning of its [[own]], the suffix “td” might be prone to conferring a completely new meaning to vijnaptimdtratd, distinguishing it thus very clearly from vijnaptimdtra. The second {{Wiki|inference}}, this one moving along the lines of inquiring on a possible explanation for the shortcomings of the English translations, would surmise that the absence of direct [[contact]] with that specific {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[interpretation]] referred to by Takeuchi may have lead [[Western]] [[scholars]] to overlook the change in meaning provided by accretion of the suffix “td” to [[Sanskrit]] [[Buddhist]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]].  
  
Be that as it may, and with the second supposition in mind, it is important to notice that among the seven renderings of vijnaptimdtrata seen so far, that is, by Willis, Anacker, Kochumuttom, Yamada, Robinson, and Lusthaus, only the last three, that is, the one’s from scholars that appear to have had contact with the abovementioned Chinese interpretation, show a clear awareness of the import of the suffix “to” in the formation of Vasubandhu’s compound concept.
+
Be that as it may, and with the second supposition in [[mind]], it is important to notice that among the seven renderings of vijnaptimdtrata seen so far, that is, by Willis, [[Anacker]], {{Wiki|Kochumuttom}}, Yamada, [[Robinson]], and [[Lusthaus]], only the last three, that is, the one’s from [[scholars]] that appear to have had [[contact]] with the abovementioned {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[interpretation]], show a clear [[awareness]] of the import of the suffix “to” in the formation of [[Vasubandhu’s]] compound {{Wiki|concept}}.
  
  
Having thus approached the grammatical functions of the elements that form Vasubandhu’s compound, we can now proceed to the second part of our inquiry, where a more direct contact with Vasubandhu’s original Sanskrit text is required.
+
Having thus approached the {{Wiki|grammatical}} functions of the [[elements]] that [[form]] [[Vasubandhu’s]] compound, we can now proceed to the second part of our inquiry, where a more direct [[contact]] with [[Vasubandhu’s]] original [[Sanskrit]] text is required.
  
  
2. Analysis of the five instances where the concepts appear in the Vimsatikd and Vimsatikavrtti after the first verse
+
2. Analysis of the five instances where the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] appear in the Vimsatikd and Vimsatikavrtti after the first verse
  
  
In order to demonstrate the difference between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimdtrata, I will now proceed to a close reading of the five instances where the terms appear in the Vimsatikd and Vimsatikavrtti after Vasubandhu’s initial statement to the effect that the entire universe (trailokadhatum) is vijnaptimatra.  
+
In order to demonstrate the difference between [[vijnaptimatra]] and vijnaptimdtrata, I will now proceed to a close reading of the five instances where the terms appear in the Vimsatikd and Vimsatikavrtti after [[Vasubandhu’s]] initial statement to the effect that the entire [[universe]] (trailokadhatum) is [[vijnaptimatra]].  
  
My purpose here is to call attention to the different meanings assumed by concepts throughout Vasubandhu’s text. In order to provide a clear view of how the terms function within their textual framework, I will provide my own translations for the passages cited while leaving the two Sanskrit terms untranslated. After proceeding through a commentary on their original formulation, I expect to find myself in a position where a new translation can be proposed.
+
My {{Wiki|purpose}} here is to call [[attention]] to the different meanings assumed by [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] throughout [[Vasubandhu’s]] text. In order to provide a clear view of how the terms function within their textual framework, I will provide my [[own]] translations for the passages cited while leaving the two [[Sanskrit]] terms untranslated. After proceeding through a commentary on their original formulation, I expect to find myself in a position where a [[new translation]] can be proposed.
  
  
  
2.1. Vijnaptimatra as a teaching (desanay.
+
2.1. [[Vijnaptimatra]] as a [[teaching]] (desanay.
  
  
  
anyatheti vijnaptimatradesana katham dharmanairatmya- pravesah vijnaptimatramidam rupadidharma-
+
anyatheti vijnaptimatradesana [[katham]] dharmanairatmya- pravesah vijnaptimatramidam rupadidharma-
pratibhasamntpadyate na tu ritpadilaksano dharmah ko’pyastiti viditvd. (Vasubandhu 2004: 127)
+
pratibhasamntpadyate na tu ritpadilaksano dharmah ko’pyastiti viditvd. ([[Vasubandhu]] 2004: 127)
Otherwise the teaching of vijnaptimatra refers to introducing the selflessness of phenomena.
+
Otherwise the [[teaching]] of [[vijnaptimatra]] refers to introducing the [[selflessness of phenomena]].
  
  
Ihus, vijnaptimatra accounts for the perceptual arising of form, etc., without in fact phenomena characterized by form having at all been known.
+
Ihus, [[vijnaptimatra]] accounts for the {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[arising]] of [[form]], etc., without in fact [[phenomena]] characterized by [[form]] having at all been known.
  
Here we find the term “vijnaptimatra'' followed by “desand” a term commonly understood as “instruction” or “teaching.” Thus “vijnaptimatra” appears as the content of a teaching, that is, of something that can be passed on through language in introducing the notion of the selflessness of phenomena. Notice that such “teaching,” however, is not described as being, in itself, an abiding in the state of selflessness.  
+
Here we find the term “[[vijnaptimatra]]'' followed by “desand” a term commonly understood as “instruction” or “[[teaching]].” Thus “[[vijnaptimatra]]” appears as the content of a [[teaching]], that is, of something that can be passed on through [[language]] in introducing the notion of the [[selflessness of phenomena]]. Notice that such “[[teaching]],” however, is not described as being, in itself, an abiding in the [[state]] of [[selflessness]].  
  
It simply “introduces” (pravesahj a characteristic of phenomena, or, for that matter, of reality as a whole, namely, that of being without a self. The adjectival function of vijnaptimatra, then (that is, that of describing reality in a peculiar way ), still takes precedence in the formulation of vijnaptimatra as something that can be taught.  
+
It simply “introduces” (pravesahj a [[characteristic]] of [[phenomena]], or, for that {{Wiki|matter}}, of [[reality]] as a whole, namely, that of being without a [[self]]. The adjectival function of [[vijnaptimatra]], then (that is, that of describing [[reality]] in a peculiar way ), still takes precedence in the formulation of [[vijnaptimatra]] as something that can be [[taught]].  
  
For what is taught is, once again, precisely a quality of reality. In the same vein, the negative import of such an adjectival function can be appraised in the next phrase, where Vasubandhu states that vijnaptimatra “accounts for the perceptual arising of form.” Here the concept clearly assumes the negative connotation that we saw being overlooked by Hall.  
+
For what is [[taught]] is, once again, precisely a [[quality]] of [[reality]]. In the same vein, the negative import of such an adjectival function can be appraised in the next [[phrase]], where [[Vasubandhu]] states that [[vijnaptimatra]] “accounts for the {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[arising]] of [[form]].” Here the {{Wiki|concept}} clearly assumes the negative connotation that we saw being overlooked by Hall.  
  
As the perceptual arising of form is understood primarily as a source of delusion, the teaching of vijnaptimatra functions as the demonstration of something to be avoided or overcome, as opposed to something that, would it possess a positive quality, should be dwelled upon.
+
As the {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[arising]] of [[form]] is understood primarily as a source of [[delusion]], the [[teaching]] of [[vijnaptimatra]] functions as the demonstration of something to be avoided or overcome, as opposed to something that, would it possess a positive [[quality]], should be dwelled upon.
  
  
  
2.2. Vijnaptimatra as responsible for the false notion of the self (kalpitendtmana):
+
2.2. [[Vijnaptimatra]] as responsible for the false notion of the [[self]] (kalpitendtmana):
  
  
Line 402: Line 402:
 
sarvadharmancini nairdtmyapraveso bhavati na tu tadastitvdpavdddt. itarathd hi vijhapterapi vijhaptyantaramarthah sydditi vijhaptimdtratvam na sidhyetdrthavatifvddvijnaptindm.  
 
sarvadharmancini nairdtmyapraveso bhavati na tu tadastitvdpavdddt. itarathd hi vijhapterapi vijhaptyantaramarthah sydditi vijhaptimdtratvam na sidhyetdrthavatifvddvijnaptindm.  
  
(Vasubandhu 2004: 127)
+
([[Vasubandhu]] 2004: 127)
Tirus, the mentally constructed self, which is inherent to representation, is precisely that which appears as vijnaptimatra and which was introduced as selfless. One is introduced to the selflessness of all phenomena through this understanding of vijhaptmdtra—not through the denial of their existence.  
+
Tirus, the [[mentally]] [[constructed]] [[self]], which is [[inherent]] to [[representation]], is precisely that which appears as [[vijnaptimatra]] and which was introduced as [[selfless]]. One is introduced to the [[selflessness]] of all [[phenomena]] through this [[understanding]] of vijhaptmdtra—not through the {{Wiki|denial}} of their [[existence]].  
  
Indeed, even if by means of representation the represented object should be understood as existing, vijhaptimdtratva would not be established because this object is being apprehended on the basis of a double representation.
+
Indeed, even if by means of [[representation]] the represented [[object]] should be understood as [[existing]], vijhaptimdtratva would not be established because this [[object]] is being apprehended on the basis of a double [[representation]].
  
  
In the above fragment we find a very clear distinction between “vijnaptimatra” and “vijnaptimatrata.” While the first concept appears as that which is responsible for the upsurge of the false notion of the self, the second appears as precisely the locus where selflessness is established. Here it is important to call attention for the various possible translations of the term “siddhi” as it appears in relation to “vijnaptimatratva.”  
+
In the above fragment we find a very clear {{Wiki|distinction}} between “[[vijnaptimatra]]” and “[[vijnaptimatrata]].” While the first {{Wiki|concept}} appears as that which is responsible for the upsurge of the false notion of the [[self]], the second appears as precisely the locus where [[selflessness]] is established. Here it is important to call [[attention]] for the various possible translations of the term “[[siddhi]]” as it appears in [[relation]] to “vijnaptimatratva.”  
  
Anacker, for instance, translates “siddhi” as “demonstration,” and “vijnaptimatratva” as “state of perception-only.” Although “state of perception-only” seems at first to properly account for the difference brought forth by the suffix “ta,” Anacker's translation of “siddhi” as “demonstration” does not satisfactorily set vijnaptimatratva as a “state,” apart from vijnaptimatra as the content of a teaching.  
+
[[Anacker]], for instance, translates “[[siddhi]]” as “demonstration,” and “vijnaptimatratva” as “[[state]] of [[perception-only]].” Although “[[state]] of [[perception-only]]” seems at first to properly account for the difference brought forth by the suffix “ta,” Anacker's translation of “[[siddhi]]” as “demonstration” does not satisfactorily set vijnaptimatratva as a “[[state]],” apart from [[vijnaptimatra]] as the content of a [[teaching]].  
  
Keeping in mind that the term “siddhi” can also be translated as “accomplishment, performance, fulfilment, or complete attainment, translating it as “establishment,” as opposed to Anacker's “demonstration,” brings “vijnaptimatratva” to function as the very accomplishment of the teaching of vijnaptimatra, that is, to be the locus where one abides after successfully learning what was presented in the teaching of vijnaptimatra. With that in perspective, in must be noted that, again, the establishment of selflessness per se occurs in vijnaptimatratva and not in vijnaptimatra.
+
Keeping in [[mind]] that the term “[[siddhi]]” can also be translated as “[[accomplishment]], performance, fulfilment, or complete [[attainment]], translating it as “establishment,” as opposed to Anacker's “demonstration,” brings “vijnaptimatratva” to function as the very [[accomplishment]] of the [[teaching]] of [[vijnaptimatra]], that is, to be the locus where one abides after successfully {{Wiki|learning}} what was presented in the [[teaching]] of [[vijnaptimatra]]. With that in {{Wiki|perspective}}, in must be noted that, again, the establishment of [[selflessness]] [[per se]] occurs in vijnaptimatratva and not in [[vijnaptimatra]].
  
  
The following appearances of the two terms in the Vimsatikav®tti occur as part of two objections posed to Vasubandhu by an opponent. I will comment on them conjunctly.
+
The following [[appearances]] of the two terms in the Vimsatikav®tti occur as part of two objections posed to [[Vasubandhu]] by an opponent. I will comment on them conjunctly.
  
  
2.3. Objection in regard to the efficacy of mental phenomena as in dreams:
+
2.3. Objection in regard to the efficacy of [[mental phenomena]] as in [[dreams]]:
  
  
yadi vijnaptimatramevedam na kasyacitkayo 'sti na vak.
+
[[yadi]] vijnaptimatramevedam na kasyacitkayo 'sti na [[vak]].
  
  
Vasubandhu 2004: 132.
+
[[Vasubandhu]] 2004: 132.
  
  
If this is in fact vijnaptimatra, then neither someone's body nor their speech can possibly exist.Vijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhagcr. Translating 137
+
If this is in fact [[vijnaptimatra]], then neither someone's [[body]] nor their {{Wiki|speech}} can possibly exist.Vijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhagcr. Translating 137
  
  
2.4. Objection in regard to the possibility of communication if all is perception-only:
+
2.4. Objection in regard to the possibility of [[communication]] if all is [[perception-only]]:
  
  
yadi vijnaptimatramevedam paracittavidah kim paracittam janantyatha na kimcatah. (Vasubandhu 2004: 133)
+
[[yadi]] vijnaptimatramevedam paracittavidah [[kim]] paracittam janantyatha na kimcatah. ([[Vasubandhu]] 2004: 133)
  
If this is in fact vijnaptimatra then how do those who understand the mind of others actually understand the mind of others?
+
If this is in fact [[vijnaptimatra]] then how do those who understand the [[mind]] of others actually understand the [[mind]] of others?
  
  
Both objections are directed to vijnaptimatra with the aim of disproving its capacity to be causally efficient. The concept is here understood by the opponent as a representation of reality that is totally detached from the empirical, external world that it represents, and not as an account of what ultimate reality is or could be. Apart from Vasubandhu’s reply to the two objections, the two fragments clearly employ the term “vijnaptimatra” in the sense of a mental process that constructs reality rather than as ultimate reality itself. As will be clear from the following fragment, the concept of ultimate reality will appear when the suffix “ta” is added to “vijnaptimatra.”
+
Both objections are directed to [[vijnaptimatra]] with the aim of disproving its capacity to be [[causally efficient]]. The {{Wiki|concept}} is here understood by the opponent as a [[representation]] of [[reality]] that is totally [[detached]] from the [[empirical]], [[external world]] that it represents, and not as an account of what [[ultimate reality]] is or could be. Apart from [[Vasubandhu’s]] reply to the two objections, the two fragments clearly employ the term “[[vijnaptimatra]]” in the [[sense]] of a [[mental]] process that constructs [[reality]] rather than as [[ultimate reality]] itself. As will be clear from the following fragment, the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[ultimate reality]] will appear when the suffix “ta” is added to “[[vijnaptimatra]].”
  
  
2.5. Vijnaptimdtratd not vijnaptimatra as being of unfathomable depth:
+
2.5. Vijnaptimdtratd not [[vijnaptimatra]] as being of unfathomable depth:
  
  
anantaviniscaya prabhedagadhagambhiryayam vijfiapti- mdtratdyam. vijhaptimatratasiddhih svasaktisadrsa mayd krteyam sarvathd sa tu na cintya. (Vasubandhu 2004: 133)
+
anantaviniscaya prabhedagadhagambhiryayam vijfiapti- mdtratdyam. vijhaptimatratasiddhih svasaktisadrsa mayd krteyam sarvathd sa tu na cintya. ([[Vasubandhu]] 2004: 133)
 
After being settled in the unfathomable depth of vijnaptimdtratd much is to be gained.
 
After being settled in the unfathomable depth of vijnaptimdtratd much is to be gained.
  
  
Although this demonstration of vijnaptimdtratd was done to the best of my abilities, in its entirety it cannot be established by means of thought.
+
Although this demonstration of vijnaptimdtratd was done to the best of my {{Wiki|abilities}}, in its entirety it cannot be established by means of [[thought]].
  
Here we find a clear demonstration a main point of our thesis, that is, that Vasubandhu employs the term “vijnaptimdtratd”— and not “vijnaptimatra”— to describe paramartha-sat. For what Vasubandhu asserts as being of “unfathomable depth,” that is, as being beyond language and subsisting in a realm free from thought construction, is precisely vijnaptimdtratd.  
+
Here we find a clear demonstration a main point of our {{Wiki|thesis}}, that is, that [[Vasubandhu]] employs the term “vijnaptimdtratd”— and not “[[vijnaptimatra]]”— to describe [[paramartha-sat]]. For what [[Vasubandhu]] asserts as being of “unfathomable depth,” that is, as being beyond [[language]] and subsisting in a [[realm]] free from [[thought]] construction, is precisely vijnaptimdtratd.  
  
We should notice that, right at the end of his work, Vasubandhu employs the word “siddhi” with a meaning nowdistinct from that of the previous passage where the “establishment” of vijnaptimdtratd was explained. At this point the English term “demonstration” seems in fact fit in rendering the Sanskrit “siddhi,” for it denotes that, at the end, the soteriological gist of the work is that of explaining how vijnaptimdtratd can be established through the understanding of vijnaptimdtra.
+
We should notice that, right at the end of his work, [[Vasubandhu]] employs the [[word]] “[[siddhi]]” with a meaning nowdistinct from that of the previous passage where the “establishment” of vijnaptimdtratd was explained. At this point the English term “demonstration” seems in fact fit in rendering the [[Sanskrit]] “[[siddhi]],” for it denotes that, at the end, the [[soteriological]] gist of the work is that of explaining how vijnaptimdtratd can be established through the [[understanding]] of vijnaptimdtra.
  
  
From the previous examples of the usage of the two concepts, we can make the following inference: while, on the one hand, vijnaptimdtra can be understood as any mentally constructed representation that exists independently of whether or not it finds an equivalent in reality, on the other hand, vijnaptimdtratd is deep (gambh¥ra), and cannot be established by means of thought (vijnaptimdtratdsiddhih ... na cintyd k®teyam).
+
From the previous examples of the usage of the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], we can make the following {{Wiki|inference}}: while, on the one hand, vijnaptimdtra can be understood as any [[mentally]] [[constructed]] [[representation]] that [[exists]] {{Wiki|independently}} of whether or not it finds an {{Wiki|equivalent}} in [[reality]], on the other hand, vijnaptimdtratd is deep (gambh¥ra), and cannot be established by means of [[thought]] (vijnaptimdtratdsiddhih ... na cintyd k®teyam).
  
  
As the above proves a clear difference in Vasubandhu's usage of the two concepts, we are now in the position to further discuss their place within Vasubandhu's soteriology and propose an alternative translation.
+
As the above proves a clear difference in [[Vasubandhu's]] usage of the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], we are now in the position to further discuss their place within [[Vasubandhu's]] {{Wiki|soteriology}} and propose an alternative translation.
  
  
  
3. The two concepts seen in relation to Vasubandhu's soteriological project
+
3. The two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] seen in [[relation]] to [[Vasubandhu's]] [[soteriological]] project
  
  
  
After having observed the distinct implications of the two concepts, it is important to keep in mind that what is at the stake in properly distinguishing “vijnaptimdtra” from “vijnaptimdtratd” is the correct understanding of the soteriological project that underlies the whole of Vasubandhu's philosophical endeavor. In order to clarify the relation between that project and the two concepts discussed, we must bring back to our inquiry the trisvabhdva theory, and observe how vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd fit into Vasubandhu's tripartite description of reality.
+
After having observed the {{Wiki|distinct}} implications of the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], it is important to keep in [[mind]] that what is at the stake in properly distinguishing “vijnaptimdtra” from “vijnaptimdtratd” is the correct [[understanding]] of the [[soteriological]] project that underlies the whole of [[Vasubandhu's]] [[philosophical]] endeavor. In order to clarify the [[relation]] between that project and the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] discussed, we must bring back to our inquiry the trisvabhdva {{Wiki|theory}}, and observe how vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd fit into [[Vasubandhu's]] tripartite description of [[reality]].
  
Recalling that while parikalpita-svabhdva appears as the category of the being of objects that exist solely as thought­constructs, and as such are merely conventional, and that parinispanna-svabhdva is the one where reality is perfected and free from this very thought construction, paratantra-svabhdva is defined as the middle category responsible for the existence of the previous two, first as mentally constructing parikalpita-svabhdva, and second as arriving at parinispanna-svabhdva after
+
Recalling that while parikalpita-svabhdva appears as the category of the being of [[objects]] that [[exist]] solely as thought­constructs, and as such are merely [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], and that parinispanna-svabhdva is the one where [[reality]] is perfected and free from this very [[thought]] construction, paratantra-svabhdva is defined as the middle category responsible for the [[existence]] of the previous two, first as [[mentally]] constructing parikalpita-svabhdva, and second as arriving at parinispanna-svabhdva after
  
 
aVijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating  139
 
aVijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating  139
  
transformation occurs in its own nature. The relation between this tripartite understanding of reality and the concepts of vijnapti, vijnaptimdtra, and vijnaptimdtratd becomes clear when we observe that the above-mentioned transformation is accomplished precisely by the paratantra-svabhdva's “self-cleansing” from nothing else than the dualistic epistemological flaws of understood as “representation.”  
+
[[transformation]] occurs in its [[own]] [[nature]]. The [[relation]] between this tripartite [[understanding]] of [[reality]] and the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of [[vijnapti]], vijnaptimdtra, and vijnaptimdtratd becomes clear when we observe that the above-mentioned [[transformation]] is accomplished precisely by the paratantra-svabhdva's “self-cleansing” from nothing else than the [[dualistic]] [[epistemological]] flaws of understood as “[[representation]].”  
  
Since such self-cleansing amounts precisely to the passage from conventional to ultimate reality, vijnapti must then show a qualitative change as it moves from the first to the second reality. This obviously brings us back to the above discussion of the nuances, and possible double meaning, of the term vijnapti. For if vijnapti in fact possesses distinct rapports with parikalpita and parinispanna-svabhdva, then, given the above formulation, it must function differently in the terms “vijnaptimdtra” and “vijnaptimdtratd.”
+
Since such self-cleansing amounts precisely to the passage from [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] to [[ultimate reality]], [[vijnapti]] must then show a qualitative change as it moves from the first to the second [[reality]]. This obviously brings us back to the above [[discussion]] of the nuances, and possible double meaning, of the term [[vijnapti]]. For if [[vijnapti]] in fact possesses {{Wiki|distinct}} rapports with [[parikalpita]] and parinispanna-svabhdva, then, given the above formulation, it must function differently in the terms “vijnaptimdtra” and “vijnaptimdtratd.”
  
  
At any rate, we are now in a position to clearly identify the place occupied by the two concepts in the trisvabhdva theory: while vijnaptimdtra (as we have seen in the first verse of the Vimsatikd) accounts precisely for what is constructed by the parikalpita-svabhdva, functioning thus as an appraisal of conventional reality, vijnaptimdtratd (as was seen, for instance, on verse 25 of the Trimsikd) accounts for paratantra-svabhdva's perfected nature, or to parinispanna-svabhdva, that is ultimate reality itself (notice that in verse 25 of the Trimsikd the term “paramdrtha” is employed by Vasubandhu precisely in the sense of “paramdrtha-sat”).
+
At any rate, we are now in a position to clearly identify the place occupied by the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] in the trisvabhdva {{Wiki|theory}}: while vijnaptimdtra (as we have seen in the first verse of the Vimsatikd) accounts precisely for what is [[constructed]] by the parikalpita-svabhdva, functioning thus as an appraisal of [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[reality]], vijnaptimdtratd (as was seen, for instance, on verse 25 of the Trimsikd) accounts for paratantra-svabhdva's perfected [[nature]], or to parinispanna-svabhdva, that is [[ultimate reality]] itself (notice that in verse 25 of the Trimsikd the term “paramdrtha” is employed by [[Vasubandhu]] precisely in the [[sense]] of “paramdrtha-sat”).
  
  
Given the above, the role of vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd in the soteriological framework of Vasubandhu's philosophy becomes obvious. For the path of salvation proposed by Vasubandhu appears now as precisely that where the passage from vijnaptimdtra to vijnaptimdtratd occurs. In other words, it is through the understanding of vijnapti as a tendency inherent in paratantra-svabhdva that we can properly perceive parikalpita- svabhdva as the realm of vijnaptimdtra and samv®ti-sat, while distinguishing it from parinispanna-svabhdva as the locus of vijnaptimdtratd and paramdrtha-sat.
+
Given the above, the role of vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd in the [[soteriological]] framework of [[Vasubandhu's]] [[philosophy]] becomes obvious. For the [[path]] of {{Wiki|salvation}} proposed by [[Vasubandhu]] appears now as precisely that where the passage from vijnaptimdtra to vijnaptimdtratd occurs. In other words, it is through the [[understanding]] of [[vijnapti]] as a tendency [[inherent]] in paratantra-svabhdva that we can properly {{Wiki|perceive}} [[parikalpita]]- [[svabhdva]] as the [[realm]] of vijnaptimdtra and samv®ti-sat, while distinguishing it from parinispanna-svabhdva as the locus of vijnaptimdtratd and paramdrtha-sat.
  
  
It cannot be overemphasized that the gist of such conversion will become clear only if one is attentive to the fact that what prevents consciousness from continuing in a state of attachment to the twofold grasping produced by vijnapti as“representation” is not, as Kochumuttom presents in his translation of verse 26 of the Trimsika, the realization that the subject-object designations are “mere representations of consciousness” (vijnaptimatra), but, once again, the realization of consciousness itself as it arrives in a state free from representation. In order to further clarify such notion, we must now look at Vasubandhu’s Trimsika verse 27:
+
It cannot be overemphasized that the gist of such [[conversion]] will become clear only if one is attentive to the fact that what prevents [[consciousness]] from continuing in a [[state]] of [[attachment]] to the twofold [[grasping]] produced by [[vijnapti]] as“representation” is not, as {{Wiki|Kochumuttom}} presents in his translation of verse 26 of the [[Trimsika]], the [[realization]] that the subject-object designations are “mere {{Wiki|representations}} of [[consciousness]]” ([[vijnaptimatra]]), but, once again, the [[realization]] of [[consciousness]] itself as it arrives in a [[state]] free from [[representation]]. In order to further clarify such notion, we must now look at [[Vasubandhu’s]] [[Trimsika]] verse 27:
  
  
 
vijnaptimatramevedamityapi hynpalambhatah\ sthapayannagratah kincit tanmdtre navatisthate ||27||
 
vijnaptimatramevedamityapi hynpalambhatah\ sthapayannagratah kincit tanmdtre navatisthate ||27||
  
Simply stating that something is ‘representation-only’ (vijnaptimatra), does not make you stand in the suchness of it.
+
Simply stating that something is ‘representation-only’ ([[vijnaptimatra]]), does not make you stand in the [[suchness]] of it.
  
Here Vasubandhu clearly asserts that the recognition of something as representation-only (vijnaptimatra) is insufficient for attaining realization of its suchness (tanmdtre). As the following verses, 28 and 29, make clear, such suchness is, in fact, arrived at only in vijnaptimatrata (or vijnaptimatratva j.
+
Here [[Vasubandhu]] clearly asserts that the {{Wiki|recognition}} of something as representation-only ([[vijnaptimatra]]) is insufficient for [[attaining]] [[realization]] of its [[suchness]] (tanmdtre). As the following verses, 28 and 29, make clear, such [[suchness]] is, in fact, arrived at only in [[vijnaptimatrata]] (or vijnaptimatratva j.
  
yadalambanam jftanam naivopalabhate tada\ sthitam vijnanamatratve grahyabhave tadagrahat ||28||
+
yadalambanam jftanam naivopalabhate tada\ [[sthitam]] vijnanamatratve grahyabhave tadagrahat ||28||
  
When consciousness does not recognize the object precisely as such [that is, as an object],
+
When [[consciousness]] does not [[recognize]] the [[object]] precisely as such [that is, as an [[object]]],
then, standing in vijnaptimatrata, it is beyond grasping.
+
then, [[standing]] in [[vijnaptimatrata]], it is beyond [[grasping]].
  
  
 
acitto ’nupalambho ’sau jftanam lokottaram ca tat\ asrayasya paravrttirdvidha dausthulyahanitah ||29||
 
acitto ’nupalambho ’sau jftanam lokottaram ca tat\ asrayasya paravrttirdvidha dausthulyahanitah ||29||
Without mind and object, it is then in the state of supra- mundane knowledge,
+
[[Without mind]] and [[object]], it is then in the [[state]] of supra- [[mundane]] [[knowledge]],
  
where the revolution of the basis does away with the two impurities.
+
where the [[revolution of the basis]] does away with the two [[impurities]].
  
Vijnaptimatrata, then, is that which, being beyond grasping, pertains to ultimate reality.Vijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating 141
+
[[Vijnaptimatrata]], then, is that which, being beyond [[grasping]], pertains to [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] reality.Vijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating 141
  
  
Line 509: Line 509:
  
  
Given the position vijnaptimatrata occupies in Vasubandhu's thought as a final realization towards which his project is directed, our task becomes, at this point, that of inquiring on the possibility of an alternative translation of the concept that would render it in a manner that more clearly expresses its soteriological implications. The first question to be posed in such inquiry, then, would be: how much differentiation from vijnaptimatra is appropriate to a rendering of vijnaptimatrata?
+
Given the position [[vijnaptimatrata]] occupies in [[Vasubandhu's]] [[thought]] as a final [[realization]] towards which his project is directed, our task becomes, at this point, that of inquiring on the possibility of an alternative translation of the {{Wiki|concept}} that would render it in a manner that more clearly expresses its [[soteriological]] implications. The first question to be posed in such inquiry, then, would be: how much differentiation from [[vijnaptimatra]] is appropriate to a rendering of [[vijnaptimatrata]]?
  
  
While the two concepts are morphologically similar in that both contain the notion of vijnapti, the above demonstration of the nuances the latter term acquires in relation to the cognitive capacities involved in the distinction between conventional and ultimate reality, that is, as “perception” as opposed to “representation,” may allow an English rendering that would not repeat a single meaning for “vijnapti” in both compounds “vijnaptimatra” and “vijnaptimatrata.”  
+
While the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] are morphologically similar in that both contain the notion of [[vijnapti]], the above demonstration of the nuances the [[latter]] term acquires in [[relation]] to the [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] capacities involved in the {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] and [[ultimate reality]], that is, as “[[perception]]” as opposed to “[[representation]],” may allow an English rendering that would not repeat a single meaning for “[[vijnapti]]” in both compounds “[[vijnaptimatra]]” and “[[vijnaptimatrata]].”  
  
In any case, all we can assert at this point is that if vijnapti is in fact accepted as assuming different meanings in each concept, then that only would justify their being translated with a higher degree of differentiation. But even if the double meaning of vijnapti is left aside, the question still remains of whether in translating texts such as Vasubandhu's it is valid to sacrifice morphological similarity in favor of clarity of philosophical content.
+
In any case, all we can assert at this point is that if [[vijnapti]] is in fact accepted as assuming different meanings in each {{Wiki|concept}}, then that only would justify their being translated with a higher [[degree]] of differentiation. But even if the double meaning of [[vijnapti]] is left aside, the question still remains of whether in translating texts such as [[Vasubandhu's]] it is valid to [[Wikipedia:sacrifice|sacrifice]] morphological similarity in favor of clarity of [[philosophical]] content.
  
  
The point here is that, considering all that stands between classical Sanskrit and modern English, one might infer that for Vasubandhu and his audience the difference we are stressing was probably already sufficiently accounted for by the accretion of the abstract suffix “ta” to the word “vijnaptimatra.” For us modern readers of an ancient work in translation, however, things appear to be somewhat different.  
+
The point here is that, considering all that stands between classical [[Sanskrit]] and {{Wiki|modern}} English, one might infer that for [[Vasubandhu]] and his audience the difference we are stressing was probably already sufficiently accounted for by the accretion of the abstract suffix “ta” to the [[word]] “[[vijnaptimatra]].” For us {{Wiki|modern}} readers of an [[ancient]] work in translation, however, things appear to be somewhat different.  
  
If we apply Vasubandhu's procedure to the English language and simply add the suffixes “ness” or “hood” to terms such as “representation-only” or “psychosophical-closure,” our result, as we have seen, will fall short of providing a clear account of the subtleties implied in the Indian philosopher's usage of the two concepts in question.  
+
If we apply [[Vasubandhu's]] procedure to the English [[language]] and simply add the suffixes “ness” or “hood” to terms such as “representation-only” or “psychosophical-closure,” our result, as we have seen, will fall short of providing a clear account of the subtleties implied in the [[Indian]] philosopher's usage of the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] in question.  
  
The problem here falls under the difficulty we encounter when, as translators, we are met with the task of clarifying to the modern reader philosophical ideas that are presented in the context of ancient dialectics, where debate tended to be carried out in a mode where the opponent's prior knowledgeof the arguments in question was usually assumed by the contenders.  
+
The problem here falls under the difficulty we encounter when, as [[translators]], we are met with the task of clarifying to the {{Wiki|modern}} reader [[philosophical]] [[ideas]] that are presented in the context of [[ancient]] [[dialectics]], where [[debate]] tended to be carried out in a mode where the opponent's prior knowledgeof the arguments in question was usually assumed by the contenders.  
  
Such being the case, simply providing an accurate structural rendering of concepts as they are employed in the original language tends to be insufficient to the correct rendering of the ideas expounded.
+
Such being the case, simply providing an accurate structural rendering of [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] as they are employed in the original [[language]] tends to be insufficient to the correct rendering of the [[ideas]] expounded.
  
  
  
At any rate, as far as this paper is concerned, my final aim now is still to propose an alternative translation for Vasubandhu’s concepts. My first step in this direction will be to look for an alternative that would not depart from the philosophical domain in which the ideas in question were developed. As the inquiry on cognition allows us to recognize the epistemological medium in which Vasubandhu’s ideas are developed, my search must be guided toward concepts that will effectively denote the perceptual subtleties involved in the difference between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata.  
+
At any rate, as far as this paper is concerned, my final aim now is still to propose an alternative translation for [[Vasubandhu’s]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. My first step in this [[direction]] will be to look for an alternative that would not depart from the [[philosophical]] domain in which the [[ideas]] in question were developed. As the inquiry on [[cognition]] allows us to [[recognize]] the [[epistemological]] {{Wiki|medium}} in which [[Vasubandhu’s]] [[ideas]] are developed, my search must be guided toward [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] that will effectively denote the {{Wiki|perceptual}} subtleties involved in the difference between [[vijnaptimatra]] and [[vijnaptimatrata]].  
  
In other words, keeping in perspective that our basic material is an epistemology that asserts a qualitative difference between what is barely cognized and the constructions that, by imputation, are accrued to such cognition, I will work with the two concepts employed above in the demonstration of the different possible meanings assumed by vijnapti in its distinct epistemological implications, “perception” and “representation.”
+
In other words, keeping in {{Wiki|perspective}} that our basic material is an epistemology that asserts a qualitative difference between what is barely [[Wikipedia:Cognition|cognized]] and the constructions that, by [[imputation]], are accrued to such [[cognition]], I will work with the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] employed above in the demonstration of the different possible meanings assumed by [[vijnapti]] in its {{Wiki|distinct}} [[epistemological]] implications, “[[perception]]” and “[[representation]].”
  
  
We must recall that while “perception” may denote simply a first moment of bare cognition, that is, a basic encounter with reality that is severed from any assumptions made about it, “representation” carries in itself the mark of intentionality together with the accrual of elements that are foreign to the bare data first cognized. With that in mind, 1 will propose a translation for Vasubandhu’s Trimsika 28 that reads as follows:
+
We must recall that while “[[perception]]” may denote simply a first [[moment]] of bare [[cognition]], that is, a basic encounter with [[reality]] that is severed from any {{Wiki|assumptions}} made about it, “[[representation]]” carries in itself the mark of {{Wiki|intentionality}} together with the accrual of [[elements]] that are foreign to the bare {{Wiki|data}} first [[Wikipedia:Cognition|cognized]]. With that in [[mind]], 1 will propose a translation for [[Vasubandhu’s]] [[Trimsika]] 28 that reads as follows:
  
  
When consciousness does not recognize the object precisely as such [that is, as an object],
+
When [[consciousness]] does not [[recognize]] the [[object]] precisely as such [that is, as an [[object]]],
  
then, standing in pureness-of-perception,
+
then, [[standing]] in pureness-of-perception,
  
[vijnaptimatratve] it is beyond grasping.
+
[vijnaptimatratve] it is beyond [[grasping]].
  
By translating vijnaptimatrata as “pureness-of-perception,” I intend to reflect the essential purity of the bare cognition that is defined by Vasubandhu as being “beyond grasping.” While “vijnaptimatra” is formulated as “pure” or “mere representation,” rendering “vijnaptimatrata” with the word “perception” in the place of “representation” clearly distinguishes the two concepts. I believe that this procedure helps clarify the epistemological grounds on which Vasubandhu’s concepts function, while at theVijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating  143
+
By translating [[vijnaptimatrata]] as “pureness-of-perception,” I intend to reflect the [[essential]] [[purity]] of the bare [[cognition]] that is defined by [[Vasubandhu]] as being “beyond [[grasping]].” While “[[vijnaptimatra]]” is formulated as “[[pure]]” or “mere [[representation]],” rendering “[[vijnaptimatrata]]” with the [[word]] “[[perception]]” in the place of “[[representation]]” clearly distinguishes the two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. I believe that this procedure helps clarify the [[epistemological]] grounds on which [[Vasubandhu’s]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] function, while at theVijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating  143
  
  
same time expressing more clearly the doctrine of two truths that underlies them.
+
same time expressing more clearly the [[doctrine]] of [[two truths]] that underlies them.
  
Accounting for the distinct epistemological spheres of operation of vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd, then, must be regarded as the first step towards correctly grasping Vasubandhu's soteriology. His soteriology is presented through a web of tightly interwoven concepts, where the two terms are a primary motor, leading the paratantra-svabhdva through dsrayapardv®tti into the level of a perfected reality free from dualism, where phenomena are encountered in their sheer immediacy, that is, that very region of phenomena that has achieved the lucidity of parinispanna- svabhdva.  
+
Accounting for the {{Wiki|distinct}} [[epistemological]] [[spheres]] of operation of vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd, then, must be regarded as the first step towards correctly [[grasping]] [[Vasubandhu's]] {{Wiki|soteriology}}. His {{Wiki|soteriology}} is presented through a web of tightly interwoven [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], where the two terms are a primary motor, leading the paratantra-svabhdva through dsrayapardv®tti into the level of a perfected [[reality]] free from [[dualism]], where [[phenomena]] are encountered in their sheer {{Wiki|immediacy}}, that is, that very region of [[phenomena]] that has achieved the [[lucidity]] of [[parinispanna]]- [[svabhdva]].  
  
And if this lucidity is precisely what is indicated with the notion of “pureness-of-perception,” the circularity becomes obvious: the passage from parikalpita to parinispanna-svabhdva must be the same as that from vijnaptimdtra to vijnaptimdtratd.
+
And if this [[lucidity]] is precisely what is indicated with the notion of “pureness-of-perception,” the circularity becomes obvious: the passage from [[parikalpita]] to parinispanna-svabhdva must be the same as that from vijnaptimdtra to vijnaptimdtratd.
  
  
The relation between vijnaptimdtratd and dsraya-pardv®tti leads us to the further and more complex relation between vijnaptimdtratd and dlayavijndna. Although an in-depth inquiry into dlayavijndna goes beyond my aims here, the question of its rapport with vijnaptimdtratd must be approached if we are to effectively indicate all the implications of the difference we are stressing between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd.  
+
The [[relation]] between vijnaptimdtratd and dsraya-pardv®tti leads us to the further and more complex [[relation]] between vijnaptimdtratd and dlayavijndna. Although an in-depth inquiry into dlayavijndna goes beyond my aims here, the question of its rapport with vijnaptimdtratd must be approached if we are to effectively indicate all the implications of the difference we are stressing between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd.  
  
Such rapport, it must be noted, can only be appraised through the use of an inferential procedure that will call forth several other concepts pertaining to the logical web expounded by Vasubandhu, and relate them mutually in a comparative manner.
+
Such rapport, it must be noted, can only be appraised through the use of an inferential procedure that will call forth several other [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] pertaining to the [[logical]] web expounded by [[Vasubandhu]], and relate them mutually in a comparative manner.
  
  
Understanding dlayavijndna as a basic or substratum consciousness that subsists under states of unconsciousness, and as such accounts for the general continuity of mental life, we must keep in mind that in order to clearly observe its rapport with vijnaptimdtratd we must first be aware of its role as the very basis for the occurrence of dsraya-pardv®tti. For dsraya-pardv®tti must be understood as, in Yamada's terms, the “converting of the substratum” (Yamada 1997: 171), which, in fact, is dlayavijndna itself.  
+
[[Understanding]] dlayavijndna as a basic or [[substratum]] [[consciousness]] that subsists under states of [[unconsciousness]], and as such accounts for the general continuity of [[mental]] [[life]], we must keep in [[mind]] that in order to clearly observe its rapport with vijnaptimdtratd we must first be {{Wiki|aware}} of its role as the very basis for the occurrence of dsraya-pardv®tti. For dsraya-pardv®tti must be understood as, in Yamada's terms, the “converting of the [[substratum]]” (Yamada 1997: 171), which, in fact, is dlayavijndna itself.  
  
The logic then becomes very simple: if vijnaptimdtratd can be understood as the result of dsraya-pardv®tti, it must also be regarded as the “converting of the substratum” that is nothing but the converting of dlayavijndna itself.  
+
The [[logic]] then becomes very simple: if vijnaptimdtratd can be understood as the result of dsraya-pardv®tti, it must also be regarded as the “converting of the [[substratum]]” that is nothing but the converting of dlayavijndna itself.  
  
This logic is obviously based on our understanding of vijnaptimdtratd as “pureness-of- perception,” for such “purity” will be in concord with theelimination of all the unwholesome seeds (b¥ja) of karma present in dlayavijnana upon its conversion through dsraya-pardvrtti, as well as with the cleansing of all the badness (dausthulya) of which the neutral substratum consciousness (dlayavijndna itself) is the receptacle.
+
This [[logic]] is obviously based on our [[understanding]] of vijnaptimdtratd as “pureness-of- [[perception]],” for such “[[purity]]” will be in [[concord]] with theelimination of all the [[unwholesome]] [[seeds]] (b¥ja) of [[karma]] {{Wiki|present}} in dlayavijnana upon its [[conversion]] through dsraya-pardvrtti, as well as with the cleansing of all the badness (dausthulya) of which the [[neutral]] [[substratum]] [[consciousness]] (dlayavijndna itself) is the receptacle.
  
  
The rapport demonstrated between vijnaptimdtratd and dlayavijndna, however, remits us to a more fundamental question that transcends merely portraying the interrelationship between concepts.  
+
The rapport demonstrated between vijnaptimdtratd and dlayavijndna, however, remits us to a more fundamental question that {{Wiki|transcends}} merely portraying the interrelationship between [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]].  
  
The question is: what would be left if the substratum consciousness that contains all the seeds of karma disappeared after its conversion through dsraya-pardv®tti? What is at stake here is the very sustainability of the entire soteriological project in which Vasubhandhu's philosophy is embedded. Schmithausen (1987: 205) formulates the problem in the following way:
+
The question is: what would be left if the [[substratum]] [[consciousness]] that contains all the [[seeds]] of [[karma]] disappeared after its [[conversion]] through dsraya-pardv®tti? What is at stake here is the very sustainability of the entire [[soteriological]] project in which Vasubhandhu's [[philosophy]] is embedded. [[Schmithausen]] (1987: 205) formulates the problem in the following way:
  
  
We simply have to accept that the text [Viniscaya Samgrahani] declares that, as soon as the process of Transmuting the Basis is completed (i.e. at the moment of attaining Arhatship), dlayavijndna itself is abandoned, and not merely emptied of unwholesome Seeds, but preserved in some other form; i.e. we have to accept that dlayavijndna is, in the Nivrtti Portion, essentially bound up with, or even nothing but a hypostasis of, Badness (dausthulya). The problems that would seem to arise from such a position - e.g. how, after the extinction of dlayavijndna, physical life can continue at all (especially in nirodhasamdpatti), or what would then be or contain the Seed(s) of the pravrttivijndnas - were, so it appears, simply not envisaged by the author/compiler.
+
We simply have to accept that the text [[[Viniscaya]] Samgrahani] declares that, as soon as the process of Transmuting the Basis is completed (i.e. at the [[moment]] of [[attaining]] [[Arhatship]]), dlayavijndna itself is abandoned, and not merely emptied of [[unwholesome]] [[Seeds]], but preserved in some other [[form]]; i.e. we have to accept that dlayavijndna is, in the [[Nivrtti]] Portion, [[essentially]] [[bound]] up with, or even nothing but a hypostasis of, Badness (dausthulya). The problems that would seem to arise from such a position - e.g. how, after the [[extinction]] of dlayavijndna, [[physical]] [[life]] can continue at all (especially in nirodhasamdpatti), or what would then be or contain the Seed(s) of the pravrttivijndnas - were, so it appears, simply not envisaged by the author/compiler.
  
  
The problem with Schmithausen's position is that, in approaching the text of the Viniscaya Samgrahani, he pursues a form of inquiry from which inference and intertextual analysis are, for the most part, ruled out. Although Schmithausen is correct in asserting that the text does not explicate what would be made of physical life once dlayavijndna is done away with,  
+
The problem with [[Schmithausen's]] position is that, in approaching the text of the [[Viniscaya]] Samgrahani, he pursues a [[form]] of inquiry from which {{Wiki|inference}} and intertextual analysis are, for the most part, ruled out. Although [[Schmithausen]] is correct in asserting that the text does not explicate what would be made of [[physical]] [[life]] once dlayavijndna is done away with,  
  
suggesting that the author/compiler would not have envisaged such a question appears to be the result of the adoption of a perspective that avoids regarding the text in relation to the body of ideas that spring from the same tradition to which it belongs. Undoubtedly, such a problem is closely related to the historical form of inquiry that appears in much current scholarship. That form of inquiry operates on the basis of preconceived notions such as, for instance, the ideaVijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating 145
+
suggesting that the author/compiler would not have envisaged such a question appears to be the result of the adoption of a {{Wiki|perspective}} that avoids regarding the text in [[relation]] to the [[body]] of [[ideas]] that spring from the same [[tradition]] to which it belongs. Undoubtedly, such a problem is closely related to the historical [[form]] of inquiry that appears in much current {{Wiki|scholarship}}. That [[form]] of inquiry operates on the basis of preconceived notions such as, for instance, the ideaVijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating 145
  
  
that texts must necessarily have a history, that the analysis of the “history” of the text can grant some form of scientific knowledge over it, and that texts can, in any case, be categorized linearly into anything that would amount to a historical arrangement.  
+
that texts must necessarily have a history, that the analysis of the “history” of the text can grant some [[form]] of [[scientific knowledge]] over it, and that texts can, in any case, be categorized linearly into anything that would amount to a historical arrangement.  
  
As such notions are taken for granted, the historical perspective limits the scope of the text to that of a product that must be regarded only in relation to its own companion artifacts, and in doing so shuns a bolder comparative approach that would provide a larger perspective on the questions themselves, as they are posited by the text.
+
As such notions are taken for granted, the historical {{Wiki|perspective}} limits the scope of the text to that of a product that must be regarded only in [[relation]] to its [[own]] companion {{Wiki|artifacts}}, and in doing so shuns a bolder comparative approach that would provide a larger {{Wiki|perspective}} on the questions themselves, as they are posited by the text.
  
  
The point here is that in dealing with philosophy, even the most blunt form of scholarship should be capable of perceiving connections among apparently unrelated texts, of pursuing an inferential form of analysis, and, most of all, approaching ideas in their own right, Schmithausen's lack of such drive leads him to overlook the fact that even though the answer to the question of what is made of physical life after the extinction of alayavijnana may not have been made explicit in the Viniscaya Samgraham, it does appear with a considerable degree of clarity in other texts of the Buddhist canon.  
+
The point here is that in dealing with [[philosophy]], even the most blunt [[form]] of {{Wiki|scholarship}} should be capable of perceiving connections among apparently unrelated texts, of pursuing an inferential [[form]] of analysis, and, most of all, approaching [[ideas]] in their [[own]] right, [[Schmithausen's]] lack of such drive leads him to overlook the fact that even though the answer to the question of what is made of [[physical]] [[life]] after the [[extinction]] of [[alayavijnana]] may not have been made explicit in the [[Viniscaya]] Samgraham, it does appear with a considerable [[degree]] of clarity in other texts of the [[Buddhist canon]].  
  
Since Buddhist texts function in a web of interrelated works that, for the most part, circle around the same basic ideas, and since such ideas were very likely already known by the audience to whom many of these texts were directed, it is very possible that the author/complier of the Viniscaya Samgrahan¥ did not find it necessary to explain how  
+
Since [[Buddhist texts]] function in a web of {{Wiki|interrelated}} works that, for the most part, circle around the same basic [[ideas]], and since such [[ideas]] were very likely already known by the audience to whom many of these texts were directed, it is very possible that the author/complier of the [[Viniscaya]] Samgrahan¥ did not find it necessary to explain how  
  
physical life appears in a state free from alayavijnana, simply because such explanation was already to be found in other texts. Given the interrelatedness of Buddhist texts, our task should be to bring them together as much as possible with the goal of clarifying the ideas they present. That would be a first step toward the further and more meaningful purpose of reworking such ideas in a larger world perspective.
+
[[physical]] [[life]] appears in a [[state]] free from [[alayavijnana]], simply because such explanation was already to be found in other texts. Given the interrelatedness of [[Buddhist texts]], our task should be to bring them together as much as possible with the goal of clarifying the [[ideas]] they {{Wiki|present}}. That would be a first step toward the further and more meaningful {{Wiki|purpose}} of reworking such [[ideas]] in a larger [[world]] {{Wiki|perspective}}.
  
  
With that in mind, my point here is that precisely by understanding vijnaptimatrata as the result of asrayaparav®tti, and as such as the point where alayavijnana is done away with, we can conceive vijnaptimatrata as the epistemological state of being of parinispana-svabhava, or a perfected reality that is free from representation. Such reality, in  
+
With that in [[mind]], my point here is that precisely by [[understanding]] [[vijnaptimatrata]] as the result of asrayaparav®tti, and as such as the point where [[alayavijnana]] is done away with, we can [[conceive]] [[vijnaptimatrata]] as the [[epistemological]] [[state of being]] of parinispana-svabhava, or a perfected [[reality]] that is free from [[representation]]. Such [[reality]], in  
  
turn, becomes the one where perception is transformed, in Vasubandhu's words, into “supramundane wisdom.” The fifth chapter of the Samdhinirmocana Sutra provides us with an account of preciselythis sort of perception and, by implication, with an answer to what is left of physical life once dlayavijndna is extinguished. In asking the Buddha how are Bodhisattvas wise with respect to the secrets of mind, thought, and consciousness, the Bodhisattva Visalamati receives the following answer:
+
turn, becomes the one where [[perception]] is [[transformed]], in [[Vasubandhu's]] words, into “[[supramundane wisdom]].” The fifth [[chapter]] of the [[Samdhinirmocana Sutra]] provides us with an account of preciselythis sort of [[perception]] and, by implication, with an answer to what is left of [[physical]] [[life]] once dlayavijndna is [[extinguished]]. In asking the [[Buddha]] how are [[Bodhisattvas]] [[wise]] with [[respect]] to the secrets of [[mind]], [[thought]], and [[consciousness]], the [[Bodhisattva]] [[Visalamati]] receives the following answer:
  
  
Visalamati, those Bodhisattvas [wise in all ways] do not perceive their own internal appropriators; they also do not perceive an appropriating consciousness, but they are in accord with reality. They also do not perceive a basis, nor do they perceive a basis-consciousness. They do not perceive accumulations, nor do they perceive mind. They do not perceive an eye, nor do they perceive form, nor to they perceive an eye-consciousness.  
+
[[Visalamati]], those [[Bodhisattvas]] [[[wise]] in all ways] do not {{Wiki|perceive}} their [[own]] internal appropriators; they also do not {{Wiki|perceive}} an appropriating [[consciousness]], but they are in accord with [[reality]]. They also do not {{Wiki|perceive}} a basis, nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} a basis-consciousness. They do not {{Wiki|perceive}} [[accumulations]], nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} [[mind]]. They do not {{Wiki|perceive}} an [[eye]], nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} [[form]], nor to they {{Wiki|perceive}} an [[eye-consciousness]].  
  
They do not perceive an ear, nor do they perceive a sound, nor do they perceive an ear­consciousness. They do not perceive a nose, nor do they perceive a smell, nor do they perceive a nose-consciousness. They do not perceive a tongue, nor do they perceive a taste, nor do they perceive a tongue consciousness. They do not perceive a body, nor do they perceive a tangible object, nor do they perceive a bodily consciousness.  
+
They do not {{Wiki|perceive}} an {{Wiki|ear}}, nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} a [[sound]], nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} an ear­consciousness. They do not {{Wiki|perceive}} a {{Wiki|nose}}, nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} a {{Wiki|smell}}, nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} a [[nose-consciousness]]. They do not {{Wiki|perceive}} a {{Wiki|tongue}}, nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} a {{Wiki|taste}}, nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} a [[tongue consciousness]]. They do not {{Wiki|perceive}} a [[body]], nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} a {{Wiki|tangible}} [[object]], nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} a [[bodily]] [[consciousness]].  
  
Visalamati, these Bodhisattvas do not perceive their own particular thoughts, nor do they perceive phenomena, nor do they perceive a mental consciousness, but they are in accord with reality. These Bodhisattvas are said to be ‘wise with respect to the ultimate.' The Tathagata designates Bodhisattvas who are wise with respect to the ultimate as also being ‘wise with respect to the secrets of mind, thought, and consciousness.' (Powers 1995: 76).
+
[[Visalamati]], these [[Bodhisattvas]] do not {{Wiki|perceive}} their [[own]] particular [[thoughts]], nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} [[phenomena]], nor do they {{Wiki|perceive}} a [[mental consciousness]], but they are in accord with [[reality]]. These [[Bodhisattvas]] are said to be ‘[[wise]] with [[respect]] to the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]].' The [[Tathagata]] designates [[Bodhisattvas]] who are [[wise]] with [[respect]] to the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] as also being ‘[[wise]] with [[respect]] to the secrets of [[mind]], [[thought]], and [[consciousness]].' ([[Powers]] 1995: 76).
  
  
  
The question of what comes after the extinction of dlayavijndna is obviously of the epistemological sort. For given the Mahayana Buddhist soteriological principle of salvation being a non-other-worldly affair, the question of life without dlayavijndna becomes that of the possibility of doing away with mind's evil doings while still staying alive. And by “doing away with mind's evil doings” nothing but a clear, pure perception of the sort described above, is understood. The Samdhinirmocana Sutra thus provides us with an answer to what seemed to have been left out from the Viniscaya Samgrahan¥.
+
The question of what comes after the [[extinction]] of dlayavijndna is obviously of the [[epistemological]] sort. For given the [[Mahayana]] [[Buddhist]] [[soteriological]] [[principle]] of {{Wiki|salvation}} being a non-other-worldly affair, the question of [[life]] without dlayavijndna becomes that of the possibility of doing away with [[mind's]] [[evil]] doings while still staying alive. And by “doing away with [[mind's]] [[evil]] doings” nothing but a clear, [[pure perception]] of the sort described above, is understood. The [[Samdhinirmocana Sutra]] thus provides us with an answer to what seemed to have been left out from the [[Viniscaya]] Samgrahan¥.
  
  
But what interests us here most of all is to observe that the sort of perception described in the sutra, that is, one where no objects are apprehended but accord with reality is still verified, can be regarded precisely as the one proposed by Vasubandhu as taking
+
But what interests us here most of all is to observe that the sort of [[perception]] described in the [[sutra]], that is, one where no [[objects]] are apprehended but accord with [[reality]] is still verified, can be regarded precisely as the one proposed by [[Vasubandhu]] as taking
  
place in vijnaptimatrata. Such objectless perception I called a “pure perception,” and the state of mind abiding in such pure perception, one of “pureness-of-perception.”
+
place in [[vijnaptimatrata]]. Such objectless [[perception]] I called a “[[pure perception]],” and the [[state of mind]] abiding in such [[pure perception]], one of “pureness-of-perception.”
  
  
Yet again attesting to the interconnectedness of Buddhist philosophical concepts, such an understanding of vijnaptimatrata will allow us to perceive its rapport with what Asanga, in the Bodhisattvabhumi, called "nirvikalpa-jhana." that is, knowledge free of conceptualization. As “pureness-of-perception,” vijnaptimatrata also acquires connotations that bring it close to other Buddhist concepts, such as, for instance, Paramartha's amalavijnana.  
+
Yet again attesting to the interconnectedness of [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], such an [[understanding]] of [[vijnaptimatrata]] will allow us to {{Wiki|perceive}} its rapport with what [[Asanga]], in the [[Bodhisattvabhumi]], called "nirvikalpa-jhana." that is, [[knowledge]] free of [[conceptualization]]. As “pureness-of-perception,” [[vijnaptimatrata]] also acquires connotations that bring it close to other [[Buddhist]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], such as, for instance, [[Paramartha's]] [[amalavijnana]].  
  
As Jonathan Gold has noted, what Vasubandhu's texts share “is a unifying vision that fits a Yogacara conceptual structure, but is not exclusively associated with any individual doxographic category.”  
+
As Jonathan {{Wiki|Gold}} has noted, what [[Vasubandhu's]] texts share “is a unifying [[vision]] that fits a [[Yogacara]] {{Wiki|conceptual}} {{Wiki|structure}}, but is not exclusively associated with any {{Wiki|individual}} doxographic category.”  
  
I would add that from a more overtly comparative perspective the correct understanding of Vasubandhu's notion can lead us into an inquiry on its relation with more recent concepts found in Western thought, especially in the field of philosophy of mind. Here a comparative approach worked between vijnaptimatrata as a state of mind abiding in “pure perception,” and the notion of “pure-experience” as developed by Nishida and William James, might shed new light on the comparative study of Yogacara philosophy and Western thought.  
+
I would add that from a more overtly comparative {{Wiki|perspective}} the correct [[understanding]] of [[Vasubandhu's]] notion can lead us into an inquiry on its [[relation]] with more recent [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] found in [[Western]] [[thought]], especially in the field of {{Wiki|philosophy of mind}}. Here a comparative approach worked between [[vijnaptimatrata]] as a [[state of mind]] abiding in “[[pure perception]],” and the notion of “pure-experience” as developed by Nishida and {{Wiki|William James}}, might shed new {{Wiki|light}} on the comparative study of [[Yogacara]] [[philosophy]] and [[Western]] [[thought]].  
  
In this regard, the correct understanding of vijnaptimatrata might work also towards demystifying much of recent East Asian thought's excessive emphasis on its own originality. In a broader sense, taking a correct grasp of Vasubandhu's philosophy as a starting point, Buddhist philosophy's existential ontological focus can be brought in perspective with  
+
In this regard, the correct [[understanding]] of [[vijnaptimatrata]] might work also towards demystifying much of recent {{Wiki|East Asian}} thought's excessive {{Wiki|emphasis}} on its [[own]] originality. In a broader [[sense]], taking a correct [[grasp]] of [[Vasubandhu's]] [[philosophy]] as a starting point, [[Buddhist]] philosophy's [[existential]] [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] focus can be brought in {{Wiki|perspective}} with  
  
Western forms of thought that propound a similar ontology, and, in this manner, work towards effacing the boundaries between ideas that have for too long been undervalued or kept apart, much at the fault, it must be said, of the scholarly approach that asserts that ideas must be kept locked within their “historical context.”  
+
[[Western]] [[forms]] of [[thought]] that propound a similar {{Wiki|ontology}}, and, in this manner, work towards effacing the [[boundaries]] between [[ideas]] that have for too long been undervalued or kept apart, much at the fault, it must be said, of the [[scholarly]] approach that asserts that [[ideas]] must be kept locked within their “historical context.”  
  
Finally, the correct apprehension of the notions propounded by a philosopher such as Vasubandhu can lead us to discover that not much is ever new in human thought, and that maybe paying closer attention to the Indian Buddhists might be a useful step towards understanding a reality that, ultimately, is a-historical.
+
Finally, the correct apprehension of the notions propounded by a [[philosopher]] such as [[Vasubandhu]] can lead us to discover that not much is ever new in [[human]] [[thought]], and that maybe paying closer [[attention]] to the [[Indian Buddhists]] might be a useful step towards [[understanding]] a [[reality]] that, ultimately, is a-historical.
  
  
Line 627: Line 627:
  
  
The title of this essay alludes to that of the Dharmadharmatdvibhdga, one of the five books of Maitreya. The book has been translated into English with the title Distinguishing Dharma and Dharmatd, and published with a commentary by Tibetan scholar Thrangu Rinpoche. His commentary begins as follows:
+
The title of this essay alludes to that of the Dharmadharmatdvibhdga, one of the five [[books]] of [[Maitreya]]. The [[book]] has been translated into English with the title Distinguishing [[Dharma]] and Dharmatd, and published with a commentary by [[Tibetan]] [[scholar]] [[Thrangu Rinpoche]]. His commentary begins as follows:
  
This text is an exposition of the Dharma-dharmata-vibhaga in Sanskrit or Distinguishing Dharma and Dharmata in English. The word dharma means “phenomena” and dharmata means “pure phenomena.” (Levinsion, 2001: 1)
+
This text is an [[exposition]] of the [[Dharma-dharmata-vibhaga]] in [[Sanskrit]] or [[Distinguishing Dharma and Dharmata]] in English. The [[word]] [[dharma]] means “[[phenomena]]” and [[dharmata]] means “[[pure]] [[phenomena]].” (Levinsion, 2001: 1)
  
  
My reason for alluding to Maitreya's title is that the relationship between “vijnaptimdtra” and “vijnaptimdtratd” in Vasubandhu's work appears to be analogous to the one existing between “dharma” and “dharmatd” in Maitreya's.  
+
My [[reason]] for alluding to [[Maitreya's]] title is that the relationship between “vijnaptimdtra” and “vijnaptimdtratd” in [[Vasubandhu's]] work appears to be analogous to the one [[existing]] between “[[dharma]]” and “dharmatd” in [[Maitreya's]].  
  
With that in mind, some of us may want to reconsider our perchance too technical approach to Buddhist philosophy, and follow the simplicity and clarity of presentation demonstrated by Thrangu Rinpoche, whose understanding of the difference between Maitreya's concepts can help us get a better grasp of Vasubandhu's.
+
With that in [[mind]], some of us may want to reconsider our perchance too technical approach to [[Buddhist philosophy]], and follow the [[simplicity]] and clarity of presentation demonstrated by [[Thrangu Rinpoche]], whose [[understanding]] of the difference between [[Maitreya's]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] can help us get a better [[grasp]] of [[Vasubandhu's]].
  
The same sort of parallel drawn between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd, and dharma and dharmatd, can be made between the notions of sunya and sunyatd as they are expounded in Madhyamaka philosophy. While the term sunya promptly assumes an adjectival function in qualifying reality as svabhdva-sunya, that is, as empty of self-nature, sunyatd appears as a noun, commonly translated as emptiness, nothingness, or openness.
+
The same sort of parallel drawn between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd, and [[dharma]] and dharmatd, can be made between the notions of [[sunya]] and sunyatd as they are expounded in [[Madhyamaka philosophy]]. While the term [[sunya]] promptly assumes an adjectival function in qualifying [[reality]] as svabhdva-sunya, that is, as [[empty of self-nature]], sunyatd appears as a {{Wiki|noun}}, commonly translated as [[emptiness]], [[nothingness]], or [[openness]].
  
  
When we keep such parallels in mind, Vasubandhu's concepts are freed from being misconceived as undifferentiated. Since their differentiation is, as we have seen, fundamental to the correct grasp of the philosopher's core ideas, this essay strove to demonstrate how English scholarship, by overlooking such distinction at the level of translation, created difficulties in correctly grasping Vasubandhu's philosophy. Admittedly, the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd may have already seemed obvious to some. My hope, then, is that this essay will work towards making it even more obvious.
+
When we keep such parallels in [[mind]], [[Vasubandhu's]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] are freed from being misconceived as undifferentiated. Since their differentiation is, as we have seen, fundamental to the correct [[grasp]] of the philosopher's core [[ideas]], this essay strove to demonstrate how English {{Wiki|scholarship}}, by overlooking such {{Wiki|distinction}} at the level of translation, created difficulties in correctly [[grasping]] [[Vasubandhu's]] [[philosophy]]. Admittedly, the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd may have already seemed obvious to some. My {{Wiki|hope}}, then, is that this essay will work towards making it even more obvious.
  
  
  
Bibliography
+
[[Bibliography]]
  
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
Anacker, Stefan. 1984. Seven Works of Vasubandhu: The Buddhist Psychological Doctor. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
+
[[Anacker]], Stefan. 1984. Seven Works of [[Vasubandhu]]: The [[Buddhist]] [[Psychological]] Doctor. [[Delhi]]: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}.
  
Dilworth, David. 1969. “The Initial Formulations of ‘Pure Experience' in Nishida Kitaro and William James.” Monumenta Nipponica 24: 93-111
+
Dilworth, David. 1969. “The Initial Formulations of ‘[[Pure]] [[Experience]]' in [[Nishida Kitaro]] and {{Wiki|William James}}.” {{Wiki|Monumenta Nipponica}} 24: 93-111
  
Gold, Jonathan. 2014. Paving the Great Way: Vasubandhu's Unifying Buddhist Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.
+
{{Wiki|Gold}}, Jonathan. 2014. Paving the Great Way: [[Vasubandhu's]] Unifying [[Buddhist Philosophy]]. [[New York]]: [[Columbia University Press]].
  
Hall, Bruce Cameron. 1986. “The Meaning of Vijnapti in Vasubandhu's Concept of Mind.” Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 9: 7-23.
+
Hall, Bruce Cameron. 1986. “The Meaning of [[Vijnapti]] in [[Vasubandhu's]] {{Wiki|Concept}} of [[Mind]].” Journal of the [[International Association of Buddhist Studies]] 9: 7-23.
  
Keenan, John P. 1989. “Introduction,” in The Realm of Awakening: A Translation and Study of the Tenth Chapter of Asanga's Mahdydnasangraha. New York: Oxford University Press
+
Keenan, John P. 1989. “Introduction,” in The [[Realm]] of [[Awakening]]: A Translation and Study of the Tenth [[Chapter]] of [[Asanga's]] Mahdydnasangraha. [[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]]
Kochumuttom, Thomas. 1982. A Buddhist Doctrine of Experience: A New Translation and Interpretation of the Works of Vasubandhu the Yogdcdrin. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
+
{{Wiki|Kochumuttom}}, Thomas. 1982. [[A Buddhist Doctrine of Experience]]: A [[New Translation]] and Interpretation of the Works of [[Vasubandhu]] the Yogdcdrin. [[Delhi]]: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}.
Levinsion, Jules (trans.). 2001. Distinguishing Dharma and Dharmata by Asanga and Maitreya. New Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications.
+
Levinsion, Jules (trans.). 2001. [[Distinguishing Dharma and Dharmata]] by [[Asanga]] and [[Maitreya]]. {{Wiki|New Delhi}}: [[Sri Satguru Publications]].
Lusthaus, Dan. 2002. Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei- shih Lun. Curzon Critical Studies in Buddhism Series. London: Routledge.
+
[[Lusthaus, Dan]]. 2002. [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Phenomenology}}: A [[Philosophical]] [[Investigation]] of [[Yogacara]] [[Buddhism]] and the Ch'eng Wei- shih [[Lun]]. Curzon Critical Studies in [[Buddhism]] Series. [[London]]: Routledge.
Powers, John. 1995. Wisdom of the Buddha: The Samdhinirmocana Sutra. Dharma Publishing.
+
[[Powers]], John. 1995. [[Wisdom of the Buddha]]: The [[Samdhinirmocana Sutra]]. [[Dharma Publishing]].
Schmithausen, Lambert. 1987. Alayavijndna: On the Origin and the Early Development of a Central Concept of Yogdcdra Philosophy. Tokyo: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies.
+
[[Schmithausen]], Lambert. 1987. Alayavijndna: On the Origin and the Early [[Development]] of a Central {{Wiki|Concept}} of Yogdcdra [[Philosophy]]. [[Tokyo]]: The International Institute for [[Buddhist Studies]].
Shaw, Miranda. 1987. “William James and Yogacara philosophy: A comparative inquiry,” Philosophy East and West 37: 223-244.
+
Shaw, Miranda. 1987. “{{Wiki|William James}} and [[Yogacara]] [[philosophy]]: A comparative inquiry,” [[Philosophy East and West]] 37: 223-244.
Takeuchi, Shoko. 1977. “Phenomena and Reality in Vijnaptimatra Thought (I): On the usages of the suffix ‘ta' in Maitreya's Treatises.” In Buddhist Thought and Asian Civilization, ed. Leslie Kawamura and Keith Scott Emeryville, CA: Dharma Publishing, p. 254-67.
+
Takeuchi, [[Shoko]]. 1977. “[[Phenomena]] and [[Reality]] in [[Vijnaptimatra]] [[Thought]] (I): On the usages of the suffix ‘ta' in [[Maitreya's]] Treatises.” In [[Buddhist]] [[Thought]] and {{Wiki|Asian}} {{Wiki|Civilization}}, ed. [[Leslie Kawamura]] and Keith Scott [[Emeryville]], CA: [[Dharma Publishing]], p. 254-67.
Vasubandhu. 2004. “The Vimsatika Vijnaptimatratasiddhi of Vasubandhu,” in Fernando Tola and Carmen Dragonetti (Eds.) Being as Consciousness, Yogacara Philosophy of Buddhism. New Delhi: Motilal Barnasidass Publishers of India.
+
[[Vasubandhu]]. 2004. “The [[Vimsatika]] [[Vijnaptimatratasiddhi]] of [[Vasubandhu]],” in [[Fernando Tola]] and [[Carmen Dragonetti]] (Eds.) Being as [[Consciousness]], [[Yogacara Philosophy]] of [[Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|New Delhi}}: Motilal Barnasidass Publishers of [[India]].
Willis, Janice Dean. 1979. On Knowing Reality: The Tattvdrtha Chapter of Asanga's Boddhisattvabhumi. New York: Columbia University Press.
+
Willis, Janice Dean. 1979. On [[Knowing]] [[Reality]]: The Tattvdrtha [[Chapter]] of [[Asanga's]] Boddhisattvabhumi. [[New York]]: [[Columbia University Press]].
Yamada, Isshi. 1977. “Vijnaptimdtra of Vasubandhu.” Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society. Volume 109, Issue 02, p. 158­176.
+
Yamada, [[Isshi]]. 1977. “Vijnaptimdtra of [[Vasubandhu]].” [[Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society]]. Volume 109, Issue 02, p. 158­176.
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
  

Latest revision as of 19:00, 5 February 2020





Roberto Pinheiro Machado*


This essay springs from a discussion that was carried out recently in a seminar on Buddhist philosophy. During a panel on Yogacara, I was met with considerable skepticism from my colleagues when I argued that Vasubandhu employed the terms “vijnaptimdtra” and “vijnaptimdtratd” with very different meanings.

My point was that Vasubandhu used the first in reference to what early Buddhist doctrine called “conventional reality,” and the second as a description of what the doctrine termed “ultimate reality.” Given the skeptical response, I decided to analyze a number of scholarly texts that mentioned the two concepts, and I noticed that although the difference that I was pointing out seemed obvious to me, it had in fact been largely overlooked by scholarship.

Above all, I realized that most English translations do not render the distinction with sufficient clarity.

In what follows I will thus approach the issue of translation and discuss the available English renderings of Vasubandhu's texts where the two concepts appear. I believe that the difference between vijnaptimatra from vijnaptimatrata is fundamental to the correct apprehension of the soteriological principles that underlie Vasubandhu's philosophy. The translations' shortcomings create the sort of difficulties that lead readers to overlook the main function of the two concepts in the philosopher's system.


Department of Letters, Federal University of Rio Grande do Sul (Brazil). Email: robertopinheiromachado@live.comMy analysis will proceed through the following steps: Firstly, I will point to the difficulties that arrive through the English translations of Vasubandhu by presenting the background in which the two concepts are developed, setting them in the context of the notion of “vijnapti,” as well as in that of the trisvabhava theory (as it appears in the Samlhinirmocana Sutra, the works of Asanga, and is discussed by Willis, Keenan, and Yamada).

With such background in mind, I will work comparatively through eight translations of Vasubandhu and Asanga where the concepts are rendered primarily in an undifferentiated manner. Secondly, I will proceed to a close reading of Vasubandhu's Vimsatika, Vimsatikav®tti, and Trimsika in the original Sanskrit, pointing to the nuances in his employment of the two concepts.

In this vein, an analysis of the five instances where the two concepts appear in the Vimsatika and Vimsatikav®tti will be approached in reference to the discussion of the role played by the suffix “ta” in the Sanskrit language (a discussion started in the Buddhist scholarly context by Takeuchi).


Thirdly, I will further develop my thesis by means of an inferential analysis where the usages of the two concepts will be seen in reference to the soteriological project that underlies Vasubandhu's philosophy. At this point I will refer to passages from selected sutras that are relevant to the Yogacara tradition in which the philosopher is inscribed, and which will corroborate with the demonstration of the distinct connotations of the two terms in question.


Finally, I will propose an alternative translation to the term “vijnaptimatrata” that will differentiate it more clearly from “vijnaptimatra.”

Before we begin our inquiry, it is important to bear in mind that in the past decades Buddhist scholars have recurrently emphasized the need of more and better translations of original Sanskrit Buddhist texts (in this vein, Janice Willis and Bruce Cameron Hall present two instances where such necessity is discussed at considerable length). This essay follows such an emphasis in an attempt to stress, and hopefully help clarify, some of the difficulties involved in the task of rendering Buddhist philosophical ideas in English in a way that does not remove their soteriological implications from our sight.


1. Background on vijnapti in relation with the trisvabhava theory and comparison of English translations

1.1 The two truths and the three svabhavas


In order to observe how vijhaptimatra and vijhaptimatrata operate in relation to conventional and ultimate reality (samvrti sat and paramartha sat, respectively), we need first have a clear understanding of the role played by the doctrine of two truths as it underlies nearly the entirety of Vasubandhu’s system of thought.

The necessity for clarifying such a role springs from the fact that instead of drawing directly on early Buddhist scripture and, in doing so, immediately embracing its twofold division of reality, the philosopher adopts the new doctrine of trisvabhava, a tripartite classification of the nature of phenomena that was first formulated by Asanga (following, primarily, the Mahayana Samdhinirmocana and Lahkavatara sutras). As Willis points out-


For Asanga, the two-truths theory was insufficient. He therefore devised a schema which states that all phenomena have three natures: (1) a mentally constructed and therefore imaginary (parikalpita) nature; (2) a dependent, or relative (paratantra) nature; and (3) a perfected or absolute (parinispanna) nature. (Willis 1979: 18).


Such a tripartite classification was adopted and further developed by Vasubandhu, who, as I argue below, added to it the dimension of non-being (abhava). By asserting the presence of non-being together with that of being, Vasubandhu established the ground for the equation of being and non-being in ultimate reality nd with it supplied a new support to the primary goal of the trisvabhava theory as established by Asanga, that is, that of clarifying the Mahayana doctrine of sunyata and providing, in Willis’ words, “an insulation against nihilism.” (Willis 1979: 18).


Be that as it may, what interests us here is to observe that the trisvabhava theory, while in fact intended to further develop and extend the older Buddhist doctrine of two truths, was never meant to deny it. And it is in this sense that, as we will see, the older division of reality into samv®ti and paramdrtha sat still holds validity both in the trisvabhava theory, as well as in the whole of Vasubandhu's system.

The point to be kept in mind here is that the purpose for the adoption of a new category of phenomena was primarily that of finding a middle ground that would account for the conversion from the first form of reality to the second. Such a middle category is, following Asanga's abovementioned formulation, the paratantra-svabhava or “dependent nature.”


In order to further clarify the meaning of paratantra- svabhava in Asanga and Vasubandhu, we must look at the source of the trisvabhava theory in the Samlhinirmocana Sutra. It is in its sixth chapter that we find the tripartite analysis of being appearing in its most basic formulation.

As the Buddha pronounces the following speech to the Bodhisattva Gunakara, the notion of the paratantra-svabhava is expounded as that which adheres to phenomena that, by arising under the rubric of co-dependent origination (prat¥tya-samutpada), are ultimately empty of self­nature:


Gunakara, in dependence upon names that are connected with signs, the imputational [[[parikalpita-svabhava]]] character is known. In dependence upon strongly adhering to the other-dependent character as being the imputational character, the other-dependent character [[[paratantra]]- svabhava] is known. In dependence upon absence of strong adherence to the other-dependent character as being the imputational character, the thoroughly established character [parinispanna-svabhdva] is known. (Powers 1995: 87)


As that which adheres to the constructed nature of phenomena, the paratantra-svabhava stands as a middle category where ignorance abides and suffering originates. The equation that expresses the relation among ignorance, suffering, and co­dependent origination appears in the sutra as follows:


Gunakara, what is the other-dependent character of phenomena? It is simply the dependent origination of phenomena. It is like this: Because this exists, that arises; because this is produced, that is produced. It ranges from: “Due to the condition of ignorance, compositional factors [arise],” up to: “In this way, the whole great assemblage of suffering arises.” (Powers 1995: 83).


We thus understand that, in opposition to both parikalpita- svabhava, the category of the being of objects (vastu or grahya) that exist only by means of (illusory) thought-construction (vikalpa), and to parinispanna-svabhava, the one where reality is perfected and free of thought construction, paratantra-svabhdva stands as the category of the subject (grahaka), which, following the traditional Buddhist doctrine of anatman, is in fact ultimately non-existent, that is, is itself a mind construct.

From this we can assume that when the sutra claims that the paratantra-svabhava is made known by the adherence of “the other dependent character as being the imputational character,” it is claiming precisely that the paratantra-svabhava is made known when that which grasps mentally constructed phenomena is taken to exist in the same mode as such grasped phenomena themselves, that is, as existing in and by themselves outside of consciousness.


But what is most important to notice is that paratantra- svabhava, besides being the nature of the phenomenon whose very nature constructs parikalpita-svabhava, is also the one that permits the conversion from this same parikalpita-svabhava to parinispanna-svabhava. The conversion itself is worked out by Asanga and Vasubandhu under the name of “dsrayapardv®tti,” a term commonly translated as “revolution of the basis.” The point is thus that through asrayaparav®tti the paratantra-svabhava is converted in parinispanna-svabhava, and as such loses its “dependent” nature, that is, it ceases to depend on mentally constructed objects in order to exist, and as such ceases all grasping.

Asrayapardv®tti is, then, the key soteriological aim for which the trisvabhava theory was built. As Keenan notes,


The theory of the three patterns (trisvabhdva) strove to show that the basic other-dependent pattern of consciousness accounts both for the genesis of imagined illusion and for the possibility of its transformation into perfect awakening and wisdom. (Keenan 1989: 50) Such transformation, understood as the perfection of reality occurring in the paratantra-svabhdva as a revolution of its basis (dsrayapardv®tti), amounts, in traditional Buddhist terms, to the overcoming of conventional reality towards the achievement of ultimate truth.


1.2 Vijnapti, vijnaptimatra, and vijhapimatrata


Intrinsically related to the process of dsrayapardv®tti, it must be noted, is the notion of vijnapti, put forth by Vasubandhu to further characterize the being of paratantra-svabhdva. Here we arrive at our first major point in the attempt to understand the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd.

For, as will become clear, it is the very notion of vijnapti with its role in the transformation from parikalpita to parinispanna-svabhdva that will provide us with the basis for correctly apprehending the different functions assumed by vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd in Vasubandhu's philosophical system.

In order to demonstrate such distinct functions, I will proceed first to an examination of the concept of vijnapti itself, and then to an analysis of the meaning it acquires when supplemented by the term mdtra. The difficulties involved in correctly grasping the new concept, now “vijnaptimdtra,” will be observed through the disagreement on its basic meaning seen in the work of two scholars, Janice Willis and Bruce Cameron Hall.

After a brief analysis of their basic assumptions, I will look into the concept's appearance in the first verse of Vasubandhu's Vimsatikd, and call forth two translations that, while agreeing on its basic meaning, support Willis's understanding of the concept. Following this, I will then call forth passages in Vasubandhu's text where “vijnaptimdtra” appears accrued by the suffix “td,” forming now “vijnaptimdtratd,” and point to how in such instances not only does agreement in translation further slacken, but also the accretion of the suffix “td” is not, in most cases, properly taken into consideration by the translators.


1.2.1. Vijnapti


Going back to the concept of vijnapti, then, we should now observe how such foundational notion has been met with difficulties in scholarly interpretation, and how such difficulties gave rise to a wealth of translations that are for the most part unhelpful in arriving at a clear understanding of the concept. Yamada (1997: 163), for instance, explains vijhapti as follows:

In our world of experience, “being conscious,” (vijhana) means that the three modes of transformation of vijhana (vijhana-parinama) have taken place. Moreover, “being conscious,” can take place only in the form of “being conscious of something.” Thus vijnana is inevitably double­faceted. Within consciousness there are two things present at one and the same time, one being being conscious (vijnana) of something and the other being something (vijneya) of which one is conscious. This double-faceted consciousness is called vijnapti, representation.


Here the concept of vijnapti appears in phenomenological terms as the reflexive consciousness that apprehends itself in the processes of apprehending the external world, creating thus a double perspective on reality. Such understanding of vijnapti, however, is unsatisfactory to the extent that it does not account for many of the nuances it assumes under Vasubandhu's usage.

As we will see after looking closely into the philosopher's original words, and attempting a new translation for the concept, this limited understanding of vijnapti is very likely one of the causes of scholars' failure to properly differentiate vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata.

At this point, however, we should notice that Yamada himself does seem to be aware that the above understanding of vijnapti is in fact not the only possible one. A clear indicator that such is the case is that throughout the abovementioned essay he translates the term vijnapti in as many as seven different ways: as “appearance” (p. 162); “internal mind” (p. 169); “mental function” (p. 169); “discursive mind” (p. 167); “relative subject” (p. 168); “empirical cognition” (p. 170); and “representation” (p. 163).


As a discussion of each of the above renderings would only lead us into a maze of confusion, we should keep in mind that the difficulty lies in the fact that nowhere in Vasubandhu can we find a clear specification that vijnapti necessarily implies a dualistic form of perception.

As a mental image, vijnapti can be understood both as a basic “perception” that does not assume anything about that which is perceived, as well as a “representation” that implies a subjective construction of what is found in the perceptive field. It must be noted, however, that the level of discussion at which vijnapti must perforce be understood as a “representation,” is solely that where all perceptions must be understood as such.

This level is the one where it is assumed that the object perceived has already changed by the time it is apprehended by the senses; at this level a vijnapti would naturally amount to a “representation,” but not necessarily to a “representation” as opposed to a “perception.”


1.2.2 From vijnapti to vijnaptimdtra: Willis vs. Hall


Be that as it may, from the variegated assortment of translations we see in Yamada—which manifest the flagrant difficulty in rendering the term vijnapti in a single and more precise way—we could expect further complications in scholarly translation when Vasubandhu adds first the wordmatra,” and then the suffix “ta,” to “vijnapti.” Starting then our comparative approach to the translations, we should begin by observing Willis's understanding of vijnaptimatra:


It is here that we find the Yogacara's important epistemological point that in every ordinary cognition, what is cognized is not an accurate portrayal of an object existing outside the mind but merely an object-like mental image (vijnaptimatra) of that; only a “conceptualizedobject, one that is solely the product of constructive imagination. (Willis 1979: 26).


Here vijnaptimatra is defined as “merely an object-like mental image.” We should pay careful attention to the appearance of term “merely” in Willis's fragment. While the term vijnapti alone could be translated as “object-like mental image” (a notion close enough to Yamada's “representation”), “matra” has an adjectival function, qualifying vijnapti into what translates now as “merely an object-like mental image” [my italics].


While the difference may seem slight, such understanding of matra as “merely” leads to a definition of vijnaptimatra that will provide the term with the capacity to describe what is expounded in traditional Buddhist thought as “conventional reality.”

The point here is that in order to assert that every ordinary cognition, or every vijnapti, is not the cognition of an object that exists in itself—that is, of an object that, were it in fact to exist in itself, would consequently pertain to ultimate reality—Vasubandhu adjoins the term matra and by doing so qualifies vijnapti as a cognition or representation that is “merely” conventional.

In other words, such cognition is defined as a “mere” representation precisely to the extent that it is incapable of accounting for the object itself, or for ultimate reality in general. Needless to say, Willis's understanding of vijnaptimdtra as “merely and object like mental image” is valid.


Although all this may sound like common sense, such an interpretation of the term mdtra as functioning in the context of Vasubandhu's texts with a meaning akin to that of the English word “merely” is not unanimously agreed upon by scholars. For this reason, the work of one scholar deserves special attention.

In “The Meaning of Vijnapti in Vasubandhu's Concept of Mind,” Bruce Cameron Hall (:1986) counters with considerable vehemence the notion that the concept mdtra functions in the context of Vasubandhu's philosophy with a meaning akin to that of the English “merely.”

Attempting an historical analysis of the concept of vijnapti, Hall starts his essay pointing to the shortcomings of the available English translations of the term vijnaptimdtra as “representation-only” (Hamilton:1938), “ideation-only” (Chan: 1957), and “perception-only” (Anacker: 1984), and then proposes an analysis of the term's usage in the original Sanskrit as the alternative to a new English translation of it.


Hall then proceeds to examine the concept's appearance in the Sarvastivadin Abhidharma, and stresses Vasubandhu's appropriation of the term and employment of it in a special sense.

Aptly citing the philosopher's Abhidharmakosa-bhdsya, Hall demonstrates how in that work the concept of vijnapti is intrinsically related to that of vijndna. There, he argues, vijnapti is understood as the very apprehension of consciousness with respect to the various sense objects (p. 12). Another important factor in understanding the term, Hall contends, relates to Vasubandhu's equation of it with other concepts used to define the notion of “mind,” a contention followed by a thorough analysis of such concepts as they mutually interact.


In the second part of his essay, Hall inquires on the meaning of the concept “mdtra,” pointing to its various possible translations. One such translation, that is, that of mdtra as “mere,” is readily dismissed. Still, Hall recognizes that an important question remains, namely, why does Vasubandhu employ the term vijnaptimdtra in his works instead of remaining faithful to the earlier notion of “cittamdtra” that appears in several sutras, as well as in the works of Asanga.


Hall then offers, somewhat against his originally stated purpose, what amounts to a translation of vijnaptimdtra, rendering the concept as “percept” and engaging it in an East/West comparative analysis where “vijnaptimatra” and “percept” are seen as equivalent. Hall's claim is that, just like a percept, a vijnapti is a representation that is independent on the existence of an external object.

Such type of representation is understood by Hall as a purely mental product, and as such is equated with the notion of “mind-only.” In Hall's words, and within his attempt to justify his linking of “vijnaptimatra” and “percept,” “when vijnapti is qualified as ‘mind-only,' it cannot be meant as a representation of anything else, especially not of an external object.” (Hall 1986: 14).


Equating the notion of vijnapti with “mind-only,” however, will lead us into serious difficulties if “mind-only” is to be understood not as a qualifier of external reality—that is, as an explanation that any object represented in consciousness does not exist outside of consciousness itself (and, in this particular sense is “mind-only”)—but as a state of being in which mind abides without being linked to the representation, or mental construction, of any object.

We should be attentive, then, to these two possible understandings of “mind-only,” namely, one that is a description of the world in its quality of a mind-constructed entity, and another that describes the state of a pure mind that does not apprehend objects as external to itself. The point to be kept in mind here, however, is that when cross-analyzing the scholarship on Vasubandhu, such a distinction between the two possible understandings of “mind-only” is—as we soon will see—largely overlooked.


Be it as it may, as such double capacity of the concept of “mind-only” is based precisely on the perception of the dual nature of reality, and in this sense is fundamental to the correct grasping of Vasubandhu's soteriology, my contention at this point is that Hall, by mistakenly applying the second sense of “mind-only” to vijnaptimatra, blurs the doctrine of the two truths out of Vasubandhu's enterprise.


In the same vein, by losing sight of the aforementioned double sense of “mind-only,” Hall appears to overlook the fact that a vijnapti cannot be regarded simply as an objectless representation, or as something that “cannot be meant as the representation of anything else,” for even if the object represented in a vijnapti had no equivalent in external reality, such representation would still be not objectless to the extent that it would still exist as a mental object.

In other words, regardless of whether or not such representation has a bearing on external reality, it still implies the presence of the very mental representation that it itself is.

If we followed Hall's argument, then, vijnaptimatra would amount to something scarcely different then vijnapti: it would be a sort of “vijnapti-only” where the external object would, given its non-necessity, be ruled out. Such understanding of vijnaptimatra, however, is also unable carry the connotation, actually implied in Hall's analysis, of “mind-only” in the sense of “mind-itself,” or of a mind free from representation or thought construction.

For such a free mind would not be the one that abides in a state of objectless representation, even if an “objectless representation” were in fact possible, but the one that would exist in the very absence of any representation. Such would be the mind in the state of what the Yogacara tradition calls nirvikalpa-jnana, or “non-discriminative perception.”


This second understanding of “mind-only,” as a state of being, as opposed to an adjective that qualifies external reality, will in fact appear, as we will see, in Willis's translation of the term “vijnaptimatrata” as it occurs in Vasubandhu's Trimsika, verse 25.

My point here, however, is not to assert that the term “mind-only” should be employed only in one of the two senses discussed above, but that, given the evident difficulties the term is prone to create, the employment of another term altogether might be a better option. At any rate, were the employment of the term to be insisted upon, we should expect that the above two senses would, at least, be clearly distinguished.


Be that as it may, before we can move look into more translations of Vasubandhu's work, it is important to emphasize that what lies at the heart of Hall's misunderstanding of the meaning of vijnaptimatra, and of his dismissal of the obviously valid translation of the term matra as “mere,” is, besides his inattentiveness of the difference between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata, the perception of a positive connotation pertaining to the concept of vijnaptimatra as it appears in Vasubandhu's system.

Linked to such perception is Hall's assertion that Vasubandhu's use of “vijnapti” in the compound vijnaptimatra instead of “vijnana” or “citta,” “seems to indicate an intent to avoid the idealist extreme.” (Hall 1986: 15).


In spite of the fact that we can find no clear evidence that to “avoid the idealist extreme” is anything that Vasubandhu himself had in mind, such avoidance would seem, to Hall, to account for a positive quality inherent in vijnaptimatra, a quality that the negative adjectival function of the word “mere” would perforce downplay.

Nevertheless, were we to grant the positive quality claimed by Hall, vijnaptimatra would appear not as a critique of reality, that is, not as a warning that the world of objects in its entirety is nothing more than, or “merely a,” mind construct, but as something else that, on the contrary, should be striven for. And it is precisely here that Hall misses the soteriological principle that directs the whole of Vasubandhu's philosophy.

For the perception of a positive connotation to vijnaptimatra leads Hall (1986: 15) to assert that “mind itself is vijnaptimatra”, an assertion that not only Vasubandhu himself is not willing to make, but that also contradicts the simple logic that if vijnaptimatra can be understood as “representation only,” then “mind itself,” in the context of Vasubandhu's soteriology, cannot be such “representation only,” but, on the contrary, it must, again, be mind free from such representation.


Another important point is that what appears to be lying at the heart of Hall's misunderstanding is a failure to effectively recognize the adjectival function assumed by the notion of vijnaptimatra in Vasubandhu's texts.

As we will see below, although the term is employed in different ways (as for instance, a “teaching,” as that which is “responsible for the false notion of the self,” and as that which “accounts for the perceptual arising of form”), its primary grammatical function in Vasubandhu's usage is that of an adjective, that is, as a description of reality.

As we will see below, if we take the first paragraph of the Vimsatikav®tti as paradigmatic, we will notice that all Vasubandhu asserts at that point is that the trailokadhatu, or the external world in its tripartite conception, is vijnaptimatra, and not that “mind itself” is so.

Paying close attention to the grammatical function of vijnaptimatra in the texts themselves, then, will lead us to see that the term qualifies the external world of objects in a negative way, that is, as something that is nothing but, or that is “merely,” a mind construct. The point to be kept in perspective is thus that since vijnaptimatra describes and qualifies the mentally constructed world, it can only describe and qualify conventional reality. And if this is correct, it then remains for us to learn what the concept would be that would describe and qualify ultimate reality.


In spite of the above misapprehensions, Hall (1986: 18) is in fact correct when, at the end of his essay, he points to the fact that “it is, after all, sainsara that is declared to be vijnaptimatra.” And, if this is so, then here again we should pose the question: if Vasubandhu uses the term vijnaptimatra to account for experience of sainsara, then what term does he use to account for nirvana?


1.2.3. A range of translations


In order to arrive at a clear understanding of the difference between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata, and of the rapport between the latter concept and that of paramartha sat, we must now look into Vasubandhu's actual texts and verify how his employment of “vijnaptimatra” is consistent with the translation of the term matra as “mere.”

After doing this, we will be in a position to look into the philosopher's usage of “vijnaptimatrata,” and to work comparatively between the two terms, with the double purpose of demonstrating their difference while at the same time showing that the blurring of their boundaries occurs, for the most part, at the level of translation.


In the first verse of the Vimsatika Vasubadhu writes:

vijnaptimatramevaitadasadarthavabhasanat| yatha taimirikasyasatkesacandradidarsanam ||1|| Below we find Kochumuttom's translation of the passage. Notice that “vijnaptimatra” is correctly rendered by the word “mere”:

It is all mere representation of consciousness, Because there is the appearance of non-existent objects;

Just as a man with a cataract Sees hairs, moons, etc. Which do not exist in reality. (Kochumuttom 1982: 166)

In the same vein, Anacker's translation of the term, albeit not inclusive of the word “mere,” does not get in the way of understanding the negative connotation of vijnaptimatra: All this is perception only, because of the appearance of non-existent objects,

just as there may be the seeing of non-existent nets of hair by someone afflicted with an optical disorder. (Anacker 1984: 161).


Here the notion “perception only” works as a qualifier of reality that devalues its contents in view of assumed limitations in cognition. Such is the agreement on the basic meaning of vijnaptimdtra. When it comes to the term "vijnaptimatrata." however, there is less agreement as to translation. Before we can point out the discrepancies, however, it is important to notice that Anacker renders “vijnaptimdtratd" in a manner that does not differentiate it from "vijnaptimatra." Here is verse 25 of the Trimsikd. followed by his translation:


dharmanam paramarthasca sa yatastathata’pi sah\ sarvakalam tathabhavat saiva vijnaptimdtratd ||25|| Anacker’s translation (1984: 188):


It is the ultimate truth of all events, and so it is “Suchness”, too, since it is just so all the time, and it’s just perception-only. As we can perceive, Anacker fails to distinguish “vijnaptimdtra" from “vijnaptimdtratd" in his translation, rendering both terms as “perception-only.” Kochumuttom’s translation (1982: 157) of Trimsikd 25, however, presents a development from Anacker’s:

That from which all elements have their ultimate reality, [Is the third naturelessness,] It is also called suclmess, Because it remains always as such;

That is itself the state [in which one realizes the meaning] Of mere representation of consciousness, too.

Here the wordstate” indicates Kochumuttom’s perception of the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd. Going from the first as “mere representation of consciousness” to the second as “the state [in which one realizes the meaning] of mere representation of consciousness,” however, may not sufficiently emphasize the difference, obscuring it for the reader who does not have prior knowledge of Vasubandhu’s arguments, or that lacks access to the original Sanskrit text. At any rate, and as we will see in more detail below, Kochumuttom’s rendering is valid.


Contrary to Anacker and Kochumuttom, Willis translates “vijnaptimatra” and “vijnaptimatrata” in a more clearly differentiated manner. Below, we find her translation of the same verse (Trimsikd, 25), which should be compared with the previously cited fragment where we observed her rendering of vijnaptimatra as “merely an object-like mental image”:


The supreme truth of all dharmas

Is nothing other than the True Norm (suchness). It is forever true to its nature, Which is the true nature of mind-only.( Willis 1979: 34)


Willis thus goes from vijnaptimatra as “merely an object­like mental image” to vijnaptimatrata as “mind-only.” Recalling Hall's renderings of Vasubandhu's concepts, and now cross­examining it with Willis's, we observe that the former employs “mind-only” in reference to vijnaptimatra, and that the latter does so in regard to vijnaptimatrata. Such a double usage of “mind- only” hides from the reader the basic difference between the two Sanskrit terms.


With that in mind, we must now observe another translation of the passage. In the following fragment we will see that, as an alternative to the previously observed efforts of Willis, Anacker and Kochumuttom, Yamada opts for leaving the term “vijnaptimatrata” untranslated (notice that he joins verses 24 and 25 of the Trimsika in his translation):


Thus, there is the next non-being-ness (nihsvabhdvatd), for that [sa = nispnanna-svabhava] is the ultimate reality of all dharmas. It is such-ness (tathatd), as it is such-being (tathdbhdva) at all times.


This is, indeed, vijnaptimdtratd. (Yamada 1997: 168)

If Yamada's rendering of Trimsikd 25 does not provide us with a translation of “vijnaptimdtratd,” at another point of the same essay where the above fragment appears he does seem to be attentive to the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd. By rendering the latter term as “Vijnapti-Only- ness” (Yamada 1997: 172), however, Yamada once again falls short of providing us with a complete translation.


We are thus provided with four translations of “vijnaptimdtratd”: Kochumuttom's “state in which one realizes the meaning of mere representation of consciousness,” Anacker's “perception-only,” Willis's “mind-only,” together with Yamada's renderings. Given that the four previous examples tend to obstruct our way into a clear distinction between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata in translation, we should now look at a fifth rendering of Trimsika 25. Richard H. Robinson's translation accomplishes a more clear differentiation between the two concepts:


Because it is the absoluteness of the elements and their suchness, Because it is ‘so' forever. It alone is perception-only-ness. (Lusthaus 2002: 299)


Here one sees the suffix “ta” added by Vasubandhu to “vijnaptimatra” being accounted for by the English particle “ness.” Such rendering allows for a more precise understanding of the concept than was possible with the previously cited translations. Robinson's version of the following verse 26 of the Trimsika provides us with another instance where a clearer understanding of vijnaptimatrata becomes evident:


yavad vijnaptimatratve vijnanam navatisthatil grahadvayasyanusayastavanna vinivartate ||26|| So long as consciousness does not remain in the state of representation-only, The residues of the twofold grasping will not cease to function. (Lusthaus 2002: 300)


Noticing that the Sanskrit suffix “tva” (appearing in the verse in the locative form “vijnaptimatratve”), possesses a grammatical function analogous to that of “ta,” we find Robinson replacing the previous particle “ness” of verse 25 with the wordstate.”

Such qualification of “representation-only” as a state of being arrived at by consciousness gives us a clear awareness of the import of “vijnaptimatrata” as something other than a qualifier of external reality. Below are alternative renderings of verse of 26: Willis (1979: 35):


Inasmuch as consciousness in its unawakened state Is not in the abode of the reality of mind-only,

The six-sense organs, their objects, and the seeds of evil desires Cannot be controlled and extirpated. Anacker (1984: 188):

As long as consciousness is not situated within perception only, the residues of a “dual” apprehension will not come to an end. Kochumuttom (1982: 158):

As long as consciousness does not abide In the realization [that the subject-object designations] Are mere representations of consciousness, The attachment to the twofold grasping Will not cease to operate.


Among the three translations, Kochumuttom's is again especially worthy of attention. If we agree with the notion that the term “vijnaptimatrata” refers to the state of being where the mind is free from conceptualization, and that such freedom occurs precisely as the “realization that the subject-object designations are mere representations of consciousness” then Kochumuttom's translation does in fact present us with a valid rendering of vijnaptimatrata, one that is, indeed, akin to that of Robinson.


The above identification of the mind free from thought construction with the realization that the dualism implied in the subject-object distinction is merely mind constructed, however, leaves room for extensive doctrinal debate.

Although we can assert with a high degree of certainty that, within the Buddhist reflection, the realization that all duality occurs primarily at the mental level is in fact a prerequisite for mind's abiding in non-conceptualization, such realization in and by itself, that is, in the sense of no more than a rational understanding, can hardly be equated with mind's freedom from thought construction.

To put in more clear terms, and always keeping in mind that we are dealing with problems at the level of translation, what we have at hand are two possible interpretations of the term “realization” that can give off two different meanings when applied in relation to vijnaptimatrata: the first, where “realization” is meant as an understanding that occurs primarily at the intellectual level, and the second where “realization” is intended as “actualization,” that is, as the coming into effect of something.


In the phrase “As long as consciousness does not abide in the realization [that the subject-object designations] are mere representations of consciousness the attachment to the twofold grasping will not cease to operate,” Kochumuttom appears to be inattentive to the nuances of the term “realization,” and therefore employs it in the first sense described, that is, as a rationalrealization” of a given idea.


Be that as it may, Kochumuttom's implication of the term “realization” with vijnaptimatrata is useful to our inquiry in that it helps us clarify our own aims. Our task here is first to demonstrate that vijnaptimatrata indeed implies “realization” in the second sense described above, that is, as “actualization,” and second to arrive at a translation of the Sanskrit term where such “realization” would be rendered in the clearest way possible.


Accomplishing the first task would thus imply a depiction of vijnaptimatrata as a realization that occurs not simply as a rational understanding of something, but as the actualization of a given element. As the element that is to be actualized is consciousness itself, the “realization” proposed would imply a transformation of consciousness, that is, its coming into a state where a change in its very nature has occurred.

Such discussion, however, will inevitably fall under the doctrinal debate about the way in which such “transformation of consciousness” should be in fact described. As we will see, this debate is, in turn, inextricably linked to the inquiries into the meaning of asraya-parav®tti, and on the role played by meditative practices in the development of Buddhist philosophical concepts.

But before we can discuss the relation between vijnaptimatrata and asraya-parav®tti, we must first look at yet another translation that will provide us with the basis to further clarify the role played by the suffix “ta” in the formation of the compound “vijnaptimatrata.” Only after we clearly understand the grammatical elements integrated in the Sanskrit term, will we be in a position to inquire on its doctrinal and philosophical implications.


Turning to Xuanzang's Chinese translation of the Trimsika, Dan Lusthaus offers us yet another rendering of “vijnaptimatrata,” presenting it now as “psychosophical-closure-hood (Lusthaus 2002: 299).” In spite of the obvious difficulty in arriving at what “psychosophical-closure” could possibly mean, we do find in Lusthaus the same sort of consistency seen in Robinson where the suffix “ta” (or “tva”) is taken into account in the formation of Vasubandhu's compound. Rendering the particle “ta” as “hood” provides Lusthaus' translation of vijnaptimatrata with the abstract quality that removes it from the adjectival function of vijnaptimdtra.


Here we must note that the question of the precise meaning of the suffix “td” in Sanskrit Buddhist texts has been discussed at length by Shoko Takeuchi in her essay “Phenomena and Reality in Vijnaptimatra Thought (I): On the usages of the suffix ‘ta' in Maitreya's Treatises.” Although in this work Takeuchi does not approach the question of the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd, her explanation of how the suffix “td” came to be understood as having a meaning of its own within Buddhist scholarship will certainly be illuminating for our discussion.


After explaining how the suffix is employed in Sanskrit to form an abstract noun, and as such does not possess an independent meaning, Takeuchi shows how the Chinese Faxiang School understood the term “tathatd” to mean “absolute reality” by virtue of the suffix “td” appended to it. In Takeuchi's words (1977: 259),


Originally the relationship between ‘phenomena' and ‘reality' was explained as ‘neither identical nor different' simply by adding the suffix “td” to a word, e.g., dharma and dharmatd, tathd and tathatd, and so on. But the unique way in which the Fa-hsiang School explained this relationship originated in its interpretation that the suffix td has an independent meaning of its own.


From the above we can derive two inferences that are closely related to our inquiry. The first, connected to our search for the clarification of the meaning of “vijnaptimdtratd,” would be that the interpretation of the Faxiang School regarding the usage of the suffix “td” in Maitreya's treatises might be valid, and as such might hold true to Vasubandhu's works as well.

In such a case, that is, by possessing an independent meaning of its own, the suffix “td” might be prone to conferring a completely new meaning to vijnaptimdtratd, distinguishing it thus very clearly from vijnaptimdtra. The second inference, this one moving along the lines of inquiring on a possible explanation for the shortcomings of the English translations, would surmise that the absence of direct contact with that specific Chinese interpretation referred to by Takeuchi may have lead Western scholars to overlook the change in meaning provided by accretion of the suffix “td” to Sanskrit Buddhist concepts.

Be that as it may, and with the second supposition in mind, it is important to notice that among the seven renderings of vijnaptimdtrata seen so far, that is, by Willis, Anacker, Kochumuttom, Yamada, Robinson, and Lusthaus, only the last three, that is, the one’s from scholars that appear to have had contact with the abovementioned Chinese interpretation, show a clear awareness of the import of the suffix “to” in the formation of Vasubandhu’s compound concept.


Having thus approached the grammatical functions of the elements that form Vasubandhu’s compound, we can now proceed to the second part of our inquiry, where a more direct contact with Vasubandhu’s original Sanskrit text is required.


2. Analysis of the five instances where the concepts appear in the Vimsatikd and Vimsatikavrtti after the first verse


In order to demonstrate the difference between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimdtrata, I will now proceed to a close reading of the five instances where the terms appear in the Vimsatikd and Vimsatikavrtti after Vasubandhu’s initial statement to the effect that the entire universe (trailokadhatum) is vijnaptimatra.

My purpose here is to call attention to the different meanings assumed by concepts throughout Vasubandhu’s text. In order to provide a clear view of how the terms function within their textual framework, I will provide my own translations for the passages cited while leaving the two Sanskrit terms untranslated. After proceeding through a commentary on their original formulation, I expect to find myself in a position where a new translation can be proposed.


2.1. Vijnaptimatra as a teaching (desanay.


anyatheti vijnaptimatradesana katham dharmanairatmya- pravesah vijnaptimatramidam rupadidharma- pratibhasamntpadyate na tu ritpadilaksano dharmah ko’pyastiti viditvd. (Vasubandhu 2004: 127) Otherwise the teaching of vijnaptimatra refers to introducing the selflessness of phenomena.


Ihus, vijnaptimatra accounts for the perceptual arising of form, etc., without in fact phenomena characterized by form having at all been known.

Here we find the term “vijnaptimatra followed by “desand” a term commonly understood as “instruction” or “teaching.” Thus “vijnaptimatra” appears as the content of a teaching, that is, of something that can be passed on through language in introducing the notion of the selflessness of phenomena. Notice that such “teaching,” however, is not described as being, in itself, an abiding in the state of selflessness.

It simply “introduces” (pravesahj a characteristic of phenomena, or, for that matter, of reality as a whole, namely, that of being without a self. The adjectival function of vijnaptimatra, then (that is, that of describing reality in a peculiar way ), still takes precedence in the formulation of vijnaptimatra as something that can be taught.

For what is taught is, once again, precisely a quality of reality. In the same vein, the negative import of such an adjectival function can be appraised in the next phrase, where Vasubandhu states that vijnaptimatra “accounts for the perceptual arising of form.” Here the concept clearly assumes the negative connotation that we saw being overlooked by Hall.

As the perceptual arising of form is understood primarily as a source of delusion, the teaching of vijnaptimatra functions as the demonstration of something to be avoided or overcome, as opposed to something that, would it possess a positive quality, should be dwelled upon.


2.2. Vijnaptimatra as responsible for the false notion of the self (kalpitendtmana):


evam vijnaptimdtrasi dpi vijhaph -antaraparikalpitendtmana nairatmyapravesdt vijhaptimdtravyavasthapanaya sarvadharmancini nairdtmyapraveso bhavati na tu tadastitvdpavdddt. itarathd hi vijhapterapi vijhaptyantaramarthah sydditi vijhaptimdtratvam na sidhyetdrthavatifvddvijnaptindm.

(Vasubandhu 2004: 127) Tirus, the mentally constructed self, which is inherent to representation, is precisely that which appears as vijnaptimatra and which was introduced as selfless. One is introduced to the selflessness of all phenomena through this understanding of vijhaptmdtra—not through the denial of their existence.

Indeed, even if by means of representation the represented object should be understood as existing, vijhaptimdtratva would not be established because this object is being apprehended on the basis of a double representation.


In the above fragment we find a very clear distinction between “vijnaptimatra” and “vijnaptimatrata.” While the first concept appears as that which is responsible for the upsurge of the false notion of the self, the second appears as precisely the locus where selflessness is established. Here it is important to call attention for the various possible translations of the term “siddhi” as it appears in relation to “vijnaptimatratva.”

Anacker, for instance, translates “siddhi” as “demonstration,” and “vijnaptimatratva” as “state of perception-only.” Although “state of perception-only” seems at first to properly account for the difference brought forth by the suffix “ta,” Anacker's translation of “siddhi” as “demonstration” does not satisfactorily set vijnaptimatratva as a “state,” apart from vijnaptimatra as the content of a teaching.

Keeping in mind that the term “siddhi” can also be translated as “accomplishment, performance, fulfilment, or complete attainment, translating it as “establishment,” as opposed to Anacker's “demonstration,” brings “vijnaptimatratva” to function as the very accomplishment of the teaching of vijnaptimatra, that is, to be the locus where one abides after successfully learning what was presented in the teaching of vijnaptimatra. With that in perspective, in must be noted that, again, the establishment of selflessness per se occurs in vijnaptimatratva and not in vijnaptimatra.


The following appearances of the two terms in the Vimsatikav®tti occur as part of two objections posed to Vasubandhu by an opponent. I will comment on them conjunctly.


2.3. Objection in regard to the efficacy of mental phenomena as in dreams:


yadi vijnaptimatramevedam na kasyacitkayo 'sti na vak.


Vasubandhu 2004: 132.


If this is in fact vijnaptimatra, then neither someone's body nor their speech can possibly exist.Vijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhagcr. Translating 137


2.4. Objection in regard to the possibility of communication if all is perception-only:


yadi vijnaptimatramevedam paracittavidah kim paracittam janantyatha na kimcatah. (Vasubandhu 2004: 133)

If this is in fact vijnaptimatra then how do those who understand the mind of others actually understand the mind of others?


Both objections are directed to vijnaptimatra with the aim of disproving its capacity to be causally efficient. The concept is here understood by the opponent as a representation of reality that is totally detached from the empirical, external world that it represents, and not as an account of what ultimate reality is or could be. Apart from Vasubandhu’s reply to the two objections, the two fragments clearly employ the term “vijnaptimatra” in the sense of a mental process that constructs reality rather than as ultimate reality itself. As will be clear from the following fragment, the concept of ultimate reality will appear when the suffix “ta” is added to “vijnaptimatra.”


2.5. Vijnaptimdtratd not vijnaptimatra as being of unfathomable depth:


anantaviniscaya prabhedagadhagambhiryayam vijfiapti- mdtratdyam. vijhaptimatratasiddhih svasaktisadrsa mayd krteyam sarvathd sa tu na cintya. (Vasubandhu 2004: 133) After being settled in the unfathomable depth of vijnaptimdtratd much is to be gained.


Although this demonstration of vijnaptimdtratd was done to the best of my abilities, in its entirety it cannot be established by means of thought.

Here we find a clear demonstration a main point of our thesis, that is, that Vasubandhu employs the term “vijnaptimdtratd”— and not “vijnaptimatra”— to describe paramartha-sat. For what Vasubandhu asserts as being of “unfathomable depth,” that is, as being beyond language and subsisting in a realm free from thought construction, is precisely vijnaptimdtratd.

We should notice that, right at the end of his work, Vasubandhu employs the wordsiddhi” with a meaning nowdistinct from that of the previous passage where the “establishment” of vijnaptimdtratd was explained. At this point the English term “demonstration” seems in fact fit in rendering the Sanskritsiddhi,” for it denotes that, at the end, the soteriological gist of the work is that of explaining how vijnaptimdtratd can be established through the understanding of vijnaptimdtra.


From the previous examples of the usage of the two concepts, we can make the following inference: while, on the one hand, vijnaptimdtra can be understood as any mentally constructed representation that exists independently of whether or not it finds an equivalent in reality, on the other hand, vijnaptimdtratd is deep (gambh¥ra), and cannot be established by means of thought (vijnaptimdtratdsiddhih ... na cintyd k®teyam).


As the above proves a clear difference in Vasubandhu's usage of the two concepts, we are now in the position to further discuss their place within Vasubandhu's soteriology and propose an alternative translation.


3. The two concepts seen in relation to Vasubandhu's soteriological project


After having observed the distinct implications of the two concepts, it is important to keep in mind that what is at the stake in properly distinguishing “vijnaptimdtra” from “vijnaptimdtratd” is the correct understanding of the soteriological project that underlies the whole of Vasubandhu's philosophical endeavor. In order to clarify the relation between that project and the two concepts discussed, we must bring back to our inquiry the trisvabhdva theory, and observe how vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd fit into Vasubandhu's tripartite description of reality.

Recalling that while parikalpita-svabhdva appears as the category of the being of objects that exist solely as thought­constructs, and as such are merely conventional, and that parinispanna-svabhdva is the one where reality is perfected and free from this very thought construction, paratantra-svabhdva is defined as the middle category responsible for the existence of the previous two, first as mentally constructing parikalpita-svabhdva, and second as arriving at parinispanna-svabhdva after

aVijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating 139

transformation occurs in its own nature. The relation between this tripartite understanding of reality and the concepts of vijnapti, vijnaptimdtra, and vijnaptimdtratd becomes clear when we observe that the above-mentioned transformation is accomplished precisely by the paratantra-svabhdva's “self-cleansing” from nothing else than the dualistic epistemological flaws of understood as “representation.”

Since such self-cleansing amounts precisely to the passage from conventional to ultimate reality, vijnapti must then show a qualitative change as it moves from the first to the second reality. This obviously brings us back to the above discussion of the nuances, and possible double meaning, of the term vijnapti. For if vijnapti in fact possesses distinct rapports with parikalpita and parinispanna-svabhdva, then, given the above formulation, it must function differently in the terms “vijnaptimdtra” and “vijnaptimdtratd.”


At any rate, we are now in a position to clearly identify the place occupied by the two concepts in the trisvabhdva theory: while vijnaptimdtra (as we have seen in the first verse of the Vimsatikd) accounts precisely for what is constructed by the parikalpita-svabhdva, functioning thus as an appraisal of conventional reality, vijnaptimdtratd (as was seen, for instance, on verse 25 of the Trimsikd) accounts for paratantra-svabhdva's perfected nature, or to parinispanna-svabhdva, that is ultimate reality itself (notice that in verse 25 of the Trimsikd the term “paramdrtha” is employed by Vasubandhu precisely in the sense of “paramdrtha-sat”).


Given the above, the role of vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd in the soteriological framework of Vasubandhu's philosophy becomes obvious. For the path of salvation proposed by Vasubandhu appears now as precisely that where the passage from vijnaptimdtra to vijnaptimdtratd occurs. In other words, it is through the understanding of vijnapti as a tendency inherent in paratantra-svabhdva that we can properly perceive parikalpita- svabhdva as the realm of vijnaptimdtra and samv®ti-sat, while distinguishing it from parinispanna-svabhdva as the locus of vijnaptimdtratd and paramdrtha-sat.


It cannot be overemphasized that the gist of such conversion will become clear only if one is attentive to the fact that what prevents consciousness from continuing in a state of attachment to the twofold grasping produced by vijnapti as“representation” is not, as Kochumuttom presents in his translation of verse 26 of the Trimsika, the realization that the subject-object designations are “mere representations of consciousness” (vijnaptimatra), but, once again, the realization of consciousness itself as it arrives in a state free from representation. In order to further clarify such notion, we must now look at Vasubandhu’s Trimsika verse 27:


vijnaptimatramevedamityapi hynpalambhatah\ sthapayannagratah kincit tanmdtre navatisthate ||27||

Simply stating that something is ‘representation-only’ (vijnaptimatra), does not make you stand in the suchness of it.

Here Vasubandhu clearly asserts that the recognition of something as representation-only (vijnaptimatra) is insufficient for attaining realization of its suchness (tanmdtre). As the following verses, 28 and 29, make clear, such suchness is, in fact, arrived at only in vijnaptimatrata (or vijnaptimatratva j.

yadalambanam jftanam naivopalabhate tada\ sthitam vijnanamatratve grahyabhave tadagrahat ||28||

When consciousness does not recognize the object precisely as such [that is, as an object], then, standing in vijnaptimatrata, it is beyond grasping.


acitto ’nupalambho ’sau jftanam lokottaram ca tat\ asrayasya paravrttirdvidha dausthulyahanitah ||29|| Without mind and object, it is then in the state of supra- mundane knowledge,

where the revolution of the basis does away with the two impurities.

Vijnaptimatrata, then, is that which, being beyond grasping, pertains to ultimate reality.Vijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating 141


4. An alternative translation


Given the position vijnaptimatrata occupies in Vasubandhu's thought as a final realization towards which his project is directed, our task becomes, at this point, that of inquiring on the possibility of an alternative translation of the concept that would render it in a manner that more clearly expresses its soteriological implications. The first question to be posed in such inquiry, then, would be: how much differentiation from vijnaptimatra is appropriate to a rendering of vijnaptimatrata?


While the two concepts are morphologically similar in that both contain the notion of vijnapti, the above demonstration of the nuances the latter term acquires in relation to the cognitive capacities involved in the distinction between conventional and ultimate reality, that is, as “perception” as opposed to “representation,” may allow an English rendering that would not repeat a single meaning for “vijnapti” in both compounds “vijnaptimatra” and “vijnaptimatrata.”

In any case, all we can assert at this point is that if vijnapti is in fact accepted as assuming different meanings in each concept, then that only would justify their being translated with a higher degree of differentiation. But even if the double meaning of vijnapti is left aside, the question still remains of whether in translating texts such as Vasubandhu's it is valid to sacrifice morphological similarity in favor of clarity of philosophical content.


The point here is that, considering all that stands between classical Sanskrit and modern English, one might infer that for Vasubandhu and his audience the difference we are stressing was probably already sufficiently accounted for by the accretion of the abstract suffix “ta” to the wordvijnaptimatra.” For us modern readers of an ancient work in translation, however, things appear to be somewhat different.

If we apply Vasubandhu's procedure to the English language and simply add the suffixes “ness” or “hood” to terms such as “representation-only” or “psychosophical-closure,” our result, as we have seen, will fall short of providing a clear account of the subtleties implied in the Indian philosopher's usage of the two concepts in question.

The problem here falls under the difficulty we encounter when, as translators, we are met with the task of clarifying to the modern reader philosophical ideas that are presented in the context of ancient dialectics, where debate tended to be carried out in a mode where the opponent's prior knowledgeof the arguments in question was usually assumed by the contenders.

Such being the case, simply providing an accurate structural rendering of concepts as they are employed in the original language tends to be insufficient to the correct rendering of the ideas expounded.


At any rate, as far as this paper is concerned, my final aim now is still to propose an alternative translation for Vasubandhu’s concepts. My first step in this direction will be to look for an alternative that would not depart from the philosophical domain in which the ideas in question were developed. As the inquiry on cognition allows us to recognize the epistemological medium in which Vasubandhu’s ideas are developed, my search must be guided toward concepts that will effectively denote the perceptual subtleties involved in the difference between vijnaptimatra and vijnaptimatrata.

In other words, keeping in perspective that our basic material is an epistemology that asserts a qualitative difference between what is barely cognized and the constructions that, by imputation, are accrued to such cognition, I will work with the two concepts employed above in the demonstration of the different possible meanings assumed by vijnapti in its distinct epistemological implications, “perception” and “representation.”


We must recall that while “perception” may denote simply a first moment of bare cognition, that is, a basic encounter with reality that is severed from any assumptions made about it, “representation” carries in itself the mark of intentionality together with the accrual of elements that are foreign to the bare data first cognized. With that in mind, 1 will propose a translation for Vasubandhu’s Trimsika 28 that reads as follows:


When consciousness does not recognize the object precisely as such [that is, as an object],

then, standing in pureness-of-perception,

[vijnaptimatratve] it is beyond grasping.

By translating vijnaptimatrata as “pureness-of-perception,” I intend to reflect the essential purity of the bare cognition that is defined by Vasubandhu as being “beyond grasping.” While “vijnaptimatra” is formulated as “pure” or “mere representation,” rendering “vijnaptimatrata” with the wordperception” in the place of “representation” clearly distinguishes the two concepts. I believe that this procedure helps clarify the epistemological grounds on which Vasubandhu’s concepts function, while at theVijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating 143


same time expressing more clearly the doctrine of two truths that underlies them.

Accounting for the distinct epistemological spheres of operation of vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd, then, must be regarded as the first step towards correctly grasping Vasubandhu's soteriology. His soteriology is presented through a web of tightly interwoven concepts, where the two terms are a primary motor, leading the paratantra-svabhdva through dsrayapardv®tti into the level of a perfected reality free from dualism, where phenomena are encountered in their sheer immediacy, that is, that very region of phenomena that has achieved the lucidity of parinispanna- svabhdva.

And if this lucidity is precisely what is indicated with the notion of “pureness-of-perception,” the circularity becomes obvious: the passage from parikalpita to parinispanna-svabhdva must be the same as that from vijnaptimdtra to vijnaptimdtratd.


The relation between vijnaptimdtratd and dsraya-pardv®tti leads us to the further and more complex relation between vijnaptimdtratd and dlayavijndna. Although an in-depth inquiry into dlayavijndna goes beyond my aims here, the question of its rapport with vijnaptimdtratd must be approached if we are to effectively indicate all the implications of the difference we are stressing between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd.

Such rapport, it must be noted, can only be appraised through the use of an inferential procedure that will call forth several other concepts pertaining to the logical web expounded by Vasubandhu, and relate them mutually in a comparative manner.


Understanding dlayavijndna as a basic or substratum consciousness that subsists under states of unconsciousness, and as such accounts for the general continuity of mental life, we must keep in mind that in order to clearly observe its rapport with vijnaptimdtratd we must first be aware of its role as the very basis for the occurrence of dsraya-pardv®tti. For dsraya-pardv®tti must be understood as, in Yamada's terms, the “converting of the substratum” (Yamada 1997: 171), which, in fact, is dlayavijndna itself.

The logic then becomes very simple: if vijnaptimdtratd can be understood as the result of dsraya-pardv®tti, it must also be regarded as the “converting of the substratum” that is nothing but the converting of dlayavijndna itself.

This logic is obviously based on our understanding of vijnaptimdtratd as “pureness-of- perception,” for such “purity” will be in concord with theelimination of all the unwholesome seeds (b¥ja) of karma present in dlayavijnana upon its conversion through dsraya-pardvrtti, as well as with the cleansing of all the badness (dausthulya) of which the neutral substratum consciousness (dlayavijndna itself) is the receptacle.


The rapport demonstrated between vijnaptimdtratd and dlayavijndna, however, remits us to a more fundamental question that transcends merely portraying the interrelationship between concepts.

The question is: what would be left if the substratum consciousness that contains all the seeds of karma disappeared after its conversion through dsraya-pardv®tti? What is at stake here is the very sustainability of the entire soteriological project in which Vasubhandhu's philosophy is embedded. Schmithausen (1987: 205) formulates the problem in the following way:


We simply have to accept that the text [[[Viniscaya]] Samgrahani] declares that, as soon as the process of Transmuting the Basis is completed (i.e. at the moment of attaining Arhatship), dlayavijndna itself is abandoned, and not merely emptied of unwholesome Seeds, but preserved in some other form; i.e. we have to accept that dlayavijndna is, in the Nivrtti Portion, essentially bound up with, or even nothing but a hypostasis of, Badness (dausthulya). The problems that would seem to arise from such a position - e.g. how, after the extinction of dlayavijndna, physical life can continue at all (especially in nirodhasamdpatti), or what would then be or contain the Seed(s) of the pravrttivijndnas - were, so it appears, simply not envisaged by the author/compiler.


The problem with Schmithausen's position is that, in approaching the text of the Viniscaya Samgrahani, he pursues a form of inquiry from which inference and intertextual analysis are, for the most part, ruled out. Although Schmithausen is correct in asserting that the text does not explicate what would be made of physical life once dlayavijndna is done away with,

suggesting that the author/compiler would not have envisaged such a question appears to be the result of the adoption of a perspective that avoids regarding the text in relation to the body of ideas that spring from the same tradition to which it belongs. Undoubtedly, such a problem is closely related to the historical form of inquiry that appears in much current scholarship. That form of inquiry operates on the basis of preconceived notions such as, for instance, the ideaVijnaptimatravijnaptimatratavibhaga: Translating 145


that texts must necessarily have a history, that the analysis of the “history” of the text can grant some form of scientific knowledge over it, and that texts can, in any case, be categorized linearly into anything that would amount to a historical arrangement.

As such notions are taken for granted, the historical perspective limits the scope of the text to that of a product that must be regarded only in relation to its own companion artifacts, and in doing so shuns a bolder comparative approach that would provide a larger perspective on the questions themselves, as they are posited by the text.


The point here is that in dealing with philosophy, even the most blunt form of scholarship should be capable of perceiving connections among apparently unrelated texts, of pursuing an inferential form of analysis, and, most of all, approaching ideas in their own right, Schmithausen's lack of such drive leads him to overlook the fact that even though the answer to the question of what is made of physical life after the extinction of alayavijnana may not have been made explicit in the Viniscaya Samgraham, it does appear with a considerable degree of clarity in other texts of the Buddhist canon.

Since Buddhist texts function in a web of interrelated works that, for the most part, circle around the same basic ideas, and since such ideas were very likely already known by the audience to whom many of these texts were directed, it is very possible that the author/complier of the Viniscaya Samgrahan¥ did not find it necessary to explain how

physical life appears in a state free from alayavijnana, simply because such explanation was already to be found in other texts. Given the interrelatedness of Buddhist texts, our task should be to bring them together as much as possible with the goal of clarifying the ideas they present. That would be a first step toward the further and more meaningful purpose of reworking such ideas in a larger world perspective.


With that in mind, my point here is that precisely by understanding vijnaptimatrata as the result of asrayaparav®tti, and as such as the point where alayavijnana is done away with, we can conceive vijnaptimatrata as the epistemological state of being of parinispana-svabhava, or a perfected reality that is free from representation. Such reality, in

turn, becomes the one where perception is transformed, in Vasubandhu's words, into “supramundane wisdom.” The fifth chapter of the Samdhinirmocana Sutra provides us with an account of preciselythis sort of perception and, by implication, with an answer to what is left of physical life once dlayavijndna is extinguished. In asking the Buddha how are Bodhisattvas wise with respect to the secrets of mind, thought, and consciousness, the Bodhisattva Visalamati receives the following answer:


Visalamati, those Bodhisattvas [[[wise]] in all ways] do not perceive their own internal appropriators; they also do not perceive an appropriating consciousness, but they are in accord with reality. They also do not perceive a basis, nor do they perceive a basis-consciousness. They do not perceive accumulations, nor do they perceive mind. They do not perceive an eye, nor do they perceive form, nor to they perceive an eye-consciousness.

They do not perceive an ear, nor do they perceive a sound, nor do they perceive an ear­consciousness. They do not perceive a nose, nor do they perceive a smell, nor do they perceive a nose-consciousness. They do not perceive a tongue, nor do they perceive a taste, nor do they perceive a tongue consciousness. They do not perceive a body, nor do they perceive a tangible object, nor do they perceive a bodily consciousness.

Visalamati, these Bodhisattvas do not perceive their own particular thoughts, nor do they perceive phenomena, nor do they perceive a mental consciousness, but they are in accord with reality. These Bodhisattvas are said to be ‘wise with respect to the ultimate.' The Tathagata designates Bodhisattvas who are wise with respect to the ultimate as also being ‘wise with respect to the secrets of mind, thought, and consciousness.' (Powers 1995: 76).


The question of what comes after the extinction of dlayavijndna is obviously of the epistemological sort. For given the Mahayana Buddhist soteriological principle of salvation being a non-other-worldly affair, the question of life without dlayavijndna becomes that of the possibility of doing away with mind's evil doings while still staying alive. And by “doing away with mind's evil doings” nothing but a clear, pure perception of the sort described above, is understood. The Samdhinirmocana Sutra thus provides us with an answer to what seemed to have been left out from the Viniscaya Samgrahan¥.


But what interests us here most of all is to observe that the sort of perception described in the sutra, that is, one where no objects are apprehended but accord with reality is still verified, can be regarded precisely as the one proposed by Vasubandhu as taking

place in vijnaptimatrata. Such objectless perception I called a “pure perception,” and the state of mind abiding in such pure perception, one of “pureness-of-perception.”


Yet again attesting to the interconnectedness of Buddhist philosophical concepts, such an understanding of vijnaptimatrata will allow us to perceive its rapport with what Asanga, in the Bodhisattvabhumi, called "nirvikalpa-jhana." that is, knowledge free of conceptualization. As “pureness-of-perception,” vijnaptimatrata also acquires connotations that bring it close to other Buddhist concepts, such as, for instance, Paramartha's amalavijnana.

As Jonathan Gold has noted, what Vasubandhu's texts share “is a unifying vision that fits a Yogacara conceptual structure, but is not exclusively associated with any individual doxographic category.”

I would add that from a more overtly comparative perspective the correct understanding of Vasubandhu's notion can lead us into an inquiry on its relation with more recent concepts found in Western thought, especially in the field of philosophy of mind. Here a comparative approach worked between vijnaptimatrata as a state of mind abiding in “pure perception,” and the notion of “pure-experience” as developed by Nishida and William James, might shed new light on the comparative study of Yogacara philosophy and Western thought.

In this regard, the correct understanding of vijnaptimatrata might work also towards demystifying much of recent East Asian thought's excessive emphasis on its own originality. In a broader sense, taking a correct grasp of Vasubandhu's philosophy as a starting point, Buddhist philosophy's existential ontological focus can be brought in perspective with

Western forms of thought that propound a similar ontology, and, in this manner, work towards effacing the boundaries between ideas that have for too long been undervalued or kept apart, much at the fault, it must be said, of the scholarly approach that asserts that ideas must be kept locked within their “historical context.”

Finally, the correct apprehension of the notions propounded by a philosopher such as Vasubandhu can lead us to discover that not much is ever new in human thought, and that maybe paying closer attention to the Indian Buddhists might be a useful step towards understanding a reality that, ultimately, is a-historical.


CODA: Vijnaptimdtravijnaptimdtratdvibhdga


The title of this essay alludes to that of the Dharmadharmatdvibhdga, one of the five books of Maitreya. The book has been translated into English with the title Distinguishing Dharma and Dharmatd, and published with a commentary by Tibetan scholar Thrangu Rinpoche. His commentary begins as follows:

This text is an exposition of the Dharma-dharmata-vibhaga in Sanskrit or Distinguishing Dharma and Dharmata in English. The word dharma means “phenomena” and dharmata means “pure phenomena.” (Levinsion, 2001: 1)


My reason for alluding to Maitreya's title is that the relationship between “vijnaptimdtra” and “vijnaptimdtratd” in Vasubandhu's work appears to be analogous to the one existing between “dharma” and “dharmatd” in Maitreya's.

With that in mind, some of us may want to reconsider our perchance too technical approach to Buddhist philosophy, and follow the simplicity and clarity of presentation demonstrated by Thrangu Rinpoche, whose understanding of the difference between Maitreya's concepts can help us get a better grasp of Vasubandhu's.

The same sort of parallel drawn between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd, and dharma and dharmatd, can be made between the notions of sunya and sunyatd as they are expounded in Madhyamaka philosophy. While the term sunya promptly assumes an adjectival function in qualifying reality as svabhdva-sunya, that is, as empty of self-nature, sunyatd appears as a noun, commonly translated as emptiness, nothingness, or openness.


When we keep such parallels in mind, Vasubandhu's concepts are freed from being misconceived as undifferentiated. Since their differentiation is, as we have seen, fundamental to the correct grasp of the philosopher's core ideas, this essay strove to demonstrate how English scholarship, by overlooking such distinction at the level of translation, created difficulties in correctly grasping Vasubandhu's philosophy. Admittedly, the difference between vijnaptimdtra and vijnaptimdtratd may have already seemed obvious to some. My hope, then, is that this essay will work towards making it even more obvious.


Bibliography

Anacker, Stefan. 1984. Seven Works of Vasubandhu: The Buddhist Psychological Doctor. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.

Dilworth, David. 1969. “The Initial Formulations of ‘Pure Experience' in Nishida Kitaro and William James.” Monumenta Nipponica 24: 93-111

Gold, Jonathan. 2014. Paving the Great Way: Vasubandhu's Unifying Buddhist Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.

Hall, Bruce Cameron. 1986. “The Meaning of Vijnapti in Vasubandhu's Concept of Mind.” Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 9: 7-23.

Keenan, John P. 1989. “Introduction,” in The Realm of Awakening: A Translation and Study of the Tenth Chapter of Asanga's Mahdydnasangraha. New York: Oxford University Press
Kochumuttom, Thomas. 1982. A Buddhist Doctrine of Experience: A New Translation and Interpretation of the Works of Vasubandhu the Yogdcdrin. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Levinsion, Jules (trans.). 2001. Distinguishing Dharma and Dharmata by Asanga and Maitreya. New Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications.
Lusthaus, Dan. 2002. Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei- shih Lun. Curzon Critical Studies in Buddhism Series. London: Routledge.
Powers, John. 1995. Wisdom of the Buddha: The Samdhinirmocana Sutra. Dharma Publishing.
Schmithausen, Lambert. 1987. Alayavijndna: On the Origin and the Early Development of a Central Concept of Yogdcdra Philosophy. Tokyo: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies.
Shaw, Miranda. 1987. “William James and Yogacara philosophy: A comparative inquiry,” Philosophy East and West 37: 223-244.
Takeuchi, Shoko. 1977. “Phenomena and Reality in Vijnaptimatra Thought (I): On the usages of the suffix ‘ta' in Maitreya's Treatises.” In Buddhist Thought and Asian Civilization, ed. Leslie Kawamura and Keith Scott Emeryville, CA: Dharma Publishing, p. 254-67.
Vasubandhu. 2004. “The Vimsatika Vijnaptimatratasiddhi of Vasubandhu,” in Fernando Tola and Carmen Dragonetti (Eds.) Being as Consciousness, Yogacara Philosophy of Buddhism. New Delhi: Motilal Barnasidass Publishers of India.
Willis, Janice Dean. 1979. On Knowing Reality: The Tattvdrtha Chapter of Asanga's Boddhisattvabhumi. New York: Columbia University Press.
Yamada, Isshi. 1977. “Vijnaptimdtra of Vasubandhu.” Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society. Volume 109, Issue 02, p. 158­176.




Source