Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "BUDDHIST ILLOGIC"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " By Avi Sion PH.D. Buddhist Illogic can be freely read online at TheLogician.net and in various other locations. It can be purchased, in print and e-book editions, i...")
 
 
(2 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 5: Line 5:
  
  
By Avi Sion PH.D.
+
By [[Avi Sion]] PH.D.
  
  
  
  
Buddhist Illogic can be freely read online at TheLogician.net and in various other locations.
+
[[Buddhist]] [[Illogic]] can be freely read online at TheLogician.net and in various other locations.
  
 
It can be purchased, in print and e-book editions, in Amazon.com, Lulu.com and many other online booksellers.
 
It can be purchased, in print and e-book editions, in Amazon.com, Lulu.com and many other online booksellers.
  
The present document contains excerpts from this book, namely: The Abstract; the Contents; and Sample text (Chapters 1 and 2).
+
The {{Wiki|present}} document contains excerpts from this [[book]], namely: The Abstract; the Contents; and Sample text (Chapters 1 and 2).
  
Avi Sion (Ph.D. Philosophy) is a researcher and writer in logic, philosophy, and spirituality. He has, since 1990, published original writings on the theory and practice of inductive and deductive logic, phenomenology, epistemology, aetiology, psychology, meditation, ethics, and much more. Over a period of some 28 years, he has published 27 books. He resides in Geneva, Switzerland.
+
[[Avi Sion]] ([[Ph.D.]] [[Philosophy]]) is a researcher and writer in [[logic]], [[philosophy]], and [[spirituality]]. He has, since 1990, published original writings on the {{Wiki|theory}} and practice of inductive and {{Wiki|deductive}} [[logic]], [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], epistemology, aetiology, {{Wiki|psychology}}, [[meditation]], [[ethics]], and much more. Over a period of some 28 years, he has published 27 [[books]]. He resides in [[Geneva]], [[Switzerland]].
  
It is very difficult to briefly summarize Avi Sion's philosophy, because it is so wide-ranging. He has labeled it ‘Logical Philosophy', because it is firmly grounded in formal logic, inductive as well as deductive. This original philosophy is dedicated to demonstrating the efficacy of human reason by detailing its actual means; and to show that the epistemological and ethical skepticism which has been increasingly fashionable and destructive since the Enlightenment was (contrary to appearances) quite illogical - the product of ignorant, incompetent and dishonest thinking.  
+
It is very difficult to briefly summarize Avi Sion's [[philosophy]], because it is so wide-ranging. He has labeled it ‘[[Logical]] [[Philosophy]]', because it is firmly grounded in [[formal logic]], inductive as well as {{Wiki|deductive}}. This original [[philosophy]] is dedicated to demonstrating the efficacy of [[human]] [[reason]] by detailing its actual means; and to show that the [[epistemological]] and [[ethical]] {{Wiki|skepticism}} which has been increasingly fashionable and {{Wiki|destructive}} since the [[Enlightenment]] was (contrary to [[appearances]]) quite [[illogical]] - the product of [[ignorant]], incompetent and dishonest [[thinking]].  
  
  
Line 24: Line 24:
  
  
Buddhist Illogic. The 2nd Century CE Indian philosopher Nagarjuna founded the Madhyamika (Middle Way) school of Mahayana Buddhism, which strongly influenced Chinese (Ch'an), Korean (Sôn) and Japanese (Zen) Buddhism, as well as Tibetan Buddhism. Nagarjuna is regarded by many Buddhist writers to this day as a very important philosopher, who they claim definitively proved the futility of ordinary human cognitive means.
+
[[Buddhist]] [[Illogic]]. The 2nd Century CE [[Indian philosopher]] [[Nagarjuna]] founded the [[Madhyamika]] ([[Middle Way]]) school of [[Mahayana Buddhism]], which strongly influenced {{Wiki|Chinese}} ([[Ch'an]]), [[Korean]] (Sôn) and [[Japanese]] ([[Zen]]) [[Buddhism]], as well as [[Tibetan Buddhism]]. [[Nagarjuna]] is regarded by many [[Buddhist]] writers to this day as a very important [[philosopher]], who they claim definitively proved the futility of ordinary [[human]] [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] means.
His writings include a series of arguments purporting to show the illogic of logic, the absurdity of reason. He considers this the way to verbalize and justify the Buddhist doctrine of “emptiness” (Shunyata). These arguments attack some of the basic tenets and techniques of reasoning, such as the laws of thought (identity, non-contradiction and the excluded middle), conceptualization and predication, our common assumptions of self, entities and essences, as well as our beliefs in motion and causation.
+
His writings include a series of arguments purporting to show the [[illogic]] of [[logic]], the absurdity of [[reason]]. He considers this the way to verbalize and justify the [[Buddhist doctrine]] of “[[emptiness]]” ([[Shunyata]]). These arguments attack some of the basic [[tenets]] and [[techniques]] of {{Wiki|reasoning}}, such as the laws of [[thought]] ([[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]], non-contradiction and the excluded middle), [[conceptualization]] and predication, our common {{Wiki|assumptions}} of [[self]], entities and [[essences]], as well as our [[beliefs]] in {{Wiki|motion}} and [[causation]].
  
The present essay demonstrates the many sophistries involved in Nagarjuna's arguments. He uses double standards, applying or ignoring the laws of thought and other norms as convenient to his goals; he manipulates his readers, by giving seemingly logical form (like the dilemma) to his discourse, while in fact engaged in non-sequiturs or appealing to doubtful premises; he plays with words, relying on unclear terminology, misleading equivocations and unfair fixations of meaning; and he ‘steals concepts', using them to deny the very percepts on which they are based.
+
The {{Wiki|present}} essay demonstrates the many sophistries involved in [[Nagarjuna's]] arguments. He uses double standards, applying or ignoring the laws of [[thought]] and other norms as convenient to his goals; he manipulates his readers, by giving seemingly [[logical]] [[form]] (like the {{Wiki|dilemma}}) to his [[discourse]], while in fact engaged in non-sequiturs or appealing to [[doubtful]] premises; he plays with words, relying on unclear {{Wiki|terminology}}, misleading equivocations and unfair fixations of meaning; and he ‘steals [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]', using them to deny the very [[percepts]] on which they are based.
  
Although a critique of the Madhyamika philosophical interpretation and defense of “emptiness”, Buddhist Illogic is not intended to dissuade readers from Buddhism. On the contrary, its aim to enhance personal awareness of actual cognitive processes, and so improve meditation. It is also an excellent primer on phenomenological epistemology.  
+
Although a critique of the [[Madhyamika]] [[philosophical]] [[interpretation]] and defense of “[[emptiness]]”, [[Buddhist]] [[Illogic]] is not intended to dissuade readers from [[Buddhism]]. On the contrary, its aim to enhance personal [[awareness]] of actual [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] {{Wiki|processes}}, and so improve [[meditation]]. It is also an {{Wiki|excellent}} primer on {{Wiki|phenomenological}} epistemology.  
  
  
1. THE TETRALEMMA.
+
===1. [[THE TETRALEMMA]].===
  
  
Western philosophical and scientific thought is based on Aristotelian logic, whose founding principles are the three “Laws of Thought”. These can be briefly stated as “A is A” (Identity), “Nothing is both A and non-A” (Non-contradiction) and “Nothing is neither A nor non-A” (Exclusion of the Middle). These are not claimed as mere hypotheses, note well, but as incontrovertible premises of all rational human thought .
+
[[Western]] [[philosophical]] and [[scientific]] [[thought]] is based on [[Aristotelian logic]], whose founding {{Wiki|principles}} are the three “Laws of [[Thought]]”. These can be briefly stated as “A is A” ({{Wiki|Identity}}), “Nothing is both A and non-A” (Non-contradiction) and “Nothing is neither A nor non-A” (Exclusion of the Middle). These are not claimed as mere {{Wiki|hypotheses}}, note well, but as incontrovertible premises of all [[rational]] [[human]] [[thought]] .
Religions like Judaism, Christianity and Islam, even while adhering to these laws in much of their discourse and paying lip-service to them, in their bids to interpret their own sacred texts and to make their doctrines seem reasonable to their converts, have often ignored these same laws. This is especially true of mystical trends within these religions, but many examples could be given from mainstream writings. The same can be said of some aspects of Buddhist philosophy.
+
[[Religions]] like {{Wiki|Judaism}}, [[Christianity]] and {{Wiki|Islam}}, even while adhering to these laws in much of their [[discourse]] and paying lip-service to them, in their bids to interpret their [[own]] [[sacred]] texts and to make their [[doctrines]] seem reasonable to their converts, have often ignored these same laws. This is especially true of [[mystical]] trends within these [[religions]], but many examples could be given from {{Wiki|mainstream}} writings. The same can be said of some aspects of [[Buddhist philosophy]].
  
The tetralemma  is a derivative of the laws of thought, with reference to any two terms or propositions, labeled A and B, and their opposites non-A and non-B. Four combinations of these four terms are conceivable, namely “A and B” (both), “non-A and non-B” (neither), “A and non¬B” and “non-A and B” (one or the other only). According to Aristotelian logic, these four statements are incompatible with each other (only one of them can be true, because if two or more were affirmed then “A and non-A” or “B and non-B” or both would be true, and the latter implications are self-contradictory) and exhaustive (at least one of them must be true, since if they were all denied then “not A and not non-A” or “not B and not non-B” or both would be true, and the latter implications go against the excluded middle).
+
The [[tetralemma]] is a derivative of the laws of [[thought]], with reference to any two terms or propositions, labeled A and B, and their opposites non-A and non-B. Four combinations of these four terms are conceivable, namely “A and B” (both), “non-A and non-B” (neither), “A and non¬B” and “non-A and B” (one or the other only). According to [[Aristotelian logic]], these four statements are incompatible with each other (only one of them can be true, because if two or more were [[affirmed]] then “A and non-A” or “B and non-B” or both would be true, and the [[latter]] implications are self-contradictory) and exhaustive (at least one of them must be true, since if they were all denied then “not A and not non-A” or “not B and not non-B” or both would be true, and the [[latter]] implications go against the excluded middle).
  
  
Now, what Nagarjuna does is insert the term A in place of B (i.e. he takes the case of B = A), and effectively claim that the above four logical possibilities of combination apply in that special case - so that “A and A (=B)”, “non-A and non-A (=non-B)”, “A and non-A (=non-B)”, “non-A and A (=B)” seem logically acceptable. He then goes on to argue that there are four existential possibilities: affirmation of A (A + A = A), denial of A (non-A + non-A = non-A), both affirmation and denial of A (A and non-A) and neither affirmation nor denial of A (not A and not non-A). He is thus apparently using the principles and terminology of common logic to arrive at a very opposite result. This gives him and readers the impression that it is quite reasonable to both affirm and deny or to neither affirm nor deny.
+
Now, what [[Nagarjuna]] does is insert the term A in place of B (i.e. he takes the case of B = A), and effectively claim that the above four [[logical]] possibilities of combination apply in that special case - so that “A and A (=B)”, “non-A and non-A (=non-B)”, “A and non-A (=non-B)”, “non-A and A (=B)” seem [[logically]] acceptable. He then goes on to argue that there are four [[existential]] possibilities: [[affirmation]] of A (A + A = A), {{Wiki|denial}} of A (non-A + non-A = non-A), both [[affirmation]] and {{Wiki|denial}} of A (A and non-A) and neither [[affirmation]] nor {{Wiki|denial}} of A (not A and not non-A). He is thus apparently using the {{Wiki|principles}} and {{Wiki|terminology}} of common [[logic]] to arrive at a very opposite result. This gives him and readers the [[impression]] that it is quite reasonable to both affirm and deny or to neither affirm nor deny.
  
But in Aristotelian logic, the latter two alternatives are at the outset excluded - “both A and non¬A” by the Law of Non-contradiction and “neither A nor non-A” by the Law of the Excluded-Middle - and the only logical possibilities left are “A” or “non-A”. The anti-Aristotelian position may be viewed, in a positive light, as an anti-Nominalist position, reminding us that things are never quite what they seem or that things cannot be precisely classified or labeled. But ultimately, they intend the death of Logic; for without the laws of thought, how are we to distinguish between true and false judgments?
+
But in [[Aristotelian logic]], the [[latter]] two alternatives are at the outset excluded - “both A and non¬A” by the Law of Non-contradiction and “neither A nor non-A” by the Law of the Excluded-Middle - and the only [[logical]] possibilities left are “A” or “non-A”. The anti-Aristotelian position may be viewed, in a positive {{Wiki|light}}, as an anti-Nominalist position, reminding us that things are never quite what they seem or that things cannot be precisely classified or labeled. But ultimately, they intend the [[death]] of [[Logic]]; for without the laws of [[thought]], how are we to distinguish between true and false judgments?
The law of identity “A is A” is a conviction that things have some identity (whatever it specifically be) rather than another, or than no identity at all.  
+
The law of [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] “A is A” is a conviction that things have some [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] (whatever it specifically be) rather than another, or than no [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] at all.  
  
It is an affirmation that knowledge is ultimately possible, and a rejection of sheer relativism or obscurantism. Nagarjuna's goal is to deny identity.
+
It is an [[affirmation]] that [[knowledge]] is ultimately possible, and a rejection of sheer {{Wiki|relativism}} or obscurantism. [[Nagarjuna's]] goal is to deny [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]].
It should be noted here that Aristotle is very precise in his formulation of the law of contradiction, stating in his Metaphysics “The same attribute cannot at the same time belong and not belong to the same subject in the same respect” (italics mine). Thus, an alternative statement of the laws of thought would be the ‘trilemma' (let us so call it) “either wholly A, or wholly non-A, or both partly A and partly non-A”, which excludes the fourth  
+
It should be noted here that {{Wiki|Aristotle}} is very precise in his formulation of the law of {{Wiki|contradiction}}, stating in his [[Metaphysics]] “The same attribute cannot at the same time belong and not belong to the same [[subject]] in the same [[respect]]” (italics mine). Thus, an alternative statement of the laws of [[thought]] would be the ‘trilemma' (let us so call it) “either wholly A, or wholly non-A, or both partly A and partly non-A”, which excludes [[the fourth]]
  
alternative “both wholly A and wholly non-A”. The Buddhist attack on the laws of thought draws some of its credibility from the fact that people subconsciously refer to this ‘trilemma', thinking superficially that indeed opposite things may occur in the same place at different times or at the same time in different places or in various respects, without thereby giving rise to logical difficulty incapable of resolution. But it should be clear that the Buddhist position is much more radical than that, accepting thoroughgoing antinomy.
+
alternative “both wholly A and wholly non-A”. The [[Buddhist]] attack on the laws of [[thought]] draws some of its credibility from the fact that [[people]] subconsciously refer to this ‘trilemma', [[thinking]] superficially that indeed opposite things may occur in the same place at different times or at the same time in different places or in various respects, without thereby giving rise to [[logical]] difficulty incapable of resolution. But it should be clear that the [[Buddhist]] position is much more radical than that, accepting thoroughgoing antinomy.
  
  
Similarly with regard to the law of the excluded middle, which affirms the situation “neither A nor non-A” to be impossible in fact. People are misled by the possibility of uncertainty in knowledge, as to whether A or non-A is the case in fact, into believing that this law of thought is open to debate. But it must be understood that the thrust of this logical rule is inductive, rather than deductive; i.e. it is a statement that at the end of the knowledge acquisition process, either “A” or “non-A” will result, and no third alternative can be expected. It does not exclude that in the interim, a situation of  
+
Similarly with regard to the law of the excluded middle, which affirms the situation “neither A nor non-A” to be impossible in fact. [[People]] are misled by the possibility of uncertainty in [[knowledge]], as to whether A or non-A is the case in fact, into believing that this law of [[thought]] is open to [[debate]]. But it must be understood that the thrust of this [[logical]] {{Wiki|rule}} is inductive, rather than {{Wiki|deductive}}; i.e. it is a statement that at the end of the [[knowledge]] acquisition process, either “A” or “non-A” will result, and no third alternative can be expected. It does not exclude that in the interim, a situation of  
  
uncertainty may occur. Nagarjuna's position exploits this confusion in people's minds.
+
uncertainty may occur. [[Nagarjuna's]] position exploits this [[confusion]] in people's [[minds]].
Nagarjuna interprets the limitation implied by the dilemma “A or non-A” as an arbitrary ‘dualism' on the part of ordinary thinkers . It only goes to show that he misunderstands formalization (or he pretends to, in an attempt to confuse gullible readers). When logicians use a variable like “B” and allow that “non-A and B” and “A and non-B” are both in principle possible, they do not intend that as a generality applicable to all values of B (such as “A”), but only as a generic statement applicable to any consistent values of B. In the specific case where B = A, the said two combinations have to be eliminated because they are illegal (i.e. breach two of the laws of thought).
+
[[Nagarjuna]] interprets the limitation implied by the {{Wiki|dilemma}} “A or non-A” as an arbitrary ‘[[dualism]]' on the part of ordinary thinkers . It only goes to show that he misunderstands formalization (or he pretends to, in an attempt to confuse gullible readers). When [[logicians]] use a variable like “B” and allow that “non-A and B” and “A and non-B” are both in [[principle]] possible, they do not intend that as a [[generality]] applicable to all values of B (such as “A”), but only as a generic statement applicable to any consistent values of B. In the specific case where B = A, the said two combinations have to be eliminated because they are illegal (i.e. breach two of the laws of [[thought]]).
  
  
The above-stated property of symbols, i.e. their applicability only conditionally within the constraints of consistency, is evident throughout the science of formal logic, and it is here totally ignored by Nagarjuna. His motive of course was to verbalize and rationalize the Buddha's doctrine that the ultimate truth is beyond nama and rupa, name and form (i.e. discrimination and discourse), knowable only by a transcendental consciousness (the Twofold Truth doctrine). More precisely, as Cheng emphasizes, Nagarjuna's intent was to show that logic is inherently inconsistent and thus that reason is confused madness to be rejected. That is, he was (here and throughout) not ultimately trying to defend a tetralemma with B equal to A - or even to affirm that things are both A and non¬A, or neither A nor non-A - but wished to get us to look altogether beyond the distinctions of conceptualization and the judgments of logic.
+
The above-stated property of [[symbols]], i.e. their applicability only conditionally within the constraints of consistency, is evident throughout the [[science]] of [[formal logic]], and it is here totally ignored by [[Nagarjuna]]. His {{Wiki|motive}} of course was to verbalize and rationalize the [[Buddha's]] [[doctrine]] that [[the ultimate truth]] is beyond [[nama]] and [[rupa]], [[name and form]] (i.e. {{Wiki|discrimination}} and [[discourse]]), knowable only by a [[transcendental]] [[consciousness]] (the [[Twofold Truth]] [[doctrine]]). More precisely, as [[Cheng]] emphasizes, [[Nagarjuna's]] intent was to show that [[logic]] is inherently inconsistent and thus that [[reason]] is confused madness to be rejected. That is, he was (here and throughout) not ultimately trying to defend a [[tetralemma]] with B {{Wiki|equal}} to A - or even to affirm that things are both A and non¬A, or neither A nor non-A - but wished to get us to look altogether beyond the {{Wiki|distinctions}} of [[conceptualization]] and the judgments of [[logic]].
  
  
But as above shown he does not succeed in this quest. For his critique depends on a misrepresentation of logical science. He claims to show that logic is confused and self-contradictory, but in truth what he presents as the thesis of logical science is not what it claims for itself but precisely what it explicitly forbids. Furthermore, suppose logical theory did lead to contradictions as he claims, this fact would not lead us to its rejection were there not also a tacit appeal to our preference for the logical in practice. If logic were false, contradictions would be acceptable. Thus, funnily enough, Nagarjuna appeals to our logical habit in his very recommendation to us to ignore logic. In sum, though he gives the illusion that it is reasonable to abandon reason, it is easy to see that his conclusion is foregone and his means are faulty.
+
But as above shown he does not succeed in this quest. For his critique depends on a misrepresentation of [[logical]] [[science]]. He claims to show that [[logic]] is confused and self-contradictory, but in [[truth]] what he presents as the {{Wiki|thesis}} of [[logical]] [[science]] is not what it claims for itself but precisely what it explicitly forbids. Furthermore, suppose [[logical]] {{Wiki|theory}} did lead to contradictions as he claims, this fact would not lead us to its rejection were there not also a tacit appeal to our preference for the [[logical]] in practice. If [[logic]] were false, contradictions would be acceptable. Thus, funnily enough, [[Nagarjuna]] appeals to our [[logical]] [[Wikipedia:Habit (psychology)|habit]] in his very recommendation to us to ignore [[logic]]. In sum, though he gives the [[illusion]] that it is reasonable to abandon [[reason]], it is easy to see that his conclusion is foregone and his means are faulty.
  
  
2. NEITHER REAL NOR UNREAL.
+
===2. [[NEITHER REAL NOR UNREAL]]===
  
  
But Nagarjuna also conceives ultimate reality (“emptiness” ) as a “middle way”   - so that the world of experience is neither to be regarded as real, nor to be regarded as unreal (“there is nothing, neither mental nor non-mental, which is real” and it “cannot be conceived as unreal,” reports Cheng). In this context, Nagarjuna is clearly relying on one of the above-mentioned logically impossible disjuncts, namely “neither A nor non-A” (be it said in passing). I want to now show why Nagarjuna's statement seems superficially reasonable and true.
+
But [[Nagarjuna]] also conceives [[ultimate reality]] (“[[emptiness]]” ) as a “[[middle way]]”   - so that the [[world]] of [[experience]] is neither to be regarded as real, nor to be regarded as unreal (“there is nothing, neither [[mental]] nor [[non-mental]], which is real” and it “cannot be [[conceived]] as unreal,” reports [[Cheng]]). In this context, [[Nagarjuna]] is clearly relying on one of the above-mentioned [[logically]] impossible disjuncts, namely “neither A nor non-A” (be it said in passing). I want to now show why [[Nagarjuna's]] statement seems superficially reasonable and true.
  
  
As I have often clarified and explained , knowledge has to be regarded or approached phenomenologically (that is the only consistent epistemological thesis). We have to start by acknowledging and observing appearances, as such, without initial judgment as to their reality or illusion. At first sight all appearances seem real enough. But after a while, we have to recognize that some appearances conflict with other appearances, and judge such appearances (i.e. one or more of those in conflict) as illusory. Since there is nothing in our ‘world' but appearances, all remaining appearances not judged as illusions (i.e. so long as they are not logically invalidated by conflicts with other appearances) maintain their initial status as realities.
+
As I have often clarified and explained , [[knowledge]] has to be regarded or approached [[phenomenologically]] (that is the only consistent [[epistemological]] {{Wiki|thesis}}). We have to start by [[acknowledging]] and observing [[appearances]], as such, without initial [[judgment]] as to their [[reality]] or [[illusion]]. At first [[sight]] all [[appearances]] seem real enough. But after a while, we have to [[recognize]] that some [[appearances]] conflict with other [[appearances]], and [[judge]] such [[appearances]] (i.e. one or more of those in conflict) as [[illusory]]. Since there is nothing in our ‘[[world]]' but [[appearances]], all remaining [[appearances]] not judged as [[illusions]] (i.e. so long as they are not [[logically]] invalidated by conflicts with other [[appearances]]) maintain their initial {{Wiki|status}} as [[realities]].
  
  
That is, the distinction between appearances as realities or illusions emerges within the world of appearances itself, merely classifying some this way and the rest that way. We have no concept of reality or illusion other than with reference to appearance. To use the category of reality with reference to something beyond appearance is concept stealing, a misuse of the concept, an extrapolation which ignores the concept's actual genesis in the context of appearance. To apply the concept of illusion to all appearances, on the basis that some appearances are illusions, is an unjustified generalization ignoring how this concept arises with reference to a specific event (namely, inconsistency between certain appearances and resulting diminishment of their innate credibilities). Moreover, to claim that no appearances are real or that all are illusions is self-defeating, since such claim itself logically falls under the category of appearance.
+
That is, the {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[appearances]] as [[realities]] or [[illusions]] emerges within the [[world]] of [[appearances]] itself, merely classifying some this way and the rest that way. We have no {{Wiki|concept}} of [[reality]] or [[illusion]] other than with reference to [[appearance]]. To use the category of [[reality]] with reference to something beyond [[appearance]] is {{Wiki|concept}} [[stealing]], a {{Wiki|misuse}} of the {{Wiki|concept}}, an extrapolation which ignores the concept's actual genesis in the context of [[appearance]]. To apply the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[illusion]] to all [[appearances]], on the basis that some [[appearances]] are [[illusions]], is an unjustified generalization ignoring how this {{Wiki|concept}} arises with reference to a specific event (namely, inconsistency between certain [[appearances]] and resulting diminishment of their innate credibilities). Moreover, to claim that no [[appearances]] are real or that all are [[illusions]] is self-defeating, since such claim itself [[logically]] falls under the category of [[appearance]].
  
  
The illusory exists even though it is not reality - it exists as appearance. The real is also apparent - some of it, at least. Therefore, appearance per se is neither to be understood as reality (since some appearances are illusory), nor can it be equated to illusion (since not all appearances have been or can be found illusory). Appearance is thus the common ground of realities and illusions, their common characteristic, the dialectical synthesis of those theses and antitheses. It is a genus, they are mutually exclusive species of it. (The difference between appearance and existence is another issue, I have dealt with elsewhere - briefly put, existence is a genus of appearance and non-appearance, the latter concepts being relative to that of consciousness whereas the former is assumed independent.)
+
The [[illusory]] [[exists]] even though it is not [[reality]] - it [[exists]] as [[appearance]]. The real is also apparent - some of it, at least. Therefore, [[appearance]] [[per se]] is neither to be understood as [[reality]] (since some [[appearances]] are [[illusory]]), nor can it be equated to [[illusion]] (since not all [[appearances]] have been or can be found [[illusory]]). [[Appearance]] is thus the common ground of [[realities]] and [[illusions]], their common [[characteristic]], the [[dialectical]] {{Wiki|synthesis}} of those theses and antitheses. It is a genus, they are mutually exclusive {{Wiki|species}} of it. (The difference between [[appearance and existence]] is another issue, I have dealt with elsewhere - briefly put, [[existence]] is a genus of [[appearance]] and non-appearance, the [[latter]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] being [[relative]] to that of [[consciousness]] whereas the former is assumed {{Wiki|independent}}.)
  
  
None of these insights allows the conclusion that appearances are “neither real nor unreal” (granting that ‘unreal' is understood to mean ‘non-real'). All we can say is that some appearances are real and some unreal. Formally, the correct logical relation between the three concepts is as follows. Deductively, appearance is implied by reality and illusion, but does not imply them; for reality and illusion are contradictory, so that they cannot both be true and they cannot both be false. Moreover, inductively, appearance implies reality, until and unless it is judged to be illusion (by virtue of some inconsistency being discovered).
+
None of these [[insights]] allows the conclusion that [[appearances]] are “neither real nor unreal” (granting that ‘unreal' is understood to mean ‘non-real'). All we can say is that some [[appearances]] are real and some unreal. Formally, the correct [[logical]] [[relation]] between the three [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] is as follows. Deductively, [[appearance]] is implied by [[reality]] and [[illusion]], but does not imply them; for [[reality]] and [[illusion]] are [[contradictory]], so that they cannot both be true and they cannot both be false. Moreover, inductively, [[appearance]] implies [[reality]], until and unless it is judged to be [[illusion]] (by [[virtue]] of some inconsistency being discovered).
  
  
More precisely, all appearances are initially classed as real. Any appearance found self¬contradictory is (deductively) illusory, and its contradictory is consequently self-evident and (deductively) real. All remaining appearances remain classed as real, so long as uncontested. Those that are contested have to be evaluated dynamically. When one appearance is belied by another, they are both put in doubt by the conflict between them, and so both become initially problematic. Thereafter, their relative credibilities have to be tentatively weighed in the overall context of available empirical and rational  
+
More precisely, all [[appearances]] are initially classed as real. Any [[appearance]] found self¬contradictory is (deductively) [[illusory]], and its [[contradictory]] is consequently [[self-evident]] and (deductively) real. All remaining [[appearances]] remain classed as real, so long as uncontested. Those that are contested have to be evaluated dynamically. When [[one appearance]] is belied by another, they are both put in [[doubt]] by the conflict between them, and so both become initially problematic. Thereafter, their [[relative]] credibilities have to be tentatively weighed in the overall context of available [[empirical]] and [[rational knowledge]] - and repeatedly reassessed thereafter, as that context develops and evolves. On this basis, one of these [[appearances]] may be judged more credible than the other, so that the former is labeled probable (close to real) and the [[latter]] relatively improbable (close to [[illusory]]). In the limit, they may be characterized as respectively effectively (inductively) real or [[illusory]]. Thus, [[reality]] and [[illusion]] are the extremes (respectively, 100% and 0%) in a broad range of probabilities with many [[intermediate]] degrees ([[including]] problemacy at the mid-point).
  
knowledge - and repeatedly reassessed thereafter, as that context develops and evolves. On this basis, one of these appearances may be judged more credible than the other, so that the former is labeled probable (close to real) and the latter relatively improbable (close to illusory). In the limit, they may be characterized as respectively effectively (inductively) real or illusory. Thus, reality and illusion are the extremes (respectively, 100% and 0%) in a broad range of probabilities with many intermediate degrees (including problemacy at the mid-point).
 
  
 +
To be still more precise, [[pure]] [[percepts]] (i.e. concrete [[appearances]], [[phenomena]]) are never [[illusory]]. The value-judgment of ‘[[illusory]]' properly concerns [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] (i.e. abstract [[appearances]], ‘universals') only. When we say of a [[percept]] that it was [[illusory]], we just mean that we misinterpreted it. That is, what we initially considered as a [[pure]] [[percept]], had in fact an admixture of {{Wiki|concept}}, which as it turned out was erroneous. For example, I see certain shapes and colors in the distance and think ‘here comes a girl on a bike', but as I get closer I realize that all I saw was a pile of rubbish by the roadside. The [[pure]] [[percept]] is the shapes and colors I see; the false [[interpretation]] is ‘girl on bike', the truer [[interpretation]] is ‘pile of rubbish'. The initial [[percept]] has not changed, but my greater proximity has added {{Wiki|perceptual}} details to it. My first [[impression]] was correct, only my initial [[judgment]] was wrong. I revise the [[latter]] {{Wiki|concept}}, not through some {{Wiki|superior}} means to [[knowledge]], but simply by means of further [[perception]] and {{Wiki|conception}}.
  
To be still more precise, pure percepts (i.e. concrete appearances, phenomena) are never illusory. The value-judgment of ‘illusory' properly concerns concepts (i.e. abstract appearances, ‘universals') only. When we say of a percept that it was illusory, we just mean that we misinterpreted it. That is, what we initially considered as a pure percept, had in fact an admixture of concept, which as it turned out was erroneous. For example, I see certain shapes and colors in the distance and think ‘here comes a girl on a bike', but as I get closer I realize that all I saw was a pile of rubbish by the roadside. The pure percept is the shapes and colors I see; the false interpretation is ‘girl on bike', the truer interpretation is ‘pile of rubbish'. The initial percept has not changed, but my greater proximity has added perceptual details to it. My first impression was correct, only my initial judgment was wrong. I revise the latter concept, not through some superior means to knowledge, but simply by means of further perception and conception.
 
  
  
 +
Strictly {{Wiki|speaking}}, then, [[perception]] is never at issue; it is our conceptions that we evaluate. It is in practice, admittedly, often very difficult to isolate a [[percept]] from its [[interpretation]], i.e. from {{Wiki|conceptual}} appendages to it. Our [[perception]] of things is, indeed, to a great extent ‘eidetic'. This fact need not, however, [[cause]] us to reject any [[perception]] (as many [[Western]] [[philosophers]], as well as [[Buddhists]], quickly do), or even all {{Wiki|conception}}. The {{Wiki|conceptual}} ‘[[impurities]]' in [[percepts]] are not necessarily wrong. We know them to have been wrong, when we discover a specific [[cause]] for complaint - namely, a
  
Strictly speaking, then, perception is never at issue; it is our conceptions that we evaluate. It is in practice, admittedly, often very difficult to isolate a percept from its interpretation, i.e. from conceptual appendages to it. Our perception of things is, indeed, to a great extent ‘eidetic'. This fact need not, however, cause us to reject any perception (as many Western philosophers, as well as Buddhists, quickly do), or even all conception. The conceptual ‘impurities' in percepts are not necessarily wrong. We know them to have been wrong, when we discover a specific cause for complaint - namely, a
+
[[logical]] or experiential {{Wiki|contradiction}}. So long as we find no such specific fault with them, they may be considered right. This just means that we have to apply the {{Wiki|rules}} of adduction  to our immediate interpretations of {{Wiki|individual}} [[percepts]], just as we do to complex theories [[relative]] to masses of [[percepts]]. These {{Wiki|rules}} are [[universal]]: no [[judgment]] is exempt from the requirement of careful {{Wiki|scrutiny}} and reevaluation.
  
logical or experiential contradiction. So long as we find no such specific fault with them, they may be considered right. This just means that we have to apply the rules of adduction  to our immediate interpretations of individual percepts, just as we do to complex theories relative to masses of percepts. These rules are universal: no judgment is exempt from the requirement of careful scrutiny and reevaluation.
 
  
  
 +
Now, judging by Cheng's account and certain quotations of [[Nagarjuna]] therein, we could interpret the [[latter]] as having been trying to say just what I have said. For instance, [[Cheng]] writes : “What [[Nagarjuna]] wanted to deny is that [[empirical]] [[phenomena]]... are absolutely real.... However, [this] does not mean that nothing [[exists]]. It does not nullify anything in the [[world]]” (my italics). I interpret this non-nullification as an [[acknowledgment]] of [[appearance]] as the minimum basis of [[knowledge]]. [[Nagarjuna]] may have had difficulties developing an appropriate {{Wiki|terminology}} (distinguishing [[existence]], [[appearance]] and [[reality]], as I do above), influenced no [[doubt]] by his penchant for {{Wiki|paradoxical}} statements seeming to express and confirm [[Buddhist]] [[mystical]] [[doctrine]].
  
Now, judging by Cheng's account and certain quotations of Nagarjuna therein, we could interpret the latter as having been trying to say just what I have said. For instance, Cheng writes : “What Nagarjuna wanted to deny is that empirical phenomena... are absolutely real.... However, [this] does not mean that nothing exists. It does not nullify anything in the world” (my italics). I interpret this non-nullification as an acknowledgment of appearance as the minimum basis of knowledge. Nagarjuna may have had difficulties developing an appropriate terminology (distinguishing existence, appearance and reality, as I do above), influenced no doubt by his penchant for paradoxical statements seeming to express and confirm Buddhist mystical doctrine.
 
  
  
 +
But if that is what he meant, then he has not succeeded to arrive at a “[[middle way]]” (a {{Wiki|denial}} of the Law of the Excluded Middle), but only at a “common way” (a granted common ground). As far as I am concerned, that is not a meager [[achievement]] - the [[philosophical]] discovery of [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]]! But for him that would be [[trivial]], if not counterproductive - for what he seeks is to deny [[ordinary consciousness]] and its inhibiting rationales, and to thereby leap into a different, [[higher consciousness]] capable of reaching [[transcendental]] [[truth]] or [[ultimate reality]].
  
But if that is what he meant, then he has not succeeded to arrive at a “middle way” (a denial of the Law of the Excluded Middle), but only at a “common way” (a granted common ground). As far as I am concerned, that is not a meager achievement - the philosophical discovery of phenomenology! But for him that would be trivial, if not counterproductive - for what he seeks is to deny ordinary consciousness and its inhibiting rationales, and to thereby leap into a different, higher consciousness capable of reaching transcendental truth or ultimate reality.
 
  
 +
It is [[interesting]] to note that the [[Madhyamika]] school's effective {{Wiki|denial}} of [[reality]] to all [[appearance]] was not accepted by a later school of [[Mahayana philosophy]], the [[Yogachara]] (7th-8th cent. CE). [[Cheng]] describes the latter's position as follows : “Every [[object]], both [[mental]] and [[non-mental]], may be [[logically]] or dialectically proven [[illusory]]. But in order to be [[illusory]], there must be a certain [[thought]] that [[suffers]] from [[illusion]]. The very fact of [[illusion]] itself proves the [[existence]] and [[reality]] of a certain [[consciousness]] or [[mind]]. To say that everything [[mental]] and [[non-mental]] is unreal is intellectually suicidal. The [[reality]] of something should at least be admitted in order to make [[sense]] of talking about [[illusion]]” (italics mine). That is the tenor of the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} argument I {{Wiki|present}} above, although my final conclusion is clearly not like Yogachara's, that everything is [[consciousness]] or [[mind]] (a type of [[Idealism]]), but leaves open the possibility of judging and classifying [[appearances]] as {{Wiki|matter}} or [[mind]] with reference to various considerations.
  
It is interesting to note that the Madhyamika school's effective denial of reality to all appearance was not accepted by a later school of Mahayana philosophy, the Yogachara (7th-8th cent. CE). Cheng describes the latter's position as follows : “Every object, both mental and non-mental, may be logically or dialectically proven illusory. But in order to be illusory, there must be a certain thought that suffers from illusion. The very fact of illusion itself proves the existence and reality of a certain consciousness or mind. To say that everything mental and non-mental is unreal is intellectually suicidal. The reality of something should at least be admitted in order to make sense of talking about illusion” (italics mine). That is the tenor of the phenomenological argument I present above, although my final conclusion is clearly not like Yogachara's, that everything is consciousness or mind (a type of Idealism), but leaves open the possibility of judging and classifying appearances as matter or mind with reference to various considerations.
 
  
  
 +
The [[Madhyamika]] rejection of ‘[[dualism]]' goes so far as to imply that “[[emptiness]]” is not to be found in [[nirvana]], the {{Wiki|antithesis}} of [[samsara]] (according to the earlier [[Buddhist]] viewpoint), but in ‘neither [[samsara]] nor [[nirvana]]'. In [[truth]], similar statements may be found in the [[Pali Canon]], i.e. in the much earlier [[Theravada]] schools, so that it is not a distinctly [[Mahayana]] construct. The difference is one of {{Wiki|emphasis}}, such statements, relatively rare in the earlier period, are the norm and frequently repeated in the later period. An example may be found in the [[Dhammapada]], a [[sutra]] dating from the 3rd cent. BCE , i.e. four or five hundred years before [[Nagarjuna]]. Here, [[samsara]] is likened to a {{Wiki|stream}} or this shore of it, and [[nirvana]] to the further shore; and we are told to get beyond the two.
  
The Madhyamika rejection of ‘dualism' goes so far as to imply that “emptiness” is not to be found in nirvana, the antithesis of samsara (according to the earlier Buddhist viewpoint), but in ‘neither samsara nor nirvana'. In truth, similar statements may be found in the Pali Canon, i.e. in the much earlier Theravada schools, so that it is not a distinctly Mahayana construct. The difference is one of emphasis, such statements, relatively rare in the earlier period, are the norm and frequently repeated in the later period. An example may be found in the Dhammapada, a sutra dating from the 3rd cent. BCE , i.e. four or five hundred years before Nagarjuna. Here, samsara is likened to a stream or this shore of it, and nirvana to the further shore; and we are told to get beyond the two.
 
  
 +
“When you have crossed the {{Wiki|stream}} of [[Samsara]], you will reach [[Nirvana]]... He has reached the other shore, then he attains the supreme [[vision]] and all his [[fetters]] are broken. He for whom there is neither this nor the further shore, nor both..”
  
“When you have crossed the stream of Samsara, you will reach Nirvana... He has reached the other shore, then he attains the supreme vision and all his fetters are broken. He for whom there is neither this nor the further shore, nor both..
+
Such a [[formula]] is legitimate if taken as a warning that pursuing [[nirvana]] ([[enlightenment]] and [[liberation]]) is an [[obstacle]] to achieving it, just a {{Wiki|subtle}} [[form]] of [[samsara]] ([[ignorance]] and [[attachment]]); there is no {{Wiki|contradiction}} in saying that the [[thought]] of [[nirvana]] as a goal of [[action]] keeps us in [[samsara]] - this is an ordinary causal statement. The [[formula]] is also [[logically]] acceptable if taken as a reminder that no [[word]] or {{Wiki|concept}} - not even ‘[[samsara]]' or ‘[[nirvana]]' - can capture or transmit the full meanings intended (i.e. ‘not' here should more precisely be stated as ‘not quite'). There is also no {{Wiki|contradiction}} in saying that one who has [[attained]] [[nirvana]] does not need to leave the [[world]] of those locked in [[samsara]], but can continue to [[exist]] and act in it though distinctively in a way free of [[attachment]].
  
Such a formula is legitimate if taken as a warning that pursuing nirvana (enlightenment and liberation) is an obstacle to achieving it, just a subtle form of samsara (ignorance and attachment); there is no contradiction in saying that the thought of nirvana as a goal of action keeps us in samsara - this is an ordinary causal statement. The formula is also logically acceptable if taken as a reminder that no word or concept - not even ‘samsara' or ‘nirvana' - can capture or transmit the full meanings intended (i.e. ‘not' here should more precisely be stated as ‘not quite'). There is also no contradiction in saying that one who has attained nirvana does not need to leave the world of those locked in samsara, but can continue to exist and act in it though distinctively in a way free of attachment.
 
  
 +
But it would be a {{Wiki|contradiction}} in terms to speak of ‘[[emptiness]]' as ‘neither [[samsara]] nor [[nirvana]]', given that [[nirvana]] as a {{Wiki|concept}} is originally defined as non-samsara; the [[truth]] cannot be a third alternative. At best, one could say that [[emptiness]] is a higher level of [[nirvana]] (in an enlarged [[sense]]), which is not to be confused with the lower level intended by the original term [[nirvana]], nor of course with [[samsara]]. In that case, [[nirvana]] (in a generic [[sense]] of the term, meaning literally non-samsara) includes both a higher {{Wiki|species}} and a lower one; and the statement ‘neither [[samsara]] nor lower- [[nirvana]]' is then compatible with the statement ‘higher [[nirvana]]'. There is a big difference between rough, {{Wiki|poetic}}, dramatic [[language]], and literal [[interpretation]] thereof.
 +
© Copyright [[Avi Sion]], 2002. All rights reserved.
  
But it would be a contradiction in terms to speak of ‘emptiness' as ‘neither samsara nor nirvana', given that nirvana as a concept is originally defined as non-samsara; the truth cannot be a third alternative. At best, one could say that emptiness is a higher level of nirvana (in an enlarged sense), which is not to be confused with the lower level intended by the original term nirvana, nor of course with samsara. In that case, nirvana (in a generic sense of the term, meaning literally non-samsara) includes both a higher species and a lower one; and the statement ‘neither samsara nor lower- nirvana' is then compatible with the statement ‘higher nirvana'. There is a big difference between rough, poetic, dramatic language, and literal interpretation thereof.
 
© Copyright Avi Sion, 2002. All rights reserved.
 
  
 
+
Protected by international copyright conventions. No part of this [[book]] may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever,
Protected by international copyright conventions. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever,
 
 
or stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, without express permission of the Author-publisher, except in case of
 
or stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, without express permission of the Author-publisher, except in case of
 
brief quotations with due acknowledgement.
 
brief quotations with due acknowledgement.
  
  
Buddhist Illogic can be freely read online at TheLogician.net and in various other locations. It can be purchased, in print and e-book editions, in Amazon.com, Lulu.com and many other online booksellers.
+
[[Buddhist]] [[Illogic]] can be freely read online at TheLogician.net and in various other locations. It can be purchased, in print and e-book editions, in Amazon.com, Lulu.com and many other online booksellers.
  
  
Line 134: Line 132:
 
[[Category:Buddhist Logic]]
 
[[Category:Buddhist Logic]]
 
[[Category:Buddhist Philosophy]]
 
[[Category:Buddhist Philosophy]]
 +
[[Category:Tetralemma]]

Latest revision as of 01:01, 3 September 2021




By Avi Sion PH.D.



Buddhist Illogic can be freely read online at TheLogician.net and in various other locations.

It can be purchased, in print and e-book editions, in Amazon.com, Lulu.com and many other online booksellers.

The present document contains excerpts from this book, namely: The Abstract; the Contents; and Sample text (Chapters 1 and 2).

Avi Sion (Ph.D. Philosophy) is a researcher and writer in logic, philosophy, and spirituality. He has, since 1990, published original writings on the theory and practice of inductive and deductive logic, phenomenology, epistemology, aetiology, psychology, meditation, ethics, and much more. Over a period of some 28 years, he has published 27 books. He resides in Geneva, Switzerland.

It is very difficult to briefly summarize Avi Sion's philosophy, because it is so wide-ranging. He has labeled it ‘Logical Philosophy', because it is firmly grounded in formal logic, inductive as well as deductive. This original philosophy is dedicated to demonstrating the efficacy of human reason by detailing its actual means; and to show that the epistemological and ethical skepticism which has been increasingly fashionable and destructive since the Enlightenment was (contrary to appearances) quite illogical - the product of ignorant, incompetent and dishonest thinking.


Abstract


Buddhist Illogic. The 2nd Century CE Indian philosopher Nagarjuna founded the Madhyamika (Middle Way) school of Mahayana Buddhism, which strongly influenced Chinese (Ch'an), Korean (Sôn) and Japanese (Zen) Buddhism, as well as Tibetan Buddhism. Nagarjuna is regarded by many Buddhist writers to this day as a very important philosopher, who they claim definitively proved the futility of ordinary human cognitive means. His writings include a series of arguments purporting to show the illogic of logic, the absurdity of reason. He considers this the way to verbalize and justify the Buddhist doctrine of “emptiness” (Shunyata). These arguments attack some of the basic tenets and techniques of reasoning, such as the laws of thought (identity, non-contradiction and the excluded middle), conceptualization and predication, our common assumptions of self, entities and essences, as well as our beliefs in motion and causation.

The present essay demonstrates the many sophistries involved in Nagarjuna's arguments. He uses double standards, applying or ignoring the laws of thought and other norms as convenient to his goals; he manipulates his readers, by giving seemingly logical form (like the dilemma) to his discourse, while in fact engaged in non-sequiturs or appealing to doubtful premises; he plays with words, relying on unclear terminology, misleading equivocations and unfair fixations of meaning; and he ‘steals concepts', using them to deny the very percepts on which they are based.

Although a critique of the Madhyamika philosophical interpretation and defense of “emptiness”, Buddhist Illogic is not intended to dissuade readers from Buddhism. On the contrary, its aim to enhance personal awareness of actual cognitive processes, and so improve meditation. It is also an excellent primer on phenomenological epistemology.


1. THE TETRALEMMA.

Western philosophical and scientific thought is based on Aristotelian logic, whose founding principles are the three “Laws of Thought”. These can be briefly stated as “A is A” (Identity), “Nothing is both A and non-A” (Non-contradiction) and “Nothing is neither A nor non-A” (Exclusion of the Middle). These are not claimed as mere hypotheses, note well, but as incontrovertible premises of all rational human thought . Religions like Judaism, Christianity and Islam, even while adhering to these laws in much of their discourse and paying lip-service to them, in their bids to interpret their own sacred texts and to make their doctrines seem reasonable to their converts, have often ignored these same laws. This is especially true of mystical trends within these religions, but many examples could be given from mainstream writings. The same can be said of some aspects of Buddhist philosophy.

The tetralemma is a derivative of the laws of thought, with reference to any two terms or propositions, labeled A and B, and their opposites non-A and non-B. Four combinations of these four terms are conceivable, namely “A and B” (both), “non-A and non-B” (neither), “A and non¬B” and “non-A and B” (one or the other only). According to Aristotelian logic, these four statements are incompatible with each other (only one of them can be true, because if two or more were affirmed then “A and non-A” or “B and non-B” or both would be true, and the latter implications are self-contradictory) and exhaustive (at least one of them must be true, since if they were all denied then “not A and not non-A” or “not B and not non-B” or both would be true, and the latter implications go against the excluded middle).


Now, what Nagarjuna does is insert the term A in place of B (i.e. he takes the case of B = A), and effectively claim that the above four logical possibilities of combination apply in that special case - so that “A and A (=B)”, “non-A and non-A (=non-B)”, “A and non-A (=non-B)”, “non-A and A (=B)” seem logically acceptable. He then goes on to argue that there are four existential possibilities: affirmation of A (A + A = A), denial of A (non-A + non-A = non-A), both affirmation and denial of A (A and non-A) and neither affirmation nor denial of A (not A and not non-A). He is thus apparently using the principles and terminology of common logic to arrive at a very opposite result. This gives him and readers the impression that it is quite reasonable to both affirm and deny or to neither affirm nor deny.

But in Aristotelian logic, the latter two alternatives are at the outset excluded - “both A and non¬A” by the Law of Non-contradiction and “neither A nor non-A” by the Law of the Excluded-Middle - and the only logical possibilities left are “A” or “non-A”. The anti-Aristotelian position may be viewed, in a positive light, as an anti-Nominalist position, reminding us that things are never quite what they seem or that things cannot be precisely classified or labeled. But ultimately, they intend the death of Logic; for without the laws of thought, how are we to distinguish between true and false judgments? The law of identity “A is A” is a conviction that things have some identity (whatever it specifically be) rather than another, or than no identity at all.

It is an affirmation that knowledge is ultimately possible, and a rejection of sheer relativism or obscurantism. Nagarjuna's goal is to deny identity. It should be noted here that Aristotle is very precise in his formulation of the law of contradiction, stating in his Metaphysics “The same attribute cannot at the same time belong and not belong to the same subject in the same respect” (italics mine). Thus, an alternative statement of the laws of thought would be the ‘trilemma' (let us so call it) “either wholly A, or wholly non-A, or both partly A and partly non-A”, which excludes the fourth

alternative “both wholly A and wholly non-A”. The Buddhist attack on the laws of thought draws some of its credibility from the fact that people subconsciously refer to this ‘trilemma', thinking superficially that indeed opposite things may occur in the same place at different times or at the same time in different places or in various respects, without thereby giving rise to logical difficulty incapable of resolution. But it should be clear that the Buddhist position is much more radical than that, accepting thoroughgoing antinomy.


Similarly with regard to the law of the excluded middle, which affirms the situation “neither A nor non-A” to be impossible in fact. People are misled by the possibility of uncertainty in knowledge, as to whether A or non-A is the case in fact, into believing that this law of thought is open to debate. But it must be understood that the thrust of this logical rule is inductive, rather than deductive; i.e. it is a statement that at the end of the knowledge acquisition process, either “A” or “non-A” will result, and no third alternative can be expected. It does not exclude that in the interim, a situation of

uncertainty may occur. Nagarjuna's position exploits this confusion in people's minds. Nagarjuna interprets the limitation implied by the dilemma “A or non-A” as an arbitrary ‘dualism' on the part of ordinary thinkers . It only goes to show that he misunderstands formalization (or he pretends to, in an attempt to confuse gullible readers). When logicians use a variable like “B” and allow that “non-A and B” and “A and non-B” are both in principle possible, they do not intend that as a generality applicable to all values of B (such as “A”), but only as a generic statement applicable to any consistent values of B. In the specific case where B = A, the said two combinations have to be eliminated because they are illegal (i.e. breach two of the laws of thought).


The above-stated property of symbols, i.e. their applicability only conditionally within the constraints of consistency, is evident throughout the science of formal logic, and it is here totally ignored by Nagarjuna. His motive of course was to verbalize and rationalize the Buddha's doctrine that the ultimate truth is beyond nama and rupa, name and form (i.e. discrimination and discourse), knowable only by a transcendental consciousness (the Twofold Truth doctrine). More precisely, as Cheng emphasizes, Nagarjuna's intent was to show that logic is inherently inconsistent and thus that reason is confused madness to be rejected. That is, he was (here and throughout) not ultimately trying to defend a tetralemma with B equal to A - or even to affirm that things are both A and non¬A, or neither A nor non-A - but wished to get us to look altogether beyond the distinctions of conceptualization and the judgments of logic.


But as above shown he does not succeed in this quest. For his critique depends on a misrepresentation of logical science. He claims to show that logic is confused and self-contradictory, but in truth what he presents as the thesis of logical science is not what it claims for itself but precisely what it explicitly forbids. Furthermore, suppose logical theory did lead to contradictions as he claims, this fact would not lead us to its rejection were there not also a tacit appeal to our preference for the logical in practice. If logic were false, contradictions would be acceptable. Thus, funnily enough, Nagarjuna appeals to our logical habit in his very recommendation to us to ignore logic. In sum, though he gives the illusion that it is reasonable to abandon reason, it is easy to see that his conclusion is foregone and his means are faulty.


2. NEITHER REAL NOR UNREAL

But Nagarjuna also conceives ultimate reality (“emptiness” ) as a “middle way” - so that the world of experience is neither to be regarded as real, nor to be regarded as unreal (“there is nothing, neither mental nor non-mental, which is real” and it “cannot be conceived as unreal,” reports Cheng). In this context, Nagarjuna is clearly relying on one of the above-mentioned logically impossible disjuncts, namely “neither A nor non-A” (be it said in passing). I want to now show why Nagarjuna's statement seems superficially reasonable and true.


As I have often clarified and explained , knowledge has to be regarded or approached phenomenologically (that is the only consistent epistemological thesis). We have to start by acknowledging and observing appearances, as such, without initial judgment as to their reality or illusion. At first sight all appearances seem real enough. But after a while, we have to recognize that some appearances conflict with other appearances, and judge such appearances (i.e. one or more of those in conflict) as illusory. Since there is nothing in our ‘world' but appearances, all remaining appearances not judged as illusions (i.e. so long as they are not logically invalidated by conflicts with other appearances) maintain their initial status as realities.


That is, the distinction between appearances as realities or illusions emerges within the world of appearances itself, merely classifying some this way and the rest that way. We have no concept of reality or illusion other than with reference to appearance. To use the category of reality with reference to something beyond appearance is concept stealing, a misuse of the concept, an extrapolation which ignores the concept's actual genesis in the context of appearance. To apply the concept of illusion to all appearances, on the basis that some appearances are illusions, is an unjustified generalization ignoring how this concept arises with reference to a specific event (namely, inconsistency between certain appearances and resulting diminishment of their innate credibilities). Moreover, to claim that no appearances are real or that all are illusions is self-defeating, since such claim itself logically falls under the category of appearance.


The illusory exists even though it is not reality - it exists as appearance. The real is also apparent - some of it, at least. Therefore, appearance per se is neither to be understood as reality (since some appearances are illusory), nor can it be equated to illusion (since not all appearances have been or can be found illusory). Appearance is thus the common ground of realities and illusions, their common characteristic, the dialectical synthesis of those theses and antitheses. It is a genus, they are mutually exclusive species of it. (The difference between appearance and existence is another issue, I have dealt with elsewhere - briefly put, existence is a genus of appearance and non-appearance, the latter concepts being relative to that of consciousness whereas the former is assumed independent.)


None of these insights allows the conclusion that appearances are “neither real nor unreal” (granting that ‘unreal' is understood to mean ‘non-real'). All we can say is that some appearances are real and some unreal. Formally, the correct logical relation between the three concepts is as follows. Deductively, appearance is implied by reality and illusion, but does not imply them; for reality and illusion are contradictory, so that they cannot both be true and they cannot both be false. Moreover, inductively, appearance implies reality, until and unless it is judged to be illusion (by virtue of some inconsistency being discovered).


More precisely, all appearances are initially classed as real. Any appearance found self¬contradictory is (deductively) illusory, and its contradictory is consequently self-evident and (deductively) real. All remaining appearances remain classed as real, so long as uncontested. Those that are contested have to be evaluated dynamically. When one appearance is belied by another, they are both put in doubt by the conflict between them, and so both become initially problematic. Thereafter, their relative credibilities have to be tentatively weighed in the overall context of available empirical and rational knowledge - and repeatedly reassessed thereafter, as that context develops and evolves. On this basis, one of these appearances may be judged more credible than the other, so that the former is labeled probable (close to real) and the latter relatively improbable (close to illusory). In the limit, they may be characterized as respectively effectively (inductively) real or illusory. Thus, reality and illusion are the extremes (respectively, 100% and 0%) in a broad range of probabilities with many intermediate degrees (including problemacy at the mid-point).


To be still more precise, pure percepts (i.e. concrete appearances, phenomena) are never illusory. The value-judgment of ‘illusory' properly concerns concepts (i.e. abstract appearances, ‘universals') only. When we say of a percept that it was illusory, we just mean that we misinterpreted it. That is, what we initially considered as a pure percept, had in fact an admixture of concept, which as it turned out was erroneous. For example, I see certain shapes and colors in the distance and think ‘here comes a girl on a bike', but as I get closer I realize that all I saw was a pile of rubbish by the roadside. The pure percept is the shapes and colors I see; the false interpretation is ‘girl on bike', the truer interpretation is ‘pile of rubbish'. The initial percept has not changed, but my greater proximity has added perceptual details to it. My first impression was correct, only my initial judgment was wrong. I revise the latter concept, not through some superior means to knowledge, but simply by means of further perception and conception.


Strictly speaking, then, perception is never at issue; it is our conceptions that we evaluate. It is in practice, admittedly, often very difficult to isolate a percept from its interpretation, i.e. from conceptual appendages to it. Our perception of things is, indeed, to a great extent ‘eidetic'. This fact need not, however, cause us to reject any perception (as many Western philosophers, as well as Buddhists, quickly do), or even all conception. The conceptualimpurities' in percepts are not necessarily wrong. We know them to have been wrong, when we discover a specific cause for complaint - namely, a

logical or experiential contradiction. So long as we find no such specific fault with them, they may be considered right. This just means that we have to apply the rules of adduction to our immediate interpretations of individual percepts, just as we do to complex theories relative to masses of percepts. These rules are universal: no judgment is exempt from the requirement of careful scrutiny and reevaluation.


Now, judging by Cheng's account and certain quotations of Nagarjuna therein, we could interpret the latter as having been trying to say just what I have said. For instance, Cheng writes : “What Nagarjuna wanted to deny is that empirical phenomena... are absolutely real.... However, [this] does not mean that nothing exists. It does not nullify anything in the world” (my italics). I interpret this non-nullification as an acknowledgment of appearance as the minimum basis of knowledge. Nagarjuna may have had difficulties developing an appropriate terminology (distinguishing existence, appearance and reality, as I do above), influenced no doubt by his penchant for paradoxical statements seeming to express and confirm Buddhist mystical doctrine.


But if that is what he meant, then he has not succeeded to arrive at a “middle way” (a denial of the Law of the Excluded Middle), but only at a “common way” (a granted common ground). As far as I am concerned, that is not a meager achievement - the philosophical discovery of phenomenology! But for him that would be trivial, if not counterproductive - for what he seeks is to deny ordinary consciousness and its inhibiting rationales, and to thereby leap into a different, higher consciousness capable of reaching transcendental truth or ultimate reality.


It is interesting to note that the Madhyamika school's effective denial of reality to all appearance was not accepted by a later school of Mahayana philosophy, the Yogachara (7th-8th cent. CE). Cheng describes the latter's position as follows : “Every object, both mental and non-mental, may be logically or dialectically proven illusory. But in order to be illusory, there must be a certain thought that suffers from illusion. The very fact of illusion itself proves the existence and reality of a certain consciousness or mind. To say that everything mental and non-mental is unreal is intellectually suicidal. The reality of something should at least be admitted in order to make sense of talking about illusion” (italics mine). That is the tenor of the phenomenological argument I present above, although my final conclusion is clearly not like Yogachara's, that everything is consciousness or mind (a type of Idealism), but leaves open the possibility of judging and classifying appearances as matter or mind with reference to various considerations.


The Madhyamika rejection of ‘dualism' goes so far as to imply that “emptiness” is not to be found in nirvana, the antithesis of samsara (according to the earlier Buddhist viewpoint), but in ‘neither samsara nor nirvana'. In truth, similar statements may be found in the Pali Canon, i.e. in the much earlier Theravada schools, so that it is not a distinctly Mahayana construct. The difference is one of emphasis, such statements, relatively rare in the earlier period, are the norm and frequently repeated in the later period. An example may be found in the Dhammapada, a sutra dating from the 3rd cent. BCE , i.e. four or five hundred years before Nagarjuna. Here, samsara is likened to a stream or this shore of it, and nirvana to the further shore; and we are told to get beyond the two.


“When you have crossed the stream of Samsara, you will reach Nirvana... He has reached the other shore, then he attains the supreme vision and all his fetters are broken. He for whom there is neither this nor the further shore, nor both..”

Such a formula is legitimate if taken as a warning that pursuing nirvana (enlightenment and liberation) is an obstacle to achieving it, just a subtle form of samsara (ignorance and attachment); there is no contradiction in saying that the thought of nirvana as a goal of action keeps us in samsara - this is an ordinary causal statement. The formula is also logically acceptable if taken as a reminder that no word or concept - not even ‘samsara' or ‘nirvana' - can capture or transmit the full meanings intended (i.e. ‘not' here should more precisely be stated as ‘not quite'). There is also no contradiction in saying that one who has attained nirvana does not need to leave the world of those locked in samsara, but can continue to exist and act in it though distinctively in a way free of attachment.


But it would be a contradiction in terms to speak of ‘emptiness' as ‘neither samsara nor nirvana', given that nirvana as a concept is originally defined as non-samsara; the truth cannot be a third alternative. At best, one could say that emptiness is a higher level of nirvana (in an enlarged sense), which is not to be confused with the lower level intended by the original term nirvana, nor of course with samsara. In that case, nirvana (in a generic sense of the term, meaning literally non-samsara) includes both a higher species and a lower one; and the statement ‘neither samsara nor lower- nirvana' is then compatible with the statement ‘higher nirvana'. There is a big difference between rough, poetic, dramatic language, and literal interpretation thereof. © Copyright Avi Sion, 2002. All rights reserved.


Protected by international copyright conventions. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever, or stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, without express permission of the Author-publisher, except in case of brief quotations with due acknowledgement.


Buddhist Illogic can be freely read online at TheLogician.net and in various other locations. It can be purchased, in print and e-book editions, in Amazon.com, Lulu.com and many other online booksellers.



Source