Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "TIME AND TEMPORALITY IN INDIAN BUDDHISM"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
(One intermediate revision by the same user not shown)
Line 13: Line 13:
  
  
It is not an easy task to give an outline of the origin and development of the concepts of time and temporality in Indian Buddhism.1 There are three main difficulties to face in pursuing this aim: first, the relatively late and frequently interpolated nature of the available sources makes it hard to state with confidence what the historical Buddha taught; second, in order to rebuild the philosophical systems of many of the following schools of Abhidharma we often have to piece together fragments of information extrapolated by texts which were produced by other schools, always questioning the correctness of their statements;  
+
It is not an easy task to give an outline of the origin and [[development]] of the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of time and temporality in [[Indian]] Buddhism.1 There are three main difficulties to face in pursuing this aim: first, the relatively late and frequently interpolated [[nature]] of the available sources makes it hard to [[state]] with [[confidence]] what the [[historical Buddha]] [[taught]]; second, in order to rebuild the [[philosophical]] systems of many of the following schools of [[Abhidharma]] we often have to piece together fragments of [[information]] extrapolated by texts which were produced by other schools, always questioning the correctness of their statements;  
  
third, the problem of time was not always treated systematically, and therefore there is no other way than draw our conclusions by analysing related concepts such as impermanence, duration, motion, et cetera. Great scholars have examined the subject in depth, but the debate on many of the issues raised is still open, and a definitive solution seems to be still to come.  With the present essay, I intend to give an outline of the different views on time and temporality developed in the context of Indian Buddhism, from the early teachings to Nāgārjuna’s Kālaparikṣa , in order to suggest a  
+
third, the problem of time was not always treated systematically, and therefore there is no other way than draw our conclusions by analysing related [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] such as [[impermanence]], duration, {{Wiki|motion}}, et cetera. Great [[scholars]] have examined the [[subject]] in depth, but the [[debate]] on many of the issues raised is still open, and a definitive {{Wiki|solution}} seems to be still to come.  With the {{Wiki|present}} essay, I intend to give an outline of the different [[views]] on time and temporality developed in the context of [[Indian Buddhism]], from the early teachings to [[Nāgārjuna’s]] Kālaparikṣa , in order to suggest a  
  
It is essential to draw a clear distinction between the categories of time and temporality. While the word ‘time’ refers to an absolute time, ontologically independent from the beings, the word ‘temporality’ indicates change as a modality of phenomenal existence.   
+
It is [[essential]] to draw a clear {{Wiki|distinction}} between the categories of time and temporality. While the [[word]] ‘time’ refers to an [[absolute]] time, [[ontologically]] {{Wiki|independent}} from the [[beings]], the [[word]] ‘temporality’ indicates change as a modality of [[phenomenal existence]].   
  
solution to the above mentioned problematic issues. Nevertheless, the extremely controversial nature of the topic leads me to keep far from claiming the absolute authority of my opinions.     
+
{{Wiki|solution}} to the above mentioned problematic issues. Nevertheless, the extremely controversial [[nature]] of the topic leads me to keep far from claiming the [[absolute]] authority of my opinions.     
 
   
 
   
  
Line 25: Line 25:
 
   
 
   
  
In the “Sūtra of the Turning the Wheel of the Dharma” (pāli Dhammacakkappavattana Sutta ), by exposing the first of the “Four Noble Truths” (pāli Cattāri Ariyasaccāni ), known as “The Truth of Dukkha ” (pāli Dukkha Ariyasaccā ), Śākyamuni Buddha gives the foundations for the following construction of a doctrine of time based on the impermanence (pāli anicca ; skt. anitya ) of each and every phenomenon.2  Then, in the “Great Sūtra on the Destruction of  
+
In the “[[Sūtra]] of the [[Turning the Wheel]] of the [[Dharma]]” ([[pāli]] [[Dhammacakkappavattana Sutta]] ), by exposing the first of the “[[Four Noble Truths]]” ([[pāli]] [[Cattāri Ariyasaccāni]] ), known as “The [[Truth]] of [[Dukkha]] ” ([[pāli]] [[Dukkha]] Ariyasaccā ), [[Śākyamuni Buddha]] gives the foundations for the following construction of a [[doctrine]] of time based on the [[impermanence]] ([[pāli]] [[anicca]] ; skt. [[anitya]] ) of each and every phenomenon.2  Then, in the “Great [[Sūtra]] on the Destruction of  
  
Craving” (pāli Mahātaṇhāsaṅkhaya Sutta ), he indicates the three marks (skt. trilakṣaṇa ) which characterize all the phenomena of the saṃsāra : suffering (skt. duḥkha ), impermanence (skt. anitya ) and no-self (skt. anātman ).  Everything is source of suffering for us, as we tend to feel desire and craving  
+
[[Craving]]” ([[pāli]] [[Mahātaṇhāsaṅkhaya Sutta]] ), he indicates the three marks (skt. [[trilakṣaṇa]] ) which characterize all the [[phenomena]] of the [[saṃsāra]] : [[suffering]] (skt. [[duḥkha]] ), [[impermanence]] (skt. [[anitya]] ) and [[no-self]] (skt. [[anātman]] ).  Everything is source of [[suffering]] for us, as we tend to [[feel]] [[desire]] and [[craving]]
  
for a world that is impermanent and has no stable substance. In other words, suffering is due to the illusory reification of temporal existence. It is caused by ignorance (skt. avidyā ), the unrecognition of the real character of existence. Existence is described as a ceaseless causal process, where any supposed stability is recognized as false, illusory, and therefore source of suffering.  
+
for a [[world]] that is [[impermanent]] and has no {{Wiki|stable}} [[substance]]. In other words, [[suffering]] is due to the [[illusory]] [[reification]] of {{Wiki|temporal}} [[existence]]. It is [[caused]] by [[ignorance]] (skt. [[avidyā]] ), the unrecognition of the real [[character]] of [[existence]]. [[Existence]] is described as a ceaseless causal process, where any supposed stability is [[recognized]] as false, [[illusory]], and therefore source of [[suffering]].  
  
Dependence by causes is the real structure of the universe: any phenomenon exists depending on its causes (skt. hetu ) and conditions (skt. pratyaya ). As the cause is impermanent, the effect (skt. phala ) will be impermanent as well.  An impersonal law of causality defines relations between events: if X occurs, Y will follow; if X does not occur, Y will not follow (pāli “ imasmiṃ s a ti, id a ṃ h o ti, im a s miṃ a s a ti, id a ṃ n a h o ti ”). This is the so-called “Dependent Origination” (skt. pratītyasamutpāda ), the core of Buddha’s middlepath between eternalism and nihilism. The teachings outlined above represent the basic standpoints which enable us to analyse the development of the concepts of time and temporality in Early Buddhism.  
+
[[Dependence]] by [[causes]] is the real {{Wiki|structure}} of the [[universe]]: any [[phenomenon]] [[exists]] depending on its [[causes]] (skt. [[hetu]] ) and [[conditions]] (skt. [[pratyaya]] ). As the [[cause]] is [[impermanent]], the effect (skt. [[phala]] ) will be [[impermanent]] as well.  An {{Wiki|impersonal}} law of [[causality]] defines relations between events: if X occurs, Y will follow; if X does not occur, Y will not follow ([[pāli]] “ imasmiṃ s [[a ti]], [[id]] a ṃ h o ti, im a s miṃ a s [[a ti]], [[id]] a ṃ n a h o ti ”). This is the so-called “[[Dependent Origination]]” (skt. [[pratītyasamutpāda]] ), the core of [[Buddha’s]] middlepath between [[eternalism and nihilism]]. The teachings outlined above represent the basic standpoints which enable us to analyse the [[development]] of the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of time and temporality in [[Early Buddhism]].  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
Line 37: Line 37:
 
   
 
   
  
Although the Buddha preached the law of impermanence, he never explained the extent and the modalities of this law. This was probably due to the fact that Buddha’s reflections about reality were directed toward the delineation of a soteriology: he did not intend to create an ontological system. On the contrary, the schools which developed during the first centuries after the Buddha’s demise needed to build up a well-defined ontological system to be able  
+
Although the [[Buddha]] [[preached]] the law of [[impermanence]], he never explained the extent and the modalities of this law. This was probably due to the fact that [[Buddha’s]] reflections about [[reality]] were directed toward the delineation of a {{Wiki|soteriology}}: he did not intend to create an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] system. On the contrary, the schools which developed during the first centuries after the [[Buddha’s]] demise needed [[to build]] up a well-defined [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] system to be able  
  
to undertake positively the challenging debates with the representatives of the other Indian religious traditions, and to be ready to defend their views during the discussions between the various doctrinal currents arisen within Buddhism itself. These schools were in accord about the fundamental tenets of the Buddhist doctrine (Four Noble Thruths, Dependent Origination, No-self,  
+
to undertake positively the challenging [[debates]] with the representatives of the other [[Indian]] [[religious]] [[traditions]], and to be ready to defend their [[views]] during the discussions between the various [[doctrinal]] currents arisen within [[Buddhism]] itself. These schools were in accord about the fundamental [[tenets]] of the [[Buddhist doctrine]] (Four [[Noble]] Thruths, [[Dependent Origination]], [[No-self]],  
  
and Impermanence). Trying not to break these principles, they made their attempt to determine the extent of the law of impermanence.  The clash of views that arose between the Abhidharma schools about temporality was very divisive, and the systems of thought that resulted from it were the most disparate.3  If we carefully consider the teachings of the Abhidharma schools it becomes clearly evident a shift in the understanding of the law of impermanence, from  
+
and [[Impermanence]]). Trying not to break these {{Wiki|principles}}, they made their attempt to determine the extent of the law of [[impermanence]].  The clash of [[views]] that arose between the [[Abhidharma]] schools about temporality was very divisive, and the systems of [[thought]] that resulted from it were the most disparate.3  If we carefully consider the teachings of the [[Abhidharma]] schools it becomes clearly evident a shift in the [[understanding]] of the law of [[impermanence]], from  
  
an empirical realization of change to a radical ontology of instantaneousness. In fact, the various standpoints held by the Abhidharma schools seem to compose a spectrum between these two poles. This view is supported by Stambaugh and Kalupahana. They both argued that, although the textual sources do not allow us to make any certain assertion, it seems reasonable to believe that at the time of the Buddha and of his early followers the concept of  
+
an [[empirical]] [[realization]] of change to a radical {{Wiki|ontology}} of instantaneousness. In fact, the various standpoints held by the [[Abhidharma]] schools seem to compose a spectrum between these two poles. This view is supported by Stambaugh and [[Kalupahana]]. They both argued that, although the textual sources do not allow us to make any certain [[assertion]], it seems reasonable to believe that at the time of the [[Buddha]] and of his early followers the {{Wiki|concept}} of  
  
impermanence was still not carried to its logical extreme: instantaneism. Radical instantaneism, logical consequence of the law of impermanence, was probably established by Abhidharma’s thinkers.4 Stcherbatsky rejects this view. He believes the doctrine of instantaneous existence to be nothing but a restoration of the Buddha’s teaching of impermanence, a teaching which was affected by corruption after the master’s demise. He even suggests that this doctrine should be considered a pre-Buddhist inheritance.5 However, in absence of decisive evidences, the theory suggested by Stcherbatsky seems quite implausible.  
+
[[impermanence]] was still not carried to its [[logical]] extreme: instantaneism. Radical instantaneism, [[logical consequence]] of the law of [[impermanence]], was probably established by [[Abhidharma’s]] thinkers.4 [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] rejects this view. He believes the [[doctrine]] of instantaneous [[existence]] to be nothing but a restoration of the [[Buddha’s teaching]] of [[impermanence]], a [[teaching]] which was affected by corruption after the [[master’s]] demise. He even suggests that this [[doctrine]] should be considered a pre-Buddhist inheritance.5 However, in absence of decisive evidences, the {{Wiki|theory}} suggested by [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] seems quite implausible.  
  
  
Bareau (1957:364); Panikkar (1974:163). 4 Stambaugh 1974:132; Kalupahana 1974:184-185.  5 Stcherbatsky 1930:108. Coomaraswamy (2003:48) agrees with the opinion of Stcherbatsky, but at the same time criticizes Stcherbatsky’s understanding of the doctrine of instantaneousness.  
+
Bareau (1957:364); Panikkar (1974:163). 4 Stambaugh 1974:132; [[Kalupahana]] 1974:184-185.  5 [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] 1930:108. [[Coomaraswamy]] (2003:48) agrees with the opinion of [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]], but at the same time criticizes Stcherbatsky’s [[understanding]] of the [[doctrine]] of instantaneousness.  
  
 
   
 
   
It is possible to highlight the steps of the development of the concept of impermanence by analysing the most important points of controversy in the saṃgha regarding temporality:  
+
It is possible to highlight the steps of the [[development]] of the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[impermanence]] by analysing the most important [[points of controversy]] in the [[saṃgha]] regarding temporality:  
 
   
 
   
1) Nature of impermanence: the Vātsīputrīya held that to state that things are impermanent does not mean that they should rise and disappear in one instant of thought. They admitted the existence of a certain degree of duration and motion (skt. gati ), and they even believed in the existence of a transmigrating “personality” (skt. pudgala ). In contrast, the Mahāsāṃghika, Mahīśāsaka, Kāśyapīya, Sarvāstivāda and Sautrāntika schools held an instantaneist doctrine, refusing to make any kind of distinction in degrees of impermanence.  
+
1) [[Nature]] of [[impermanence]]: the [[Vātsīputrīya]] held that to [[state]] that things are [[impermanent]] does not mean that they should rise and disappear in [[one instant of thought]]. They admitted the [[existence]] of a certain [[degree]] of duration and {{Wiki|motion}} (skt. [[gati]] ), and they even believed in the [[existence]] of a transmigrating “[[personality]]” (skt. [[pudgala]] ). In contrast, the [[Mahāsāṃghika]], [[Mahīśāsaka]], [[Kāśyapīya]], [[Sarvāstivāda]] and [[Sautrāntika]] schools held an instantaneist [[doctrine]], refusing to make any kind of {{Wiki|distinction}} in degrees of [[impermanence]].  
 
   
 
   
2) Extent of the law of instantaneity: should radical instantaneism be applied only to mental phenomena, or even to the material world? The Theravāda and the Vātsīputrīya school maintained that the thought is instantaneous (skt. kṣaṇika ), while the matter, although does not last, is not instantaneous, but rather momentary (skt. anitya ). In other words, for these two schools the rhythm of appearance and disappearance was not the same for mental and material  
+
2) Extent of the law of instantaneity: should radical instantaneism be applied only to [[mental phenomena]], or even to the [[material world]]? The [[Theravāda]] and the [[Vātsīputrīya]] school maintained that the [[thought]] is instantaneous (skt. kṣaṇika ), while the {{Wiki|matter}}, although does not last, is not instantaneous, but rather momentary (skt. [[anitya]] ). In other words, for these two schools the rhythm of [[appearance]] and [[disappearance]] was not the same for [[mental]] and [[material phenomena]]. The [[Theravādin]] even established a rate of [[conversion]]: in their [[views]], one material instant corresponded to sixteen or seventeen [[mental]] instant. In contrast, the other schools [[affirmed]] the same [[identical]] [[impermanence]] for any [[conditioned dharma]] , without any dinstinction between [[mental]] and material [[dharmas]] .   
 
 
phenomena. The Theravādin even established a rate of conversion: in their views, one material instant corresponded to sixteen or seventeen mental instant. In contrast, the other schools affirmed the same identical impermanence for any conditioned dharma , without any dinstinction between mental and material dharmas .   
 
 
   
 
   
  
3) Nature of the instant (skt. kṣaṇa ): after defining  dharmas as instantaneous, taking in consideration that a dharma rise and disappear, the Theravādin argued that an instant should be divided in three moments: one for birth (pāli uppāda ), one for duration (pāli ṭhiti ), and one for cessation (pāli bhaṅga ). The Sarvāstivādin believed in the existence of four stages: birth (skt. jāti ), duration (skt. sthiti ), perishing (skt. jarā ) and cessation (skt. nāśā ). Contrary to these claims, the Sautrāntika believed in the existence of just two phases: birth (skt. utpāda ) and cessation (skt. vyaya ).  
+
3) [[Nature]] of the instant (skt. [[kṣaṇa]] ): after defining  [[dharmas]] as instantaneous, taking in [[consideration]] that a [[dharma]] rise and disappear, the [[Theravādin]] argued that an instant should be divided in three moments: one for [[birth]] ([[pāli]] [[uppāda]] ), one for duration ([[pāli]] ṭhiti ), and one for [[cessation]] ([[pāli]] [[bhaṅga]] ). The [[Sarvāstivādin]] believed in the [[existence]] of four stages: [[birth]] (skt. [[jāti]] ), duration (skt. [[sthiti]] ), perishing (skt. [[jarā]] ) and [[cessation]] (skt. nāśā ). Contrary to these claims, the [[Sautrāntika]] believed in the [[existence]] of just two phases: [[birth]] (skt. [[utpāda]] ) and [[cessation]] (skt. [[vyaya]] ).  
 
   
 
   
4) Existence of past and future dharmas : the Sarvāstivādin upheld the theory of the existence not only of present dharmas , but also of past and future ones. By doing so, they dissociated the couple existence-efficiency: for the Theravādin and for the Sautrāntika, as a matter of fact, the existence of a dharma was determined on the ground of its efficiency, in other words on its presence. For the Sarvāstivādin, efficiency is a mark of presence, but not of  
+
4) [[Existence]] of {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}} [[dharmas]] : the [[Sarvāstivādin]] upheld the {{Wiki|theory}} of the [[existence]] not only of {{Wiki|present}} [[dharmas]] , but also of {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}} ones. By doing so, they dissociated the couple existence-efficiency: for the [[Theravādin]] and for the [[Sautrāntika]], as a {{Wiki|matter}} of fact, the [[existence]] of a [[dharma]] was determined on the ground of its efficiency, in other words on its presence. For the [[Sarvāstivādin]], efficiency is a mark of presence, but not of  
  
existence. Early Mahāsāṃghika, early Mahīśāsaka and the Vātsīputrīya mantained the existence of present dharmas only, as the Theravādin and Sautrāntika did. A position between these two standpoints was held by the Kāśyapīya, who believed in the existence of some past dharmas (the ones which still not bore fruit) and some future dharmas (the ones which will surely appear as a consequence of already performed actions – i.e. the fruits already established by the law of karma ). The late Mahāsāṃghika mantained the “possession” of past and future experiences in the present.  
+
[[existence]]. Early [[Mahāsāṃghika]], early [[Mahīśāsaka]] and the [[Vātsīputrīya]] mantained the [[existence]] of {{Wiki|present}} [[dharmas]] only, as the [[Theravādin]] and [[Sautrāntika]] did. A position between these two standpoints was held by the [[Kāśyapīya]], who believed in the [[existence]] of some {{Wiki|past}} [[dharmas]] (the ones which still not bore fruit) and some {{Wiki|future}} [[dharmas]] (the ones which will surely appear as a consequence of already performed [[actions]] – i.e. the {{Wiki|fruits}} already established by the [[law of karma]] ). The late [[Mahāsāṃghika]] mantained the “possession” of {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}} [[experiences]] in the {{Wiki|present}}.  
 
   
 
   
  
From this brief analysis we can infer a shift from a concept of impermanence which did not exclude a certain degree of duration to a law of momentariness which preserved duration for material dharmas only, to finally get to a radical theory of instantaneousness for both material and mental dharmas . In this context, reflections on some problems in the fields of epistemology and causality lead to the spread of several variations.  
+
From this brief analysis we can infer a shift from a {{Wiki|concept}} of [[impermanence]] which did not exclude a certain [[degree]] of duration to a law of [[momentariness]] which preserved duration for material [[dharmas]] only, to finally get to a radical {{Wiki|theory}} of instantaneousness for both material and [[mental]] [[dharmas]] . In this context, reflections on some problems in the fields of epistemology and [[causality]] lead to the spread of several variations.  
 
   
 
   
In contrast with the multiplicity of views concerning temporality , it seems to me that there was a general agreement between the early Buddhist schools about the status of time .6  Most of the schools of Abhidharma refused the concept of an absolute time having an ontological status independent from the beings contained in it. From their perspective, the time-container should be reduced to what it is commonly understood as contained in it: the beings.  
+
In contrast with the multiplicity of [[views]] concerning temporality , it seems to me that there was a general agreement between the [[early Buddhist schools]] about the {{Wiki|status}} of time .6  Most of the schools of [[Abhidharma]] refused the {{Wiki|concept}} of an [[absolute]] time having an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|status}} {{Wiki|independent}} from the [[beings]] contained in it. From their {{Wiki|perspective}}, the time-container should be reduced to what it is commonly understood as contained in it: the [[beings]].  
  
Therefore time was not considered to be an eternal substance; it was not understood as an ontological receptacle divided in three segments (past, present and future). Schayer claims that Buddhism, originally, maintained a theory of a spatialized time-container, and afterwards abandoned this view to espouse the ‘reductionist’ theory elaborated by the schools of Abhidharma.7 But Schayer himself affirms that his opinion is nothing more than a hypothesis, and admits that it is a hard task to give a definitive answer to the question.  
+
Therefore time was not considered to be an [[eternal substance]]; it was not understood as an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] receptacle divided in three segments ({{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|present}} and {{Wiki|future}}). Schayer claims that [[Buddhism]], originally, maintained a {{Wiki|theory}} of a spatialized time-container, and afterwards abandoned this view to espouse the ‘reductionist’ {{Wiki|theory}} elaborated by the schools of Abhidharma.7 But Schayer himself affirms that his opinion is nothing more than a {{Wiki|hypothesis}}, and admits that it is a hard task to give a definitive answer to the question.  
  
  
See note 1. 7 Schayer 1938:15. I define ‘reductionist’ a theory which claims that the time-container should be reduced to its content. In this perspective, time is not considered as a real and independent substance.  
+
See note 1. 7 Schayer 1938:15. I define ‘reductionist’ a {{Wiki|theory}} which claims that the time-container should be reduced to its content. In this {{Wiki|perspective}}, time is not considered as a real and {{Wiki|independent}} [[substance]].  
  
Sinha, opposing to Schayer’s opinion, argues: “[...] a reservoir ideal of Time is totally alien to the basic Buddhist ontological framework, and it is very implausible to attribute it even to the pre-Ābhidhārmika Buddhism”.8 I tend to agree with Sinha’s argument. The principle on non-duality of beings and time could be considered the basic and foundamental standpoint which usually marks the distinction between Buddhist and nonBuddhist systems.9 Nevertheless, this  
+
[[Sinha]], opposing to Schayer’s opinion, argues: “[...] a reservoir {{Wiki|ideal}} of Time is totally alien to the basic [[Buddhist]] [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] framework, and it is very implausible to attribute it even to the pre-Ābhidhārmika Buddhism”.8 I tend to agree with Sinha’s argument. The [[principle]] on [[non-duality]] of [[beings]] and time could be considered the basic and foundamental standpoint which usually marks the {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[Buddhist]] and nonBuddhist systems.9 Nevertheless, this  
  
does not mean that there were no Buddhists claiming the independent and real existence of an absolute time. In this sense I agree with Schayer, who states that “[...] there is no general Buddhist theory of Time accepted by all schools and sects. If therefore we characterize Buddhists as antagonists of the kālavāda , then even this characterization will be correct only in reference to some school belonging, it is true, to the most representative ones”.10  
+
does not mean that there were no [[Buddhists]] claiming the {{Wiki|independent}} and [[real existence]] of an [[absolute]] time. In this [[sense]] I agree with Schayer, who states that “[...] there is no general [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of Time accepted by all schools and sects. If therefore we characterize [[Buddhists]] as {{Wiki|antagonists}} of the kālavāda , then even this characterization will be correct only in reference to some school belonging, it is true, to the most representative ones”.10  
 
   
 
   
  
Line 84: Line 82:
 
   
 
   
  
For the sake of clarity, it would be necessary to give a detailed account of the ontology of the Sarvāstivāda School, as the interpretation of its teachings became source of confusion and polemic between great scholars. Unfortunately, I have not enough space here to treat it in a proper way. Therefore  
+
For the [[sake]] of clarity, it would be necessary to give a detailed account of the {{Wiki|ontology}} of the [[Sarvāstivāda School]], as the [[interpretation]] of its teachings became source of [[confusion]] and polemic between great [[scholars]]. Unfortunately, I have not enough [[space]] here to treat it in a proper way. Therefore  
  
I will just illustrate the controversial point, and give my opinion about.  Some foundamental misreadings of the Sarvāstivāda doctrine known as the ‘everything exist’ (skt. s a r v a m a sti ) theory lead scholars like  8 Sinha 1983:93. 9 For a comparison between Vaiśeṣika and Mīmāṃsaka’s Kālavāda doctrines and early Buddhist systems, see Schayer 1938:1-27. 10 Schayer 1938:14.   
+
I will just illustrate the controversial point, and give my opinion about.  Some foundamental misreadings of the [[Sarvāstivāda]] [[doctrine]] known as the ‘everything [[exist]]’ (skt. s a r v a m a sti ) {{Wiki|theory}} lead [[scholars]] like  8 [[Sinha]] 1983:93. 9 For a comparison between [[Vaiśeṣika]] and Mīmāṃsaka’s Kālavāda [[doctrines]] and early [[Buddhist]] systems, see Schayer 1938:1-27. 10 Schayer 1938:14.   
  
  
Kalupahana, Stambaugh, Koller and Williams to believe that the Sarvāstivādins were upholders of the existence of the Three Times (past, present and future).11 These scholars have probably been deceived by the sources they referred to. Some of them relied on a text which does not belong to the Sarvāstivāda tradition, but to a rival one, without questioning it. Kalupahana, for instance, reports that in the Kathāvatthu , during a debate with the  
+
[[Kalupahana]], Stambaugh, Koller and [[Williams]] to believe that the [[Sarvāstivādins]] were upholders of the [[existence]] of the Three Times ({{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|present}} and future).11 These [[scholars]] have probably been deceived by the sources they referred to. Some of them relied on a text which does not belong to the [[Sarvāstivāda]] [[tradition]], but to a rival one, without questioning it. [[Kalupahana]], for instance, reports that in the [[Kathāvatthu]] , during a [[debate]] with the  
  
  
Theravādins, the Sarvāstivādins admit the existence of the Three Times as independent realities.12 But the Kathāvatthu is a Theravāda text, and therefore we cannot rely on it if we aim to understand Sarvāstivāda’s doctrines. As Prasad points out, Theravādins’ criticism of Sarvāstivāda thought reveals that they have not properly understood their rivals’ doctrine.13 Scholars who draw their conclusion by examining Sarvāstivāda’s texts, such as the Mahāvibāṣā ,  
+
[[Theravādins]], the [[Sarvāstivādins]] admit the [[existence]] of the Three Times as {{Wiki|independent}} realities.12 But the [[Kathāvatthu]] is a [[Theravāda]] text, and therefore we cannot rely on it if we aim to understand Sarvāstivāda’s [[doctrines]]. As [[Prasad]] points out, [[Theravādins]]’ [[criticism]] of [[Sarvāstivāda]] [[thought]] reveals that they have not properly understood their rivals’ doctrine.13 [[Scholars]] who draw their conclusion by examining Sarvāstivāda’s texts, such as the Mahāvibāṣā ,  
  
were often confused by the ambiguous use of the word ‘ avasthā ’ (usually translated as ‘position’) in Vasumitra’s version of the sarvam asti doctrine.14 In this regard, Sinha claims: “[The term avasthā ] has both spatial and temporal connotations. Avasthā can be translated both as ‘a state of affair’ or ‘a time span in the personal history’   
+
were often confused by the {{Wiki|ambiguous}} use of the [[word]] [[avasthā]] ’ (usually translated as ‘position’) in [[Vasumitra’s]] version of the [[sarvam asti]] doctrine.14 In this regard, [[Sinha]] claims: “[The term [[avasthā]] ] has both spatial and {{Wiki|temporal}} connotations. [[Avasthā]] can be translated both as ‘a [[state]] of affair’ or ‘a time span in the personal history’   
  
  
Stambaugh (1974:132), Koller (1974:204-5) and Williams (1977:288). Stambaugh states that Sarvāstivādins claim “that all three times exist”, and that they “all are real”. Williams rectifies his own statements in a following work, maintaining that Sarvāstivādins believed in the existence of past, present and future dharmas , and did not believe in the existence of the Three Times. He rightly claims that the sarvam asti doctrine has noting to do with the problem  
+
Stambaugh (1974:132), Koller (1974:204-5) and [[Williams]] (1977:288). Stambaugh states that [[Sarvāstivādins]] claim “that all three times [[exist]]”, and that they “all are real”. [[Williams]] rectifies his [[own]] statements in a following work, maintaining that [[Sarvāstivādins]] believed in the [[existence]] of {{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|present}} and {{Wiki|future}} [[dharmas]] , and did not believe in the [[existence]] of the Three Times. He rightly claims that the [[sarvam asti]] [[doctrine]] has noting to do with the problem  
  
of the ontological status of time (Williams 2000:259). 12 Kalupahana 1974:187. 13 Prasad 1988:107. 14 Both the Mahāvibāṣā and l’ Abhidharmakośabhāṣya indicate Vasumitra’s interpretation ( Avasthā-anyathātva ) as the orthodox version of Sarvāstivāda’s doctrine. The other three reported versions are Dharmatrāta’s Bhāvānyathātva , Ghoṣaka’s Lakṣaṇa-anyathātva and Buddhadeva’s Anyathā-anyathika .  
+
of the [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|status}} of time ([[Williams]] 2000:259). 12 [[Kalupahana]] 1974:187. 13 [[Prasad]] 1988:107. 14 Both the Mahāvibāṣā and l’ [[Abhidharmakośabhāṣya]] indicate [[Vasumitra’s]] [[interpretation]] ( Avasthā-anyathātva ) as the [[orthodox]] version of Sarvāstivāda’s [[doctrine]]. The other three reported versions are Dharmatrāta’s Bhāvānyathātva , Ghoṣaka’s Lakṣaṇa-anyathātva and [[Buddhadeva’s]] Anyathā-anyathika .  
  
of an entity. A spatial rendering or interpretation of the term Avasthā in the passages of the Mahāvibāṣā [...] seems to have obscured a proper appraisal of Ābhidhārmic conception of temporal determinations”.15 In fact, the spatial rendering of the term ‘ avasthā ’ lead these scholars to believe that the  
+
of an [[entity]]. A spatial rendering or [[interpretation]] of the term [[Avasthā]] in the passages of the Mahāvibāṣā [...] seems to have obscured a proper appraisal of Ābhidhārmic {{Wiki|conception}} of {{Wiki|temporal}} determinations”.15 In fact, the spatial rendering of the term ‘ [[avasthā]] ’ lead these [[scholars]] to believe that the  
  
sarvam asti doctrine involves the idea of dharmas floating through the Three Times. However, if we examine the Mahāvibāṣā and the other Sarvāstivāda texts available to us, we do not find any statement supporting the theory of the existence of the Three Times. On the contrary, we find a clear refusal of it: “The Vibhajyavādins  
+
[[sarvam asti]] [[doctrine]] involves the [[idea]] of [[dharmas]] floating through the Three Times. However, if we examine the Mahāvibāṣā and the other [[Sarvāstivāda]] texts available to us, we do not find any statement supporting the {{Wiki|theory}} of the [[existence]] of the Three Times. On the contrary, we find a clear refusal of it: “The [[Vibhajyavādins]]
  
maintain that the nature of time is permanent and the nature of phenomena is impermanent; they claim that phenomena move from one time to another, like a fruit transferred from a basket to another, or like a person who moves from an house to another; they believe that in the same way phenomena move from the future to the present, and from the present to the past. In order to counter their views, we reveal that the nature of time is not different from the  
+
maintain that the [[nature]] of time is [[permanent]] and the [[nature]] of [[phenomena]] is [[impermanent]]; they claim that [[phenomena]] move from one time to another, like a fruit transferred from a basket to another, or like a [[person]] who moves from an house to another; they believe that in the same way [[phenomena]] move from the {{Wiki|future}} to the {{Wiki|present}}, and from the {{Wiki|present}} to the {{Wiki|past}}. In order to counter their [[views]], we reveal that the [[nature]] of time is not different from the  
  
nature of phenomena. In reality, time is phenomena and phenomena are nothing but time”.16 It is therefore clear that the purpose of the sarvam asti doctrine was not to investigate the possible existence of time as an independent reality or its threefold division in past, present and future. Time as an ontological category is not part of Sarvāstivāda’s system.  
+
[[nature]] of [[phenomena]]. In [[reality]], time is [[phenomena]] and [[phenomena]] are nothing but time”.16 It is therefore clear that the {{Wiki|purpose}} of the [[sarvam asti]] [[doctrine]] was not to investigate the possible [[existence]] of time as an {{Wiki|independent}} [[reality]] or its threefold [[division]] in {{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|present}} and {{Wiki|future}}. Time as an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] category is not part of Sarvāstivāda’s system.  
 
   
 
   
The Sarvāstivādins postulated the existence of dharmas as past, present and future, not in the past, in the present and in the future.17 Past, present                                            15 Sinha 1983:126. 16 「如譬喩者分別論師。彼作是説。世體是常行體無常。行行世時如器中果。從此器出轉
+
The [[Sarvāstivādins]] postulated the [[existence]] of [[dharmas]] as {{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|present}} and {{Wiki|future}}, not in the {{Wiki|past}}, in the {{Wiki|present}} and in the future.17 Past, {{Wiki|present}}                                             15 [[Sinha]] 1983:126. 16 「如譬喩者分別論師。彼作是説。世體是常行體無常。行行世時如器中果。從此器出轉
  
入彼器 。亦如多人從此 舍出轉入 彼舍。諸行亦爾。從未來 世入現在世。從現在世入 過去 世。爲止彼意顯世與行體無差別。謂世即行行即是世」(Taishō Shinshū Daizōkyō  1545 393a11-16). 17 Sinha 1983:91.  
+
入彼器 。亦如多人從此 舍出轉入 彼舍。諸行亦爾。從未來 世入現在世。從現在世入 過去 世。爲止彼意顯世與行體無差別。謂世即行行即是世」(Taishō [[Shinshū]] [[Daizōkyō]] 1545 393a11-16). 17 [[Sinha]] 1983:91.  
  
and future are not self-existent distinct realms containing  
+
and {{Wiki|future}} are not [[self-existent]] {{Wiki|distinct}} [[realms]] containing  
dharmas . Consequently, it seems to me completely misleading to describe them both as kālavādin (upholders of the real and independent existence of time) and as traikālyavādin (upholders of the real and independent existence of the Three Times).  
+
[[dharmas]] . Consequently, it seems to me completely misleading to describe them both as kālavādin (upholders of the real and {{Wiki|independent}} [[existence]] of time) and as traikālyavādin (upholders of the real and {{Wiki|independent}} [[existence]] of the Three Times).  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
Line 120: Line 118:
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
Nāgārjuna’s standpoint concerning time is expounded in chapter XIX of his Mūlamadhyamakakārikā , called “Examination of Time” (skt. Kālaparikṣa ).18 His criticism of time is grounded on the fact that the Three Times are dependent on each other by definition. As two beings have to be coexistent to be dependent on each other, if the present and the future are dependent on the past, so they should be in the past, existing contemporaneously with the past.  
+
[[Nāgārjuna’s]] standpoint concerning time is expounded in [[chapter]] XIX of his [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] , called “Examination of Time” (skt. Kālaparikṣa ).18 His [[criticism]] of time is grounded on the fact that the Three Times are dependent on each other by [[definition]]. As two [[beings]] have to be coexistent to be dependent on each other, if the {{Wiki|present}} and the {{Wiki|future}} are dependent on the {{Wiki|past}}, so they should be in the {{Wiki|past}}, [[existing]] contemporaneously with the {{Wiki|past}}.  
  
It is not possible to define the present and the future independently by the past: the Three Times could exist only if reciprocally correlated. Therefore, without present, there are not past and future; without future, there are not past and present; without past, there are not present and future. The Three Times should be co-existent, otherwise they could not exist. Nevertheless, past, present and future cannot exist simultaneously by their very nature: past and future are distinguished by the fact that they are  
+
It is not possible to define the {{Wiki|present}} and the {{Wiki|future}} {{Wiki|independently}} by the {{Wiki|past}}: the Three Times could [[exist]] only if reciprocally correlated. Therefore, without {{Wiki|present}}, there are not {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}}; without {{Wiki|future}}, there are not {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|present}}; without {{Wiki|past}}, there are not {{Wiki|present}} and {{Wiki|future}}. The Three Times should be co-existent, otherwise they could not [[exist]]. Nevertheless, {{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|present}} and {{Wiki|future}} cannot [[exist]] simultaneously by their very [[nature]]: {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}} are {{Wiki|distinguished}} by the fact that they are  
  
  
before and after the present now. If the past would be present, it would not be past. The same apply for any of the other combinations. As the Three Times can be neither independent nor co-existent, their existence is conceptual, it is not real.19 As the Three Times are not existent in themselves, the theory of time as an ontological reality, receptacle of change, is refused. To whom is addressed the criticism of Nāgārjuna? It is a common opinion that his intention was to confute the “everything exists” doctrine held by the Sarvāstivādin. Kalupahana, for instance, states that “there is no doubt that it was  
+
before and after the {{Wiki|present}} now. If the {{Wiki|past}} would be {{Wiki|present}}, it would not be {{Wiki|past}}. The same apply for any of the other combinations. As the Three Times can be neither {{Wiki|independent}} nor co-existent, their [[existence]] is {{Wiki|conceptual}}, it is not real.19 As the Three Times are not [[existent]] in themselves, the {{Wiki|theory}} of time as an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] [[reality]], receptacle of change, is refused. To whom is addressed the [[criticism]] of [[Nāgārjuna]]? It is a common opinion that his [[intention]] was to confute the “everything [[exists]]” [[doctrine]] held by the [[Sarvāstivādin]]. [[Kalupahana]], for instance, states that “there is no [[doubt]] that it was  
  
the Sarvāstivāda conception of time which drew the criticism from Nāgārjuna”.20 Koller, following Kalupahana, affirms that Nāgārjuna’s analysis of time is “directed primarily at the Sarvāstivādin, who took time to be an ontological container of change and divided the container into three segments: past, present, and future”.21 Nāgārjuna’s criticism was clearly directed toward the idea of a tripartite time-container, receptacle of change.22 However, I cannot agree with Koller in attributing this theory to the Sarvāstivādin, for the simple reason that, as I demonstrated above, they never claimed the real existence of an independent time-container. It is much more likely that Nāgārjuna was  
+
the [[Sarvāstivāda]] {{Wiki|conception}} of time which drew the [[criticism]] from Nāgārjuna”.20 Koller, following [[Kalupahana]], affirms that [[Nāgārjuna’s]] analysis of time is “directed primarily at the [[Sarvāstivādin]], who took time to be an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] container of change and divided the container into three segments: {{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|present}}, and future”.21 [[Nāgārjuna’s]] [[criticism]] was clearly directed toward the [[idea]] of a tripartite time-container, receptacle of change.22 However, I cannot agree with Koller in attributing this {{Wiki|theory}} to the [[Sarvāstivādin]], for the simple [[reason]] that, as I demonstrated above, they never claimed the [[real existence]] of an {{Wiki|independent}} time-container. It is much more likely that [[Nāgārjuna]] was  
 
              
 
              
There is a great resemblance between the arguments of Nāgārjuna and Buddhadeva regarding the relativity of the words “past”, “present” and “future” (see Williams 1977:2801). 20 Kalupahana 1974:187. 21 In the same article, Koller even claims that Nāgārjuna’s intention was only to negate Sarvāstivādin’s views, not to negate the reality of Time (Koller 1974:204-5). 22 A first evidence for this claim is the term used by Nāgārjuna to indicate “time”: kāla .  
+
There is a great resemblance between the arguments of [[Nāgārjuna]] and [[Buddhadeva]] regarding the [[relativity]] of the words “{{Wiki|past}}”, “{{Wiki|present}}” and “{{Wiki|future}}” (see [[Williams]] 1977:2801). 20 [[Kalupahana]] 1974:187. 21 In the same article, Koller even claims that [[Nāgārjuna’s]] [[intention]] was only to negate Sarvāstivādin’s [[views]], not to negate the [[reality]] of Time (Koller 1974:204-5). 22 A first {{Wiki|evidence}} for this claim is the term used by [[Nāgārjuna]] to indicate “time”: [[kāla]] .  
  
The word kāla usually refers to time as an eternal substance. It rarely appears in Buddhist texts, but when it does appear it is mainly used for its secondary meaning of “opportune time”, an “appropriate” or “convenient moment”.  
+
The [[word]] [[kāla]] usually refers to time as an [[eternal substance]]. It rarely appears in [[Buddhist texts]], but when it does appear it is mainly used for its secondary meaning of “opportune time”, an “appropriate” or “convenient [[moment]]”.  
  
arguing against a school which maintained the substantial reality of time, maybe the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika.23 In Stcherbatsky’s view “Les réflexions de Nāgārjuna sur le temps ne représentent aucune théorie. Ce n’est que l’application, au sujet du temps, d’une méthode dialectique négative , qui reste toujours la même, peu importe l’object auquel elle est appliquée”.24 To a certain extent, it is true that Nāgārjuna does not suggest any theory about time. His  
+
arguing against a school which maintained the substantial [[reality]] of time, maybe the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika.23 In Stcherbatsky’s view “Les réflexions de [[Nāgārjuna]] sur le temps ne représentent aucune théorie. Ce n’est que l’application, au sujet du temps, d’une méthode dialectique négative , qui reste toujours la même, peu importe l’object auquel elle est appliquée”.24 To a certain extent, it is true that [[Nāgārjuna]] does not suggest any {{Wiki|theory}} about time. His  
  
negative approach seems to be nothing more than a reductio ad absurdum of the time-container theory. Nevertheless, though Nāgārjuna himself claims to have no opinion (skt. pratijña ) to demonstrate,25 he describes himself as a śūnyatāvādin ,26 an upholder of the doctrine of emptiness (skt. śūnyatā ). In my opinion, it is through the standpoint  
+
negative approach seems to be nothing more than a {{Wiki|reductio ad absurdum}} of the time-container {{Wiki|theory}}. Nevertheless, though [[Nāgārjuna]] himself claims to have no opinion (skt. pratijña ) to demonstrate,25 he describes himself as a śūnyatāvādin ,26 an upholder of the [[doctrine of emptiness]] (skt. [[śūnyatā]] ). In my opinion, it is through the standpoint  
  
of emptiness that we can correctly evaluate his criticism of time, and understand his teaching. Nāgārjuna criticized the concept of a self-existent time-container, as most of Abhidharma’s schools did, in clu din g S a r v ā stiv ā d a . As Miyamoto suggests, Nāgārjuna agrees with the Sarvāstivādin in refuting the existence of a time-container, but opposing to the concept of “selfexistence” (skt. svabhāva ) introduced by them, he draws his conclusions  
+
of [[emptiness]] that we can correctly evaluate his [[criticism]] of time, and understand his [[teaching]]. [[Nāgārjuna]] criticized the {{Wiki|concept}} of a [[self-existent]] time-container, as most of [[Abhidharma’s]] schools did, in clu din g S a r v ā stiv ā d a . As Miyamoto suggests, [[Nāgārjuna]] agrees with the [[Sarvāstivādin]] in refuting the [[existence]] of a time-container, but opposing to the {{Wiki|concept}} of “selfexistence” (skt. [[svabhāva]] ) introduced by them, he draws his conclusions  
  
through the negation of substantiality (skt. niḥsvabhāva ), re-establishing Buddha’s teaching of no-self.27 Sinha, holding the same opinion, mantains: “It is conceivable that Nāgārjuna would have opposed the Sarvāstivādin articulation of temporality in terms of the svabhāva of a dharma . But no explicit rejection of Sarvāstivāda can be discerned in the Kālaparikṣa, nor  For an analysis of the concept of time in the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika, see Prasad 1984. 24 Stcherbatsky 1926:32-3. 25 Vigraha Vyāvartanī, stanza 29 (Nāgārjuna 1979:147). 26 Vigraha Vyāvartanī, stanza 70 (Nāgārjuna 1979:156). 27 Miyamoto 1959:9.  
+
through the {{Wiki|negation}} of substantiality (skt. [[niḥsvabhāva]] ), re-establishing [[Buddha’s teaching]] of no-self.27 [[Sinha]], holding the same opinion, mantains: “It is conceivable that [[Nāgārjuna]] would have opposed the [[Sarvāstivādin]] articulation of temporality in terms of the [[svabhāva]] of a [[dharma]] . But no explicit rejection of [[Sarvāstivāda]] can be discerned in the Kālaparikṣa, nor  For an analysis of the [[concept of time]] in the [[Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika]], see [[Prasad]] 1984. 24 [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] 1926:32-3. 25 [[Vigraha]] Vyāvartanī, [[stanza]] 29 ([[Nāgārjuna]] 1979:147). 26 [[Vigraha]] Vyāvartanī, [[stanza]] 70 ([[Nāgārjuna]] 1979:156). 27 Miyamoto 1959:9.  
  
is there any claim that Sarvāstivādin believed in the indipendent reality status of time”.28  
+
is there any claim that [[Sarvāstivādin]] believed in the indipendent [[reality]] {{Wiki|status}} of time”.28  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
Line 147: Line 145:
 
   
 
   
  
Through the present essay I illustrated the development of the concept of time and temporality in Indian Buddhism. It seems evident a shift from the epistemological perspective of the sūtrapiṭaka to the Abhidharmikas’ ontological approach in the analysis of the nature of existence. This shift corresponds to a gradual development of the teaching of impermanence, which came to be understood as a law of instantaneousness. The several standpoints of  
+
Through the {{Wiki|present}} essay I illustrated the [[development]] of the [[concept of time]] and temporality in [[Indian Buddhism]]. It seems evident a shift from the [[epistemological]] {{Wiki|perspective}} of the sūtrapiṭaka to the [[Abhidharmikas]]’ [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] approach in the analysis of the [[nature]] of [[existence]]. This shift corresponds to a [[gradual]] [[development]] of the [[teaching]] of [[impermanence]], which came to be understood as a law of instantaneousness. The several standpoints of  
  
the Abhidharma schools regarding temporality fairly represent the different stages of this development. In contrast with the multiplicity of views concerning temporality , the general agreement between the schools about the status of time is striking. The refusal of the idea of a substantive tripartite time receptacle containing floating beings seems to be one of the main marks which characterize the dinstinction between Buddhist and non-
+
the [[Abhidharma]] schools regarding temporality fairly represent the different stages of this [[development]]. In contrast with the multiplicity of [[views]] concerning temporality , the general agreement between the schools about the {{Wiki|status}} of time is striking. The refusal of the [[idea]] of a substantive tripartite time receptacle containing floating [[beings]] seems to be one of the main marks which characterize the dinstinction between [[Buddhist]] and non-
  
Buddhist systems. There are, of course, some exceptions to this general statement, but the small number of those exceptions leads me to the conclusion that probably even preAbhidharmikas rejected the duality of beings and time.  
+
[[Buddhist]] systems. There are, of course, some exceptions to this general statement, but the small number of those exceptions leads me to the conclusion that probably even preAbhidharmikas rejected the [[duality]] of [[beings]] and time.  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
  
 
   
 
   
===Bibliography===  
+
===[[Bibliography]]===  
 
   
 
   
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
Aung, S. Z., Davids, R., Points of Controversy, or Subjects of Discourse, b ein g a tr a n sla tio n of th e K a th ā - v a tth u fr o m th e A b hidhamma-pitaka Oxford University Press Warehouse, 1915.  
+
[[Aung]], S. Z., Davids, R., [[Points of Controversy]], or [[Subjects]] of [[Discourse]], b ein g a tr a n sla tio n of th e K a th ā - v a tth u fr o m th e A b hidhamma-pitaka [[Oxford University Press]] Warehouse, 1915.  
 
   
 
   
Bareau, André, “The Notion of Time in Early Buddhism”, East and West , 7, n. 4 (1957), pp. 353-64.  
+
Bareau, André, “The Notion of Time in [[Early Buddhism]]”, [[East]] and [[West]] , 7, n. 4 (1957), pp. 353-64.  
 
   
 
   
Conze, Edward, Buddhist Thought in India , London, George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1962.  
+
{{Wiki|Conze}}, Edward, [[Buddhist]] [[Thought]] in [[India]] , [[London]], George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1962.  
 
   
 
   
Coomaraswamy, Ānanda K.,  
+
[[Coomaraswamy]], [[Ānanda]] K.,  
 
Tempo ed Eternità , Milano, Luni Editrice,  
 
Tempo ed Eternità , Milano, Luni Editrice,  
 
2003.  
 
2003.  
 
   
 
   
Das, S.R., “Notion of Time in Hindu Philosophy”,  
+
Das, S.R., “Notion of Time in {{Wiki|Hindu Philosophy}}”,  
 
In dia n Histo ric al  
 
In dia n Histo ric al  
 
Quarterly , 9 (1933), pp. 149-53.  
 
Quarterly , 9 (1933), pp. 149-53.  
 
   
 
   
Davids, T. W. Rhys, The questions of King Milinda , ed. By F. Max Müller, Sacred Books of the East, vol. XXXV, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1890.  
+
Davids, T. W. Rhys, The questions of [[King Milinda]] , ed. By F. {{Wiki|Max Müller}}, [[Sacred Books of the East]], vol. XXXV, [[Oxford]], Clarendon Press, 1890.  
 
   
 
   
Fuji, Kenkyo (藤 謙敬), “Time Theory of Nāgārjuna” (龍樹哲學の時間論), Annual Report of Nihon Butsugakuin (日本佛學院), 1940, pp. 159-208.  
+
{{Wiki|Fuji}}, Kenkyo (藤 謙敬), “Time {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Nāgārjuna]]” (龍樹哲學の時間論), Annual Report of [[Nihon]] Butsugakuin (日本佛學院), 1940, pp. 159-208.  
 
   
 
   
  
Garfield, Jay L., The fundamental wisdom of the middle way: Nāgārjuna ’s Mūlamadhyamakakārikā , translation and commentary by Jay L. Garfield, New York, Oxford University Press, 1995.  
+
Garfield, Jay L., The [[fundamental wisdom of the middle way]]: [[Nāgārjuna]] ’s [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikā]] , translation and commentary by [[Jay L. Garfield]], [[New York]], [[Oxford University Press]], 1995.  
 
   
 
   
Gupta, Rita, “The Buddhist Doctrine of Momentariness and its Presupposition: Dharmakīrti’s Arguments in Hetubindu”, J o u r n al of In dia n Philosophy , 8 (1980), pp.47-68.  
+
[[Gupta]], Rita, “The [[Buddhist Doctrine]] of [[Momentariness]] and its Presupposition: [[Dharmakīrti’s]] Arguments in [[Hetubindu]]”, J o u r n al of In dia n [[Philosophy]] , 8 (1980), pp.47-68.  
 
   
 
   
Inada, Kenneth K., “Time and temporality – A Buddhist approach”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 171-179.  
+
Inada, Kenneth K., “Time and temporality – A [[Buddhist]] approach”, [[Philosophy East and West]] , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 171-179.  
 
   
 
   
Jha, G.N. (trad.), “Examination of the doctrine of ‘Traikālya’ – Things continuing to exist during three points of Time”, The Tattvasaṃgraha of Ś ā n ta r a k ṣita with th e C o m m e n ta r y o f K a m ala śīla , Oriental Institute, Baroda, 1939, Vol. II, pp. 861-86.  
+
Jha, G.N. (trad.), “Examination of the [[doctrine]] of ‘Traikālya’ – Things continuing to [[exist]] during three points of Time”, The [[Tattvasaṃgraha]] of Ś ā n ta r a k ṣita with th e C o m m e n ta r y o f K a m ala [[śīla]] , [[Oriental Institute]], Baroda, 1939, Vol. II, pp. 861-86.  
 
   
 
   
Kalupahana, David J., “The Buddhist conception of time and temporality”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 181-191.  
+
[[Kalupahana]], David J., “The [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|conception}} of time and temporality”, [[Philosophy East and West]] , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 181-191.  
 
   
 
   
Keith, A.B., “The Doctrine of Reality (The Nature of Time)”,  
+
Keith, A.B., “The [[Doctrine]] of [[Reality]] (The [[Nature]] of Time)”,  
Buddhist  
+
[[Buddhist Philosophy]] in [[India]] and [[Ceylon]] , [[Oxford University Press]], 1923, pp. 163-68.  
Philosophy in India and Ceylon , Oxford University Press, 1923, pp. 163-68.  
 
 
   
 
   
Koller, John M., “On Buddhist views of devouring time”,  
+
Koller, John M., “On [[Buddhist]] [[views]] of devouring time”,  
Philosophy East  
+
[[Philosophy East and West]] , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 201-8.  
and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 201-8.  
 
 
   
 
   
Lancaster, Lewis R., “Discussion of time in Mahāyāna texts”,  
+
[[Lancaster, Lewis]] R., “[[Discussion]] of time in [[Mahāyāna texts]]”,  
Philosophy  
+
[[Philosophy East and West]] , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 209-14.  
East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 209-14.  
 
 
   
 
   
  
La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, “La controverse de temps et du pudgala dans le Vijñānakāya”, Études Asiatiques (École Française d’Extrême-Orient ) , 1925, pp. 343-76.  
+
[[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|La Vallée Poussin]], Louis de, “La controverse de temps et du [[pudgala]] dans le [[Vijñānakāya]]”, Études Asiatiques (École Française d’Extrême-Orient ) , 1925, pp. 343-76.  
 
   
 
   
La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, L’Abhidharmakośa de Vasubandhu Chapter V ,
+
[[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|La Vallée Poussin]], Louis de, L’Abhidharmakośa de [[Vasubandhu]] [[Chapter]] V ,
Paul Geuthner, Paris, 1925, pp. 50-66.  
+
Paul Geuthner, {{Wiki|Paris}}, 1925, pp. 50-66.  
 
   
 
   
La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, “Notes sur le ‘moment’ ou kṣaṇa des bouddhistes”, Rocznik Orientalistyczny , 8 (1932), pp.1-9.  
+
[[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|La Vallée Poussin]], Louis de, “Notes sur le ‘[[moment]]’ ou [[kṣaṇa]] des bouddhistes”, Rocznik Orientalistyczny , 8 (1932), pp.1-9.  
 
   
 
   
La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, “Documents d’Abhidharma : la controverse du temps”, Mélanges chinois bouddhiques , 5 (1937), pp. 7-158.  
+
[[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|La Vallée Poussin]], Louis de, “Documents d’Abhidharma : la controverse du temps”, Mélanges chinois bouddhiques , 5 (1937), pp. 7-158.  
 
   
 
   
Loy, David, “The Mahāyāna Deconstruction of Time”, Philosophy East and West , 36, n.1 (January 1986), pp. 13-23.  
+
Loy, David, “The [[Mahāyāna]] Deconstruction of Time”, [[Philosophy East and West]] , 36, n.1 (January 1986), pp. 13-23.  
 
   
 
   
Loy, David, “Language Against Its Own Mystifications: Deconstruction in Nāgārjuna and Dōgen”, Philosophy East and West , 49, n.3 (July 1999), pp. 245-260.  
+
Loy, David, “[[Language]] Against Its [[Own]] Mystifications: Deconstruction in [[Nāgārjuna]] and [[Dōgen]]”, [[Philosophy East and West]] , 49, n.3 (July 1999), pp. 245-260.  
 
   
 
   
Masunaga, Reihō (増永 霊鳳), Bukkyō ni okeru Jikanron (佛教における時 間論), Tōkyō, Sankibō Busshorin, 1966.  
+
Masunaga, Reihō (増永 霊鳳), Bukkyō ni okeru Jikanron (佛教における時 間論), [[Tōkyō]], Sankibō Busshorin, 1966.  
 
   
 
   
McDermott, A. Charlene, “The Sautrāntika arguments against the traikālyavāda in the light of the contemporary tense revolution”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 193-200.  
+
McDermott, A. Charlene, “The [[Sautrāntika]] arguments against the traikālyavāda in the {{Wiki|light}} of the contemporary tense {{Wiki|revolution}}”, [[Philosophy East and West]] , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 193-200.  
 
   
 
   
McGovern, W.M., “Cosmic Synthesis”, A Manual of Buddhist Philosophy , London, 1923, pp. 43-48.  
+
McGovern, W.M., “[[Cosmic]] Synthesis”, [[A Manual of Buddhist Philosophy]] , [[London]], 1923, pp. 43-48.  
  
 
   
 
   
McKeon, Richard, “Time and temporality”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 123-128.  
+
McKeon, Richard, “Time and temporality”, [[Philosophy East and West]] , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 123-128.  
 
   
 
   
Miyamoto, Shoson, “Time and Eternity in Buddhism”, Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies , 7, n.2 (1959), pp. 3-18.  
+
Miyamoto, Shoson, “Time and {{Wiki|Eternity}} in [[Buddhism]]”, Journal of [[Indian]] and [[Buddhist Studies]] , 7, n.2 (1959), pp. 3-18.  
 
   
 
   
Mookerjee, Satkari, “The Buddhist Doctrine of Flux (The Nature of Existence)”, T h e B u d d hist P hilo s o p h y o f U niv e r s al Flu x , University of Calcutta, 1935, pp. 1-19.  
+
[[Mookerjee]], Satkari, “The [[Buddhist Doctrine]] of Flux (The [[Nature]] of [[Existence]])”, T h e B u d d hist P hilo s o p h y o f U niv e r s al Flu x , [[University of Calcutta]], 1935, pp. 1-19.  
 
   
 
   
Murti, T.R.V., The central philosophy of Buddhism , London, George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1955.   
+
[[Murti]], T.R.V., The central [[philosophy]] of [[Buddhism ]], [[London]], George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1955.   
 
   
 
   
Nāgārjuna,  
+
[[Nāgārjuna]],  
L e Sta n z e d el C a m min o di M e z z o ( M a d h y a m a k a K ā rik ā ) , introduzione, traduzione e note di Raniero Gnoli, Torino, Biblioteca Boringhieri, 1979.  
+
L e Sta n z e d el C a m min o di M e z z o ( M a d h y a m a k a K ā rik ā ) , introduzione, traduzione e note di [[Raniero Gnoli]], Torino, Biblioteca Boringhieri, 1979.  
 
   
 
   
Panikkar, Raimundo, “Toward a typology of time and temporality in the ancient Indian tradition”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 161-164.  
+
Panikkar, Raimundo, “Toward a [[typology]] of time and temporality in the {{Wiki|ancient Indian}} [[tradition]]”, [[Philosophy East and West]] , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 161-164.  
 
   
 
   
Prasad, Hari Shankar, “Time and Change in Sāṁkya-Yoga”,  
+
[[Prasad]], [[Hari]] Shankar, “Time and Change in Sāṁkya-Yoga”,  
Journal of Indian Philosophy , 12 (March 1984), pp. 35-49.  
+
[[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] , 12 (March 1984), pp. 35-49.  
 
   
 
   
Prasad, Hari Shankar, “Time as Substantive Reality in Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika”, East and West , 34 (1984), pp. 233-66.  
+
[[Prasad]], [[Hari]] Shankar, “Time as Substantive [[Reality]] in [[Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika]]”, [[East]] and [[West]] , 34 (1984), pp. 233-66.  
 
   
 
   
  
Prasad, Hari Shankar, “The Concept of Time in Pali Buddhism”, East and West , 38 (1988), pp. 107-36.  
+
[[Prasad]], [[Hari]] Shankar, “The [[Concept of Time]] in [[Pali]] [[Buddhism]]”, [[East]] and [[West]] , 38 (1988), pp. 107-36.  
 
   
 
   
Prasad, Hari Shankar,  
+
[[Prasad]], [[Hari]] Shankar,  
Essays on Time in Buddhism , Bibliotheca Indobuddhica No. 78, Delhi, Sri Satguru Publications, 1991.  
+
Essays on [[Time in Buddhism]] , Bibliotheca Indobuddhica No. 78, [[Delhi]], [[Sri Satguru Publications]], 1991.  
 
   
 
   
Rahula, Walpola, What the Buddha Taught , Oneworld Publications, 1997.  
+
[[Rahula, Walpola]], What the [[Buddha]] [[Taught]] , Oneworld Publications, 1997.  
 
   
 
   
 
Ronkin, Noa,  
 
Ronkin, Noa,  
Early Buddhist metaphysics: the making of a philoso phical  
+
Early [[Buddhist metaphysics]]: the making of a philoso phical  
tradition , London, RoutledgeCurzon, 2005.  
+
[[tradition]] , [[London]], RoutledgeCurzon, 2005.  
 
   
 
   
Sasaki, Genjun H., “The Time Concept in Abhidharma”,  
+
[[Sasaki]], Genjun H., “The Time {{Wiki|Concept}} in [[Abhidharma]]”,  
 
Proceedings of  
 
Proceedings of  
the 26 th International Congress of Orientalists , New Delhi, 1964, pp. 47180.  
+
the 26 th International Congress of [[Orientalists]] , {{Wiki|New Delhi}}, 1964, pp. 47180.  
 
   
 
   
 
Schayer, Stanislaw,  
 
Schayer, Stanislaw,  
 
C o n trib u tio n s to th e P r o ble m of Tim e in In dia n  
 
C o n trib u tio n s to th e P r o ble m of Tim e in In dia n  
Philosophy , Krakow, Polski Builetyn Orientalistyczny,1938.  
+
[[Philosophy]] , Krakow, Polski Builetyn Orientalistyczny,1938.  
 
   
 
   
 
Silburn, Lilian,  
 
Silburn, Lilian,  
In sta n t e t C a u s e , L e Dis c o n tin u d a n s la P e n s é e Philosophique de l’Inde , Paris, De Boccard, 1989.  
+
In sta n t e t C a u s e , L e Dis c o n tin u d a n s la P e n s é e Philosophique de l’Inde , {{Wiki|Paris}}, De Boccard, 1989.  
 
   
 
   
Sinha, Braj Mohan,  
+
[[Sinha]], Braj Mohan,  
 
Tim e a n d T e m p o r ality in S ā ṁ k y a - Y o g a a n d  
 
Tim e a n d T e m p o r ality in S ā ṁ k y a - Y o g a a n d  
Abhidharma Buddhism , Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers Pvt. Ltd., 1983.  
+
[[Abhidharma]] [[Buddhism ]], Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers Pvt. Ltd., 1983.  
 
   
 
   
Stambaugh, Joan, “Time, finitude, and finality”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 129-35.
+
Stambaugh, Joan, “Time, finitude, and finality”, [[Philosophy East and West]] , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 129-35.
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky, Th., “Vasubandhu on the Fundamental Principle of the Sarvāstivāda School”, T h e C e ntr al C o n c e p tio n o f B u d d his m a n d th e  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]], Th., “[[Vasubandhu]] on the Fundamental [[Principle]] of the [[Sarvāstivāda School]]”, T h e C e ntr al C o n c e p tio n o f B u d d his m a n d th e  
  
Meaning of the Word “Dharma” , Royal Asiatique Society, London, 1923, pp. 76-91.  
+
Meaning of the [[Word]] “[[Dharma]]” , {{Wiki|Royal}} Asiatique [[Society]], [[London]], 1923, pp. 76-91.  
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky, Th., “Le temps (kāla)”, La théorie de la connaissance et la logique chez les bouddhistes tardifs , Librarie Orientaliste Paul Geuthner, Paris, 1926, pp. 12-39.  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]], Th., “Le temps ([[kāla]])”, La théorie de la connaissance et la logique chez les bouddhistes tardifs , Librarie Orientaliste Paul Geuthner, {{Wiki|Paris}}, 1926, pp. 12-39.  
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky, Th., “The Theory of Instantaneous Being (Kṣaṇabhaṅgavāda)”, B u d d hist L o gic , Dover Publications, New York, 1962, (First published by the Academy of sciences of the USSR, Leningrad, 1930), pp. 79-118.  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]], Th., “The {{Wiki|Theory}} of Instantaneous Being (Kṣaṇabhaṅgavāda)”, B u d d hist L o gic , Dover Publications, [[New York]], 1962, (First published by the {{Wiki|Academy}} of [[sciences]] of the {{Wiki|USSR}}, [[Wikipedia:Saint Petersburg|Leningrad]], 1930), pp. 79-118.  
 
   
 
   
 
Tamaki, Kōshirō (玉城 康四郎), “Bukkyō no Jikanron (仏教の時間論)”, Risō, 460 (September 1971), pp. 64-78.  
 
Tamaki, Kōshirō (玉城 康四郎), “Bukkyō no Jikanron (仏教の時間論)”, Risō, 460 (September 1971), pp. 64-78.  
 
   
 
   
Tu, Wei-Ming, “An introductory note on time and temporality”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 119-22.  
+
Tu, Wei-Ming, “An introductory note on time and temporality”, [[Philosophy East and West]] , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 119-22.  
 
   
 
   
Williams, Paul, “Buddhadeva and Temporality”,  
+
[[Williams]], Paul, “[[Buddhadeva]] and Temporality”,  
 
J o u r n al o f In dia n  
 
J o u r n al o f In dia n  
Philosophy , 4 (1977), pp. 279-94.  
+
[[Philosophy]] , 4 (1977), pp. 279-94.  
 
   
 
   
Williams, Paul,  
+
[[Williams]], Paul,  
Buddhist thought: a complete introduction to the In dian  
+
[[Buddhist]] [[thought]]: a complete introduction to the In dian  
tradition , London, Routledge, 2000.  
+
[[tradition]] , [[London]], Routledge, 2000.  
 
   
 
   
Williams, Paul, Mahāyāna Buddhism: the doctrinal foundations , 2nd edition, New York, Routledge, 2008.
+
[[Williams]], Paul, [[Mahāyāna Buddhism]]: the [[doctrinal]] foundations , 2nd edition, [[New York]], Routledge, 2008.
  
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
Line 297: Line 292:
 
{{R}}
 
{{R}}
 
[[Category:Buddhist Cosmology]]
 
[[Category:Buddhist Cosmology]]
 +
[[Category:Buddhism]]
 +
[[Category:Buddhist Philosophy]]

Latest revision as of 21:32, 1 February 2020




by Michel Gauvain


Introduction

It is not an easy task to give an outline of the origin and development of the concepts of time and temporality in Indian Buddhism.1 There are three main difficulties to face in pursuing this aim: first, the relatively late and frequently interpolated nature of the available sources makes it hard to state with confidence what the historical Buddha taught; second, in order to rebuild the philosophical systems of many of the following schools of Abhidharma we often have to piece together fragments of information extrapolated by texts which were produced by other schools, always questioning the correctness of their statements;

third, the problem of time was not always treated systematically, and therefore there is no other way than draw our conclusions by analysing related concepts such as impermanence, duration, motion, et cetera. Great scholars have examined the subject in depth, but the debate on many of the issues raised is still open, and a definitive solution seems to be still to come. With the present essay, I intend to give an outline of the different views on time and temporality developed in the context of Indian Buddhism, from the early teachings to Nāgārjuna’s Kālaparikṣa , in order to suggest a

It is essential to draw a clear distinction between the categories of time and temporality. While the word ‘time’ refers to an absolute time, ontologically independent from the beings, the word ‘temporality’ indicates change as a modality of phenomenal existence.

solution to the above mentioned problematic issues. Nevertheless, the extremely controversial nature of the topic leads me to keep far from claiming the absolute authority of my opinions.


Early teachings about the nature of existence

In the “Sūtra of the Turning the Wheel of the Dharma” (pāli Dhammacakkappavattana Sutta ), by exposing the first of the “Four Noble Truths” (pāli Cattāri Ariyasaccāni ), known as “The Truth of Dukkha ” (pāli Dukkha Ariyasaccā ), Śākyamuni Buddha gives the foundations for the following construction of a doctrine of time based on the impermanence (pāli anicca ; skt. anitya ) of each and every phenomenon.2 Then, in the “Great Sūtra on the Destruction of

Craving” (pāli Mahātaṇhāsaṅkhaya Sutta ), he indicates the three marks (skt. trilakṣaṇa ) which characterize all the phenomena of the saṃsāra : suffering (skt. duḥkha ), impermanence (skt. anitya ) and no-self (skt. anātman ). Everything is source of suffering for us, as we tend to feel desire and craving

for a world that is impermanent and has no stable substance. In other words, suffering is due to the illusory reification of temporal existence. It is caused by ignorance (skt. avidyā ), the unrecognition of the real character of existence. Existence is described as a ceaseless causal process, where any supposed stability is recognized as false, illusory, and therefore source of suffering.

Dependence by causes is the real structure of the universe: any phenomenon exists depending on its causes (skt. hetu ) and conditions (skt. pratyaya ). As the cause is impermanent, the effect (skt. phala ) will be impermanent as well. An impersonal law of causality defines relations between events: if X occurs, Y will follow; if X does not occur, Y will not follow (pāli “ imasmiṃ s a ti, id a ṃ h o ti, im a s miṃ a s a ti, id a ṃ n a h o ti ”). This is the so-called “Dependent Origination” (skt. pratītyasamutpāda ), the core of Buddha’s middlepath between eternalism and nihilism. The teachings outlined above represent the basic standpoints which enable us to analyse the development of the concepts of time and temporality in Early Buddhism.


Abhidharma schools’ views on time and temporality

Although the Buddha preached the law of impermanence, he never explained the extent and the modalities of this law. This was probably due to the fact that Buddha’s reflections about reality were directed toward the delineation of a soteriology: he did not intend to create an ontological system. On the contrary, the schools which developed during the first centuries after the Buddha’s demise needed to build up a well-defined ontological system to be able

to undertake positively the challenging debates with the representatives of the other Indian religious traditions, and to be ready to defend their views during the discussions between the various doctrinal currents arisen within Buddhism itself. These schools were in accord about the fundamental tenets of the Buddhist doctrine (Four Noble Thruths, Dependent Origination, No-self,

and Impermanence). Trying not to break these principles, they made their attempt to determine the extent of the law of impermanence. The clash of views that arose between the Abhidharma schools about temporality was very divisive, and the systems of thought that resulted from it were the most disparate.3 If we carefully consider the teachings of the Abhidharma schools it becomes clearly evident a shift in the understanding of the law of impermanence, from

an empirical realization of change to a radical ontology of instantaneousness. In fact, the various standpoints held by the Abhidharma schools seem to compose a spectrum between these two poles. This view is supported by Stambaugh and Kalupahana. They both argued that, although the textual sources do not allow us to make any certain assertion, it seems reasonable to believe that at the time of the Buddha and of his early followers the concept of

impermanence was still not carried to its logical extreme: instantaneism. Radical instantaneism, logical consequence of the law of impermanence, was probably established by Abhidharma’s thinkers.4 Stcherbatsky rejects this view. He believes the doctrine of instantaneous existence to be nothing but a restoration of the Buddha’s teaching of impermanence, a teaching which was affected by corruption after the master’s demise. He even suggests that this doctrine should be considered a pre-Buddhist inheritance.5 However, in absence of decisive evidences, the theory suggested by Stcherbatsky seems quite implausible.


Bareau (1957:364); Panikkar (1974:163). 4 Stambaugh 1974:132; Kalupahana 1974:184-185. 5 Stcherbatsky 1930:108. Coomaraswamy (2003:48) agrees with the opinion of Stcherbatsky, but at the same time criticizes Stcherbatsky’s understanding of the doctrine of instantaneousness.


It is possible to highlight the steps of the development of the concept of impermanence by analysing the most important points of controversy in the saṃgha regarding temporality:

1) Nature of impermanence: the Vātsīputrīya held that to state that things are impermanent does not mean that they should rise and disappear in one instant of thought. They admitted the existence of a certain degree of duration and motion (skt. gati ), and they even believed in the existence of a transmigrating “personality” (skt. pudgala ). In contrast, the Mahāsāṃghika, Mahīśāsaka, Kāśyapīya, Sarvāstivāda and Sautrāntika schools held an instantaneist doctrine, refusing to make any kind of distinction in degrees of impermanence.

2) Extent of the law of instantaneity: should radical instantaneism be applied only to mental phenomena, or even to the material world? The Theravāda and the Vātsīputrīya school maintained that the thought is instantaneous (skt. kṣaṇika ), while the matter, although does not last, is not instantaneous, but rather momentary (skt. anitya ). In other words, for these two schools the rhythm of appearance and disappearance was not the same for mental and material phenomena. The Theravādin even established a rate of conversion: in their views, one material instant corresponded to sixteen or seventeen mental instant. In contrast, the other schools affirmed the same identical impermanence for any conditioned dharma , without any dinstinction between mental and material dharmas .


3) Nature of the instant (skt. kṣaṇa ): after defining dharmas as instantaneous, taking in consideration that a dharma rise and disappear, the Theravādin argued that an instant should be divided in three moments: one for birth (pāli uppāda ), one for duration (pāli ṭhiti ), and one for cessation (pāli bhaṅga ). The Sarvāstivādin believed in the existence of four stages: birth (skt. jāti ), duration (skt. sthiti ), perishing (skt. jarā ) and cessation (skt. nāśā ). Contrary to these claims, the Sautrāntika believed in the existence of just two phases: birth (skt. utpāda ) and cessation (skt. vyaya ).

4) Existence of past and future dharmas : the Sarvāstivādin upheld the theory of the existence not only of present dharmas , but also of past and future ones. By doing so, they dissociated the couple existence-efficiency: for the Theravādin and for the Sautrāntika, as a matter of fact, the existence of a dharma was determined on the ground of its efficiency, in other words on its presence. For the Sarvāstivādin, efficiency is a mark of presence, but not of

existence. Early Mahāsāṃghika, early Mahīśāsaka and the Vātsīputrīya mantained the existence of present dharmas only, as the Theravādin and Sautrāntika did. A position between these two standpoints was held by the Kāśyapīya, who believed in the existence of some past dharmas (the ones which still not bore fruit) and some future dharmas (the ones which will surely appear as a consequence of already performed actions – i.e. the fruits already established by the law of karma ). The late Mahāsāṃghika mantained the “possession” of past and future experiences in the present.


From this brief analysis we can infer a shift from a concept of impermanence which did not exclude a certain degree of duration to a law of momentariness which preserved duration for material dharmas only, to finally get to a radical theory of instantaneousness for both material and mental dharmas . In this context, reflections on some problems in the fields of epistemology and causality lead to the spread of several variations.

In contrast with the multiplicity of views concerning temporality , it seems to me that there was a general agreement between the early Buddhist schools about the status of time .6 Most of the schools of Abhidharma refused the concept of an absolute time having an ontological status independent from the beings contained in it. From their perspective, the time-container should be reduced to what it is commonly understood as contained in it: the beings.

Therefore time was not considered to be an eternal substance; it was not understood as an ontological receptacle divided in three segments (past, present and future). Schayer claims that Buddhism, originally, maintained a theory of a spatialized time-container, and afterwards abandoned this view to espouse the ‘reductionist’ theory elaborated by the schools of Abhidharma.7 But Schayer himself affirms that his opinion is nothing more than a hypothesis, and admits that it is a hard task to give a definitive answer to the question.


See note 1. 7 Schayer 1938:15. I define ‘reductionist’ a theory which claims that the time-container should be reduced to its content. In this perspective, time is not considered as a real and independent substance.

Sinha, opposing to Schayer’s opinion, argues: “[...] a reservoir ideal of Time is totally alien to the basic Buddhist ontological framework, and it is very implausible to attribute it even to the pre-Ābhidhārmika Buddhism”.8 I tend to agree with Sinha’s argument. The principle on non-duality of beings and time could be considered the basic and foundamental standpoint which usually marks the distinction between Buddhist and nonBuddhist systems.9 Nevertheless, this

does not mean that there were no Buddhists claiming the independent and real existence of an absolute time. In this sense I agree with Schayer, who states that “[...] there is no general Buddhist theory of Time accepted by all schools and sects. If therefore we characterize Buddhists as antagonists of the kālavāda , then even this characterization will be correct only in reference to some school belonging, it is true, to the most representative ones”.10


A remark on Sarvāstivāda

For the sake of clarity, it would be necessary to give a detailed account of the ontology of the Sarvāstivāda School, as the interpretation of its teachings became source of confusion and polemic between great scholars. Unfortunately, I have not enough space here to treat it in a proper way. Therefore

I will just illustrate the controversial point, and give my opinion about. Some foundamental misreadings of the Sarvāstivāda doctrine known as the ‘everything exist’ (skt. s a r v a m a sti ) theory lead scholars like 8 Sinha 1983:93. 9 For a comparison between Vaiśeṣika and Mīmāṃsaka’s Kālavāda doctrines and early Buddhist systems, see Schayer 1938:1-27. 10 Schayer 1938:14.


Kalupahana, Stambaugh, Koller and Williams to believe that the Sarvāstivādins were upholders of the existence of the Three Times (past, present and future).11 These scholars have probably been deceived by the sources they referred to. Some of them relied on a text which does not belong to the Sarvāstivāda tradition, but to a rival one, without questioning it. Kalupahana, for instance, reports that in the Kathāvatthu , during a debate with the


Theravādins, the Sarvāstivādins admit the existence of the Three Times as independent realities.12 But the Kathāvatthu is a Theravāda text, and therefore we cannot rely on it if we aim to understand Sarvāstivāda’s doctrines. As Prasad points out, Theravādinscriticism of Sarvāstivāda thought reveals that they have not properly understood their rivals’ doctrine.13 Scholars who draw their conclusion by examining Sarvāstivāda’s texts, such as the Mahāvibāṣā ,

were often confused by the ambiguous use of the wordavasthā ’ (usually translated as ‘position’) in Vasumitra’s version of the sarvam asti doctrine.14 In this regard, Sinha claims: “[The term avasthā ] has both spatial and temporal connotations. Avasthā can be translated both as ‘a state of affair’ or ‘a time span in the personal history’


Stambaugh (1974:132), Koller (1974:204-5) and Williams (1977:288). Stambaugh states that Sarvāstivādins claim “that all three times exist”, and that they “all are real”. Williams rectifies his own statements in a following work, maintaining that Sarvāstivādins believed in the existence of past, present and future dharmas , and did not believe in the existence of the Three Times. He rightly claims that the sarvam asti doctrine has noting to do with the problem

of the ontological status of time (Williams 2000:259). 12 Kalupahana 1974:187. 13 Prasad 1988:107. 14 Both the Mahāvibāṣā and l’ Abhidharmakośabhāṣya indicate Vasumitra’s interpretation ( Avasthā-anyathātva ) as the orthodox version of Sarvāstivāda’s doctrine. The other three reported versions are Dharmatrāta’s Bhāvānyathātva , Ghoṣaka’s Lakṣaṇa-anyathātva and Buddhadeva’s Anyathā-anyathika .

of an entity. A spatial rendering or interpretation of the term Avasthā in the passages of the Mahāvibāṣā [...] seems to have obscured a proper appraisal of Ābhidhārmic conception of temporal determinations”.15 In fact, the spatial rendering of the term ‘ avasthā ’ lead these scholars to believe that the

sarvam asti doctrine involves the idea of dharmas floating through the Three Times. However, if we examine the Mahāvibāṣā and the other Sarvāstivāda texts available to us, we do not find any statement supporting the theory of the existence of the Three Times. On the contrary, we find a clear refusal of it: “The Vibhajyavādins

maintain that the nature of time is permanent and the nature of phenomena is impermanent; they claim that phenomena move from one time to another, like a fruit transferred from a basket to another, or like a person who moves from an house to another; they believe that in the same way phenomena move from the future to the present, and from the present to the past. In order to counter their views, we reveal that the nature of time is not different from the

nature of phenomena. In reality, time is phenomena and phenomena are nothing but time”.16 It is therefore clear that the purpose of the sarvam asti doctrine was not to investigate the possible existence of time as an independent reality or its threefold division in past, present and future. Time as an ontological category is not part of Sarvāstivāda’s system.

The Sarvāstivādins postulated the existence of dharmas as past, present and future, not in the past, in the present and in the future.17 Past, present 15 Sinha 1983:126. 16 「如譬喩者分別論師。彼作是説。世體是常行體無常。行行世時如器中果。從此器出轉

入彼器 。亦如多人從此 舍出轉入 彼舍。諸行亦爾。從未來 世入現在世。從現在世入 過去 世。爲止彼意顯世與行體無差別。謂世即行行即是世」(Taishō Shinshū Daizōkyō 1545 393a11-16). 17 Sinha 1983:91.

and future are not self-existent distinct realms containing dharmas . Consequently, it seems to me completely misleading to describe them both as kālavādin (upholders of the real and independent existence of time) and as traikālyavādin (upholders of the real and independent existence of the Three Times).


Nāgārjuna’s Kālaparikṣa

Nāgārjuna’s standpoint concerning time is expounded in chapter XIX of his Mūlamadhyamakakārikā , called “Examination of Time” (skt. Kālaparikṣa ).18 His criticism of time is grounded on the fact that the Three Times are dependent on each other by definition. As two beings have to be coexistent to be dependent on each other, if the present and the future are dependent on the past, so they should be in the past, existing contemporaneously with the past.

It is not possible to define the present and the future independently by the past: the Three Times could exist only if reciprocally correlated. Therefore, without present, there are not past and future; without future, there are not past and present; without past, there are not present and future. The Three Times should be co-existent, otherwise they could not exist. Nevertheless, past, present and future cannot exist simultaneously by their very nature: past and future are distinguished by the fact that they are


before and after the present now. If the past would be present, it would not be past. The same apply for any of the other combinations. As the Three Times can be neither independent nor co-existent, their existence is conceptual, it is not real.19 As the Three Times are not existent in themselves, the theory of time as an ontological reality, receptacle of change, is refused. To whom is addressed the criticism of Nāgārjuna? It is a common opinion that his intention was to confute the “everything existsdoctrine held by the Sarvāstivādin. Kalupahana, for instance, states that “there is no doubt that it was

the Sarvāstivāda conception of time which drew the criticism from Nāgārjuna”.20 Koller, following Kalupahana, affirms that Nāgārjuna’s analysis of time is “directed primarily at the Sarvāstivādin, who took time to be an ontological container of change and divided the container into three segments: past, present, and future”.21 Nāgārjuna’s criticism was clearly directed toward the idea of a tripartite time-container, receptacle of change.22 However, I cannot agree with Koller in attributing this theory to the Sarvāstivādin, for the simple reason that, as I demonstrated above, they never claimed the real existence of an independent time-container. It is much more likely that Nāgārjuna was

There is a great resemblance between the arguments of Nāgārjuna and Buddhadeva regarding the relativity of the words “past”, “present” and “future” (see Williams 1977:2801). 20 Kalupahana 1974:187. 21 In the same article, Koller even claims that Nāgārjuna’s intention was only to negate Sarvāstivādin’s views, not to negate the reality of Time (Koller 1974:204-5). 22 A first evidence for this claim is the term used by Nāgārjuna to indicate “time”: kāla .

The word kāla usually refers to time as an eternal substance. It rarely appears in Buddhist texts, but when it does appear it is mainly used for its secondary meaning of “opportune time”, an “appropriate” or “convenient moment”.

arguing against a school which maintained the substantial reality of time, maybe the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika.23 In Stcherbatsky’s view “Les réflexions de Nāgārjuna sur le temps ne représentent aucune théorie. Ce n’est que l’application, au sujet du temps, d’une méthode dialectique négative , qui reste toujours la même, peu importe l’object auquel elle est appliquée”.24 To a certain extent, it is true that Nāgārjuna does not suggest any theory about time. His

negative approach seems to be nothing more than a reductio ad absurdum of the time-container theory. Nevertheless, though Nāgārjuna himself claims to have no opinion (skt. pratijña ) to demonstrate,25 he describes himself as a śūnyatāvādin ,26 an upholder of the doctrine of emptiness (skt. śūnyatā ). In my opinion, it is through the standpoint

of emptiness that we can correctly evaluate his criticism of time, and understand his teaching. Nāgārjuna criticized the concept of a self-existent time-container, as most of Abhidharma’s schools did, in clu din g S a r v ā stiv ā d a . As Miyamoto suggests, Nāgārjuna agrees with the Sarvāstivādin in refuting the existence of a time-container, but opposing to the concept of “selfexistence” (skt. svabhāva ) introduced by them, he draws his conclusions

through the negation of substantiality (skt. niḥsvabhāva ), re-establishing Buddha’s teaching of no-self.27 Sinha, holding the same opinion, mantains: “It is conceivable that Nāgārjuna would have opposed the Sarvāstivādin articulation of temporality in terms of the svabhāva of a dharma . But no explicit rejection of Sarvāstivāda can be discerned in the Kālaparikṣa, nor For an analysis of the concept of time in the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika, see Prasad 1984. 24 Stcherbatsky 1926:32-3. 25 Vigraha Vyāvartanī, stanza 29 (Nāgārjuna 1979:147). 26 Vigraha Vyāvartanī, stanza 70 (Nāgārjuna 1979:156). 27 Miyamoto 1959:9.

is there any claim that Sarvāstivādin believed in the indipendent reality status of time”.28


Conclusions

Through the present essay I illustrated the development of the concept of time and temporality in Indian Buddhism. It seems evident a shift from the epistemological perspective of the sūtrapiṭaka to the Abhidharmikasontological approach in the analysis of the nature of existence. This shift corresponds to a gradual development of the teaching of impermanence, which came to be understood as a law of instantaneousness. The several standpoints of

the Abhidharma schools regarding temporality fairly represent the different stages of this development. In contrast with the multiplicity of views concerning temporality , the general agreement between the schools about the status of time is striking. The refusal of the idea of a substantive tripartite time receptacle containing floating beings seems to be one of the main marks which characterize the dinstinction between Buddhist and non-

Buddhist systems. There are, of course, some exceptions to this general statement, but the small number of those exceptions leads me to the conclusion that probably even preAbhidharmikas rejected the duality of beings and time.



Bibliography

Aung, S. Z., Davids, R., Points of Controversy, or Subjects of Discourse, b ein g a tr a n sla tio n of th e K a th ā - v a tth u fr o m th e A b hidhamma-pitaka Oxford University Press Warehouse, 1915.
 
Bareau, André, “The Notion of Time in Early Buddhism”, East and West , 7, n. 4 (1957), pp. 353-64.
 
Conze, Edward, Buddhist Thought in India , London, George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1962.
 
Coomaraswamy, Ānanda K.,
Tempo ed Eternità , Milano, Luni Editrice,
2003.
 
Das, S.R., “Notion of Time in Hindu Philosophy”,
In dia n Histo ric al
Quarterly , 9 (1933), pp. 149-53.
 
Davids, T. W. Rhys, The questions of King Milinda , ed. By F. Max Müller, Sacred Books of the East, vol. XXXV, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1890.
 
Fuji, Kenkyo (藤 謙敬), “Time Theory of Nāgārjuna” (龍樹哲學の時間論), Annual Report of Nihon Butsugakuin (日本佛學院), 1940, pp. 159-208.
 

Garfield, Jay L., The fundamental wisdom of the middle way: Nāgārjuna ’s Mūlamadhyamakakārikā , translation and commentary by Jay L. Garfield, New York, Oxford University Press, 1995.
 
Gupta, Rita, “The Buddhist Doctrine of Momentariness and its Presupposition: Dharmakīrti’s Arguments in Hetubindu”, J o u r n al of In dia n Philosophy , 8 (1980), pp.47-68.
 
Inada, Kenneth K., “Time and temporality – A Buddhist approach”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 171-179.
 
Jha, G.N. (trad.), “Examination of the doctrine of ‘Traikālya’ – Things continuing to exist during three points of Time”, The Tattvasaṃgraha of Ś ā n ta r a k ṣita with th e C o m m e n ta r y o f K a m ala śīla , Oriental Institute, Baroda, 1939, Vol. II, pp. 861-86.
 
Kalupahana, David J., “The Buddhist conception of time and temporality”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 181-191.
 
Keith, A.B., “The Doctrine of Reality (The Nature of Time)”,
Buddhist Philosophy in India and Ceylon , Oxford University Press, 1923, pp. 163-68.
 
Koller, John M., “On Buddhist views of devouring time”,
Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 201-8.
 
Lancaster, Lewis R., “Discussion of time in Mahāyāna texts”,
Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 209-14.
 

La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, “La controverse de temps et du pudgala dans le Vijñānakāya”, Études Asiatiques (École Française d’Extrême-Orient ) , 1925, pp. 343-76.
 
La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, L’Abhidharmakośa de Vasubandhu Chapter V ,
Paul Geuthner, Paris, 1925, pp. 50-66.
 
La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, “Notes sur le ‘moment’ ou kṣaṇa des bouddhistes”, Rocznik Orientalistyczny , 8 (1932), pp.1-9.
 
La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, “Documents d’Abhidharma : la controverse du temps”, Mélanges chinois bouddhiques , 5 (1937), pp. 7-158.
 
Loy, David, “The Mahāyāna Deconstruction of Time”, Philosophy East and West , 36, n.1 (January 1986), pp. 13-23.
 
Loy, David, “Language Against Its Own Mystifications: Deconstruction in Nāgārjuna and Dōgen”, Philosophy East and West , 49, n.3 (July 1999), pp. 245-260.
 
Masunaga, Reihō (増永 霊鳳), Bukkyō ni okeru Jikanron (佛教における時 間論), Tōkyō, Sankibō Busshorin, 1966.
 
McDermott, A. Charlene, “The Sautrāntika arguments against the traikālyavāda in the light of the contemporary tense revolution”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 193-200.
 
McGovern, W.M., “Cosmic Synthesis”, A Manual of Buddhist Philosophy , London, 1923, pp. 43-48.

 
McKeon, Richard, “Time and temporality”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 123-128.
 
Miyamoto, Shoson, “Time and Eternity in Buddhism”, Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies , 7, n.2 (1959), pp. 3-18.
 
Mookerjee, Satkari, “The Buddhist Doctrine of Flux (The Nature of Existence)”, T h e B u d d hist P hilo s o p h y o f U niv e r s al Flu x , University of Calcutta, 1935, pp. 1-19.
 
Murti, T.R.V., The central philosophy of Buddhism , London, George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1955.
 
Nāgārjuna,
L e Sta n z e d el C a m min o di M e z z o ( M a d h y a m a k a K ā rik ā ) , introduzione, traduzione e note di Raniero Gnoli, Torino, Biblioteca Boringhieri, 1979.
 
Panikkar, Raimundo, “Toward a typology of time and temporality in the ancient Indian tradition”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 161-164.
 
Prasad, Hari Shankar, “Time and Change in Sāṁkya-Yoga”,
Journal of Indian Philosophy , 12 (March 1984), pp. 35-49.
 
Prasad, Hari Shankar, “Time as Substantive Reality in Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika”, East and West , 34 (1984), pp. 233-66.
 

Prasad, Hari Shankar, “The Concept of Time in Pali Buddhism”, East and West , 38 (1988), pp. 107-36.
 
Prasad, Hari Shankar,
Essays on Time in Buddhism , Bibliotheca Indobuddhica No. 78, Delhi, Sri Satguru Publications, 1991.
 
Rahula, Walpola, What the Buddha Taught , Oneworld Publications, 1997.
 
Ronkin, Noa,
Early Buddhist metaphysics: the making of a philoso phical
tradition , London, RoutledgeCurzon, 2005.
 
Sasaki, Genjun H., “The Time Concept in Abhidharma”,
Proceedings of
the 26 th International Congress of Orientalists , New Delhi, 1964, pp. 47180.
 
Schayer, Stanislaw,
C o n trib u tio n s to th e P r o ble m of Tim e in In dia n
Philosophy , Krakow, Polski Builetyn Orientalistyczny,1938.
 
Silburn, Lilian,
In sta n t e t C a u s e , L e Dis c o n tin u d a n s la P e n s é e Philosophique de l’Inde , Paris, De Boccard, 1989.
 
Sinha, Braj Mohan,
Tim e a n d T e m p o r ality in S ā ṁ k y a - Y o g a a n d
Abhidharma Buddhism , Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers Pvt. Ltd., 1983.
 
Stambaugh, Joan, “Time, finitude, and finality”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 129-35.
 
 
Stcherbatsky, Th., “Vasubandhu on the Fundamental Principle of the Sarvāstivāda School”, T h e C e ntr al C o n c e p tio n o f B u d d his m a n d th e

Meaning of the WordDharma” , Royal Asiatique Society, London, 1923, pp. 76-91.
 
Stcherbatsky, Th., “Le temps (kāla)”, La théorie de la connaissance et la logique chez les bouddhistes tardifs , Librarie Orientaliste Paul Geuthner, Paris, 1926, pp. 12-39.
 
Stcherbatsky, Th., “The Theory of Instantaneous Being (Kṣaṇabhaṅgavāda)”, B u d d hist L o gic , Dover Publications, New York, 1962, (First published by the Academy of sciences of the USSR, Leningrad, 1930), pp. 79-118.
 
Tamaki, Kōshirō (玉城 康四郎), “Bukkyō no Jikanron (仏教の時間論)”, Risō, 460 (September 1971), pp. 64-78.
 
Tu, Wei-Ming, “An introductory note on time and temporality”, Philosophy East and West , 24, n.2 (April 1974), pp. 119-22.
 
Williams, Paul, “Buddhadeva and Temporality”,
J o u r n al o f In dia n
Philosophy , 4 (1977), pp. 279-94.
 
Williams, Paul,
Buddhist thought: a complete introduction to the In dian
tradition , London, Routledge, 2000.
 
Williams, Paul, Mahāyāna Buddhism: the doctrinal foundations , 2nd edition, New York, Routledge, 2008.


Source