Difference between revisions of "Nishida Kitarō"
(Created page with " Nishida Kitarō First published Fri Feb 25, 2005; substantive revision Thu Oct 22, 2015 Nishida Kitarō was the most significant and influential Japan...") |
|||
Line 20: | Line 20: | ||
− | [[Nishida Kitarō]] was the most significant and influential [[Japanese philosopher]] of the twentieth-century. His work is path-breaking in several respects: it established in Japan the creative discipline of philosophy as practiced in Europe and the Americas; it enriched that discipline by infusing Anglo-European philosophy with Asian sources of thought; it provided a new basis for philosophical treatments of East Asian Buddhist thought; and it produced novel theories of self and world with rich implications for contemporary philosophizing. | + | [[Nishida Kitarō]] was the most significant and influential [[Japanese philosopher]] of the twentieth-century. His work is path-breaking in several respects: it established in [[Japan]] the creative [[discipline]] of [[philosophy]] as practiced in {{Wiki|Europe}} and the Americas; it enriched that [[discipline]] by infusing Anglo-European [[philosophy]] with {{Wiki|Asian}} sources of [[thought]]; it provided a new basis for [[philosophical]] treatments of {{Wiki|East Asian}} [[Buddhist]] [[thought]]; and it produced {{Wiki|novel}} theories of [[self]] and [[world]] with rich implications for contemporary philosophizing. |
− | Nishida’s work is also frustrating for its repetitive and often obscure style, exceedingly abstract formulations, and detailed but frequently dead-end investigations. Nishida once said of his work, “I have always been a miner of ore; I have never managed to refine it” (Nishida 1958, Preface). A concise presentation of his achievements therefore will require extensive selection, interpretation and clarification. | + | Nishida’s work is also [[frustrating]] for its repetitive and often obscure style, exceedingly abstract formulations, and detailed but frequently dead-end investigations. Nishida once said of his work, “I have always been a miner of ore; I have never managed to refine it” (Nishida 1958, Preface). A concise presentation of his achievements therefore will require extensive selection, [[interpretation]] and clarification. |
− | This article presents his work in a roughly chronological order. We may understand his philosophical project overall as an attempt to restore to experience and consciousness the rigor, necessity and universality accorded to logic. | + | This article presents his work in a roughly {{Wiki|chronological}} order. We may understand his [[philosophical]] project overall as an attempt to restore to [[experience]] and [[consciousness]] the rigor, necessity and universality accorded to [[logic]]. |
− | This project developed in a direction quite opposite to that of psychologism, which would reduce logic to the contingencies of the individual mind or brain. It also differed from efforts to establish pure logic as a self-explanatory realm in that Nishida insisted on the starting point of experience, a priority he shared with Husserl’s phenomenology and William | + | This project developed in a [[direction]] quite opposite to that of psychologism, which would reduce [[logic]] to the contingencies of the {{Wiki|individual}} [[mind]] or {{Wiki|brain}}. It also differed from efforts to establish [[pure]] [[logic]] as a self-explanatory [[realm]] in that Nishida insisted on the starting point of [[experience]], a priority he shared with [[Husserl’s phenomenology]] and {{Wiki|William James}}’ radical {{Wiki|empiricism}}. |
− | We might characterize his philosophy in general as a phenomenological metaphysics for its universalizing of first-person experience. It can also be considered an ontology of logical forms for its investigations of their experiential basis, with one qualification: although Nishida proposed a unitary source of such forms, that source is neither exclusionary nor positive; in other words the source itself cannot be described monistically as a single, more basic form or thing. | + | We might characterize his [[philosophy]] in general as a {{Wiki|phenomenological}} [[metaphysics]] for its universalizing of first-person [[experience]]. It can also be considered an {{Wiki|ontology}} of [[logical]] [[forms]] for its investigations of their experiential basis, with one qualification: although Nishida proposed a unitary source of such [[forms]], that source is neither exclusionary nor positive; in other words the source itself cannot be described monistically as a single, more basic [[form]] or thing. |
− | Nishida eventually called this source “mu” (nothingness), a notion he found particularly prominent in the traditions of the East. His interests led him to develop a philosophy of culture, and his status as Japan’s premier philosopher led government officials to call upon him for justification of Japanese expansionism in the late 1930s and early 40s. His last work recapitulated his non-dualistic account of world and self, but also reinterpreted the meaning of death. | + | Nishida eventually called this source “mu” ([[nothingness]]), a notion he found particularly prominent in the [[traditions]] of the [[East]]. His interests led him to develop a [[philosophy]] of {{Wiki|culture}}, and his {{Wiki|status}} as {{Wiki|Japan’s}} premier [[philosopher]] led government officials to call upon him for {{Wiki|justification}} of [[Japanese]] expansionism in the late 1930s and early 40s. His last work recapitulated his [[non-dualistic]] account of [[world]] and [[self]], but also reinterpreted the meaning of [[death]]. |
Line 46: | Line 46: | ||
<poem> | <poem> | ||
− | 1. Biography | + | 1. {{Wiki|Biography}} |
− | 2. Theory of Experience and Consciousness | + | 2. {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Experience]] and [[Consciousness]] |
− | 2.1 Pure Experience | + | 2.1 [[Pure]] [[Experience]] |
− | 2.2 Self-Awareness | + | 2.2 [[Self-Awareness]] |
− | 3. Theory of Universals and the Logic of Place | + | 3. {{Wiki|Theory}} of Universals and the [[Logic]] of Place |
− | 3.1 Absolute Nothingness | + | 3.1 [[Absolute]] [[Nothingness]] |
− | 3.2 Analogies to the Logic of Place | + | 3.2 Analogies to the [[Logic]] of Place |
− | 4. Theory of the Historical World | + | 4. {{Wiki|Theory}} of the Historical [[World]] |
− | 4.1 Enactive Intuition | + | 4.1 Enactive {{Wiki|Intuition}} |
− | 4.2 Theory of Relations: Self and Other, One and Many | + | 4.2 {{Wiki|Theory}} of Relations: [[Self]] and Other, One and Many |
− | 5. Nishida’s Theology: the Finite Self meets the Absolute | + | 5. Nishida’s {{Wiki|Theology}}: the Finite [[Self]] meets the [[Absolute]] |
− | 6. Political Theory: Religion, Culture, and Nations | + | 6. {{Wiki|Political}} {{Wiki|Theory}}: [[Religion]], {{Wiki|Culture}}, and Nations |
− | 7. Methods in Nishida’s Thought | + | 7. [[Methods]] in Nishida’s [[Thought]] |
− | 8. The Unity and Development of Nishida’s Philosophy | + | 8. The Unity and [[Development]] of Nishida’s [[Philosophy]] |
8.1 The Attempt to Unify the Varying Themes | 8.1 The Attempt to Unify the Varying Themes | ||
− | 8.2 Stages in Nishida’s Thought | + | 8.2 Stages in Nishida’s [[Thought]] |
− | 9. The Place of Asian Philosophies in Nishida’s Thought | + | 9. The Place of {{Wiki|Asian}} [[Philosophies]] in Nishida’s [[Thought]] |
− | 10. Critiques of Nishida’s Philosophy | + | 10. Critiques of Nishida’s [[Philosophy]] |
11. Nishida’s Influence | 11. Nishida’s Influence | ||
− | Bibliography | + | [[Bibliography]] |
Nishida’s works | Nishida’s works | ||
− | Secondary Literature | + | Secondary {{Wiki|Literature}} |
− | Academic Tools | + | {{Wiki|Academic}} Tools |
− | Other Internet Resources | + | Other [[Internet]] Resources |
Related Entries | Related Entries | ||
Line 81: | Line 81: | ||
− | 1. Biography | + | 1. {{Wiki|Biography}} |
Line 89: | Line 89: | ||
− | Nishida was born on May 19, 1870 in the village of Unoke on the Sea of Japan just north of the city of Kanazawa. His birthplace, later incorporated into the town of Kahoku, is the site today of archives and a monumental museum, perhaps the world’s largest architectural structure dedicated to a single philosopher. | + | Nishida was born on May 19, 1870 in the village of Unoke on the {{Wiki|Sea of Japan}} just [[north]] of the city of Kanazawa. His birthplace, later incorporated into the town of Kahoku, is the site today of archives and a monumental museum, perhaps the world’s largest architectural {{Wiki|structure}} dedicated to a single [[philosopher]]. |
− | Nishida grew up in the early years of the Meiji era (1868–1912), when Japan had reopened to the world after two and a half centuries of relative isolation and was undergoing a revolutionary Europeanization of its political, educational and cultural institutions. As it touched Nishida’s early years, this | + | Nishida grew up in the early years of the [[Wikipedia:Meiji period|Meiji era]] (1868–1912), when [[Japan]] had reopened to the [[world]] after two and a half centuries of [[relative]] isolation and was undergoing a {{Wiki|revolutionary}} Europeanization of its {{Wiki|political}}, educational and {{Wiki|cultural}} {{Wiki|institutions}}. As it touched Nishida’s early years, this “[[modernization]]” came in the [[form]] of both a rigid, often oppressive school {{Wiki|atmosphere}} that demanded obeisance to the [[emperor]], and a liberating exposure to the progressive [[ideas]] of the [[Japanese]] “[[Enlightenment]]” that had introduced {{Wiki|western philosophy}} to [[Japan]]. |
− | In high school in Kanazawa he studied Chinese Confucian, Neo-Confucian and Daoist classics, learned to read English and German, excelled in mathematics, and attempted briefly to penetrate works of Hegel and Kant. | + | In high school in Kanazawa he studied {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Wikipedia:Confucianism|Confucian]], {{Wiki|Neo-Confucian}} and [[Daoist]] classics, learned to read English and [[German]], excelled in [[mathematics]], and attempted briefly to penetrate works of [[Wikipedia:Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]] and {{Wiki|Kant}}. |
− | He formed a life-long friendship with fellow student D.T. Suzuki, and with him dropped out of high school in 1890. Admitted into Tokyo Imperial University as a “limited | + | He formed a life-long [[friendship]] with fellow [[student]] {{Wiki|D.T. Suzuki}}, and with him dropped out of high school in 1890. Admitted into [[Tokyo]] {{Wiki|Imperial}} {{Wiki|University}} as a “limited {{Wiki|status}}” [[student]] the following year, Nishida studied {{Wiki|Kant}}, [[Wikipedia:Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]] and {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} under the first [[philosophy]] professors in [[Japan]]. |
− | After graduating in 1894 with a thesis on Hume’s theory of causation, he married and held teaching positions at several provincial high schools and universities. During the next decade, despite the demands of family life and teaching German among other subjects, he published a few philosophical essays but was more intent on formal meditation practice under Zen masters in Kyoto. | + | After graduating in 1894 with a {{Wiki|thesis}} on [[Hume’s]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[causation]], he [[married]] and held [[teaching]] positions at several provincial high schools and [[universities]]. During the next decade, despite the demands of [[family]] [[life]] and [[teaching]] [[German]] among other [[subjects]], he published a few [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|essays}} but was more intent on formal [[meditation practice]] under [[Zen masters]] in {{Wiki|Kyoto}}. |
− | He began composing what later appeared as An Inquiry into the Good in 1905 and on the basis of that work secured a position at Kyoto Imperial University in 1910, becoming Professor of Philosophy there in 1914. | + | He began composing what later appeared as [[An Inquiry into the Good]] in 1905 and on the basis of that work secured a position at {{Wiki|Kyoto}} {{Wiki|Imperial}} {{Wiki|University}} in 1910, becoming [[Professor]] of [[Philosophy]] there in 1914. |
− | Nishida concentrated on the philosophical books that made their way into Japan and for the next decade wrote numerous essays that reworked ideas from the Neo-Kantians, Royce, Bergson, Hermann Lotze and, to a lesser extent, Husserl. | + | Nishida [[concentrated]] on the [[philosophical]] [[books]] that made their way into [[Japan]] and for the next decade wrote numerous {{Wiki|essays}} that reworked [[ideas]] from the Neo-Kantians, Royce, Bergson, Hermann Lotze and, to a lesser extent, [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]]. |
− | These essays were collected into books that investigated a wide range of topics, including art and morality, from the perspective of a theory of consciousness and the will. Nishida’s fame began to spread in the 1920s. | + | These {{Wiki|essays}} were collected into [[books]] that investigated a wide range of topics, [[including]] [[art]] and [[morality]], from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of a {{Wiki|theory}} of [[consciousness]] and the will. Nishida’s [[fame]] began to spread in the 1920s. |
− | He was instrumental in securing positions at Kyoto University for Tanabe Hajime, Watsuji Tetsurō, and Kuki Shuzō, and attracted students such as Nishitani Keiji, Miki Kiyoshi and Tosaka Jun, who all became significant philosophers in Japan. | + | He was instrumental in securing positions at [[Kyoto University]] for [[Tanabe]] Hajime, [[Watsuji]] Tetsurō, and Kuki Shuzō, and attracted students such as [[Nishitani Keiji]], Miki Kiyoshi and Tosaka Jun, who all became significant [[philosophers]] in [[Japan]]. |
− | He developed his signature theory of place (basho) in the mid 1920s, and continued to elaborate it after he became professor emeritus and moved to Kamakura in 1929. In the early 1930s his interests turned to the nature of human actions and interactions in the historical and social world, and eventually to the meaning of culture and nationhood. | + | He developed his signature {{Wiki|theory}} of place (basho) in the mid 1920s, and continued to elaborate it after he became [[professor]] {{Wiki|emeritus}} and moved to [[Wikipedia:Kamakura, Kanagawa|Kamakura]] in 1929. In the early 1930s his interests turned to the [[nature]] of [[human]] [[actions]] and interactions in the historical and {{Wiki|social}} [[world]], and eventually to the meaning of {{Wiki|culture}} and nationhood. |
− | Because of his prestige as Japan’s premier philosopher, government officials—among them his former student and then Prime Minister Konoe Fumimaro—appealed to him to justify Japanese nationalism. Nishida complied by addressing the issues, if not legitimizing Japan’s expansionism. Yet he considered much of that work a distraction. He lectured on “The Problem of Japanese | + | Because of his prestige as {{Wiki|Japan’s}} premier [[philosopher]], government officials—among them his former [[student]] and then [[Prime Minister]] {{Wiki|Konoe}} Fumimaro—appealed to him to justify [[Japanese]] [[nationalism]]. Nishida complied by addressing the issues, if not legitimizing {{Wiki|Japan’s}} expansionism. Yet he considered much of that work a [[distraction]]. He lectured on “The Problem of [[Japanese]] {{Wiki|Culture}}” in 1938; when published two years later the [[book]] quickly sold some 60,000 copies. He delivered an invited address to the [[emperor]] in 1941 that advocated {{Wiki|academic}} freedom and a place for each {{Wiki|nation}} in the global [[world]], with each developing its [[own]] global {{Wiki|perspective}}.[1] Addresses on the “{{Wiki|Principles}} for the New [[World]] Order” and on “The [[Body]] (or [[Essence]]) of the Nation” ([[kokutai]]) followed. During this time Nishida’s critics on the right considered his {{Wiki|political}} writings either too abstract or insufficiently supportive of the government; after the [[Second World War]] his leftist critics found them profusely nationalistic. Despite his failing [[health]] and the bombing of cities all around him, Nishida persisted in his [[philosophical]] investigations, using for example {{Wiki|Descartes}}’ Cogito and Leibniz’s Preestablished [[Harmony]] as points of departure. He completed the seminal essay, “The [[Logic]] of Place and the [[Religious]] Worldview,” just two months before his [[death]] on June 7, 1945. Publication of his collected works in 19 volumes began two years later. An extant photograph shows dozens of [[people]] camped out all night long awaiting the issue of the first volume on July 20, 1947. |
− | Nishida’s private life, reflected only faintly in his philosophical work, nevertheless left its stamp on its tenor. His perseverance through turmoil explains perhaps some of the intensity of his writing. Comprehending reality for him was an emotive as well as intellectual achievement; his calligraphy and poetry, renowned in their own right, evince an acute awareness of transience and transcendence. Nishida experienced the death of his first wife and four of his eight children; upon the passing of his first son he wrote this waka poem: | + | Nishida’s private [[life]], reflected only faintly in his [[philosophical]] work, nevertheless left its stamp on its tenor. His perseverance through turmoil explains perhaps some of the intensity of his [[writing]]. Comprehending [[reality]] for him was an {{Wiki|emotive}} as well as [[intellectual]] [[achievement]]; his {{Wiki|calligraphy}} and [[poetry]], renowned in their [[own]] right, evince an acute [[awareness]] of transience and {{Wiki|transcendence}}. Nishida [[experienced]] the [[death]] of his first wife and four of his eight children; upon the passing of his first son he wrote this waka poem: |
Line 131: | Line 131: | ||
till twenty-three | till twenty-three | ||
how could he disappear | how could he disappear | ||
− | like a dream | + | like a [[dream]] |
(Yusa 2002, 314–18). | (Yusa 2002, 314–18). | ||
Line 142: | Line 142: | ||
− | The bottom of my soul has such depth; | + | The bottom of my [[soul]] has such depth; |
− | Neither joy nor the waves of sorrow can reach it | + | Neither [[joy]] nor the waves of [[sorrow]] can reach it |
(Nishida 1958, frontispiece). | (Nishida 1958, frontispiece). | ||
Line 152: | Line 152: | ||
− | 2. Theory of Experience and Consciousness | + | 2. {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Experience]] and [[Consciousness]] |
− | 2.1 Pure Experience | + | 2.1 [[Pure]] [[Experience]] |
Line 163: | Line 163: | ||
− | Starting with An Inquiry Into the Good, Nishida’s early work calls into question two basic presuppositions of most modern epistemology: the assumptions that experience is individual and subjective, and that it leads to knowledge only via a corrective process with input from the mind or other individuals. | + | Starting with An Inquiry Into the Good, Nishida’s early work calls into question two basic presuppositions of most {{Wiki|modern}} epistemology: the {{Wiki|assumptions}} that [[experience]] is {{Wiki|individual}} and [[subjective]], and that it leads to [[knowledge]] only via a corrective process with input from the [[mind]] or other {{Wiki|individuals}}. |
− | For Nishida, experience in its original form is not the exercise of individuals equipped with sensory and mental abilities who contact an exterior world; rather it precedes the differentiation into subject experiencing and object experienced, and the individual is formed out of it. “The moment of seeing a color or hearing a | + | For Nishida, [[experience]] in its original [[form]] is not the exercise of {{Wiki|individuals}} equipped with sensory and [[mental]] {{Wiki|abilities}} who [[contact]] an exterior [[world]]; rather it precedes the differentiation into [[subject]] experiencing and [[object]] [[experienced]], and the {{Wiki|individual}} is formed out of it. “The [[moment]] of [[seeing]] a {{Wiki|color}} or hearing a [[sound]]” is prior not only to the [[thought]] that the {{Wiki|color}} or [[sound]] is the [[activity]] of an [[external object]] or that one is sensing it, but also to the [[judgment]] of what the {{Wiki|color}} or [[sound]] might be (Nishida 1990a, 3). |
− | + | “[[Pure experience]]” names not only the basic [[form]] of every [[sensuous]] and every [[intellectual]] [[experience]] but also the fundamental [[form]] of [[reality]], indeed the “one and only [[reality]]” from which all differentiated [[phenomena]] are to be understood. [[Cognitive]] [[activities]] such as [[thinking]] or judging, willing, and [[intellectual]] [[intuition]] are all derivative [[forms]] of [[pure experience]] but still [[manifest]] it insofar as they are in [[action]] —when [[thinking]], willing, etc. are going on. | |
− | The experience of a running horse, for example, underlies the judgment that the horse is running, and the activity of judging is an exercise of pure experience prior to a subsequent judgment that “I am now judging.” Objective phenomena likewise derive from pure experience; when unified they are called | + | The [[experience]] of a running [[horse]], for example, underlies the [[judgment]] that the [[horse]] is running, and the [[activity]] of judging is an exercise of [[pure experience]] prior to a subsequent [[judgment]] that “I am now judging.” [[Objective phenomena]] likewise derive from [[pure experience]]; when unified they are called “[[nature]],” while “[[spirit]]” names the [[activity]] of unifying. [[Pure experience]] launches the dynamic process of [[reality]] that differentiates into [[subjective]] and [[objective phenomena]] on their way to a higher {{Wiki|unity}}, and the recapture of our unitary foundation is what Nishida means by the Good. |
− | Nishida would deny that his position is a kind of idealism, either subjective or transcendental, because no subjective mind, human or divine, is the origin of what is taken as reality, and no personified or ego-aware spirit is its beginning or end. His notion of pure experience clearly shows the influence of William James, Ernst Mach, and others, but it differs from their notions as well as from twentieth-century expositions of pre-reflective experience by its emphasis on the non-individuated character and the seamless development of such experience. It is the pre-individual basis of a systematic and all-comprehensive process. If we call his view a | + | Nishida would deny that his position is a kind of [[idealism]], either [[subjective]] or [[transcendental]], because no [[subjective mind]], [[human]] or [[divine]], is the origin of what is taken as [[reality]], and no personified or ego-aware [[spirit]] is its beginning or end. His notion of [[pure experience]] clearly shows the influence of {{Wiki|William James}}, Ernst Mach, and others, but it differs from their notions as well as from twentieth-century [[expositions]] of pre-reflective [[experience]] by its {{Wiki|emphasis}} on the non-individuated [[character]] and the seamless [[development]] of such [[experience]]. It is the pre-individual basis of a systematic and all-comprehensive process. If we call his view a “{{Wiki|theory}}” of [[experience]], we should be {{Wiki|aware}} that from his standpoint the {{Wiki|theory}} is a natural outgrowth of unitary [[experience]] and not a {{Wiki|reflection}} on it as proceeding from a different source. The question of how [[pure experience]] grounds reflective [[knowledge]] would occupy Nishida in works composed after An Inquiry Into the Good. |
− | The directness, relative simplicity, and systematic approach of this book made it perhaps the most accessible and popular of his works; and many commentators have tended to emphasize it more than later writings, despite Nishida’s own misgivings about its latent psychologism. Indeed Nishida’s initial position anticipates several developments in his later thought. For example, the early statements of experience prior to a subject experiencing and an object experienced are re-formulated in the late 1920s as | + | The directness, [[relative]] [[simplicity]], and systematic approach of this [[book]] made it perhaps the most accessible and popular of his works; and many commentators have tended to {{Wiki|emphasize}} it more than later writings, despite Nishida’s [[own]] misgivings about its latent psychologism. Indeed Nishida’s initial position anticipates several developments in his later [[thought]]. For example, the early statements of [[experience]] prior to a [[subject]] experiencing and an [[object]] [[experienced]] are re-formulated in the late 1920s as “[[seeing]] without a [[seer]], hearing without a hearer.” |
− | The nullification of the self in pure experience is later expressed as seeing the self from the perspective of the world, where world is understood phenomenologically as a determining horizon of experience. The notion of the individual as determined by the universal concealed within (Nishida 1990a, 18) pre-figures Nishida’s later adaptation of Hegel’s concrete universal; the later works speak of the individual as the self-determination of the universal. Finally, the ways in which pure experience can be said to be most concrete, to enfold all reality and indicate its undifferentiated ground, reflect methods that characterize Nishida’s philosophy as a whole. | + | The nullification of the [[self]] in [[pure experience]] is later expressed as [[seeing]] the [[self]] from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of the [[world]], where [[world]] is understood [[phenomenologically]] as a determining horizon of [[experience]]. The notion of the {{Wiki|individual}} as determined by the [[universal]] concealed within (Nishida 1990a, 18) pre-figures Nishida’s later [[adaptation]] of Hegel’s concrete [[universal]]; the later works speak of the {{Wiki|individual}} as the [[self-determination]] of the [[universal]]. Finally, the ways in which [[pure experience]] can be said to be most concrete, to enfold all [[reality]] and indicate its undifferentiated ground, reflect [[methods]] that characterize Nishida’s [[philosophy]] as a whole. |
− | 2.2 Self-Awareness | + | 2.2 [[Self-Awareness]] |
− | The question of how reflective thought is grounded in pure experience finds a tentative answer in Nishida’s next essays. How can pure experience develop into reflective thought that would seem to interrupt and interpret it from an external vantage point? The self-reflection known as self-consciousness or self-awareness (jikaku) provides an answer. | + | The question of how reflective [[thought]] is grounded in [[pure experience]] finds a tentative answer in Nishida’s next {{Wiki|essays}}. How can [[pure experience]] develop into reflective [[thought]] that would seem to interrupt and interpret it from an external vantage point? The self-reflection known as [[self-consciousness]] or [[self-awareness]] ([[jikaku]]) provides an answer. |
− | There is a form of consciousness that inherently reflects or mirrors itself within itself, so that there is no difference between that which reflects and what is reflected. In self-awareness, immediate experiencing and reflection are unified. In epistemological terms, knower and known are the same, and this instance of unity serves as the prototype of all knowledge. | + | There is a [[form]] of [[consciousness]] that inherently reflects or mirrors itself within itself, so that there is no difference between that which reflects and what is reflected. In [[self-awareness]], immediate experiencing and {{Wiki|reflection}} are unified. In [[epistemological]] terms, knower and known are the same, and this instance of {{Wiki|unity}} serves as the prototype of all [[knowledge]]. |
− | Two points may prevent a misunderstanding of Nishida’s position here. First, his talk of self-awareness and self-reflection does not imply the pre-given existence of some personal self that at times may be self-conscious. | + | Two points may prevent a {{Wiki|misunderstanding}} of Nishida’s position here. First, his talk of [[self-awareness]] and self-reflection does not imply the pre-given [[existence]] of some personal [[self]] that at times may be self-conscious. |
− | Secondly, if consciousness is not placed in a pre-given self, it also is not placed in the objective world as a complex of brain cells or as the effect of material objects on the mind or brain. As in modern phenomenology, consciousness for Nishida means simply that which makes manifest or, to use a visual metaphor, that which illuminates. | + | Secondly, if [[consciousness]] is not placed in a pre-given [[self]], it also is not placed in the [[objective world]] as a complex of {{Wiki|brain}} {{Wiki|cells}} or as the effect of [[material objects]] on the [[mind]] or {{Wiki|brain}}. As in {{Wiki|modern}} [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], [[consciousness]] for Nishida means simply that which makes [[manifest]] or, to use a [[visual]] {{Wiki|metaphor}}, that which illuminates. |
− | To emphasize its non-objectifiable character, Nishida later will place consciousness “in” nothingness, that is, consider it a | + | To {{Wiki|emphasize}} its non-objectifiable [[character]], Nishida later will place [[consciousness]] “in” [[nothingness]], that is, consider it a “[[form]]” of [[nothingness]], and will eventually consider this a [[form]] of [[relative]] or oppositional [[nothingness]], a [[non-being]] with [[respect]] to [[beings]]. In the meantime, he formulated it as the [[activity]] that precedes but ultimately unifies [[self]] and [[world]]. [[Knowledge]] of things in the [[world]] begins with the differentiation of unitary [[consciousness]] into knower and known and ends with [[self]] and things becoming one again. |
− | Such unification takes form not only in knowing but in the valuing (of truth) that directs knowing, the willing that directs action, and the feeling or emotive reach that directs sensing. In this stage of his work Nishida, influenced by Fichte and Schopenhauer, considered | + | Such unification takes [[form]] not only in [[knowing]] but in the valuing (of [[truth]]) that directs [[knowing]], the willing that directs [[action]], and the [[feeling]] or {{Wiki|emotive}} reach that directs sensing. In this stage of his work Nishida, influenced by Fichte and {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}}, considered “[[absolute]] will” as the preeminent [[form]] of [[self-awareness]] and saw it as the source of acts of [[moral]] [[decision]] and of the creation and [[appreciation]] of [[art]]. Since the [[activity]] of the will eludes {{Wiki|reflection}}, however, Nishida eventually abandoned this formulation of a unitary source. |
Line 211: | Line 211: | ||
− | 3. Theory of Universals and the Logic of Place | + | 3. {{Wiki|Theory}} of Universals and the [[Logic]] of Place |
Line 217: | Line 217: | ||
− | Nishida’s epistemological motivation gradually gave way to an examination of common ontological assumptions that underlie epistemology in the Western philosophical tradition. Not content merely to expose such assumptions, however, Nishida formulated a novel ontology of experience and self-awareness that would give them logical necessity. | + | Nishida’s [[epistemological]] [[motivation]] gradually gave way to an {{Wiki|examination}} of common [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|assumptions}} that underlie epistemology in the [[Western]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]]. Not content merely to expose such {{Wiki|assumptions}}, however, Nishida formulated a {{Wiki|novel}} {{Wiki|ontology}} of [[experience]] and [[self-awareness]] that would give them [[logical]] necessity. |
− | Considering what is taken as the ordinary consciousness of objects, Nishida’s analysis questions both the notion of consciousness and that of objects. We can explicate Nishida’s first concern, with the ontology of consciousness, in the following way: | + | Considering what is taken as the [[ordinary consciousness]] of [[objects]], Nishida’s analysis questions both the notion of [[consciousness]] and that of [[objects]]. We can explicate Nishida’s first [[concern]], with the {{Wiki|ontology}} of [[consciousness]], in the following way: |
− | If the basic form of consciousness did not have the reflexivity of self-awareness, then the | + | If the basic [[form]] of [[consciousness]] did not have the reflexivity of [[self-awareness]], then the “[[consciousness]]” of [[objects]] would be [[blind]], as it were, like a mechanical or {{Wiki|neurological}} {{Wiki|reaction}} to {{Wiki|stimuli}} with no [[awareness]] whatsoever, and no way to account for [[awareness]]. |
− | The problem appears in attempts to define consciousness in a non-circular way. A definition of consciousness as a state of awareness or sentience, for example, or a state in which there is something it feels like to be in that state, merely replaces consciousness with its synonyms. In a sense, awareness is irreducible, but it has a logical structure that accounts for its connection to a world of objects. | + | The problem appears in attempts to define [[consciousness]] in a non-circular way. A [[definition]] of [[consciousness]] as a [[state of awareness]] or [[sentience]], for example, or a [[state]] in which there is something it [[feels]] like to be in that [[state]], merely replaces [[consciousness]] with its synonyms. In a [[sense]], [[awareness]] is irreducible, but it has a [[logical]] {{Wiki|structure}} that accounts for its [[connection]] to a [[world]] of [[objects]]. |
− | Structurally, awareness mirrors itself in itself, in a manner analogous to the way an infinite set mirrors itself in its equivalent subsets, or to the way an ideal map mirrors itself in all accurate representations of that map.[2] (Note that the English awareness can be used without the word self but the Japanese word that translates as self-awareness is an inseparable compound, ji-kaku.) If such self-awareness is to have logical necessity, it cannot be explained as a contingent property of a particular mind or consciousness that sometimes reflects on itself, that is, as a second order consciousness of being conscious of something. | + | Structurally, [[awareness]] mirrors itself in itself, in a manner analogous to the way an [[infinite]] set mirrors itself in its {{Wiki|equivalent}} subsets, or to the way an {{Wiki|ideal}} map mirrors itself in all accurate {{Wiki|representations}} of that map.[2] (Note that the English [[awareness]] can be used without the [[word]] [[self]] but the [[Japanese]] [[word]] that translates as [[self-awareness]] is an [[inseparable]] compound, ji-kaku.) If such [[self-awareness]] is to have [[logical]] necessity, it cannot be explained as a contingent property of a particular [[mind]] or [[consciousness]] that sometimes reflects on itself, that is, as a second order [[consciousness]] of being [[conscious]] of something. |
− | Similarly, if self-awareness is to be an awareness of more than merely oneself, it cannot be interior to the self alone. Modern epistemology’s solution was to split the world in two, mind and nature, and then to see the mind as a mirror of nature, and ideas as representations of real objects. Nishida’s solution was to see the world as mirroring itself in all the things “in the world.” | + | Similarly, if [[self-awareness]] is to be an [[awareness]] of more than merely oneself, it cannot be interior to the [[self]] alone. {{Wiki|Modern}} epistemology’s {{Wiki|solution}} was to split the [[world]] in two, [[mind]] and [[nature]], and then to see the [[mind]] as a [[mirror]] of [[nature]], and [[ideas]] as {{Wiki|representations}} of real [[objects]]. Nishida’s {{Wiki|solution}} was to see the [[world]] as mirroring itself in all the things “in the [[world]].” |
− | Whatever is “in the | + | Whatever is “in the [[world]]” is a mirroring of the [[world]]. In this [[sense]] it is the [[world]] that is “[[self-aware]]” or self-reflexive; and there is no outside to it. An individual’s “[[self-awareness]]” is a partial mirroring of the [[world]]; Nishida later described the [[individual self]] as a focal point of the [[world]]. |
− | While he was still thinking in terms of consciousness, however, Nishida avoided pinpointing awareness and spoke of the world as a field of consciousness to indicate the extension of the term beyond the individual self. This field is similar to Kant’s Bewußtsein überhaupt, in that it functions as the condition for the possibility of particular acts of consciousness, but unlike Kant’s notion that turns everything into an object of consciousness, its reflexive structure allows it to take itself into account without making it another object. | + | While he was still [[thinking]] in terms of [[consciousness]], however, Nishida avoided pinpointing [[awareness]] and spoke of the [[world]] as a field of [[consciousness]] to indicate the extension of the term beyond the [[individual self]]. This field is similar to [[Kant’s]] Bewußtsein überhaupt, in that it functions as the [[condition]] for the possibility of particular acts of [[consciousness]], but unlike [[Kant’s]] notion that turns everything into an [[object]] of [[consciousness]], its reflexive {{Wiki|structure}} allows it to take itself into account without making it another [[object]]. |
− | We may use Nishida’s own terms to explain his second concern, the way that objects ordinarily function in judgments. | + | We may use Nishida’s [[own]] terms to explain his second [[concern]], the way that [[objects]] ordinarily function in judgments. |
− | In what Nishida alternatively called the logic of objects or subjective logic, objects of consciousness are made the grammatical subject of propositions or judgments, and are specified by predicating properties of the subject. Eventually a subject is reached that cannot itself be predicated of anything else, recalling Aristotle’s hypokeimenon or individual substance that can be subject but never predicate. | + | In what Nishida alternatively called the [[logic]] of [[objects]] or [[subjective]] [[logic]], [[objects]] of [[consciousness]] are made the {{Wiki|grammatical}} [[subject]] of propositions or judgments, and are specified by predicating properties of the [[subject]]. Eventually a [[subject]] is reached that cannot itself be predicated of anything else, recalling Aristotle’s hypokeimenon or {{Wiki|individual}} [[substance]] that can be [[subject]] but never predicate. |
− | Even when modern epistemology eschewed or at least modified Aristotle’s notion of substance as a substrate for contingent properties, it appealed to substances in the sense that they define the primary subject of a judgment, that is, the judgment’s topic and grammatical subject. | + | Even when {{Wiki|modern}} epistemology eschewed or at least modified Aristotle’s notion of [[substance]] as a substrate for contingent properties, it appealed to {{Wiki|substances}} in the [[sense]] that they define the primary [[subject]] of a [[judgment]], that is, the judgment’s topic and {{Wiki|grammatical}} [[subject]]. |
− | Similar to phenomenologists, Nishida wanted to account for the consciousness that posits such substances and underlies the subject of a judgment. Essays in From That Which Acts to That Which Sees (1927) and subsequent works invert Aristotle’s notion of the hypokeimenon and propose that consciousness is the | + | Similar to [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologists]], Nishida wanted to account for the [[consciousness]] that posits such {{Wiki|substances}} and underlies the [[subject]] of a [[judgment]]. Essays in From That Which Acts to That Which Sees (1927) and subsequent works invert Aristotle’s notion of the hypokeimenon and propose that [[consciousness]] is the “[[transcendental]] predicate” that can never be a [[subject]]; in other words [[consciousness]] in act can never be made an [[object]] of [[consciousness]] that could become a {{Wiki|grammatical}} [[subject]]. |
− | Nishida is aware of the paradox of such formulations that would make consciousness the subject of sentences that describe it, and he sometimes resorts to explicitly paradoxical descriptions such as | + | Nishida is {{Wiki|aware}} of the [[paradox]] of such formulations that would make [[consciousness]] the [[subject]] of sentences that describe it, and he sometimes resorts to explicitly {{Wiki|paradoxical}} descriptions such as “[[seeing]] without a [[seer]]” and “[[seeing]] the [[form]] of the [[formless]], hearing the {{Wiki|voice}} of the voiceless.” |
− | But he again also uses the straightforward metaphor, the “field of consciousness,” to indicate its non-subjective and non-objectifiable character. Consciousness cannot be grasped as the property of an individual substance nor as anything like a substance or underlying substrate itself. It functions as the field that is the opening of world and self. | + | But he again also uses the straightforward {{Wiki|metaphor}}, the “field of [[consciousness]],” to indicate its non-subjective and non-objectifiable [[character]]. [[Consciousness]] cannot be grasped as the property of an {{Wiki|individual}} [[substance]] nor as anything like a [[substance]] or underlying substrate itself. It functions as the field that is the opening of [[world]] and [[self]]. |
− | If judgments describe things and states of affairs and thus would give us access to reality by setting themselves over against that reality, we must step back as it were and consider a wider reality that includes judgments. In other words, we must place judgments that predicate universals of things into a wider field of predication, that is, in the | + | If judgments describe things and states of affairs and thus would give us access to [[reality]] by setting themselves over against that [[reality]], we must step back as it were and consider a wider [[reality]] that includes judgments. In other words, we must place judgments that predicate universals of things into a wider field of predication, that is, in the “[[transcendental]] predicate” of [[consciousness]]. Here Nishida might have further developed a [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] of the agency of predication, but instead he moves to a more [[logical]] account of its scope and developed what he called a predicate [[logic]].[3] He [[thinks]] of universals as fields of possibility that becomes specified or determined (more accurately, that determine themselves) in their particular instantiations. There is a necessary {{Wiki|hierarchy}} of concreteness among universals that Nishida expresses as the order of topoi or places (basho). |
− | Most abstract are the universals that serve as predicates in particular judgments. Judging or predication in turn takes place in the topos of consciousness, which is further concretized as the universal or topos of reflexive self-awareness wherein acts of seeing, knowing, desiring and willing take place. And just as the world of self-awareness enfolds the world of nature described in judgments, it in turn is enfolded in the topos (Nishida calls it “the intelligible | + | Most abstract are the universals that serve as predicates in particular judgments. Judging or predication in turn takes place in the topos of [[consciousness]], which is further concretized as the [[universal]] or topos of reflexive [[self-awareness]] wherein acts of [[seeing]], [[knowing]], [[desiring]] and willing take place. And just as the [[world]] of [[self-awareness]] enfolds the [[world]] of [[nature]] described in judgments, it in turn is enfolded in the topos (Nishida calls it “the intelligible [[world]]”) within which the creative [[self]] pursues {{Wiki|ideal}} values like [[truth]], [[beauty]] and [[goodness]]. Here Nishida echoes the {{Wiki|medieval}}, seemingly all-inclusive transcendentalia that transcend all categories. In his terms, all predication would be a mirroring of the transcendentals of being and of the one (unum), the true (verum), and the good (bonum). But those transcendentals, insofar as they themselves all elude predication, actually point to a more inclusive and undifferentiated topos, [[absolute]] [[nothingness]]. |
− | In summary, Nishida initially formulated his logic of place or topos to counter Neo-Kantian epistemology that took knowledge to be the subject’s form-ruled construction of an objective world. He sought not only to undermine the distinctions between subjective and objective but also to place both sides within a more comprehensive and concrete conception. | + | In summary, Nishida initially formulated his [[logic]] of place or topos to counter Neo-Kantian epistemology that took [[knowledge]] to be the subject’s form-ruled construction of an [[objective world]]. He sought not only to undermine the {{Wiki|distinctions}} between [[subjective]] and [[objective]] but also to place both sides within a more comprehensive and concrete {{Wiki|conception}}. |
− | That is, while he first construed knowledge on the model of self-awareness in which self reflects itself within itself, he also felt compelled to find a locus of non-differentiation behind the distinction between such awareness and things seen from its vantage point. | + | That is, while he first construed [[knowledge]] on the model of [[self-awareness]] in which [[self]] reflects itself within itself, he also felt compelled to find a locus of non-differentiation behind the {{Wiki|distinction}} between such [[awareness]] and things seen from its vantage point. |
− | As non-differentiated and inclusive, that locus is field-like, a metaphor that Nishida at first replaced with the notion of topos or “place” (basho). Then he placed the topos of self-awareness in the even more inclusive and concrete value-forming world. That world of creative activity anticipates what Nishida eventually considered the ultimate topos that defies description, predication, or determination by something beyond or different from it. His logic of place offered an alternative to the logic of substances presupposed in much traditional metaphysics. | + | As non-differentiated and inclusive, that locus is field-like, a {{Wiki|metaphor}} that Nishida at first replaced with the notion of topos or “place” (basho). Then he placed the topos of [[self-awareness]] in the even more inclusive and concrete value-forming [[world]]. That [[world]] of creative [[activity]] anticipates what Nishida eventually considered the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] topos that defies description, predication, or [[determination]] by something beyond or different from it. His [[logic]] of place [[offered]] an alternative to the [[logic]] of {{Wiki|substances}} presupposed in much [[traditional]] [[metaphysics]]. |
− | The logical schema of topoi is paralleled by an ontological account. Nishida articulated the topoi also in terms of what we may call a me-ontology, from the Greek meon or non-being. The topos of being describes the world of nature. The topos of relative nothingness comprises the field of consciousness that is no-thing with respect to the things of which it is conscious. | + | The [[logical]] {{Wiki|schema}} of topoi is paralleled by an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] account. Nishida articulated the topoi also in terms of what we may call a me-ontology, from the {{Wiki|Greek}} meon or [[non-being]]. The topos of being describes the [[world]] of [[nature]]. The topos of [[relative]] [[nothingness]] comprises the field of [[consciousness]] that is no-thing with [[respect]] to the things of which it is [[conscious]]. |
− | This nothingness however is still opposed to being, and so differs from the absolute nothingness that underlies both sides of the opposition. Here and elsewhere Nishida plays on the word for absolute in Japanese, zettai, which literally means breaking through or overcoming opposition. His premise is that the meaning of “to be” is “to be within”; the ultimate “within” is the topos of absolute nothingness. | + | This [[nothingness]] however is still opposed to being, and so differs from the [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] that underlies both sides of the [[opposition]]. Here and elsewhere Nishida plays on the [[word]] for [[absolute]] in [[Japanese]], zettai, which literally means breaking through or [[overcoming]] [[opposition]]. His premise is that the meaning of “to be” is “to be within”; the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] “within” is the topos of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]]. |
− | 3.1 Absolute Nothingness | + | 3.1 [[Absolute]] [[Nothingness]] |
− | The topos of absolute nothingness is the ultimate “within which” all reality takes place. It can be understood as an alternative to a transcendent determiner of the world as conceptualized, for example, in medieval philosophy’s notion of God, Fichte’s transcendental ego, or Husserl’s transcendental subjectivity. | + | The topos of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] is the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] “within which” all [[reality]] takes place. It can be understood as an alternative to a [[transcendent]] determiner of the [[world]] as [[conceptualized]], for example, in {{Wiki|medieval}} philosophy’s notion of [[God]], Fichte’s [[transcendental]] [[ego]], or Husserl’s [[transcendental]] [[subjectivity]]. |
− | Nishida did use the language of transcendence to explain absolute nothingness, saying it transcended the opposition between being and non-being for example; but such language did not indicate any thing, power, or consciousness beyond the world. | + | Nishida did use the [[language]] of {{Wiki|transcendence}} to explain [[absolute]] [[nothingness]], saying it transcended the [[opposition]] between [[being and non-being]] for example; but such [[language]] did not indicate any thing, power, or [[consciousness]] beyond the [[world]]. |
− | Absolute nothingness is infinitely determinable and its determinates form the actual world, but this | + | [[Absolute]] [[nothingness]] is infinitely determinable and its determinates [[form]] the actual [[world]], but this “[[self-determination]]” occurs “without anything that does the determining,” like an agency without an agent. |
− | Equally paradoxical are the positive descriptions Nishida gives it, in spite of the implicit claim that it defies description. Rather than a mere absence of being, meaning, or function, absolute nothingness is active and creative in forming the actual world; and it manifests or awakens to itself through self-awareness. | + | Equally {{Wiki|paradoxical}} are the positive descriptions Nishida gives it, in spite of the implicit claim that it defies description. Rather than a mere absence of being, meaning, or function, [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] is active and creative in forming the actual [[world]]; and it [[manifests]] or awakens to itself through [[self-awareness]]. |
− | It is the foundation of the world and of the self which is a focal point of the world; but it is an uncommon kind of foundation in that it functions through self-negation. It cannot be called | + | It is the foundation of the [[world]] and of the [[self]] which is a focal point of the [[world]]; but it is an uncommon kind of foundation in that it functions through self-negation. It cannot be called “[[absolute]]” unless it negates any particular [[determination]] of it and simultaneously enfolds them all. It is the [[universal]] of universals. Nishida was not able to combine these various descriptions into one coherent notion, but they partially converge in the [[sense]] of an undifferentiated whole that includes all its differentiations. |
Line 298: | Line 298: | ||
− | 3.2 Analogies to the Logic of Place | + | 3.2 Analogies to the [[Logic]] of Place |
− | Nishida intended his theory of place or topos to provide a logical foundation for his previous philosophy of experience and self-awareness. Several overlapping models help make sense of this logic. Nishida drew upon some models explicitly, for example, Plato’s notion of the receptacle (chora) of ideas in the Timeus and Aristotle’s adaptation in his notion of topos in On the Soul. | + | Nishida intended his {{Wiki|theory}} of place or topos to provide a [[logical]] foundation for his previous [[philosophy]] of [[experience]] and [[self-awareness]]. Several overlapping models help make [[sense]] of this [[logic]]. Nishida drew upon some models explicitly, for example, [[Wikipedia:Plato|Plato’s]] notion of the receptacle (chora) of [[ideas]] in the Timeus and Aristotle’s [[adaptation]] in his notion of topos in On the [[Soul]]. |
− | Another model Nishida used early on was the notion of fields in modern physics and relativity theory, in which space-time is a field inseparable from the physical objects within it and determining how (when and where) they exist. Analogously, for Nishida, all perceived and conceptualized objects are “in” the “field of | + | Another model Nishida used early on was the notion of fields in {{Wiki|modern}} [[physics]] and [[relativity]] {{Wiki|theory}}, in which {{Wiki|space-time}} is a field [[inseparable]] from the [[physical objects]] within it and determining how (when and where) they [[exist]]. Analogously, for Nishida, all [[perceived]] and [[conceptualized]] [[objects]] are “in” the “field of [[consciousness]]” (Nishida borrowed the term from {{Wiki|William James}}). |
− | Another early model was the logic of universals that serve as predicates. Particulars or individuals are placed within universals to specify their difference from other particulars or individuals, and less extensive universals are placed within more extensive ones, until one reaches the ultimate, boundless universal called nothingness. | + | Another early model was the [[logic]] of universals that serve as predicates. Particulars or {{Wiki|individuals}} are placed within universals to specify their difference from other particulars or {{Wiki|individuals}}, and less extensive universals are placed within more extensive ones, until one reaches the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]], [[boundless]] [[universal]] called [[nothingness]]. |
− | This | + | This “[[transcendental]] predicate” cannot become the [[subject]] {{Wiki|matter}} of any description or proposition in positive terms, but it is ultimately entailed by every specification. |
− | Other analogies, although not explicitly mentioned by Nishida, nevertheless serve to clarify his logic at least in part. A model of interpretation is relevant: every text has its context, which in turn may be made a text or thematized by appealing to a further context. There is no final context that can be specified without referring to yet another context. | + | Other analogies, although not explicitly mentioned by Nishida, nevertheless serve to clarify his [[logic]] at least in part. A model of [[interpretation]] is relevant: every text has its context, which in turn may be made a text or thematized by appealing to a further context. There is no final context that can be specified without referring to yet another context. |
− | For Nishida this relation would not be settled by invoking the notion of an infinite regress; rather it indicates the necessity of an ultimate context of a different order, one that allows the distinction between a specific text and its context. This ultimately unspecifiable context in Nishida’s terms is called absolute nothingness. | + | For Nishida this [[relation]] would not be settled by invoking the notion of an [[infinite]] regress; rather it indicates the necessity of an [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] context of a different order, one that allows the {{Wiki|distinction}} between a specific text and its context. This ultimately unspecifiable context in Nishida’s terms is called [[absolute]] [[nothingness]]. |
− | The analysis of successful physical theories provides yet another model. Each of Nishida’s successive topoi serves as a level of analysis that resolves contradictions on less comprehensive levels, as Einstein’s relativity theory encompasses Newtonian theory and resolves contradictions in it. But for Nishida the final level that holds differences or contradictions together is ultimately unanalyzable absolute nothingness. | + | The analysis of successful [[physical]] theories provides yet another model. Each of Nishida’s successive topoi serves as a level of analysis that resolves contradictions on less comprehensive levels, as Einstein’s [[relativity]] {{Wiki|theory}} encompasses Newtonian {{Wiki|theory}} and resolves contradictions in it. But for Nishida the final level that holds differences or contradictions together is ultimately unanalyzable [[absolute]] [[nothingness]]. |
− | Despite Nishida’s relative ignorance of modern logic and his identification of predicates with universals, we may also find parallels to his logic of place in mathematical logic: an axiomatic system is a topos that, according to Gödel’s theorem, is not self-explanatory or self-generating since it contains undecidable propositions, and there is no final system with a self-explanatory foundation. Nishida’s absolute nothingness is the place beyond discursive determination. | + | Despite Nishida’s [[relative]] [[ignorance]] of [[modern logic]] and his identification of predicates with universals, we may also find parallels to his [[logic]] of place in {{Wiki|mathematical}} [[logic]]: an axiomatic system is a topos that, according to Gödel’s theorem, is not self-explanatory or self-generating since it contains undecidable propositions, and there is no final system with a self-explanatory foundation. Nishida’s [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] is the place beyond discursive [[determination]]. |
− | Discourse analysis also suggests parallels: it analyzes how a discourse is framed or directed to an audience with certain interests, but the analysis too has its own frame that does not terminate in any definitive or final frame. Foundationalist theories of knowledge and reality might seem to provide a model of Nishida’s logic of place, but in Nishida the metaphor of grounding gives way to that of placing, locating, or encompassing, and in any case the ultimate place is more an Abgrund or void than a positive ground. | + | [[Discourse]] analysis also suggests parallels: it analyzes how a [[discourse]] is framed or directed to an audience with certain interests, but the analysis too has its [[own]] frame that does not terminate in any definitive or final frame. Foundationalist theories of [[knowledge]] and [[reality]] might seem to provide a model of Nishida’s [[logic]] of place, but in Nishida the {{Wiki|metaphor}} of grounding gives way to that of placing, locating, or encompassing, and in any case the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] place is more an Abgrund or [[void]] than a positive ground. |
Line 336: | Line 336: | ||
− | 4. Theory of the Historical World | + | 4. {{Wiki|Theory}} of the Historical [[World]] |
Line 344: | Line 344: | ||
− | It is clear that Nishida proposed his various topoi not as static contexts terminating in an ultimate genus, but rather as a dynamic process of contextualization or world-formation. This always implied the temporality of the | + | It is clear that Nishida proposed his various topoi not as static contexts terminating in an [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] genus, but rather as a dynamic process of contextualization or world-formation. This always implied the temporality of the “[[self-aware]]” [[world]], and not merely time as a [[dimension]] of the [[physical world]]. |
− | Nevertheless, Nishida did not explicitly take account of the historical nature of the world until the early 1930s, after his critics, in particular his younger colleague, Tanabe Hajime, and his former students, Miki Kiyoshi and Tosaka Jun, turned his attention to the historical dimension of reality and human action. | + | Nevertheless, Nishida did not explicitly take account of the historical [[nature]] of the [[world]] until the early 1930s, after his critics, in particular his younger colleague, [[Tanabe]] Hajime, and his former students, Miki Kiyoshi and Tosaka Jun, turned his [[attention]] to the historical [[dimension]] of [[reality]] and [[human]] [[action]]. |
− | The critics suggested that Nishida ignored the world determined by individual human action by replacing individual human subjectivity with trans-individual experience or consciousness and eventually shifting human agency to the world as a universal. In response, Nishida began to articulate the world as a dialectical universal. | + | The critics suggested that Nishida ignored the [[world]] determined by {{Wiki|individual}} [[human]] [[action]] by replacing {{Wiki|individual}} [[human]] [[subjectivity]] with trans-individual [[experience]] or [[consciousness]] and eventually shifting [[human]] agency to the [[world]] as a [[universal]]. In response, Nishida began to articulate the [[world]] as a [[dialectical]] [[universal]]. |
− | The basic idea is that the world is a place of mediation between acting individuals. It is not a transcendent topos that one-sidedly determines individuals but a topos that arises with them through their creative interactions. There are two sides of this idea to consider: the world and the interacting individuals. | + | The basic [[idea]] is that the [[world]] is a place of [[mediation]] between acting {{Wiki|individuals}}. It is not a [[transcendent]] topos that one-sidedly determines {{Wiki|individuals}} but a topos that arises with them through their creative interactions. There are two sides of this [[idea]] to consider: the [[world]] and the interacting {{Wiki|individuals}}. |
Line 356: | Line 356: | ||
− | We conceptualize the formation of the world as history, but must think of history in terms of the logic of place and not simply as a temporal process. At any moment the world in process mirrors the indeterminacy or openness of absolute nothingness and contains the conditions for novelty and future possibilities; however it also encompasses everything that has already been determined. In Nishida’s words, the historical world proceeds “from the created to the creating.” | + | We conceptualize the formation of the [[world]] as history, but must think of history in terms of the [[logic]] of place and not simply as a {{Wiki|temporal}} process. At any [[moment]] the [[world]] in process mirrors the indeterminacy or [[openness]] of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] and contains the [[conditions]] for novelty and {{Wiki|future}} possibilities; however it also encompasses everything that has already been determined. In Nishida’s words, the historical [[world]] proceeds “from the created to the creating.” |
− | And it so proceeds not in a linear fashion, as if viewed from some point outside the world, but rather “in” every moment or, conversely, out of an “eternal now” or | + | And it so proceeds not in a linear fashion, as if viewed from some point outside the [[world]], but rather “in” every [[moment]] or, conversely, out of an “eternal now” or “[[absolute]] {{Wiki|present}}” that describes the topos of its continual creation. This {{Wiki|present}} in its [[absolute]] presence is the place where history can happen precisely because it enfolds the {{Wiki|past}} though is not entirely determined by the {{Wiki|past}} and it holds the {{Wiki|future}} as [[infinite]] possibility. It is eternal or [[absolute]] in the [[sense]] that it contains [[infinite]] time by negating (fixed) time (NKZ VIII, 76ff.). Viewed in terms of the [[absolute]] present—the ever-present juncture between a determined {{Wiki|past}} and an open future—the [[world]] appears as a “continuity of discontinuities.” |
− | Similarly, we conceptualize the historical world sometimes as produced out of nature by human work and activity, sometimes as producing the individuals who interact in it, but we should think of it primarily as the mediating place of interactive creation. Individuals create their identities through their interactions in the world, and that world is continually created with them. (Nishida’s idea of a mediating place finds a distant analogue in Einstein’s theory of gravitational space, where space is not independent of the physical objects in it but rather is shaped by them). The historical world forms itself through the actions of embodied individuals who mutually form each other. Adapting a phenomenological perspective, Nishida argues that the historical world as the most concrete topos of our reality must be the starting point for understanding the more abstract world of life and even more abstract natural world. | + | Similarly, we conceptualize the historical [[world]] sometimes as produced out of [[nature]] by [[human]] work and [[activity]], sometimes as producing the {{Wiki|individuals}} who interact in it, but we should think of it primarily as the mediating place of interactive creation. {{Wiki|Individuals}} create their {{Wiki|identities}} through their interactions in the [[world]], and that [[world]] is continually created with them. (Nishida’s [[idea]] of a mediating place finds a distant analogue in Einstein’s {{Wiki|theory}} of gravitational [[space]], where [[space]] is not {{Wiki|independent}} of the [[physical objects]] in it but rather is shaped by them). The historical [[world]] [[forms]] itself through the [[actions]] of [[embodied]] {{Wiki|individuals}} who mutually [[form]] each other. Adapting a {{Wiki|phenomenological}} {{Wiki|perspective}}, Nishida argues that the historical [[world]] as the most concrete topos of our [[reality]] must be the starting point for [[understanding]] the more abstract [[world]] of [[life]] and even more abstract natural [[world]]. |
− | Gradually Nishida came to recognize the importance of embodiment for human interaction and communication, and introduced the notion of the expressive or historical body. The body is not primarily a physical object and product of the natural world, but a historical subject and co-creator of the world. Insofar as the many historical bodies of the one world differ from each another, they too form a “discontinuous continuity.” Nishida was fond of calling this type of totality, which holds together differences without sublating them into a higher unity, a “self-identity of contradictories.” | + | Gradually Nishida came to [[recognize]] the importance of [[embodiment]] for [[human]] interaction and [[communication]], and introduced the notion of the expressive or historical [[body]]. The [[body]] is not primarily a [[physical object]] and product of the natural [[world]], but a historical [[subject]] and co-creator of the [[world]]. Insofar as the many historical [[bodies]] of the one [[world]] differ from each another, they too [[form]] a “discontinuous continuity.” Nishida was fond of calling this type of {{Wiki|totality}}, which holds together differences without sublating them into a higher {{Wiki|unity}}, a “self-identity of contradictories.” |
− | Two parts of Nishida’s theory deserve further explication: his novel conception of enactive intuition and his explanation of the relations between self & other and one & many. | + | Two parts of Nishida’s {{Wiki|theory}} deserve further explication: his {{Wiki|novel}} {{Wiki|conception}} of enactive [[intuition]] and his explanation of the relations between [[self]] & other and one & many. |
− | 4.1 Enactive Intuition | + | 4.1 Enactive {{Wiki|Intuition}} |
− | In attempting to explain the formation and working of the historical world, Nishida coined the term “action-oriented | + | In attempting to explain the formation and working of the historical [[world]], Nishida coined the term “action-oriented [[intuition]]” or “enactive [[intuition]]” (kōi-teki chokkan). His texts suggest a reciprocity between [[action]] and [[intuition]], so that we could also speak of “intuition-oriented [[action]]” or simply of “action-intuition.” Here again Nishida sought to discover the topos or common [[space]] that underlies a {{Wiki|distinction}}, this time between [[intuition]] or [[seeing]] as a more or less passive {{Wiki|reception}} of the [[world]] and its [[objects]], and [[action]] as the human-engendered production of the [[world]]. Hence, this is another case of his “self-identity of contradictories.” The common [[space]] is the enactive or performative [[intuition]] exemplified by artistic creation. |
− | For example, we might ordinarily conceive of the artist as a pre-given entity who views, is inspired by, and utilizes pre-given things in the world around her as she then goes about making her work. The production of the work would then be a causative process contributing in turn to the production of the historical world. We might also understand the work as an objectification of the artist, an expression of her inner spirit that externalizes and actualizes it. Nishida envisioned an alternative, however. | + | For example, we might ordinarily [[conceive]] of the artist as a pre-given [[entity]] who [[views]], is inspired by, and utilizes pre-given things in the [[world]] around her as she then goes about making her work. The production of the work would then be a [[causative]] process contributing in turn to the production of the historical [[world]]. We might also understand the work as an [[objectification]] of the artist, an expression of her inner [[spirit]] that externalizes and actualizes it. Nishida envisioned an alternative, however. |
− | For Nishida, the artist takes in or intuits the world and transforms or enacts it, both of which are but two moments in a single unfolding—not only of the world but of the artist as well. Both artist and work are formed mutually and are reflected in one another. Whereas this mutual formation can be described in terms of a causative process taking time, with the person first intuiting or internalizing and then acting or externalizing, Nishida described it in terms of the place or topos wherein intuiting entails acting and acting entails intuiting, and wherein the difference between internal and external collapses. Granted, the work can take on a life of its own as an object of appreciation or criticism, but it always carries its reference to the artist, as the identity of the artist likewise cannot be separated from her work. | + | For Nishida, the artist takes in or intuits the [[world]] and transforms or enacts it, both of which are but two moments in a single unfolding—not only of the [[world]] but of the artist as well. Both artist and work are formed mutually and are reflected in one another. Whereas this mutual formation can be described in terms of a [[causative]] process taking time, with the [[person]] first intuiting or internalizing and then acting or externalizing, Nishida described it in terms of the place or topos wherein intuiting entails acting and acting entails intuiting, and wherein the difference between internal and external collapses. Granted, the work can take on a [[life]] of its [[own]] as an [[object]] of [[appreciation]] or [[criticism]], but it always carries its reference to the artist, as the [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] of the artist likewise cannot be separated from her work. |
− | Artistic creation is only one example of such poiesis, as Nishida called it. Scientific experimentation also provides an example of enactive intuition insofar as experiments require the performance of a body acting and understanding through instruments (NKZ VIII, 326). Enactive or performative intuition is operative in praxis or political-social action as well, insofar as it grasps the world as including the self. Nishida emphasized that enactive intuition is a bodily achievement, the performance of an embodied individual who in turn is formed by the world; again, both body and world must be conceived as historical. While enactive intuition pertains to the dialectical way the individual historical body forms and is formed by the world, the way the world forms is described by the phrase “from the created to the creating.” | + | Artistic creation is only one example of such poiesis, as Nishida called it. [[Scientific]] experimentation also provides an example of enactive [[intuition]] insofar as experiments require the performance of a [[body]] acting and [[understanding]] through instruments (NKZ VIII, 326). Enactive or performative [[intuition]] is operative in praxis or political-social [[action]] as well, insofar as it [[grasps]] the [[world]] as [[including]] the [[self]]. Nishida emphasized that enactive [[intuition]] is a [[bodily]] [[achievement]], the performance of an [[embodied]] {{Wiki|individual}} who in turn is formed by the [[world]]; again, both [[body]] and [[world]] must be [[conceived]] as historical. While enactive [[intuition]] pertains to the [[dialectical]] way the {{Wiki|individual}} historical [[body]] [[forms]] and is formed by the [[world]], the way the [[world]] [[forms]] is described by the [[phrase]] “from the created to the creating.” |
− | 4.2 Theory of Relations: Self and Other, One and Many | + | 4.2 {{Wiki|Theory}} of Relations: [[Self]] and Other, One and Many |
− | Self and Other | + | [[Self]] and Other |
− | We can shift the focus from the action of the individual historical body to the interaction between distinct individuals, once again with the world as the mediating space of mutual formation. In fact, Nishida maintains that the individual, precisely as distinct, entails a plurality of interrelated individuals. The relation between “I and Thou” was the first part that Nishida considered, although he continued to intertwine that relation with an internal relation in self-awareness. Where his previous analysis of individual self-awareness described it as a self-reflection of the universal of self-awareness, his description now incorporated the dimension of recognition. My recognition of you as not me makes me who I am, and your recognition of me as not-you makes you who you are. Each is a relative other to the self. | + | We can shift the focus from the [[action]] of the {{Wiki|individual}} historical [[body]] to the interaction between {{Wiki|distinct}} {{Wiki|individuals}}, once again with the [[world]] as the mediating [[space]] of mutual formation. In fact, Nishida maintains that the {{Wiki|individual}}, precisely as {{Wiki|distinct}}, entails a plurality of {{Wiki|interrelated}} {{Wiki|individuals}}. The [[relation]] between “I and Thou” was the first part that Nishida considered, although he continued to intertwine that [[relation]] with an internal [[relation]] in [[self-awareness]]. Where his previous analysis of {{Wiki|individual}} [[self-awareness]] described it as a self-reflection of the [[universal]] of [[self-awareness]], his description now incorporated the [[dimension]] of {{Wiki|recognition}}. My {{Wiki|recognition}} of you as not me makes me who I am, and your {{Wiki|recognition}} of me as not-you makes you who you are. Each is a [[relative]] other to the [[self]]. |
− | That Hegelian analysis is incomplete, however, without the recognition of the absolute other in the self’s interior. This other, recalling Nishida’s notion of absolute, does not exclude the self; rather it constitutes self-identity as continually negating what it has been. My personal self-awareness arises not when I recognize my identity through memory, for example, nor simply when I encounter an other I; rather it arises in experiencing the groundlessness of my own existence, in recognizing what is absolutely other to a substantial self-same self. Recognizing the absolute other within constitutes not simply a reflexive self-awareness but a self-awakening, a realizing of the | + | That Hegelian analysis is incomplete, however, without the {{Wiki|recognition}} of the [[absolute]] other in the self’s interior. This other, recalling Nishida’s notion of [[absolute]], does not exclude the [[self]]; rather it constitutes self-identity as continually negating what it has been. My personal [[self-awareness]] arises not when I [[recognize]] my [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] through [[memory]], for example, nor simply when I encounter an other I; rather it arises in experiencing the groundlessness of my [[own]] [[existence]], in [[recognizing]] what is absolutely other to a substantial self-same [[self]]. [[Recognizing]] the [[absolute]] other within constitutes not simply a reflexive [[self-awareness]] but a [[self-awakening]], a [[realizing]] of the “[[true self]].” |
− | Nishida’s term for self-awareness is jikaku, which can also be translated as self-awakening, a Buddhist reading he undoubtedly intends. Nishida allows for the Buddhist view that there is actually no self to awaken by referring to the self-awakening of absolute nothingness; its awakening is the awakening of the | + | Nishida’s term for [[self-awareness]] is [[jikaku]], which can also be translated as [[self-awakening]], a [[Buddhist]] reading he undoubtedly intends. Nishida allows for the [[Buddhist view]] that there is actually [[no self]] to [[awaken]] by referring to the [[self-awakening]] of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]]; its [[awakening]] is the [[awakening]] of the “[[true self]].” [[Absolute]] [[nothingness]] in [[action]], as it were, entails a {{Wiki|negation}} (of a substantial, self-same [[self]]) and an [[affirmation]] (of the [[true self]]). In the manner of self-negation, I am one with you while not being the same as you. Not only between us does a “continuity of [[absolute]] discontinuities” obtain, but also within each of us, insofar as our [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] is in continual formation. In the end, then, Nishida denies the substantiality of the [[self]] and rejects both the radical alterity of other persons and the {{Wiki|transcendence}} of an [[absolute]] other, in the guise of [[God]] for example. |
One and Many | One and Many | ||
− | Eventually Nishida saw that the “I-You” relation does not exhaust the discontinuous continuity of our being. We must also take into account the third party, the relative other, “he” or “she,” who forms at least an implicit reference to every “I-you” interaction. Nishida seems intent not so much on explaining alterity, however, as preserving interdependent individuality, which of course still requires difference. He has in mind the individuation of all phenomena but begins with the prototype of individuality, the self-aware human person, who is more concretely an individual than other single living beings, not to speak of individuated atoms or particles at the most abstract level. What determines individuality at the most concrete level is the one historical world that functions dialectically as the place or medium of interaction among innumerable individuals. The world is one yet many; individuals are many yet one in their mutual determination. (Nishida uses the Buddhist connective soku to indicate the relation between one and many and to emphasize their inherent reversibility. Soku translates roughly as “and at the same time”: “one and at the same time many”, “many and at the same time one.” Otherwise, however, his terminology in this part of his philosophy is often more Hegelian than Buddhist.) | + | Eventually Nishida saw that the “I-You” [[relation]] does not exhaust the discontinuous continuity of our being. We must also take into account the third party, the [[relative]] other, “he” or “she,” who [[forms]] at least an implicit reference to every “I-you” interaction. Nishida seems intent not so much on explaining alterity, however, as preserving [[interdependent]] [[individuality]], which of course still requires difference. He has in [[mind]] the individuation of all [[phenomena]] but begins with the prototype of [[individuality]], the [[self-aware]] [[human]] [[person]], who is more concretely an {{Wiki|individual}} than other single [[living beings]], not to speak of individuated [[atoms]] or {{Wiki|particles}} at the most abstract level. What determines [[individuality]] at the most concrete level is the one historical [[world]] that functions dialectically as the place or {{Wiki|medium}} of interaction among {{Wiki|innumerable}} {{Wiki|individuals}}. The [[world]] is one yet many; {{Wiki|individuals}} are many yet one in their mutual [[determination]]. (Nishida uses the [[Buddhist]] connective [[soku]] to indicate the [[relation]] between one and many and to {{Wiki|emphasize}} their [[inherent]] reversibility. [[Soku]] translates roughly as “and at the same time”: “one and at the same time many”, “many and at the same time one.” Otherwise, however, his {{Wiki|terminology}} in this part of his [[philosophy]] is often more Hegelian than [[Buddhist]].) |
− | Nishida’s own formulations once again make use of the pattern of an undifferentiated whole differentiating or determining itself, in this case as distinct individuals. Although the topological account of a self- or immanently determining historical world seems to invoke more spatial than temporal notions, the description of this topos as the space wherein individuals interact and mutually determine one another is meant to accommodate the temporal dimension as well. The world is formed in conjunction with the individual embodied selves who interact in it; like Einstein’s space-time, it is not independent of the things “in” it and does not preexist them. But for Nishida the realization or awareness of individual selves entails the realization or awareness of the world as well. As mentioned earlier, the world too is | + | Nishida’s [[own]] formulations once again make use of the pattern of an undifferentiated whole differentiating or determining itself, in this case as {{Wiki|distinct}} {{Wiki|individuals}}. Although the topological account of a [[self]]- or immanently determining historical [[world]] seems to invoke more spatial than {{Wiki|temporal}} notions, the description of this topos as the [[space]] wherein {{Wiki|individuals}} interact and mutually determine one another is meant to accommodate the {{Wiki|temporal}} [[dimension]] as well. The [[world]] is formed in {{Wiki|conjunction}} with the {{Wiki|individual}} [[embodied]] selves who interact in it; like Einstein’s {{Wiki|space-time}}, it is not {{Wiki|independent}} of the things “in” it and does not preexist them. But for Nishida the [[realization]] or [[awareness]] of {{Wiki|individual}} selves entails the [[realization]] or [[awareness]] of the [[world]] as well. As mentioned earlier, the [[world]] too is “[[self-aware]]” (jikaku-teki) not only in the [[sense]] of being self-reflexive but also in the [[sense]] of [[realizing]] and [[recognizing]] itself via its {{Wiki|individual}} selves who are its “focal points.” Here we see another instance of Nishida’s way of universalizing first-person [[experience]]. In the discussions of the one and the many, however, Nishida relatively neglected the notion of self-awakening––the other, Buddhist-tinged reading of [[jikaku]] that is such an important part of the I-You [[relation]]. |
− | 5. Nishida’s Theology: the Finite Self meets the Absolute | + | 5. Nishida’s {{Wiki|Theology}}: the Finite [[Self]] meets the [[Absolute]] |
− | Toward the end of his life, perhaps thinking of the significance of death for understanding individuality, perhaps re-considering the theme of self-awakening as a kind of death and re-birth, Nishida delved deeper into the relation between the individual finite human self and the absolute or God. In his view, this relation logically defines the place of religion. Experientially it comes to the fore in death. We will consider the meaning of death first, then the nature of God or the absolute in relation to the finite self. | + | Toward the end of his [[life]], perhaps [[thinking]] of the significance of [[death]] for [[understanding]] [[individuality]], perhaps re-considering the theme of [[self-awakening]] as a kind of [[death]] and [[re-birth]], Nishida delved deeper into the [[relation]] between the {{Wiki|individual}} finite [[human]] [[self]] and the [[absolute]] or [[God]]. In his view, this [[relation]] [[logically]] defines the place of [[religion]]. Experientially it comes to the fore in [[death]]. We will consider the meaning of [[death]] first, then the [[nature]] of [[God]] or the [[absolute]] in [[relation]] to the finite [[self]]. |
− | The theme of personal death is absent in Nishida’s early work on pure experience and self-awareness, and mentioned only abstractly in essays on the historical world and the self, for example: “In absolute dialectics, mediation as absolute negation is mediation as absolute death, living by dying absolutely” (NKZ VII, 314). In the last completed essay, “The Logic of Place and the Religious Worldview” (1945), Nishida is more experiential. Death is not an event at the end of one’s life but penetrates life at each and every moment. It is the ever-present opening, so to speak, where one’s utter finitude can come to light. Insofar as this is the finitude of the individual self, it also implies a logic of individuation where the role of other relative selves is diminished. “I am myself by knowing my own | + | The theme of personal [[death]] is absent in Nishida’s early work on [[pure experience]] and [[self-awareness]], and mentioned only abstractly in {{Wiki|essays}} on the historical [[world]] and the [[self]], for example: “In [[absolute]] [[dialectics]], [[mediation]] as [[absolute negation]] is [[mediation]] as [[absolute]] [[death]], living by dying absolutely” (NKZ VII, 314). In the last completed essay, “The [[Logic]] of Place and the [[Religious]] Worldview” (1945), Nishida is more experiential. [[Death]] is not an event at the end of one’s [[life]] but penetrates [[life]] at each and every [[moment]]. It is the ever-present opening, so to speak, where one’s utter finitude can come to {{Wiki|light}}. Insofar as this is the finitude of the [[individual self]], it also implies a [[logic]] of individuation where the role of other [[relative]] selves is diminished. “I am myself by [[knowing]] my [[own]] [[death]]” (NKZ XI, 420) is both a declaration of [[existential]] [[self-awareness]] and a statement of what makes me uniquely me. What makes me an {{Wiki|individual}} is not merely my differences from others nor my [[sameness]] with some [[essential]] core; it is precisely what most makes me not me, what negates me, in any [[moment]] of [[action]]. In this context, [[death]] {{Wiki|signifies}} the self-negation of the finite [[self]]. |
− | If death is an ever-present opening, the other side of that opening, so to speak, is the absolute. To die is to stand vis-à-vis the absolute. In the discussion of the “I-You” relation, this term appeared as the absolute other in one’s interior; here it shifts to the absolute in contradistinction to finite beings. Nishida calls it God as well, but makes clear that he is not referring to a personal, transcendent being. If transcendence is involved, it is a going beyond by going within. He also implies that it is not synonymous with absolute nothingness. If relative nothingness as opposed to being is implied, it is in the verbal sense of self-negating. The absolute arises through its own self-negation and inclusion of the relative self. It does not die in the sense that relative beings do, for it embraces all others whereas they, by being individual, exclude others. God cannot be wholly transcendent to or exclusive of the self or the world. Even Nishida’s early work, An Inquiry Into the Good , had spoken of God in a way that undermined the notion of a transcendent being outside the world; it conceived of God as the infinite activity of unification at work behind the articulations of spirit and nature out of pure experience. | + | If [[death]] is an ever-present opening, the other side of that opening, so to speak, is the [[absolute]]. To [[die]] is to stand vis-à-vis the [[absolute]]. In the [[discussion]] of the “I-You” [[relation]], this term appeared as the [[absolute]] other in one’s interior; here it shifts to the [[absolute]] in contradistinction to finite [[beings]]. Nishida calls it [[God]] as well, but makes clear that he is not referring to a personal, [[transcendent]] being. If {{Wiki|transcendence}} is involved, it is a going beyond by going within. He also implies that it is not {{Wiki|synonymous}} with [[absolute]] [[nothingness]]. If [[relative]] [[nothingness]] as opposed to being is implied, it is in the [[verbal]] [[sense]] of self-negating. The [[absolute]] arises through its [[own]] self-negation and inclusion of the [[relative]] [[self]]. It does not [[die]] in the [[sense]] that [[relative]] [[beings]] do, for it embraces all others whereas they, by being {{Wiki|individual}}, exclude others. [[God]] cannot be wholly [[transcendent]] to or exclusive of the [[self]] or the [[world]]. Even Nishida’s early work, An Inquiry Into the Good , had spoken of [[God]] in a way that undermined the notion of a [[transcendent]] being outside the [[world]]; it [[conceived]] of [[God]] as the [[infinite]] [[activity]] of unification at work behind the articulations of [[spirit]] and [[nature]] out of [[pure experience]]. |
− | In his final essay, Nishida admits that his notion of an absolute totally embracing the relative, even in its diabolical forms, is more in tune with a Mahayana Buddhist tradition than with the Christian sources that inspired him. To express the relation between a God and the relative finite self, Nishida introduces a new term, “inverse correlation”(gyaku taiō). This relation is another instance of opposites held together in a unity, a kind of “self-identity of contradictories,” but this time not a symmetrical one. The more one faces one’s death, the negation of one’s life as an individual, the more acutely one is self-aware as an individual. The closer the finite self approaches God the stronger the difference between them becomes. This peculiar kind of relation implies that God and the relative self are inseparable but asymmetrically co-dependent. God or the absolute embraces and never excludes the human or relative, and the relative self never coincides with or dissolves into God. Nishida’s inverse correlation is perhaps comparable to some theological notions of non-reciprocal dependence, where for example it is said that God is my being yet I am not God’s being. But in Nishida’s case, insofar as the distinction entails an undifferentiated source of their difference, an absolute nothingness, the more that source is contacted the stronger the distinction holds. | + | In his final essay, Nishida admits that his notion of an [[absolute]] totally embracing the [[relative]], even in its diabolical [[forms]], is more in tune with a [[Mahayana Buddhist tradition]] than with the [[Christian]] sources that inspired him. To express the [[relation]] between a [[God]] and the [[relative]] finite [[self]], Nishida introduces a new term, “inverse correlation”(gyaku taiō). This [[relation]] is another instance of opposites held together in a {{Wiki|unity}}, a kind of “self-identity of contradictories,” but this time not a symmetrical one. The more one faces one’s [[death]], the {{Wiki|negation}} of one’s [[life]] as an {{Wiki|individual}}, the more acutely one is [[self-aware]] as an {{Wiki|individual}}. The closer the finite [[self]] approaches [[God]] the stronger the difference between them becomes. This peculiar kind of [[relation]] implies that [[God]] and the [[relative]] [[self]] are [[inseparable]] but asymmetrically co-dependent. [[God]] or the [[absolute]] embraces and never excludes the [[human]] or [[relative]], and the [[relative]] [[self]] never coincides with or dissolves into [[God]]. Nishida’s inverse correlation is perhaps comparable to some {{Wiki|theological}} notions of non-reciprocal [[dependence]], where for example it is said that [[God]] is my being yet I am not [[God’s]] being. But in Nishida’s case, insofar as the {{Wiki|distinction}} entails an undifferentiated source of their difference, an [[absolute]] [[nothingness]], the more that source is contacted the stronger the {{Wiki|distinction}} holds. |
− | 6. Political Theory: Religion, Culture, and Nations | + | 6. {{Wiki|Political}} {{Wiki|Theory}}: [[Religion]], {{Wiki|Culture}}, and Nations |
− | Nishida’s discussion of the absolute and the finite self does not neglect the notion of religion and its relation to culture and the nation-state. These themes already formed an integral part of his theory of the historical world but became all the more pressing in a time of world war. The concern with death was perhaps as much a political as a personal matter for Nishida, whose health in 1945 was quickly failing. In one respect, he distanced himself from his milieu where everyday life was dominated by an authoritarian state. In his last completed essay, he focuses on the individual in relation to an absolute that in no way is subject to an absolutist state. His notion of the essentiality of religion is remarkably individualistic, removed from all social contingencies. He locates the core of religion in the heart of the individual: religious awareness arises in one’s knowing one’s own death. | + | Nishida’s [[discussion]] of the [[absolute]] and the finite [[self]] does not neglect the notion of [[religion]] and its [[relation]] to {{Wiki|culture}} and the nation-state. These themes already formed an integral part of his {{Wiki|theory}} of the historical [[world]] but became all the more pressing in a time of [[world]] [[war]]. The [[concern]] with [[death]] was perhaps as much a {{Wiki|political}} as a personal {{Wiki|matter}} for Nishida, whose [[health]] in 1945 was quickly failing. In one [[respect]], he distanced himself from his {{Wiki|milieu}} where everyday [[life]] was dominated by an {{Wiki|authoritarian}} [[state]]. In his last completed essay, he focuses on the {{Wiki|individual}} in [[relation]] to an [[absolute]] that in no way is [[subject]] to an [[absolutist]] [[state]]. His notion of the [[essentiality]] of [[religion]] is remarkably individualistic, removed from all {{Wiki|social}} contingencies. He locates the core of [[religion]] in the [[heart]] of the {{Wiki|individual}}: [[religious]] [[awareness]] arises in one’s [[knowing]] one’s [[own]] [[death]]. |
− | On the other hand, Nishida recognizes that religion is a social and cultural phenomenon, and that the contemporary individual is a subject of a state. He seems however to reverse any implied priority of culture over religion and state over individual: it is because culture is religious in its core that we find religion in every culture; and obedience to the nation must be based on true religious awareness. To be sure, writing under a totalitarian government in 1945, Nishida couches his statements carefully in language that would deter his imprisonment on grounds of lèse majesté. He also says, for example, that insofar as the individual self is historically formed it must be understood as a nationally identified self; and further that it is selfish merely to seek one’s own peace of mind. In the end, Nishida remains ambiguous about the extent to which individuals are, or should be, formed by the will of the state, and whether religion can or should criticize the state or society. | + | On the other hand, Nishida [[recognizes]] that [[religion]] is a {{Wiki|social}} and {{Wiki|cultural}} [[phenomenon]], and that the contemporary {{Wiki|individual}} is a [[subject]] of a [[state]]. He seems however to reverse any implied priority of {{Wiki|culture}} over [[religion]] and [[state]] over {{Wiki|individual}}: it is because {{Wiki|culture}} is [[religious]] in its core that we find [[religion]] in every {{Wiki|culture}}; and {{Wiki|obedience}} to the {{Wiki|nation}} must be based on true [[religious]] [[awareness]]. To be sure, [[writing]] under a totalitarian government in 1945, Nishida couches his statements carefully in [[language]] that would deter his imprisonment on grounds of lèse majesté. He also says, for example, that insofar as the [[individual self]] is historically formed it must be understood as a nationally identified [[self]]; and further that it is [[selfish]] merely to seek one’s [[own]] [[peace]] of [[mind]]. In the end, Nishida remains {{Wiki|ambiguous}} about the extent to which {{Wiki|individuals}} are, or should be, formed by the will of the [[state]], and whether [[religion]] can or should criticize the [[state]] or [[society]]. |
− | To say that culture is essentially religious means that it too is an | + | To say that {{Wiki|culture}} is [[essentially]] [[religious]] means that it too is an “[[affirmation]] of the self-negating [[absolute]]” (NKZ XI, 458). [[Religion]] and {{Wiki|culture}} are each framed in the singular here, as something [[essential]] to all [[religions]] and cultures in the plural. At this level {{Wiki|culture}} and [[religion]] function almost as regulative [[ideas]]. They are not the result but the telos of the one [[world]] forming its self-identity. Nishida’s formulations recapitulate much of his {{Wiki|theory}} of the historical [[world]]. As the various {{Wiki|ethnic}} peoples in the [[world]] become {{Wiki|aware}} of themselves as constituents of a global [[world]], that is, as they become “world-historical” nations, they [[mirror]] the formation of the historical [[world]]. As [[self-aware]] and globally historical, the [[world]] will be mirrored variously in each {{Wiki|nation}}. |
− | If we hear Hegelian echoes in these formulations, we should also note Nishida’s difference from Hegel: the formation of the “world-historical” world does not imply a hierarchy of cultures evolving as forms of increasing rationality; and it is exemplified in the everyday, as Nishida says, not the exceptional. Nishida’s global world seems more open to a genuine pluralism of cultures, world religions and national identities. Each can retain its uniqueness but to do so each must become self-aware by becoming aware of the plurality, by relativizing or negating itself. This self-negation creates the space in which true intercultural encounter can take place. Nishida implies that the proper relation between cultures is parallel to that between “I and Thou.” In simpler language: “A true world culture will be formed only by various cultures preserving their own respective viewpoints, but simultaneously developing themselves through global | + | If we hear Hegelian echoes in these formulations, we should also note Nishida’s difference from [[Wikipedia:Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]]: the formation of the “world-historical” [[world]] does not imply a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} of cultures evolving as [[forms]] of increasing {{Wiki|rationality}}; and it is exemplified in the everyday, as Nishida says, not the [[exceptional]]. Nishida’s global [[world]] seems more open to a genuine [[pluralism]] of cultures, [[world]] [[religions]] and national {{Wiki|identities}}. Each can retain its [[uniqueness]] but to do so each must become [[self-aware]] by becoming {{Wiki|aware}} of the plurality, by relativizing or negating itself. This self-negation creates the [[space]] in which true intercultural encounter can take place. Nishida implies that the proper [[relation]] between cultures is parallel to that between “I and Thou.” In simpler [[language]]: “A true [[world]] {{Wiki|culture}} will be formed only by various cultures preserving their [[own]] respective viewpoints, but simultaneously developing themselves through global [[mediation]]” (NKZ VII, pp. 452–3). |
− | Nevertheless a special place is accorded the nation of Japan. The Japanese nation is in a position to foster not only an awareness of the East but also a global awareness on the part of every nation. For Japan is the nation in Asia that has best retained Asian traditions while adapting Western technology and values. In the new world order Japan can stand for Asia, and stand against the domination of the West. Nishida’s language, perhaps deliberately ambiguous to avoid his incarceration, ostensibly wavers as to whether this special mission describes Japan’s calling, what it can be for the world, or refers to its current practice in its war-time struggle with other nations. A charitable reading of Nishida’s statements on the special place of Japan interprets them as advocating that his country overcome its outdated vision of itself as a colonizing nation, and embrace a global conception of itself as a nation interacting with other nations in a world of mutually defining equals.[4] A more critical reading interprets these statements as falsely absolutizing the particular nation of Japan, suggesting that Japan embraces other nations of the East which is abstractly opposed to the West. Similar challenges face us in the twenty-first century not only in a world of continuing imperialism and contesting nations with different religious and cultural traditions but also in single nations of multicultural composition. | + | Nevertheless a special place is accorded the {{Wiki|nation}} of [[Japan]]. The [[Japanese]] {{Wiki|nation}} is in a position to foster not only an [[awareness]] of the [[East]] but also a global [[awareness]] on the part of every {{Wiki|nation}}. For [[Japan]] is the {{Wiki|nation}} in {{Wiki|Asia}} that has best retained {{Wiki|Asian}} [[traditions]] while adapting [[Western]] technology and values. In the new [[world]] order [[Japan]] can stand for {{Wiki|Asia}}, and stand against the {{Wiki|domination}} of the [[West]]. Nishida’s [[language]], perhaps deliberately {{Wiki|ambiguous}} to avoid his incarceration, ostensibly wavers as to whether this special [[mission]] describes {{Wiki|Japan’s}} calling, what it can be for the [[world]], or refers to its current practice in its war-time struggle with other nations. A charitable reading of Nishida’s statements on the special place of [[Japan]] interprets them as advocating that his country overcome its outdated [[vision]] of itself as a colonizing {{Wiki|nation}}, and embrace a global {{Wiki|conception}} of itself as a {{Wiki|nation}} interacting with other nations in a [[world]] of mutually defining equals.[4] A more critical reading interprets these statements as falsely absolutizing the particular {{Wiki|nation}} of [[Japan]], suggesting that [[Japan]] embraces other nations of the [[East]] which is abstractly opposed to the [[West]]. Similar challenges face us in the twenty-first century not only in a [[world]] of continuing {{Wiki|imperialism}} and contesting nations with different [[religious]] and {{Wiki|cultural}} [[traditions]] but also in single nations of multicultural composition. |
− | 7. Methods in Nishida’s Thought | + | 7. [[Methods]] in Nishida’s [[Thought]] |
− | Nishida composed essays on interrelated themes rather than sequential and tightly edited books. Major essays were subsequently collected and published as books, but often do not form chapters of a single coherent work. Instead of investigating a problem in a series of straightforward linear arguments, he tended to write in spirals that kept circling back on previous formulations and reworking them in new contexts. His style is akin to the manner in which one repeatedly practices a traditional Japanese art like calligraphy, poetry or even Zen mediation: working at a particular activity or expression, getting better and better at it without erasing one’s previous attempts. It is possible, however, to discern four methods that pervade his philosophy and make it easier for the reader to follow the train of his thought. | + | Nishida composed {{Wiki|essays}} on {{Wiki|interrelated}} themes rather than sequential and tightly edited [[books]]. Major {{Wiki|essays}} were subsequently collected and published as [[books]], but often do not [[form]] chapters of a single coherent work. Instead of investigating a problem in a series of straightforward linear arguments, he tended to write in spirals that kept circling back on previous formulations and reworking them in new contexts. His style is akin to the manner in which one repeatedly practices a [[traditional]] [[Japanese]] [[art]] like {{Wiki|calligraphy}}, [[poetry]] or even [[Zen]] [[mediation]]: working at a particular [[activity]] or expression, getting better and better at it without erasing one’s previous attempts. It is possible, however, to discern four [[methods]] that pervade his [[philosophy]] and make it easier for the reader to follow the train of his [[thought]]. |
− | First is Nishida’s way of taking the more inclusive as the more concrete, and the more restricted as the more abstract. This makes sense insofar as abstraction involves removal of parts, but Nishida also uses this method to reverse the usual order of things in explanatory schemas or hierarchies. As mentioned earlier, the historical world lived by human beings, for example, is more concrete than the material world studied by physics since the historical, human world comprehends (in both senses of the word) the merely physical and can never be reduced to it. Between these two worlds is the biological realm of life forms, less concrete than the human world but more concrete than the physical world. | + | First is Nishida’s way of taking the more inclusive as the more concrete, and the more restricted as the more abstract. This makes [[sense]] insofar as {{Wiki|abstraction}} involves removal of parts, but Nishida also uses this method to reverse the usual order of things in explanatory schemas or hierarchies. As mentioned earlier, the historical [[world]] lived by [[human beings]], for example, is more concrete than the [[material world]] studied by [[physics]] since the historical, [[human world]] comprehends (in both [[senses]] of the [[word]]) the merely [[physical]] and can never be reduced to it. Between these two [[worlds]] is the {{Wiki|biological}} [[realm]] of {{Wiki|life forms}}, less concrete than the [[human world]] but more concrete than the [[physical world]]. |
− | Second is Nishida’s recourse to the explanatory schema of wholes that reflect themselves in their parts. Here Nishida adapts the idea of self-representative systems presented in Josiah Royce and Richard Dedekind’s idea of an infinite system reflected in its parts. For Nishida, if there are no parts outside a whole, its evident differentiation must be explained. After his first major book, An Inquiry into the Good, Nishida came to explain this differentiating development not in terms of a temporal process but as the self-reflective or self-mirroring structure of a whole. Knowledge, for example, is not a matter of two disparate realities, a knowing mind and a known object, conforming to one another, but a single concrete reality that “reflects itself in itself” on differing levels that give rise to the more abstract notions of knowing subject and known objects. And after Nishida described self-awareness (jikaku) as the activity of self reflecting itself within itself, he came to speak of other structural wholes, including place or topos and even the world itself, as | + | Second is Nishida’s recourse to the explanatory {{Wiki|schema}} of wholes that reflect themselves in their parts. Here Nishida adapts the [[idea]] of self-representative systems presented in {{Wiki|Josiah Royce}} and Richard Dedekind’s [[idea]] of an [[infinite]] system reflected in its parts. For Nishida, if there are no parts outside a whole, its evident differentiation must be explained. After his first major [[book]], [[An Inquiry into the Good]], Nishida came to explain this differentiating [[development]] not in terms of a {{Wiki|temporal}} process but as the self-reflective or self-mirroring {{Wiki|structure}} of a whole. [[Knowledge]], for example, is not a {{Wiki|matter}} of two disparate [[realities]], a [[knowing]] [[mind]] and a known [[object]], conforming to one another, but a single concrete [[reality]] that “reflects itself in itself” on differing levels that give rise to the more abstract notions of [[knowing]] [[subject]] and known [[objects]]. And after Nishida described [[self-awareness]] ([[jikaku]]) as the [[activity]] of [[self]] {{Wiki|reflecting}} itself within itself, he came to speak of other structural wholes, [[including]] place or topos and even the [[world]] itself, as “[[self-aware]]” (jikaku-teki) insofar as they reflected themselves within themselves. |
− | Third is Nishida’s way of elaborating this “within” in terms of enfolding or enwrapping, as a whole enfolds or contains parts that partially reflect it , or as the universal of color encompasses that of red, for example. Nishida also referred to more limited realms as particularizations or “self-determinations” of more inclusive realms, but he often used the metaphor of wrapping to describe the manner of determination. The ultimate universal or enfolding whole has no determinate features; it is | + | Third is Nishida’s way of elaborating this “within” in terms of enfolding or enwrapping, as a whole enfolds or contains parts that partially reflect it , or as the [[universal]] of {{Wiki|color}} encompasses that of [[red]], for example. Nishida also referred to more limited [[realms]] as particularizations or “self-determinations” of more inclusive [[realms]], but he often used the {{Wiki|metaphor}} of wrapping to describe the manner of [[determination]]. The [[ultimate universal]] or enfolding whole has no {{Wiki|determinate}} features; it is “[[nothingness]]” (mu). |
− | The fourth method is Nishida’s way of treating oppositions and distinctions, emphasizing alternatively their undifferentiated ground or their irreducible relation. He often sought to return oppositions and distinctions to the non-differentiated condition that underlies them, ultimately to the nothingness that gives rise to (or determines itself as) various distinctions. Although terms translating as “ground” or “foundation” are found throughout his works, this emphasis undermines any recourse to a founding principle or entity wholly transcendent to, and thus ultimately different from, the world or reality. | + | The fourth method is Nishida’s way of treating oppositions and {{Wiki|distinctions}}, {{Wiki|emphasizing}} alternatively their undifferentiated ground or their irreducible [[relation]]. He often sought to return oppositions and {{Wiki|distinctions}} to the non-differentiated [[condition]] that underlies them, ultimately to the [[nothingness]] that gives rise to (or determines itself as) various {{Wiki|distinctions}}. Although terms translating as “ground” or “foundation” are found throughout his works, this {{Wiki|emphasis}} undermines any recourse to a founding [[principle]] or [[entity]] wholly [[transcendent]] to, and thus ultimately different from, the [[world]] or [[reality]]. “[[Absolute]] [[nothingness]]” may be understood as the lack of any positively definable [[transcendent]] ground. When for example Nishida writes “[[absolute]] [[nothingness]] {{Wiki|transcends}} all that is, but at the same time all that is arises through it” (NKZ IX, 6), we may interpret him as pointing to an undifferentiated source beyond the {{Wiki|distinctions}} it gives rise to, a source that is necessarily entailed by their being brought together precisely as {{Wiki|distinct}} from one another. |
− | The emphasis on relation similarly undermines any attempt to reduce opposed or distinguished terms to some element common to both. In mid career Nishida used the language of dialectics to describe relations, while insisting that the opposed terms were not sublated into a higher unity. Later he used expressions like “the self-identity of absolute contradictories” to describe the way in which opposed terms are held together, the many and the one for example. His notion of an “inverse correlation” also reflects this method. Nishida’s emphasis on relation modifies his notion of self-reflective structures to make it clear that they maintain difference within a whole and are not simply self-replicating or recursive. This is noticeable in his last essay, for example, when he describes individual selves as focal points where world reflects itself in itself (NKZ XI, 378). His rejection of a positive foundation or substratum, and his insistence on irreducible but inseparable terms in relation, explain why the holistic tendency evident in his methodology does not devolve into a simple monism, and why many commentators refer to his philosophy as non-dualist instead. | + | The {{Wiki|emphasis}} on [[relation]] similarly undermines any attempt to reduce opposed or {{Wiki|distinguished}} terms to some [[element]] common to both. In mid career Nishida used the [[language]] of [[dialectics]] to describe relations, while insisting that the opposed terms were not sublated into a higher {{Wiki|unity}}. Later he used {{Wiki|expressions}} like “the self-identity of [[absolute]] contradictories” to describe the way in which opposed terms are held together, the many and the one for example. His notion of an “inverse correlation” also reflects this method. Nishida’s {{Wiki|emphasis}} on [[relation]] modifies his notion of self-reflective structures to make it clear that they maintain difference within a whole and are not simply self-replicating or recursive. This is noticeable in his last essay, for example, when he describes {{Wiki|individual}} selves as focal points where [[world]] reflects itself in itself (NKZ XI, 378). His rejection of a positive foundation or [[substratum]], and his insistence on irreducible but [[inseparable]] terms in [[relation]], explain why the {{Wiki|holistic}} tendency evident in his [[Wikipedia:scientific method|methodology]] does not devolve into a simple {{Wiki|monism}}, and why many commentators refer to his [[philosophy]] as non-dualist instead. |
− | 8. The Unity and Development of Nishida’s Philosophy | + | 8. The Unity and [[Development]] of Nishida’s [[Philosophy]] |
8.1 The Attempt to Unify the Varying Themes | 8.1 The Attempt to Unify the Varying Themes | ||
− | A grasp of both the unity and the development of Nishida’s thought is also crucial to understanding it. As should be obvious, Nishida’s thought underwent extensive changes over the course of four decades. Less evident is that the varying themes are united by a deepening of the same basic insights. The Preface to the third volume of his Philosophical Essays published in 1939 gives us his own view of the unity of his progression: “It is said that that I repeatedly discuss the same problems, and [indeed] from An Inquiry into the Good on my objective has been to see things and think things from the most direct and fundamental standpoint—to grasp all things from the standpoint of whence they come and whither they go.” (NKZ IX, 3). A Preface written three years earlier to the reprint of An Inquiry into the Good identifies some of the crucial connections in the changing thematic: the standpoint of pure experience articulated in that maiden work developed into that of absolute will, and later into the notion of place or topos, concretized further as a dialectical universal, which in turn gets expressed as action-intuition. “That which I called...the world of pure experience I have now come to think of as the world of historical reality. The world of enactive intuition—the world of poiesis—is none other than the world of pure | + | A [[grasp]] of both the {{Wiki|unity}} and the [[development]] of Nishida’s [[thought]] is also crucial to [[understanding]] it. As should be obvious, Nishida’s [[thought]] underwent extensive changes over the course of four decades. Less evident is that the varying themes are united by a deepening of the same basic [[insights]]. The Preface to the third volume of his [[Philosophical]] Essays published in 1939 gives us his [[own]] view of the {{Wiki|unity}} of his progression: “It is said that that I repeatedly discuss the same problems, and [indeed] from [[An Inquiry into the Good]] on my [[objective]] has been to see things and think things from the most direct and fundamental standpoint—to [[grasp]] all things from the standpoint of whence they come and whither they go.” (NKZ IX, 3). A Preface written three years earlier to the reprint of [[An Inquiry into the Good]] identifies some of the crucial connections in the changing thematic: the standpoint of [[pure experience]] articulated in that maiden work developed into that of [[absolute]] will, and later into the notion of place or topos, concretized further as a [[dialectical]] [[universal]], which in turn gets expressed as action-intuition. “That which I called...the [[world]] of [[pure experience]] I have now come to think of as the [[world]] of historical [[reality]]. The [[world]] of enactive intuition—the [[world]] of poiesis—is none other than the [[world]] of [[pure experience]]” (Nishida 1990, xxxiii). |
− | Since Nishida composed his essays in a language and for a culture that had known philosophy as a distinct discipline for little more than half a century, his view of that discipline is equally crucial for understanding the unity and progression of his thought. Although his view likewise evolved over the course of his life, it reveals one abiding feature: philosophy should be not only the articulation but also the awareness of the most fundamental unities of experience, knowledge, action, and ultimately self and world. | + | Since Nishida composed his {{Wiki|essays}} in a [[language]] and for a {{Wiki|culture}} that had known [[philosophy]] as a {{Wiki|distinct}} [[discipline]] for little more than half a century, his view of that [[discipline]] is equally crucial for [[understanding]] the {{Wiki|unity}} and progression of his [[thought]]. Although his view likewise evolved over the course of his [[life]], it reveals one abiding feature: [[philosophy]] should be not only the articulation but also the [[awareness]] of the most fundamental unities of [[experience]], [[knowledge]], [[action]], and ultimately [[self]] and [[world]]. |
− | Relatively early in his career, when he was still under the sway of Fichte, the Neo-Kantians, and Bergson he defined philosophy as science [gakumon], i.e. unified conceptual knowledge, more specifically the first and universal science that “reflects on the basic concepts of the particular sciences in general and constructs of them one system of knowledge.” Yet “its object of study is not simply the fundamental concepts of reality. Basic normative notions such as truth, goodness and beauty must of course enter into philosophical study. Philosophy not only clarifies basic notions of reality, but must also elucidate the ideals of human life, the ‘ought’ itself. Philosophy is not simply a worldview; it is a view of human life.” Within his extended definition Nishida, commenting on Bergson, clarifies the role of intuition so crucial to his own thought: | + | Relatively early in his career, when he was still under the sway of Fichte, the Neo-Kantians, and Bergson he defined [[philosophy]] as [[science]] [gakumon], i.e. unified {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[knowledge]], more specifically the first and [[universal]] [[science]] that “reflects on the basic [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of the particular [[sciences]] in general and constructs of them one system of [[knowledge]].” Yet “its [[object]] of study is not simply the fundamental [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of [[reality]]. Basic normative notions such as [[truth]], [[goodness]] and [[beauty]] must of course enter into [[philosophical]] study. [[Philosophy]] not only clarifies basic notions of [[reality]], but must also elucidate the ideals of [[Wikipedia:Human life|human life]], the ‘ought’ itself. [[Philosophy]] is not simply a worldview; it is a view of [[Wikipedia:Human life|human life]].” Within his extended [[definition]] Nishida, commenting on Bergson, clarifies the role of [[intuition]] so crucial to his [[own]] [[thought]]: “‘[[intuition]]’ as such cannot be called [[philosophy]]. Even if its contents can derive from [[intuition]], [[philosophy]] has its raison d’être when [[intuition]] takes the [[form]] of {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[knowledge]].” (NKZ 13, 254). |
− | Then, later in his career, Nishida paradoxically formed concepts of the limits of such knowledge and formulated his philosophy of absolute nothingness that is ultimately mirrored in self-awareness. Such awareness became a task for philosophy or, more specifically, for the philosopher. Throughout his life Nishida’s own practice of philosophy attempted to realize an abiding insight expressed in the various terms he recounts in the Preface cited above. In that sense his thought is systematic, while not forming a closed system. It is a consistent attempt to re-conceptualize philosophy, to reframe the terms in which many philosophers think about self and world. This is what is meant by saying that Nishida would have us think from the perspective of the world rather than the “I.” | + | Then, later in his career, Nishida {{Wiki|paradoxically}} formed [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of the limits of such [[knowledge]] and formulated his [[philosophy]] of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] that is ultimately mirrored in [[self-awareness]]. Such [[awareness]] became a task for [[philosophy]] or, more specifically, for the [[philosopher]]. Throughout his [[life]] Nishida’s [[own]] practice of [[philosophy]] attempted to realize an abiding [[insight]] expressed in the various terms he recounts in the Preface cited above. In that [[sense]] his [[thought]] is systematic, while not forming a closed system. It is a consistent attempt to re-conceptualize [[philosophy]], to reframe the terms in which many [[philosophers]] think about [[self]] and [[world]]. This is what is meant by saying that Nishida would have us think from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of the [[world]] rather than the “I.” |
− | 8.2 Stages in Nishida’s Thought | + | 8.2 Stages in Nishida’s [[Thought]] |
− | Many readers of Nishida have attempted to delineate stages in the development of his philosophy (Elberfeld 1999, 71ff.); others have rejected a division into discrete stages (Heisig 2001, 104). As a heuristic approach to a summary of his thought, we may broadly distinguish three stages. The first is defined by an overwhelming conviction that concrete reality is at base unitary and can be articulated from the standpoint of consciousness. We have seen that Nishida successively names its most basic form | + | Many readers of Nishida have attempted to [[delineate]] stages in the [[development]] of his [[philosophy]] (Elberfeld 1999, 71ff.); others have rejected a [[division]] into discrete stages (Heisig 2001, 104). As a {{Wiki|heuristic}} approach to a summary of his [[thought]], we may broadly distinguish three stages. The first is defined by an overwhelming conviction that concrete [[reality]] is at base unitary and can be articulated from the standpoint of [[consciousness]]. We have seen that Nishida [[successively]] names its most basic [[form]] “[[pure experience]],” “[[self-awareness]],” and “[[absolute]] [[free will]].” Each of these exemplifies the [[fundamental reality]] from which all else becomes [[manifest]] through a process of differentiation. In An Inquiry Into the Good (1911), [[pure experience]] describes the primal [[undifferentiated form]] that subsequently dirempts into differentiated [[forms]]: experiencing [[subject]] and [[experienced]] [[objects]], [[intellectual]] [[intuition]] and reflective [[thought]], objectified [[nature]] and objectifying spirit—all on their way to a higher {{Wiki|unity}}. {{Wiki|Intuition}} and {{Wiki|Reflection}} in [[Self-Awareness]] (1917) shifts that {{Wiki|idealistic}} description to [[epistemological]] questions. It explicates [[self-awareness]] as the [[form]] in which {{Wiki|reflection}} and immediate [[experience]] or [[intuition]] are unified, the [[form]] that reflects itself within itself and gives rise not only to differentiating judgments but to differently [[experienced]] systems such as [[spirit]] and {{Wiki|matter}} and to “[[worlds]]” such as [[art]] and [[religion]]. Eventually Nishida proposes that the most basic [[form]] of [[self-awareness]] is not a kind of [[knowing]] at all, but a willing or “[[absolute]] [[free will]]” evident in valuing and creating. He develops this proposal in Problems of [[Consciousness]] (1920) and [[Art]] and [[Morality]] (1923). Nishida later said his first attempts, formulated from the standpoint of [[consciousness]], invited the charges of psychologism (Nishida 1990, xxxi), and [[mysticism]] (Nishida 1987, xxiii), and so he abandoned the [[language]] of [[pure experience]] and [[absolute]] will. It is clear, however, that his initial convictions persisted a good deal longer: the most concrete [[form]] of [[reality]] is undifferentiated, and [[consciousness]] as the [[manifestation]] of [[reality]] is [[inseparable]] from it. |
− | The second stage, broadly speaking, is defined by the standpoint of place or topos (basho). This involves the attempts to articulate levels of differentiation and place them in more and more inclusive circles (to use one of Nishida’s metaphors) until one reaches the most concrete and comprehensive circle, a circle without circumference whose center is everywhere. Nishida calls each such circle a place or topos, which allow things to be and to be seen as what they are. The final topos places self-awareness in the world of action and expression which contextualizes it, and ultimately in absolute nothingness. Nishida refers to the ultimate topos, alluding to Buddhist doctrine, as “the form of the formless,” clearly replacing earlier attempts to describe the basic form of concrete reality in positive and subjectivistic terms such as pure experience, self-awareness and absolute free will, This stage is evident in essays in From That Which Acts to That Which Sees (1927) and The Self-aware System of Universals (1930), and extends to much of The Self-aware Determination of Nothingness (1932). A Hegelian language of dialectics gradually became more and more prominent in his formulations, as he turned his attention to the place of individuals interacting in the world. He wrote of individuals as the “self-determinations” of the universal of self-awareness; and of absolute nothingness as a dialectical universal. | + | The second stage, broadly {{Wiki|speaking}}, is defined by the standpoint of place or topos (basho). This involves the attempts to articulate levels of differentiation and place them in more and more inclusive circles (to use one of Nishida’s {{Wiki|metaphors}}) until one reaches the most concrete and comprehensive circle, a circle without circumference whose center is everywhere. Nishida calls each such circle a place or topos, which allow things to be and to be seen as what they are. The final topos places [[self-awareness]] in the [[world]] of [[action]] and expression which contextualizes it, and ultimately in [[absolute]] [[nothingness]]. Nishida refers to the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] topos, alluding to [[Buddhist doctrine]], as “the [[form]] of the [[formless]],” clearly replacing earlier attempts to describe the basic [[form]] of concrete [[reality]] in positive and subjectivistic terms such as [[pure experience]], [[self-awareness]] and [[absolute]] [[free will]], This stage is evident in {{Wiki|essays}} in From That Which Acts to That Which Sees (1927) and The Self-aware System of Universals (1930), and extends to much of The Self-aware [[Determination]] of [[Nothingness]] (1932). A Hegelian [[language]] of [[dialectics]] gradually became more and more prominent in his formulations, as he turned his [[attention]] to the place of {{Wiki|individuals}} interacting in the [[world]]. He wrote of {{Wiki|individuals}} as the “self-determinations” of the [[universal]] of [[self-awareness]]; and of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] as a [[dialectical]] [[universal]]. |
− | The third stage sharpens the focus on the dialectical world as a place of mediation between interacting individuals as historically embodied selves. Nishida now conceptualizes the world as the historical manifestation of absolute nothingness. This stage represents what is for Nishida the most comprehensive and concrete standpoint, that of the historical world. The world unfolds “from the created to the creating,” not in a straightforward linear progression but out of an | + | The third stage sharpens the focus on the [[dialectical]] [[world]] as a place of [[mediation]] between interacting {{Wiki|individuals}} as historically [[embodied]] selves. Nishida now conceptualizes the [[world]] as the historical [[manifestation]] of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]]. This stage represents what is for Nishida the most comprehensive and concrete standpoint, that of the historical [[world]]. The [[world]] unfolds “from the created to the creating,” not in a straightforward linear progression but out of an “[[absolute]] {{Wiki|present}}” that in each [[moment]] holds together {{Wiki|past}} [[determinations]] and decisions for the {{Wiki|future}}. The historical [[world]] as such is a “self-identity of contradictories.” The [[self]] realizes itself not in [[knowing]] itself as {{Wiki|distinct}} from other selves or things but through [[forms]] of self-negation. One [[form]] calls for the [[self]] to [[recognize]] the [[absolute]] other in its [[own]] core to relate truly to the Thou or other [[relative]] selves. Another [[form]] calls for one to give oneself over to things or “become one with” the things it would know—through “enactive [[intuition]],” [[seeing]] them by interacting with them and interacting by [[seeing]] them from their [[own]] {{Wiki|perspective}}. In this stage relations come to the fore: the relations between I and Thou, the one and the many, the expressive [[self]] and its {{Wiki|expressions}}, the [[Japanese]] {{Wiki|nation}} and other nations. Each of these relations constitutes a self-identity of contradictories and resists a {{Wiki|monistic}} [[interpretation]]. This stage, understood heuristically, stretches from the final {{Wiki|essays}} in The Self-aware [[Determination]] of [[Nothingness]] through The [[World]] of [[Action]] and The [[Dialectical]] [[World]] (collected as The Fundamental [[Problems of Philosophy]], 1934), seven volumes of [[Philosophical]] Essays (1935–45) and several {{Wiki|political}} writings, to Nishida last essay, “The [[Logic]] of Place and the [[Religious]] Worldview”(1945). The final essay returns to the theme of [[religious]] [[awareness]] and makes more explicit the [[Buddhist]] references, as well as the [[Christian]], influence, latent in much of Nishida’s [[philosophy]]. The focus on [[death]] and finitude, while consistent with the [[idea]] of self-negation, suggests a shift of standpoint, but Nishida’s final reflections are too brief to be called a new stage in his [[philosophy]]. |
− | 9. The Place of Asian Philosophies in Nishida’s Thought | + | 9. The Place of {{Wiki|Asian}} [[Philosophies]] in Nishida’s [[Thought]] |
− | Because Nishida throughout his career cited Western philosophers far more often than Asian sources, it is easy to read his thought as an ongoing engagement with problems that have their origin in Western traditions. In addressing the concerns of Western thinkers he followed the path taken by nearly all Japanese professors of philosophy since the inception of the academic discipline in the 1880s. Yet his appropriation of ideas from Asian philosophies is also evident to the discerning reader, if more by way of allusion and affinity than by direct citation. It was not always necessary for him to name his Asian sources as explicitly, for he could appeal to the general education of Japanese readers who would be familiar with the classics of Asia and with the convention of appropriating ideas without directly referring to them. While commentators have long pointed out the debt of Nishida to Zen Buddhist practice and thought, they have only recently begun to identify other Asian sources of his philosophy by researching his vast library in Asian languages (Dalissier 2009b). In retrospect, it is clear that all along Nishida was infusing Western philosophy with Asian thought far more pervasively than the few references to Buddhism above might indicate. | + | Because Nishida throughout his career cited [[Western]] [[philosophers]] far more often than {{Wiki|Asian}} sources, it is easy to read his [[thought]] as an ongoing engagement with problems that have their origin in [[Western]] [[traditions]]. In addressing the concerns of [[Western]] thinkers he followed the [[path]] taken by nearly all [[Japanese]] professors of [[philosophy]] since the inception of the {{Wiki|academic}} [[discipline]] in the 1880s. Yet his appropriation of [[ideas]] from {{Wiki|Asian}} [[philosophies]] is also evident to the discerning reader, if more by way of allusion and [[affinity]] than by direct citation. It was not always necessary for him to [[name]] his {{Wiki|Asian}} sources as explicitly, for he could appeal to the general [[education]] of [[Japanese]] readers who would be familiar with the classics of {{Wiki|Asia}} and with the convention of appropriating [[ideas]] without directly referring to them. While commentators have long pointed out the debt of Nishida to [[Zen Buddhist]] practice and [[thought]], they have only recently begun to identify other {{Wiki|Asian}} sources of his [[philosophy]] by researching his vast library in {{Wiki|Asian}} [[languages]] (Dalissier 2009b). In retrospect, it is clear that all along Nishida was infusing {{Wiki|Western philosophy}} with {{Wiki|Asian}} [[thought]] far more pervasively than the few references to [[Buddhism]] above might indicate. |
− | In general, we can discern two ways that Nishida made use of Asian sources: anecdotally and systematically. Nishida’s writings are strewn with unacknowledged quotations or paraphrases of verses in classical Chinese sources, as well as allusions that may or may not identify their source in Indian, Chinese, or Japanese literature. This sort of allusion is anecdotal. Unobtrusively placed in the current of a discussion on a particular issue, the anecdotal allusions serve to clarify an idea, to provide a concrete example, or to insert a playful turn of phrase into otherwise ponderous prose. One example is the passage in the early work, Intuition and Reflection in Self-Consciousness, where Nishida argues that the will of the individual can freely express absolute will as the creative activity of the universe when the individual will operates spontaneously, without reflection or objectification. Nishida inserts a saying from the Zen Buddhist Record of Linji in the middle of a sentence to express this undivided spontaneity: “To think of the infinite behind the finite, or of noumenon behind actuality, is to enter the realm of objectified knowledge. In the immediate, lived experience of willing, however, the finite is immediately infinite, actuality is immediately noumenon, one walks when needing to walk and sits when needing to sit, and there is no interval for conceptual analysis” (NKZ II, 299; see Nishida 1987b, 147). Nishida also incorporates Confucian phrases, often without identifying them as such. In his first book, An Inquiry Into the Good, for example, arguing that logical reasons are often not sufficient to motivate good conduct, he alludes to a maxim of Confucius: “The saying Do not do unto others what you would not have others do unto you, is nearly meaningless without the motivation of | + | In general, we can discern two ways that Nishida made use of {{Wiki|Asian}} sources: anecdotally and systematically. Nishida’s writings are strewn with unacknowledged quotations or [[Wikipedia:paraphrase|paraphrases]] of verses in classical {{Wiki|Chinese}} sources, as well as {{Wiki|allusions}} that may or may not identify their source in [[Indian]], {{Wiki|Chinese}}, or [[Japanese]] {{Wiki|literature}}. This sort of allusion is anecdotal. Unobtrusively placed in the current of a [[discussion]] on a particular issue, the anecdotal {{Wiki|allusions}} serve to clarify an [[idea]], to provide a concrete example, or to insert a playful turn of [[phrase]] into otherwise ponderous prose. One example is the passage in the early work, {{Wiki|Intuition}} and {{Wiki|Reflection}} in [[Self-Consciousness]], where Nishida argues that the will of the {{Wiki|individual}} can freely express [[absolute]] will as the creative [[activity]] of the [[universe]] when the {{Wiki|individual}} will operates spontaneously, without {{Wiki|reflection}} or [[objectification]]. Nishida inserts a saying from the [[Zen Buddhist]] Record of [[Linji]] in the middle of a sentence to express this undivided spontaneity: “To think of the [[infinite]] behind the finite, or of {{Wiki|noumenon}} behind [[actuality]], is to enter the [[realm]] of objectified [[knowledge]]. In the immediate, lived [[experience]] of willing, however, the finite is immediately [[infinite]], [[actuality]] is immediately {{Wiki|noumenon}}, one walks when needing to walk and sits when needing to sit, and there is no {{Wiki|interval}} for {{Wiki|conceptual}} analysis” (NKZ II, 299; see Nishida 1987b, 147). Nishida also incorporates [[Wikipedia:Confucianism|Confucian]] phrases, often without identifying them as such. In his first [[book]], An Inquiry Into the Good, for example, arguing that [[logical]] [[reasons]] are often not sufficient to motivate [[good conduct]], he alludes to a maxim of [[Confucius]]: “The saying Do not do unto others what you would not have others do unto you, is nearly meaningless without the [[motivation]] of [[sympathy]]” (Nishida 1990, 113; NKZ I, 132). |
− | Nishida makes use of Asian philosophies systematically both in key notions such as nothingness and in the methods that characterize his thinking. The notion of absolute nothingness recalls Indian ideas as well as Chinese Daoist and Buddhist expressions. Indeed, Nishida once suggested that we can distinguish traditional Eastern and Western philosophies by the East’s prioritizing of nothingness and the West’s reliance on being (NKZ VII, 429–30; Nishida 1970b, 237). He explicitly mentions the profound idea of nothingness developed in Indian religion (Nishida 1970b, 239), and we can find a precedent to his notion of absolute nothingness as beyond being and nonbeing in the Hymn of Creation in book ten of the Rg Veda: “nonbeing existed not, nor being” (Radhakrishnan 1957, 23). Nishida also had in mind the Chinese Daoist classics attributed to Laozi and Zhuangzi, where “the Way (or Dao) was clearly said to be ‘nonbeing’” (Nishida 1970b, 242). The Japanese term Nishida uses is mu (wu in Chinese), a sinogram that in Chinese literature usually functions simply as a negation of being or having and in this respect fails to convey Nishida’s full sense of nothingness that does not reduce to a lack of being. Nevertheless, philosophical Daoist literature provided a precedent that Nishida could draw upon. In chapter 40 of Laozi’s Daodejing we find the statement, “The myriad things are born from being. Being is born from nonbeing.” Reminiscent of Nishida’s absolute nothingness as a creative source, the Daodejing refers to the generative power of nonbeing and to the non-nameable Dao or Way that gives rise to the myriad things. And suggestive of Nishida’s sense of absolute nothingness as the most inclusive and undifferentiated place, the text known by its legendary author’s name, the Zhuangzi, refers to a Dao that has never known boundaries but preserves the possibility of distinctions. Taken up by Chinese Buddhism, wu not only referred to non-existence but also served as a variant of the Mahayana Buddhist notion of emptiness (śūnyatā), a negation of the self-subsistence of individual beings and an affirmation of their interdependence. Nishida drew upon such Buddhist and Daoist precedents in formulating his critique of substantialist metaphysics and his notion of absolute nothingness as an all-encompassing, ultimate frame of reference that is creative yet not transcendent to the world. | + | Nishida makes use of {{Wiki|Asian}} [[philosophies]] systematically both in key notions such as [[nothingness]] and in the [[methods]] that characterize his [[thinking]]. The notion of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] recalls [[Indian]] [[ideas]] as well as {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Daoist]] and [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|expressions}}. Indeed, Nishida once suggested that we can distinguish [[traditional]] Eastern and [[Western]] [[philosophies]] by the East’s prioritizing of [[nothingness]] and the West’s reliance on being (NKZ VII, 429–30; Nishida 1970b, 237). He explicitly mentions the profound [[idea]] of [[nothingness]] developed in [[Indian]] [[religion]] (Nishida 1970b, 239), and we can find a precedent to his notion of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] as beyond being and nonbeing in the Hymn of Creation in [[book]] ten of the [[Rg Veda]]: “nonbeing existed not, nor being” ([[Radhakrishnan]] 1957, 23). Nishida also had in [[mind]] the {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Daoist]] classics attributed to [[Laozi]] and [[Zhuangzi]], where “the Way (or [[Dao]]) was clearly said to be ‘nonbeing’” (Nishida 1970b, 242). The [[Japanese]] term Nishida uses is mu (wu in {{Wiki|Chinese}}), a sinogram that in {{Wiki|Chinese}} {{Wiki|literature}} usually functions simply as a {{Wiki|negation}} of being or having and in this [[respect]] fails to convey Nishida’s full [[sense]] of [[nothingness]] that does not reduce to a lack of being. Nevertheless, [[philosophical]] [[Daoist]] {{Wiki|literature}} provided a precedent that Nishida could draw upon. In [[chapter]] 40 of Laozi’s {{Wiki|Daodejing}} we find the statement, “The {{Wiki|myriad}} things are born from being. Being is born from nonbeing.” Reminiscent of Nishida’s [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] as a creative source, the {{Wiki|Daodejing}} refers to the generative power of nonbeing and to the non-nameable [[Dao]] or Way that gives rise to the {{Wiki|myriad}} things. And suggestive of Nishida’s [[sense]] of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] as the most inclusive and undifferentiated place, the text known by its legendary author’s [[name]], the [[Zhuangzi]], refers to a [[Dao]] that has never known [[boundaries]] but preserves the possibility of {{Wiki|distinctions}}. Taken up by [[Chinese Buddhism]], wu not only referred to [[non-existence]] but also served as a variant of the [[Mahayana]] [[Buddhist notion of emptiness]] ([[śūnyatā]]), a {{Wiki|negation}} of the self-subsistence of {{Wiki|individual}} [[beings]] and an [[affirmation]] of their [[interdependence]]. Nishida drew upon such [[Buddhist]] and [[Daoist]] precedents in formulating his critique of substantialist [[metaphysics]] and his notion of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] as an all-encompassing, [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] frame of reference that is creative yet not [[transcendent]] to the [[world]]. |
− | Systematic use of Asian philosophies is also apparent in Nishida’s methods. Where his arguments seek higher forms of inclusion rather than rejection of opposing views, he harks back to Chinese Buddhist schemes of explanation that absorb and contextualize rival doctrines rather than exclude them. Nishida’s manner of contextualizing, in his theory of place or topos, draws from Chinese cosmological methods in which “to explain and infer is to locate within the pattern” (Graham 1989, 320; cited in Dalissier 2009b, 226). Yogacara Buddhist theories of consciousness as the primary reality and explanatory principle most likely influenced Nishida’s tendency in his early works to explain all reality in terms of consciousness. Later, his way of unifying opposites and defining things in terms of self-negation adapts a Buddhist prajñapāramitā logic of negation, in which individuated terms entail their negation and are understood as co-relational rather than exclusive. | + | Systematic use of {{Wiki|Asian}} [[philosophies]] is also apparent in Nishida’s [[methods]]. Where his arguments seek higher [[forms]] of inclusion rather than rejection of opposing [[views]], he harks back to {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Buddhist]] schemes of explanation that absorb and contextualize rival [[doctrines]] rather than exclude them. Nishida’s manner of contextualizing, in his {{Wiki|theory}} of place or topos, draws from {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[cosmological]] [[methods]] in which “to explain and infer is to locate within the pattern” (Graham 1989, 320; cited in Dalissier 2009b, 226). [[Yogacara]] [[Buddhist]] theories of [[consciousness]] as the primary [[reality]] and explanatory [[principle]] most likely influenced Nishida’s tendency in his early works to explain all [[reality]] in terms of [[consciousness]]. Later, his way of unifying opposites and defining things in terms of self-negation adapts a [[Buddhist]] [[prajñapāramitā]] [[logic]] of {{Wiki|negation}}, in which individuated terms entail their {{Wiki|negation}} and are understood as co-relational rather than exclusive. |
− | Even where there is no evidence of direct influence, the affinity of some key notions and arguments with classical Indian Buddhist ideas is striking. It is possible for example to read Nishida’s development of the three topoi or places of being, relative nothingness, and absolute nothingness, as a deepening of awareness that resembles the progression of awareness, described in many Buddhist schemes, that allows one to see first through the realm of desire, then through the realm of forms, to the formless realm beyond discrimination (Stevens 2009, 71). Also suggestive of the convictions underlying Nishida’s philosophy are arguments of the Mādhyamaka school of Nāgārjuna pressing for the relationality of all existents, and exhortations to appreciate the “groundlessless of things” in the Vimalakīrti-nirdeśa Sūtra (Priest 2009, 472). | + | Even where there is no {{Wiki|evidence}} of direct influence, the [[affinity]] of some key notions and arguments with classical [[Indian Buddhist]] [[ideas]] is striking. It is possible for example to read Nishida’s [[development]] of the three topoi or places of being, [[relative]] [[nothingness]], and [[absolute]] [[nothingness]], as a deepening of [[awareness]] that resembles the progression of [[awareness]], described in many [[Buddhist]] schemes, that allows one to see first through the [[realm of desire]], then through the [[realm]] of [[forms]], to the [[formless realm]] beyond {{Wiki|discrimination}} (Stevens 2009, 71). Also suggestive of the convictions underlying Nishida’s [[philosophy]] are arguments of the [[Mādhyamaka school]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] pressing for the relationality of all [[existents]], and exhortations to appreciate the “groundlessless of things” in the [[Vimalakīrti-nirdeśa Sūtra]] ([[Priest]] 2009, 472). |
− | 10. Critiques of Nishida’s Philosophy | + | 10. Critiques of Nishida’s [[Philosophy]] |
− | Criticisms of Nishida’s thought were a significant part of its development during his lifetime, and continue to this day to inform debates about its meaning and relevance. Insofar as Nishida aimed at a comprehensive “system of self- | + | Criticisms of Nishida’s [[thought]] were a significant part of its [[development]] during his [[lifetime]], and continue to this day to inform [[debates]] about its meaning and relevance. Insofar as Nishida aimed at a comprehensive “system of [[self-awareness]]” (Nishida 1987b, 70)––ultimately the system of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]] determining itself as the historical world––his [[philosophy]] seems to preclude the possibility of radical internal critique. Nishida did not envision his system as closed to [[development]] or to an open {{Wiki|future}}. But several key notions that he never abandoned leave scant room for [[acknowledging]] the incomprehensible: the notions of a [[universal]] that reflects itself clearly if not completely in its particulars, of a [[world]] that mirrors itself in its {{Wiki|individuals}}, of more inclusive topoi that fully envelop less inclusive topoi, or of an [[absolute]] that is immanent in all [[relative]] selves. How does such a system account for fallibility, unpredictability, [[distortion]] or [[violence]]? And where does the author Nishida stand in [[relation]] to the system that he describes. Is the author too merely a {{Wiki|reflection}} of the system? |
− | In contrast to interpreting Nishida’s thought as presenting a system that would preempt problems, one can also read it as a series of attempts to clarify for himself the activity of living a philosophical life. From this perspective, critique appears as a constant feature of Nishida’s personal development. During his lifetime Nishida took his critics seriously and sometimes changed course because of their criticisms. Takahashi Satomi, while still a graduate student at the University of Tokyo, criticized Nishida’s notion of pure experience and spurred him to clarify it in an article published soon after An Inquiry Into the Good. His colleague at Kyoto University, Sōda Kiichiro, criticized the lack of clarity in his initial formulation of basho (place) in 1926 and prompted him to remove Neo-Kantian comparisons. More significantly, in the early 1930s his younger colleague Tanabe Hajime and his former student and Marxist philosopher Tosaka Jun criticized Nishida’s focus on consciousness and lack of attention to history and social being; Nishida subsequently developed his notions of the historical world and the historical body. In the last years of his life, he seemed to anticipate his death and recognize human finitude more strongly as an inevitable disruption of any comprehensive systematic account. Two years before his death in 1945, he wrote, “Our life and our existence are not our own. They are the determinations of absolute | + | In contrast to interpreting Nishida’s [[thought]] as presenting a system that would preempt problems, one can also read it as a series of attempts to clarify for himself the [[activity]] of living a [[philosophical]] [[life]]. From this {{Wiki|perspective}}, critique appears as a [[constant]] feature of Nishida’s personal [[development]]. During his [[lifetime]] Nishida took his critics seriously and sometimes changed course because of their {{Wiki|criticisms}}. [[Takahashi]] Satomi, while still a graduate [[student]] at the {{Wiki|University}} of [[Tokyo]], criticized Nishida’s notion of [[pure experience]] and spurred him to clarify it in an article published soon after An Inquiry Into the Good. His colleague at [[Kyoto University]], Sōda Kiichiro, criticized the lack of clarity in his initial formulation of basho (place) in 1926 and prompted him to remove Neo-Kantian comparisons. More significantly, in the early 1930s his younger colleague [[Tanabe]] Hajime and his former [[student]] and [[Marxist]] [[philosopher]] Tosaka Jun criticized Nishida’s focus on [[consciousness]] and lack of [[attention]] to history and {{Wiki|social}} being; Nishida subsequently developed his notions of the historical [[world]] and the historical [[body]]. In the last years of his [[life]], he seemed to anticipate his [[death]] and [[recognize]] [[human]] finitude more strongly as an inevitable disruption of any comprehensive systematic account. Two years before his [[death]] in 1945, he wrote, “Our [[life]] and our [[existence]] are not our [[own]]. They are the [[determinations]] of [[absolute]] [[nothingness]]…. [[Philosophy]] begins with the [[self]] set on living truly. It is a way for the [[self]] to become [[self-aware]] and to live” (NKZ 10, 401, 472).[5] |
11. Nishida’s Influence | 11. Nishida’s Influence | ||
− | Nishida is often called the father of the Kyoto School of philosophy because of his influence on a group of thinkers who were his students or younger colleagues. Best known outside Japan are his colleague and critic, Tanabe Hajime, frequently considered the School’s co-founder, and his student Nishitani Keiji. As a “school” the group comprises a rather fuzzy set that includes Marxist-leaning former students such as Miki Kiyoshi and Tosaka Jun, more nationalistic students like Kōyama Iwao and Kōsaka Masaaki, and lesser known but close disciples like Mutai Risaku and Shimomura Toratarō. Other colleagues, students and friends on the fringes of the School proper nevertheless show the impact of Nishida’s ideas: the Zen Buddhist scholar-teachers D. T. Suzuki and Hisamatsu Shin’ichi, the ethical theorist Watsuji Tetsurō, and Kuki Shūzō, the interpreter of Japanese aesthetics and culture. A third generation of the School includes Tanabe’s student Takeuchi Yoshinori, Nishitani’s student Ueda Shizuteru and Hisamatsu’s student Abe Masao, who have been especially effective in introducing Nishida’s philosophy in Europe and North America and in applying Nishida’s thought to inter-religious Buddhist-Christian dialogue. | + | Nishida is often called the father of the [[Kyoto School]] of [[philosophy]] because of his influence on a group of thinkers who were his students or younger [[colleagues]]. Best known outside [[Japan]] are his colleague and critic, [[Tanabe]] Hajime, frequently considered the School’s co-founder, and his [[student]] [[Nishitani Keiji]]. As a “school” the group comprises a rather fuzzy set that includes Marxist-leaning former students such as Miki Kiyoshi and Tosaka Jun, more nationalistic students like Kōyama Iwao and Kōsaka Masaaki, and lesser known but close [[disciples]] like Mutai Risaku and Shimomura Toratarō. Other [[colleagues]], students and friends on the fringes of the School proper nevertheless show the impact of Nishida’s [[ideas]]: the [[Zen Buddhist]] scholar-teachers [[D. T. Suzuki]] and Hisamatsu Shin’ichi, the [[ethical]] theorist [[Watsuji]] Tetsurō, and Kuki Shūzō, the interpreter of [[Japanese]] aesthetics and {{Wiki|culture}}. A third generation of the School includes Tanabe’s [[student]] Takeuchi Yoshinori, Nishitani’s [[student]] [[Ueda]] Shizuteru and Hisamatsu’s [[student]] Abe Masao, who have been especially effective in introducing Nishida’s [[philosophy]] in {{Wiki|Europe}} and [[North America]] and in applying Nishida’s [[thought]] to inter-religious Buddhist-Christian {{Wiki|dialogue}}. |
− | Nishida’s investigations inspired current interpretations of Mahayana Buddhism, just as his thought was influenced by Buddhist ideas. For many people, his explication of pure experience and self-awareness re-interprets Zen awakening; his intertwining of self and world develops the Buddhist teaching of co-dependent origination; and his philosophy of nothingness articulates the notion of emptiness and the experience of mu (nothing). His philosophy has also presented to his Buddhist and Christian readers serious challenges, such as a notion of a non-dual relation between God and man, and an emphasis, unusual in Buddhism, on the embodied self in the historical world. | + | Nishida’s investigations inspired current interpretations of [[Mahayana Buddhism]], just as his [[thought]] was influenced by [[Buddhist]] [[ideas]]. For many [[people]], his explication of [[pure experience]] and [[self-awareness]] re-interprets [[Zen]] [[awakening]]; his intertwining of [[self]] and [[world]] develops the [[Buddhist teaching]] of co-dependent origination; and his [[philosophy]] of [[nothingness]] articulates the notion of [[emptiness]] and the [[experience]] of mu (nothing). His [[philosophy]] has also presented to his [[Buddhist]] and [[Christian]] readers serious challenges, such as a notion of a [[non-dual]] [[relation]] between [[God]] and man, and an {{Wiki|emphasis}}, unusual in [[Buddhism]], on the [[embodied]] [[self]] in the historical [[world]]. |
− | Nishida’s logic of place has been a resource for theoreticians working in various scientific fields, for example Imanishi Kinji in biology and ecology, Shimizu Hiroshi in complexity theory and information science, Nonaka Ikujiro in management theory, and Ko Hojo in the philosophy of chemistry. The architect Ando Tadao, and artists like the calligrapher Morita Shiryū have also drawn from Nishida’s philosophy, as has the psychotherapist Kimura Bin. Ultimately, Nishida himself is best considered an independent thinker, as the growing literature in Japanese and Western languages attests. | + | Nishida’s [[logic]] of place has been a resource for theoreticians working in various [[scientific]] fields, for example Imanishi Kinji in {{Wiki|biology}} and {{Wiki|ecology}}, Shimizu Hiroshi in complexity {{Wiki|theory}} and [[information]] [[science]], Nonaka Ikujiro in {{Wiki|management}} {{Wiki|theory}}, and Ko [[Hojo]] in the [[philosophy]] of {{Wiki|chemistry}}. The {{Wiki|architect}} Ando Tadao, and {{Wiki|artists}} like the [[calligrapher]] Morita Shiryū have also drawn from Nishida’s [[philosophy]], as has the psychotherapist Kimura Bin. Ultimately, Nishida himself is best considered an {{Wiki|independent}} thinker, as the growing {{Wiki|literature}} in [[Japanese]] and [[Western]] [[languages]] attests. |
− | Bibliography | + | [[Bibliography]] |
Nishida’s works | Nishida’s works | ||
− | Note: Some of the works referenced below were published in Volumes 1-7 of the series Frontiers in Japanese Philosophy, James W. Heisig et al. (eds.), 2006–2010, Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion. A copy of the works listed below that are marked [*] can be found linked into the following webpage: Frontiers in Japanese Philosophy. | + | Note: Some of the works referenced below were published in Volumes 1-7 of the series Frontiers in [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]], James W. Heisig et al. (eds.), 2006–2010, [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]]. A copy of the works listed below that are marked [*] can be found linked into the following webpage: Frontiers in [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]]. |
− | Nishida Kitarō Zenshū, 4th edition 1987–89, Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten. (Complete Works of Nishida Kitarō, in nineteen volumes, cited as NKZ followed by volume and page number.) | + | Nishida Kitarō Zenshū, 4th edition 1987–89, [[Tokyo]]: [[Iwanami]] Shoten. (Complete Works of Nishida Kitarō, in nineteen volumes, cited as NKZ followed by volume and page number.) |
− | –––, New Edition 2002–09, twenty four volumes, edited by A. Takeda, K. Riesenhueber, K. Kosaka & M. Fujita, Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten. | + | –––, New Edition 2002–09, twenty four volumes, edited by A. Takeda, K. Riesenhueber, K. Kosaka & M. [[Fujita]], [[Tokyo]]: [[Iwanami]] Shoten. |
Representative Translations | Representative Translations | ||
− | 1958. Intelligibility and the Philosophy of Nothingness: Three Philosophical Essays, Robert Shinzinger (trans.), Honolulu: East-West Center Press. | + | 1958. Intelligibility and the [[Philosophy]] of [[Nothingness]]: Three [[Philosophical]] Essays, Robert Shinzinger (trans.), [[Honolulu]]: East-West [[Center]] Press. |
− | 1960, reprint edition 1988. A Study of the Good, V.H. Viglielmo (trans.), Westport, Connecticut and London: Greenwood Press. | + | 1960, reprint edition 1988. A Study of the Good, V.H. Viglielmo (trans.), Westport, {{Wiki|Connecticut}} and [[London]]: Greenwood Press. |
− | 1970a. “Toward a Philosophy of Religion with the Concept of Preestablished Harmony as a Guide,” David Dilworth (trans.), The Eastern Buddhist, 3(1): 19–46. | + | 1970a. “Toward a [[Philosophy]] of [[Religion]] with the {{Wiki|Concept}} of Preestablished [[Harmony]] as a Guide,” David Dilworth (trans.), The Eastern [[Buddhist]], 3(1): 19–46. |
− | 1970b. Fundamental Problems of Philosophy, David Dilworth (trans.), Tokyo: Sophia University. | + | 1970b. Fundamental [[Problems of Philosophy]], David Dilworth (trans.), [[Tokyo]]: [[Sophia]] {{Wiki|University}}. |
− | 1970c. | + | 1970c. “[[Religious]] [[Consciousness]] and the [[Logic]] of the [[Prajñapāramitā]] [[Sūtra]],” David Dilworth (trans.), {{Wiki|Monumenta Nipponica}}, 25: 3–15. |
− | 1973. Art and Morality, David Dilworth and Valdo Viglielmo (trans.), Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. | + | 1973. [[Art]] and [[Morality]], David Dilworth and Valdo Viglielmo (trans.), [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University}} of [[Hawai’i]] Press. |
− | 1979. “Affective Feeling,” David Dilworth and Valdo Viglielmo (trans.), in Japanese Phenomenology (Analecta Husserliana VIII), Y. Nitta and H. Tatematsu (eds.), Dordrecht, Boston & London: D. Reidel Publishing Company. | + | 1979. “Affective [[Feeling]],” David Dilworth and Valdo Viglielmo (trans.), in [[Japanese]] {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} (Analecta Husserliana VIII), Y. Nitta and H. Tatematsu (eds.), Dordrecht, [[Boston]] & [[London]]: D. Reidel Publishing Company. |
− | 1985. “La crisis de la cultura japonesa,” “El problema de la rasón de estado,” “Teoría dek kokutai,” in Estado y Filosofía, Agustin Jacinto Zavala (trans.), Michoacan, Mexico: El Colegio de Michoacan. | + | 1985. “La crisis de la cultura japonesa,” “El problema de la rasón de estado,” “Teoría dek [[kokutai]],” in Estado y Filosofía, Agustin Jacinto Zavala (trans.), Michoacan, {{Wiki|Mexico}}: El Colegio de Michoacan. |
− | 1986. “The Logic of Topos and the Religious Worldview,” Michiko Yusa (trans.), The Eastern Buddhist 19(2): 1–29 & 20(1): 81–119. | + | 1986. “The [[Logic]] of Topos and the [[Religious]] Worldview,” Michiko Yusa (trans.), The Eastern [[Buddhist]] 19(2): 1–29 & 20(1): 81–119. |
− | 1987a. Last Writings: Nothingness and the Religious Worldview, David Dilworth (trans.), Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. | + | 1987a. Last Writings: [[Nothingness]] and the [[Religious]] Worldview, David Dilworth (trans.), [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University}} of [[Hawai’i]] Press. |
− | 1987b. Intuition and Reflection in Self-Consciousness, Valdo H. Viglielmo, Takeuchi Toshinori and Joseph S. O’Leary (trans.), Albany: State University of New York Press. | + | 1987b. {{Wiki|Intuition}} and {{Wiki|Reflection}} in [[Self-Consciousness]], Valdo H. Viglielmo, Takeuchi Toshinori and Joseph S. O’Leary (trans.), [[Albany]]: [[State University of New York Press]]. |
1989. Über das Gute: Eine Philosophie der reinen Erfahrung, Peter Pörtner (trans.), Frankfurt am Mein and Leipzig. | 1989. Über das Gute: Eine Philosophie der reinen Erfahrung, Peter Pörtner (trans.), Frankfurt am Mein and Leipzig. | ||
− | 1990a. An Inquiry Into the Good, Masao Abe and Christopher Ives (trans.), New Haven and London: Yale University Press. | + | 1990a. An Inquiry Into the Good, [[Masao Abe]] and Christopher Ives (trans.), New Haven and [[London]]: {{Wiki|Yale University Press}}. |
− | 1990b. “Selbstidentität und Kontinuität der Welt,” “Das künstlerische Schaffen als Gestaltungsakt der Geschichte,” E. Weinmayr (trans.), in Die Philsophie der Kyōto Schule, Ôhashi Ryōsuke (ed.), Freiburg & London: Karl Alber. | + | 1990b. “Selbstidentität und Kontinuität der Welt,” “Das künstlerische Schaffen als Gestaltungsakt der Geschichte,” E. Weinmayr (trans.), in [[Die]] Philsophie der [[Kyōto]] Schule, Ôhashi Ryōsuke (ed.), Freiburg & [[London]]: Karl Alber. |
− | 1990c. | + | 1990c. “[[Die]] Welt als dialektisches Allgemeines,” Matsudo Yukio (trans.), [[Die]] Welt als dialektisches Allgemeines: Eine Einführung in [[die]] Spätphilosophie von Kitarō Nishida, [[Berlin]]: Vista. |
− | 1991. La Culture Japonaise en Question, Pierre Lavelle (trans.), Paris: Publications Orientalistes de France. | + | 1991. La {{Wiki|Culture}} Japonaise en Question, Pierre Lavelle (trans.), {{Wiki|Paris}}: Publications Orientalistes de {{Wiki|France}}. |
1995. “La experiencia pura,” “Problemas de la cultura japonesa,” “Discurso ente el Tennō: Sobre la filosofía de la historia,” “Fundamentación filosófica de las matemáticas,” “Lógica del topos y cosmovisión religiosa,” Agustín Jacinto Zavala (trans.), in Textos de la filosofía japonesa moderna, Michoacán: El Colegio de Michoacán. | 1995. “La experiencia pura,” “Problemas de la cultura japonesa,” “Discurso ente el Tennō: Sobre la filosofía de la historia,” “Fundamentación filosófica de las matemáticas,” “Lógica del topos y cosmovisión religiosa,” Agustín Jacinto Zavala (trans.), in Textos de la filosofía japonesa moderna, Michoacán: El Colegio de Michoacán. | ||
1996. L’io e il tu, R. Andolfato (trans.), Padova: Unipress. | 1996. L’io e il tu, R. Andolfato (trans.), Padova: Unipress. | ||
− | 1997. “Coincidentia Oppositorum and Love,” W. S. Yokoyama (trans.), The Eastern Buddhist, 30(1): 7–12. | + | 1997. “Coincidentia Oppositorum and [[Love]],” W. S. Yokoyama (trans.), The Eastern [[Buddhist]], 30(1): 7–12. |
− | 1998. “The Historical Body,” “The World as Identity of Absolute Contradiction,” “Fundamental Principles of a New World Order,” “On the National Polity,” David Dilworth and Valdo Viglielmo (trans.), in Sourcebook for Modern Japanese Philosophy: Selected Documents, Westport, Connecticut and London: Greenwood Press. | + | 1998. “The Historical [[Body]],” “The [[World]] as {{Wiki|Identity}} of [[Absolute]] Contradiction,” “Fundamental {{Wiki|Principles}} of a New [[World]] Order,” “On the National Polity,” David Dilworth and Valdo Viglielmo (trans.), in Sourcebook for {{Wiki|Modern}} [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]]: Selected Documents, Westport, {{Wiki|Connecticut}} and [[London]]: Greenwood Press. |
− | 1999a. Logik des Ortes: Der Anfang der modernen Philosophie in Japan, Rolf Elberfeld (trans.), Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. | + | 1999a. Logik des Ortes: Der Anfang der modernen Philosophie in [[Japan]], Rolf Elberfeld (trans.), Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. |
− | 1999b. “Une étude sur le bein,” Bernard Stevens (trans.), “Logique prédicative,” Jacynthe Tremblay (trans.), “Logique de lieu et vision religieuse du monde,” Yasuhiko Sugimura & Syvain Cardonnel (trans.), Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 97. | + | 1999b. “Une étude sur le bein,” Bernard Stevens (trans.), “Logique prédicative,” Jacynthe Tremblay (trans.), “Logique de lieu et [[vision]] religieuse du monde,” Yasuhiko Sugimura & Syvain Cardonnel (trans.), Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 97. |
− | 2001. “L’intuizione attiva (Kōiteki chokkan),” “Saggio sulla filosofia di Cartesio (Dekaruto tetsugaku ni tsuite),” in Il corpo e la conoscenza, Matteo Cestari (trans.), Venice: Libreria Editrice Cafoscarina. | + | 2001. “L’intuizione attiva (Kōiteki chokkan),” “Saggio sulla filosofia di Cartesio (Dekaruto tetsugaku ni tsuite),” in Il corpo e la conoscenza, Matteo Cestari (trans.), [[Venice]]: Libreria Editrice Cafoscarina. |
− | 2003a. L’Éveil à soi, Jacynthe Tremblay (trans.), Paris: CNRS Éditions. [essays of Nishida composed between 1931 and 1944]. | + | 2003a. L’Éveil à soi, Jacynthe Tremblay (trans.), {{Wiki|Paris}}: CNRS Éditions. [{{Wiki|essays}} of Nishida composed between 1931 and 1944]. |
− | 2003b. “On the Role of Religion,” Gereon Kopf (trans.), The Eastern Buddhist, 25(1–2): 229–39. | + | 2003b. “On the Role of [[Religion]],” Gereon Kopf (trans.), The Eastern [[Buddhist]], 25(1–2): 229–39. |
− | 2005. “General Summary of The System of Self-Consciousness of the Universal,” Robert J. Wargo (trans), in The Logic of Nothingness: An Essay on Nishida Kitarō, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press, 2005. | + | 2005. “General Summary of The System of [[Self-Consciousness]] of the [[Universal]],” Robert J. Wargo (trans), in The [[Logic]] of [[Nothingness]]: An Essay on Nishida Kitarō, [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University}} of [[Hawai’i]] Press, 2005. |
2008. “L’Autodétermination du maintenant eternal,” Jacynthe Tremblay (trans.), Laval théologique et philosophique, 64(2): 245–76. | 2008. “L’Autodétermination du maintenant eternal,” Jacynthe Tremblay (trans.), Laval théologique et philosophique, 64(2): 245–76. | ||
2008. “L’Intuition agissante,” Kuroda Akinobu (trans.), Laval théologique et philosophique, 64(2): 277–93. | 2008. “L’Intuition agissante,” Kuroda Akinobu (trans.), Laval théologique et philosophique, 64(2): 277–93. | ||
− | 2011. | + | 2011. “[[Pure]] [[Experience]],” “The [[Logic]] of Place,” “The Eternal in [[Art]] and [[Poetry]],” “A [[Religious]] View of the [[World]],” “My [[Logic]],” [[Masao Abe]], Christopher Ives, James Heisig, Michiko Yusa (trans.), in [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]]: A Sourcebook, J. Heisig, T. [[Kasulis]] and J. Maraldo (eds.), [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University}} of [[Hawai’i]] Press. |
− | 2012a. Place & Dialectic: Two Essays by Nishida Kitarō, John W. Krummel and Shigenori Nagatomo (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. | + | 2012a. Place & [[Dialectic]]: Two Essays by Nishida Kitarō, John W. Krummel and Shigenori Nagatomo (trans.), [[Oxford]]: [[Oxford University Press]]. |
− | 2012b. “The Unsolved Issue of Consciousness,” J.W.M. Krummel (trans.), Philosophy East and West, 62(1): 44–59. | + | 2012b. “The Unsolved Issue of [[Consciousness]],” J.W.M. Krummel (trans.), [[Philosophy East and West]], 62(1): 44–59. |
− | 2012c. Ontology of Production: 3 Essays, William Haver (trans.), Durham and London: Duke University Press. | + | 2012c. {{Wiki|Ontology}} of Production: 3 Essays, William Haver (trans.), Durham and [[London]]: {{Wiki|Duke University}} Press. |
− | Secondary Literature | + | Secondary {{Wiki|Literature}} |
− | Abe, Masao, 1988, “Nishida’s Philosophy of ‘Place,’” International Philosophical Quarterly, 28: 355–371. | + | Abe, Masao, 1988, “Nishida’s [[Philosophy]] of ‘Place,’” International [[Philosophical]] Quarterly, 28: 355–371. |
− | –––, 1992, “‘Inverse Correspondence’ in the Philosophy of Nishida: The Emergence of the Notion,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 32(1): 325–344, | + | –––, 1992, “‘Inverse Correspondence’ in the [[Philosophy]] of Nishida: The [[Emergence]] of the Notion,” International [[Philosophical]] Quarterly, 32(1): 325–344, |
− | –––, 1995, “The Problem of ‘Inverse Correspondence’ in the Philosophy of Nishida: Toward a Critical Understanding,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 35(4): 419–436. | + | –––, 1995, “The Problem of ‘Inverse Correspondence’ in the [[Philosophy]] of Nishida: Toward a Critical [[Understanding]],” International [[Philosophical]] Quarterly, 35(4): 419–436. |
− | Arisaka, Yoko, 1996, “The Nishida Enigma: ‘The Principle of the New World Order’,” Monumenta Npponica, 51(1): 81–106. | + | Arisaka, Yoko, 1996, “The Nishida Enigma: ‘The [[Principle]] of the New [[World]] Order’,” Monumenta Npponica, 51(1): 81–106. |
− | –––, 1999, “Beyond | + | –––, 1999, “Beyond ‘[[East]] and [[West]]’: Nishida’s [[Universalism]] and Postcolonial Critique,” The Review of Politics, 59(3): 541–560. |
− | –––, 2001, “The Ontological Co-emergence of | + | –––, 2001, “The [[Ontological]] Co-emergence of ‘[[Self]] and Other’ in [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]],” Journal of [[Consciousness]] Studies, 8(5–7): 197–208. |
− | Axtell, G.S., 1991, “Comparative Dialectics: Nishida Kitarō’s Logic of Place and Western Dialectical Thought,” Philosophy East and West, 41(2): 163–184. | + | Axtell, G.S., 1991, “Comparative [[Dialectics]]: Nishida Kitarō’s [[Logic]] of Place and [[Western]] [[Dialectical]] [[Thought]],” [[Philosophy East and West]], 41(2): 163–184. |
− | Baek, Jin, 2008, “From the ‘Topos of | + | Baek, Jin, 2008, “From the ‘Topos of [[Nothingness]]’ to the ‘[[Space]] of Transparency’: Kitarō Nishida’s Notion of Shintai and Its Influence on [[Art]] and [[Architecture]] (Part 1),” [[Philosophy East and West]], 58(1): 83–107. |
− | Botz-Bornstein, Thorsten, 2003, “Nishida and Wittgenstein: from | + | Botz-Bornstein, Thorsten, 2003, “Nishida and {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}: from ‘[[pure experience]]’ to Lebensform or new perspectives for a [[philosophy]] of intercultural [[communication]],” {{Wiki|Asian}} [[Philosophy]], 13(1): 53–70 |
− | –––, 2004, “The ‘I’ and the ‘Thou’: A Dialogue between Nishida Kitarō and Mikhail Bakhtin,” Japan Review, 16: 259–284. | + | –––, 2004, “The ‘I’ and the ‘Thou’: A Dialogue between Nishida Kitarō and Mikhail Bakhtin,” [[Japan]] Review, 16: 259–284. |
− | Carter, Robert E., second edition 1998, The Nothingness Beyond God: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Nishida Kitarō, St. Paul: Paragon House. | + | Carter, Robert E., second edition 1998, The [[Nothingness]] Beyond [[God]]: An Introduction to the [[Philosophy]] of Nishida Kitarō, {{Wiki|St. Paul}}: Paragon House. |
− | Cestari, Matteo, 1998, “The Knowing Body: Nishida’s Philosophy of Active Intuition,” The Eastern Buddhist, 31(2): 179–208. | + | Cestari, Matteo, 1998, “The [[Knowing]] [[Body]]: Nishida’s [[Philosophy]] of Active {{Wiki|Intuition}},” The Eastern [[Buddhist]], 31(2): 179–208. |
− | –––, 2006, “From Seeing to Acting: Rethinking Nishida Kitarō’s Practical Philosophy,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 6, Raquel Bouso and James W. Heisig (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | –––, 2006, “From [[Seeing]] to Acting: Rethinking Nishida Kitarō’s Practical [[Philosophy]],” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 6, Raquel Bouso and James W. Heisig (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Cheung Ching-yuen, 2009, “The Potential and Limits of Nishida Kitarō’s Philosophy,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Cheung Ching-yuen, 2009, “The Potential and Limits of Nishida Kitarō’s [[Philosophy]],” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Dalissier, Michel, 2006, “The Idea of the Mirror in Dōgen and Nishida,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Dalissier, Michel, 2006, “The [[Idea]] of the [[Mirror]] in [[Dōgen]] and Nishida,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2009a, Anfractuosité et unification. La philosophie de Nishida Kitarō, Geneva: Droz. | + | –––, 2009a, Anfractuosité et unification. La philosophie de Nishida Kitarō, [[Geneva]]: Droz. |
− | –––, 2009b, “Nishida Kitarō and Chinese Philosophy,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | –––, 2009b, “Nishida Kitarō and [[Chinese Philosophy]],” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2010, “Nishida Kitarō and Chinese Philosophy: Debt and Distance,” Japan Review, 22: 137–170. | + | –––, 2010, “Nishida Kitarō and [[Chinese Philosophy]]: Debt and Distance,” [[Japan]] Review, 22: 137–170. |
− | Davis, Bret W., 2006a, “Provocative Ambivalences in Japanese Philosophy of Religion: with a Focus on Nishida and Zen,” in Japanese Philosophy Abroad, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Davis, Bret W., 2006a, “Provocative Ambivalences in [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] of [[Religion]]: with a Focus on Nishida and [[Zen]],” in [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] Abroad, James W. Heisig (ed.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2006b, “Toward a World of Worlds: Nishida, the Kyoto School, and the Place of Cross-Cultural Dialogue”, in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | –––, 2006b, “Toward a [[World]] of [[Worlds]]: Nishida, the [[Kyoto School]], and the Place of Cross-Cultural Dialogue”, in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
–––, 2013, “Nishida’s Multicultural Worldview: Contemporary Significance and Immanent Critique,” Nishida Tetsugakkai Nempō, 10: 183–203. | –––, 2013, “Nishida’s Multicultural Worldview: Contemporary Significance and Immanent Critique,” Nishida Tetsugakkai Nempō, 10: 183–203. | ||
− | –––, 2014, | + | –––, 2014, “[[Ethical]] and [[Religious]] Alterity: Nishida after Levinas,” in Kitarō Nishida in der Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts, Elberfeld, Rolf, and Yōko Arisaka (eds.), Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber. |
− | Dilworth, David, 1969, “The Initial Formation of | + | Dilworth, David, 1969, “The Initial Formation of ‘[[Pure]] [[Experience]]’ in Nishida Kitarō and {{Wiki|William James}},” Moumenta Nipponica, 24(1–2): 93–111. |
− | –––, 1970, “Nishida’s Early Pantheistic Voluntarism,” Philosophy East and West, 20(1): 35–49. | + | –––, 1970, “Nishida’s Early [[Pantheistic]] Voluntarism,” [[Philosophy East and West]], 20(1): 35–49. |
− | –––, 1973, “Nishida Kitarō: Nothingness as the Negative Space of Experiential Immediacy,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 13(4): 463–483. | + | –––, 1973, “Nishida Kitarō: [[Nothingness]] as the Negative [[Space]] of Experiential Immediacy,” International [[Philosophical]] Quarterly, 13(4): 463–483. |
− | Elberfeld, Rolf, 1999, Kitarō Nishida (1870–1945): Das Verstehen der Kulturen: Moderne japanische Philosophie und die Frage nach der Interkulturalität, Amsterdam & Atlanta: Rodopi. | + | Elberfeld, Rolf, 1999, Kitarō Nishida (1870–1945): Das Verstehen der Kulturen: Moderne japanische Philosophie und [[die]] Frage nach der Interkulturalität, {{Wiki|Amsterdam}} & Atlanta: Rodopi. |
Elberfeld, Rolf, and Yōko Arisaka (eds.), 2014, Kitarō Nishida in der Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts, Mit Texten Nishidas in deutscher Übersetzung, Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber. | Elberfeld, Rolf, and Yōko Arisaka (eds.), 2014, Kitarō Nishida in der Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts, Mit Texten Nishidas in deutscher Übersetzung, Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber. | ||
− | Elwood, Brian D, 1994, “The Problem of the Self in the Later Nishida and in Sartre,” Philosophy East and West, 44(2): 303–316. | + | Elwood, Brian D, 1994, “The Problem of the [[Self]] in the Later Nishida and in {{Wiki|Sartre}},” [[Philosophy East and West]], 44(2): 303–316. |
− | Feenberg, Andrew and Yoko Arisaka, 1990, “Experiential Ontology: The Origins of the Nishida Philosophy in the Doctrine of Pure Experience,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 30(2): 173–205. | + | Feenberg, Andrew and Yoko Arisaka, 1990, “Experiential {{Wiki|Ontology}}: The Origins of the Nishida [[Philosophy]] in the [[Doctrine]] of [[Pure]] [[Experience]],” International [[Philosophical]] Quarterly, 30(2): 173–205. |
− | –––, 1999, | + | –––, 1999, “[[Experience]] and {{Wiki|Culture}}: Nishida’s [[Path]] ‘To the Things Themselves,’” [[Philosophy East and West]], 49(1): 28–44. |
− | Ghilardi, Marcello, 2008, “Between Aesthetics and Ethics: The Experience of Seeing in Nicholas Cusanus and Nishida Kitarō,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Ghilardi, Marcello, 2008, “Between {{Wiki|Aesthetics}} and [[Ethics]]: The [[Experience]] of [[Seeing]] in Nicholas Cusanus and Nishida Kitarō,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Girard, Frédéric, 2008, “Le Lieu chez Nishida Kitarō et l’espace bouddhique,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Girard, Frédéric, 2008, “Le Lieu chez Nishida Kitarō et l’espace bouddhique,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Goto-Jones, Christopher S, 2005, Political Philosophy in Japan: Nishida, the Kyoto School, and Co-Prosperity, London and New York: Routledge. | + | Goto-Jones, Christopher S, 2005, {{Wiki|Political}} [[Philosophy]] in [[Japan]]: Nishida, the [[Kyoto School]], and Co-Prosperity, [[London]] and [[New York]]: Routledge. |
− | Graupe, Silja, 2006, “The Locus of Science and its Place in Japanese Culture: Nishida on the Relationship of Science and Culture,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Graupe, Silja, 2006, “The Locus of [[Science]] and its Place in [[Japanese]] {{Wiki|Culture}}: Nishida on the Relationship of [[Science]] and {{Wiki|Culture}},” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2007, The Basho of Economics: An Intercultural Analysis of the Process of Economics, New Brunswick, New Jersey: Ontos Verlag. | + | –––, 2007, The Basho of {{Wiki|Economics}}: An Intercultural Analysis of the Process of {{Wiki|Economics}}, New Brunswick, {{Wiki|New Jersey}}: Ontos Verlag. |
− | –––, 2008, “Nishida and the Dynamic Nature of Knowledge: Why Economists Should Take Nishida Seriously,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | –––, 2008, “Nishida and the Dynamic [[Nature]] of [[Knowledge]]: Why Economists Should Take Nishida Seriously,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Graham, A.C., 1981, Chuang-Tsu: The Inner Chapters, London and Boston: Unwin Publishers. | + | Graham, A.C., 1981, Chuang-Tsu: The Inner Chapters, [[London]] and [[Boston]]: Unwin Publishers. |
− | –––, 1989, Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argumentation in Ancient China, LaSalle, IL: Open Court. | + | –––, 1989, Disputers of the [[Tao]]: [[Philosophical]] Argumentation in [[Ancient China]], LaSalle, IL: Open Court. |
− | Hashi, Hisaki, 2007, “The Significance of Einstein’s Theory of Relativity in Nishida’s | + | Hashi, Hisaki, 2007, “The Significance of Einstein’s {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Relativity]] in Nishida’s ‘[[Logic]] of Field’,” [[Philosophy East and West]], 57(4): 457–481. |
− | Haver, William, 2012, “Introduction,” in Ontology of Production: 3 Essays by Nishida Kitarō, Durham and London: Duke University Press. | + | Haver, William, 2012, “Introduction,” in {{Wiki|Ontology}} of Production: 3 Essays by Nishida Kitarō, Durham and [[London]]: {{Wiki|Duke University}} Press. |
− | Heisig, James W. and John C. Maraldo (eds.), 1994, Rude Awakenings: Zen, The Kyoto School, and the Question of Nationalism, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. | + | Heisig, James W. and John C. Maraldo (eds.), 1994, Rude Awakenings: [[Zen]], The [[Kyoto School]], and the Question of [[Nationalism]], [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University}} of [[Hawai’i]] Press. |
− | Heisig, James W. et. al. (eds.), 2006–2010, Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy, Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion. [*] | + | Heisig, James W. et. al. (eds.), 2006–2010, Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]], [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]]. [*] |
− | Heisig, James W., Thomas P. Kasulis, and John C. Maraldo (eds.), 2011, Japanese Philosophy: A Sourcebook, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. | + | Heisig, James W., Thomas P. [[Kasulis]], and John C. Maraldo (eds.), 2011, [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]]: A Sourcebook, [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University}} of [[Hawai’i]] Press. |
− | Heisig, James W., 2000, “Non-I and Thou: Nishida, Buber, and the Moral Consequences of Self-actualization,” Philosophy East and West, 50(2) (April 2000): 179–207. | + | Heisig, James W., 2000, “Non-I and Thou: Nishida, Buber, and the [[Moral]] Consequences of Self-actualization,” [[Philosophy East and West]], 50(2) (April 2000): 179–207. |
− | –––, 2001, Philosophers of Nothingness, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. | + | –––, 2001, [[Philosophers]] of [[Nothingness]], [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University}} of [[Hawai’i]] Press. |
− | –––, 2004, “Nishida’s Medieval Bent,” Japanese Journal of Religious Studies, 31(1): 55–72. | + | –––, 2004, “Nishida’s {{Wiki|Medieval}} Bent,” [[Japanese]] Journal of {{Wiki|Religious Studies}}, 31(1): 55–72. |
− | –––, 2012, “An Inquiry Into the Good and Nishida’s Missing Basho,” Comparative and Continental Philosophy, 4(2): 237–251. | + | –––, 2012, “An Inquiry Into the Good and Nishida’s Missing Basho,” Comparative and Continental [[Philosophy]], 4(2): 237–251. |
− | –––, 2015, “Nishida’s Philosophical Equivalents of Enlightenment and No-Self,” Bulletin of the Nanzan Institute for Religion and Culture, 39: 36–60. [Available online (PDF)] | + | –––, 2015, “Nishida’s [[Philosophical]] Equivalents of [[Enlightenment]] and [[No-Self]],” Bulletin of the Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] and {{Wiki|Culture}}, 39: 36–60. [Available online (PDF)] |
− | Huang, Wen-hong, 2009, “The Shift in Nishida’s Logic of Place,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Huang, Wen-hong, 2009, “The Shift in Nishida’s [[Logic]] of Place,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Huh, Woo-Sung, 1990, “The Philosophy of History in the ‘Later’ Nishida: A Philosophic Turn,” Philosophy East and West, 40(3): 343–374. | + | Huh, Woo-Sung, 1990, “The [[Philosophy]] of History in the ‘Later’ Nishida: A [[Philosophic]] Turn,” [[Philosophy East and West]], 40(3): 343–374. |
− | –––, 2009, | + | –––, 2009, “[[Thinking]] and Perceiving: Nishida and Park as [[Embodied]] [[Subjects]]?” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Jacinto Zavala, Agustin, 1989, Filosofía de la Transformación del Mundo, Michoacan, Mexico: El Colegio de Michoacan. | + | Jacinto Zavala, Agustin, 1989, Filosofía de la Transformación del Mundo, Michoacan, {{Wiki|Mexico}}: El Colegio de Michoacan. |
− | –––, 1994, La fiosofía social de Nishida Kitarō: 1935–1945, two volumes, Michoacan: El Colegio de Michoacan. | + | –––, 1994, La fiosofía {{Wiki|social}} de Nishida Kitarō: 1935–1945, two volumes, Michoacan: El Colegio de Michoacan. |
− | –––, 2009, | + | –––, 2009, “{{Wiki|Aristotle}} and the {{Wiki|Epistemology}} of Nishida Kitarō (1924–1928),” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 6, Raquel Bouso and James W. Heisig (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, (ed.), 2012, Alternatives Filosóicas: Investigaciones recientes sobre Nishida Kitarō, Michoacan, Mexico: El Colegio de Michoacan. | + | –––, (ed.), 2012, Alternatives Filosóicas: Investigaciones recientes sobre Nishida Kitarō, Michoacan, {{Wiki|Mexico}}: El Colegio de Michoacan. |
− | Jiang, Tao, 2005, “The Problematic of Continuity: Nishida Kitarō and Aristotle,” Philosophy Esat and West, 55(3): 447–460. | + | [[Jiang]], [[Tao]], 2005, “The Problematic of Continuity: Nishida Kitarō and {{Wiki|Aristotle}},” [[Philosophy]] Esat and [[West]], 55(3): 447–460. |
Kobayashi,Toshiaki, 2002, Denken des Fremden: Am Beispiel von Kitarō Nishida, Frankfurt am Mein: Stroemfeld Verlag. | Kobayashi,Toshiaki, 2002, Denken des Fremden: Am Beispiel von Kitarō Nishida, Frankfurt am Mein: Stroemfeld Verlag. | ||
− | Kopf, Gereon, 2001, Beyond Personal Identity: Dōgen, Nishida, and a Phenomenology of No-Self, Richmond, Surrey: Curzon Press. | + | Kopf, Gereon, 2001, Beyond Personal {{Wiki|Identity}}: [[Dōgen]], Nishida, and a {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} of [[No-Self]], Richmond, Surrey: [[Curzon Press]]. |
− | –––, 2003, “On the Brink of Postmodernity: Recent Japanese Language Publications on the Philosophy of Nishida Kitarō,” Japanese Journal of Religious Studies, 30(1–2): 133–156. | + | –––, 2003, “On the Brink of Postmodernity: Recent [[Japanese]] [[Language]] Publications on the [[Philosophy]] of Nishida Kitarō,” [[Japanese]] Journal of {{Wiki|Religious Studies}}, 30(1–2): 133–156. |
− | –––, 2004, “Between Identity and Difference: Three Ways of Reading Nishida’s Non-Dualism,” Japanese Journal of Religious Studies, 31(1): 73–103. | + | –––, 2004, “Between {{Wiki|Identity}} and Difference: [[Three Ways]] of Reading Nishida’s Non-Dualism,” [[Japanese]] Journal of {{Wiki|Religious Studies}}, 31(1): 73–103. |
− | Kracht, Klaus, 1984, “Nishida Kitarō as a Philosopher of the State,”in Europe Interprets Japan, Gordon Daniels (ed.), Tenterden, Kent: Paul Norbury Publications. | + | Kracht, Klaus, 1984, “Nishida Kitarō as a [[Philosopher]] of the State,”in {{Wiki|Europe}} Interprets [[Japan]], Gordon Daniels (ed.), Tenterden, Kent: Paul Norbury Publications. |
− | –––, 1997, “Zum Verständnis der Nishida-Philosophie unter dem Aspekt des Verhänisses von Form und Inhalt,” Japonica Humboldtina, 1: 199–217. | + | –––, 1997, “Zum Verständnis der Nishida-Philosophie unter dem Aspekt des Verhänisses von [[Form]] und Inhalt,” Japonica Humboldtina, 1: 199–217. |
− | –––, 2001–2002,“Nishida und die Politik,” Japonica Humboldtina, 5: 205–250; 6: 183–249. | + | –––, 2001–2002,“Nishida und [[die]] Politik,” Japonica Humboldtina, 5: 205–250; 6: 183–249. |
− | Krummel, John W. M., 2012, “Basho , World, and Dialectics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Nishida Kitarō,” in Place & Dialectic: Two Essays by Nishida Kitarō, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. | + | [[Krummel, John]] W. M., 2012, “Basho , [[World]], and [[Dialectics]]: An Introduction to the [[Philosophy]] of Nishida Kitarō,” in Place & [[Dialectic]]: Two Essays by Nishida Kitarō, [[Oxford]] and [[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]]. |
− | –––, 2015, Nishida Kitarō’s Chiasmatic Chorology: Place of Dialectic, Dialectic of Place, Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press. | + | –––, 2015, Nishida Kitarō’s Chiasmatic Chorology: Place of [[Dialectic]], [[Dialectic]] of Place, [[Bloomington]], [[Indiana]]: [[Indiana University]] Press. |
− | Lam, Win-keung, 2006, “Redefining Philosophy Through Assimilation: Nishida Kitarō and Mou Zong-san,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Lam, Win-keung, 2006, “Redefining [[Philosophy]] Through Assimilation: Nishida Kitarō and [[Mou]] Zong-san,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Lange, Elena Louisa, 2014, “Waren-und Subsstanzfetisch–Zum Verhältnis von Intention und Explikation in Nishida Kitarōs ‘Ort’,” in Begriff und Bild der modernen japanischen Philosophie, R. C. Steineck, E. L. Lange and P. Kaufmann (eds.), Stuttgart–Bad Cannstatt: Frommann–Holzboog. | + | Lange, Elena Louisa, 2014, “Waren-und Subsstanzfetisch–Zum Verhältnis von [[Intention]] und Explikation in Nishida Kitarōs ‘Ort’,” in Begriff und Bild der modernen japanischen Philosophie, R. C. Steineck, E. L. Lange and P. Kaufmann (eds.), Stuttgart–Bad Cannstatt: Frommann–Holzboog. |
− | Laozi, Daodejing, Roger Ames and David Hall (trans.), Dao De Jing: A Philosophical Translation, New York: Ballantine Books, 2003. | + | [[Laozi]], {{Wiki|Daodejing}}, Roger Ames and David Hall (trans.), [[Dao De Jing]]: A [[Philosophical]] Translation, [[New York]]: {{Wiki|Ballantine Books}}, 2003. |
− | Lavelle, Pierre, 1994, “The Political Thought of Nishida Kitarō,” Monumenta Nipponica, 49(2): 139–165. | + | Lavelle, Pierre, 1994, “The {{Wiki|Political}} [[Thought]] of Nishida Kitarō,” {{Wiki|Monumenta Nipponica}}, 49(2): 139–165. |
− | Mafli, Paul, 1996, Nishida Kitarōs Denkweg, Munich: Iudicium Verlag. | + | Mafli, Paul, 1996, Nishida Kitarōs Denkweg, [[Munich]]: Iudicium Verlag. |
− | Maraldo, John C., 1989, “Translating Nishida,” Philosophy East and West, 39(4): 465–496. | + | Maraldo, John C., 1989, “Translating Nishida,” [[Philosophy East and West]], 39(4): 465–496. |
− | –––, 1995, “The Problem of World Culture: Towards an Appropriation of Nishida’s Philosophy of Nation and Culture,”The Eastern Buddhist, 28(2): 183–197. | + | –––, 1995, “The Problem of [[World]] {{Wiki|Culture}}: Towards an Appropriation of Nishida’s [[Philosophy]] of Nation and Culture,”The Eastern [[Buddhist]], 28(2): 183–197. |
− | –––, 2003, “Rethinking God: Heidegger in the Light of Absolute Nothing, Nishida in the Shadow of Onto-Theology,” in Religious Experience and the End of Metaphysics, Jeffrey Bloechl (ed.), Indiana University Press. | + | –––, 2003, “Rethinking [[God]]: [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] in the Light of [[Absolute]] Nothing, Nishida in the Shadow of Onto-Theology,” in [[Religious]] [[Experience]] and the End of [[Metaphysics]], Jeffrey Bloechl (ed.), [[Indiana University]] Press. |
− | –––, 2006a, “Self-Mirroring and Self-Awareness: Dedekind, Royce, and Nishida,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | –––, 2006a, “Self-Mirroring and [[Self-Awareness]]: Dedekind, Royce, and Nishida,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2006b, “The War Over the Kyoto School,” Monumenta Nipponica, 61(3): 375–406. | + | –––, 2006b, “The [[War]] Over the [[Kyoto School]],” {{Wiki|Monumenta Nipponica}}, 61(3): 375–406. |
− | –––, 2010, “Nothing Gives: Marion and Nishida on Gift-giving and God,” in Japanese and Continental Philosophy, Bret W. Davis and Brian Schroeder (eds.), Bloomington: Indiana University Press. | + | –––, 2010, “Nothing Gives: Marion and Nishida on Gift-giving and [[God]],” in [[Japanese]] and Continental [[Philosophy]], Bret W. Davis and Brian Schroeder (eds.), [[Bloomington]]: [[Indiana University]] Press. |
− | –––, 2014, “Nishida’s Kōiteki chokkan and the Notion of Enaction in Cognitive Science,” in Kitarō Nishida in der Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts, Elberfeld, Rolf, and Yōko Arisaka (eds.), Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber. | + | –––, 2014, “Nishida’s Kōiteki chokkan and the Notion of Enaction in [[Cognitive]] [[Science]],” in Kitarō Nishida in der Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts, Elberfeld, Rolf, and Yōko Arisaka (eds.), Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber. |
− | Nishitani, Keiji, 1991, Nishida Kitarō, Yamamoto Seisaku and James W. Heisig (trans.), Berkeley, Los Angeles, Oxford: University of California Press. | + | Nishitani, Keiji, 1991, Nishida Kitarō, [[Yamamoto Seisaku]] and James W. Heisig (trans.), [[Berkeley]], [[Los Angeles]], [[Oxford]]: {{Wiki|University of California Press}}. |
− | Odagiri, Takushi, 2008, “From Self-Reflexivity to Contingency: Nishida Kitarō on Self-Knowledge,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Odagiri, Takushi, 2008, “From Self-Reflexivity to Contingency: Nishida Kitarō on Self-Knowledge,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2012, “On Nishida’s Rationality Thesis,” Philosophy East and West, 62(2): 197–222. | + | –––, 2012, “On Nishida’s {{Wiki|Rationality}} {{Wiki|Thesis}},” [[Philosophy East and West]], 62(2): 197–222. |
− | Parkes, Graham, 1997, “The Putative Fascism of the Kyoto School and the Political Correctness of the Modern Academy,” Philosophy East and West, 47(3): 305–336. | + | Parkes, Graham, 1997, “The Putative Fascism of the [[Kyoto School]] and the {{Wiki|Political}} Correctness of the {{Wiki|Modern}} {{Wiki|Academy}},” [[Philosophy East and West]], 47(3): 305–336. |
− | Peerenboom, R.P., “The Religious Foundation of Nishida’s Philosophy,” Asian Philosophy, 1(2): 161–1743. | + | Peerenboom, R.P., “The [[Religious]] Foundation of Nishida’s [[Philosophy]],” {{Wiki|Asian}} [[Philosophy]], 1(2): 161–1743. |
− | Priest, Graham, 2009, “The Structure of Emptiness,” Philosophy East and West, 59(4): 467–480. | + | [[Priest]], Graham, 2009, “The Structure of [[Emptiness]],” [[Philosophy East and West]], 59(4): 467–480. |
− | Putney, David, 1991, | + | Putney, David, 1991, “{{Wiki|Identity}} and the Unity of [[Experience]]: A Critique of Nishida’s {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Self]],” {{Wiki|Asian}} [[Philosophy]], 1(2): 127–160. |
− | Radhakrishnan, Sarvepalli, and Charles Moore, 1957, Sourcebook in Indian Philosophy, Princeton: Princeton University Press. | + | [[Radhakrishnan]], Sarvepalli, and Charles Moore, 1957, Sourcebook in [[Indian Philosophy]], [[Princeton]]: [[Princeton University Press]]. |
− | Raud, Rein, 2004, “‘Place’ and ‘Being-time’: Spatiotemporal Concepts in the Thought of Nishida Kitarō and Dōgen Kigen,” Philosophy East and West, 54(1): 29–51. | + | Raud, Rein, 2004, “‘Place’ and ‘Being-time’: Spatiotemporal Concepts in the [[Thought]] of Nishida Kitarō and [[Dōgen Kigen]],” [[Philosophy East and West]], 54(1): 29–51. |
− | Rigsby, Curtis A., 2009, “Nishida on God, Barth and Christianity,” Asian Philosophy, 19(2): 119–157. | + | Rigsby, Curtis A., 2009, “Nishida on [[God]], Barth and [[Christianity]],” {{Wiki|Asian}} [[Philosophy]], 19(2): 119–157. |
− | Sakabe, Megume, 2010, | + | Sakabe, Megume, 2010, “[[Subject]] of the Absence and Absence of the Critique,” in {{Wiki|Asian}} {{Wiki|Aesthetics}}, Ken-ichi [[Sasaki]] (ed.), {{Wiki|Kyoto}}: [[Kyoto University]] Press. |
− | Schultz, Lucy, 2012, “Nishida Kitarō, G.W.F. Hegel, and the Pursuit of the Concrete: A Dialectic of Dialectics,” Philosophy East and West, 62(3): 319–338. | + | Schultz, Lucy, 2012, “Nishida Kitarō, G.W.F. [[Wikipedia:Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]], and the Pursuit of the Concrete: A [[Dialectic]] of [[Dialectics]],” [[Philosophy East and West]], 62(3): 319–338. |
− | Shimizu, Takashi, 2008, “Quasi-Predicate Theory: A New Interpretation of Nishida,” in Frontiers of Japanese | + | Shimizu, Takashi, 2008, “Quasi-Predicate {{Wiki|Theory}}: A New Interpretation of Nishida,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Stehlin, Laurent, 2008, Mondes de soi et lieu des mondes chez Nishida Kitarō, Paris: Peter Lang AG. | + | Stehlin, Laurent, 2008, Mondes de soi et lieu des mondes chez Nishida Kitarō, {{Wiki|Paris}}: Peter Lang AG. |
− | Steineck, Christian, 1998, “ Wirklichkeit und Interkulturalität bei Nishida Kitarō: Eine Kritik,” in Ogawa, Tadashi, Michael Lazarin and Guido Rappe (eds.), Interkulturelle Philosophie und Phänomenologie in Japan. Beiträge zum Gespräch über Grenzen hinweg, Munich: Iudicium Verlag. | + | Steineck, [[Christian]], 1998, “ Wirklichkeit und Interkulturalität bei Nishida Kitarō: Eine Kritik,” in [[Ogawa]], Tadashi, Michael Lazarin and Guido Rappe (eds.), Interkulturelle Philosophie und Phänomenologie in [[Japan]]. Beiträge zum Gespräch über Grenzen hinweg, [[Munich]]: Iudicium Verlag. |
Stevens, Bernard, 1995, “Basho et khōra. Nishida en son lieu,” Etudes Phénoménologiques, 21: 81–109. | Stevens, Bernard, 1995, “Basho et khōra. Nishida en son lieu,” Etudes Phénoménologiques, 21: 81–109. | ||
–––, 1999, “La première esquisse du système nishidien,” Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 97: 9–18. | –––, 1999, “La première esquisse du système nishidien,” Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 97: 9–18. | ||
− | –––, 2000, Topologie du néant: Une approche de l’école de Kyōto, Louvain-Paris:Éditions Peeters. | + | –––, 2000, Topologie du néant: Une approche de l’école de [[Kyōto]], Louvain-Paris:Éditions Peeters. |
− | –––, 2005, Invitation à la philosophie japnonaise: Autour de Nishida, Paris: CNRS Éditions. | + | –––, 2005, Invitation à la philosophie japnonaise: Autour de Nishida, {{Wiki|Paris}}: CNRS Éditions. |
− | –––, 2008, | + | –––, 2008, “[[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], Nishida et la ‘crise’: Hier et aujourd’hui,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Tremblay, Jacynthe, 1999, “Universel et individual dans la logique du basho de Nishida”, Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 97: 30–56. | + | Tremblay, Jacynthe, 1999, “Universel et {{Wiki|individual}} dans la logique du basho de Nishida”, Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 97: 30–56. |
− | –––, 2006, “Nishida Kitarō: Approches actuelles et recherché future,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | –––, 2006, “Nishida Kitarō: Approches actuelles et recherché {{Wiki|future}},” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2007a, Introduction à la philosophie de Nishida, Paris: L’Harmattan. | + | –––, 2007a, Introduction à la philosophie de Nishida, {{Wiki|Paris}}: L’Harmattan. |
− | –––, 2007b, Auto-éveil et temporalité: Les défis posés par la philosophie de Nishida, Paris: L’Harmattan. | + | –––, 2007b, Auto-éveil et temporalité: Les défis posés par la philosophie de Nishida, {{Wiki|Paris}}: L’Harmattan. |
− | –––, 2008, “Hidden Aspects of Temporality from Nishida to Watsuji,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 2, Victor Sōgen Hori and Melissa Anne-Marie Curley (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion and Culture. [*] | + | –––, 2008, “Hidden Aspects of Temporality from Nishida to [[Watsuji]],” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 2, Victor Sōgen Hori and Melissa Anne-Marie Curley (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] and {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2009a, “The Potential of Nishida’s ‘Encompassing’ Language,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | –––, 2009a, “The Potential of Nishida’s ‘Encompassing’ [[Language]],” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2009b, “Nishida Kitarō’s Language and Structure of Thought in the | + | –––, 2009b, “Nishida Kitarō’s [[Language]] and Structure of [[Thought]] in the ‘[[Logic]] of Basho’,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 6, Raquel Bouso and James W. Heisig (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Ueda, Shizuteru, 1993, | + | [[Ueda]], Shizuteru, 1993, “[[Pure]] [[Experience]], [[Self-Awareness]], ‘Basho,’” Etudes Phénoménologiques, 18: 63–86. |
− | –––, 1995a, “Nishida’s Thought,” The Eastern Buddhist, 28(1): 29–47. | + | –––, 1995a, “Nishida’s [[Thought]],” The Eastern [[Buddhist]], 28(1): 29–47. |
− | –––, 1995b, “The Difficulty of Understanding Nishida’s Philosophy,” The Eastern Buddhist, 28(2): 175–182. | + | –––, 1995b, “The Difficulty of [[Understanding]] Nishida’s [[Philosophy]],” The Eastern [[Buddhist]], 28(2): 175–182. |
− | Uehara Mayuko, 2006, “The Conceptualization and Translation of Jikaku and Jiko in Nishida Kitarō”, in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig, (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] | + | Uehara Mayuko, 2006, “The [[Conceptualization]] and Translation of [[Jikaku]] and Jiko in Nishida Kitarō”, in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 1, James W. Heisig, (ed.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | –––, 2009, | + | –––, 2009, “[[Japanese]] Aspects of Nishida’s Basho: [[Seeing]] the ‘[[Form]] without [[Form]]’,” in Frontiers of [[Japanese]] [[Philosophy]] 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), [[Nagoya]]: Nanzan Institute for [[Religion]] & {{Wiki|Culture}}. [*] |
− | Uhl, Christian, 2009, “Displacing Japan: Takeuchi Yoshimi’s Lu Xun in Light of Nishida’s Philosophy, and Vice Versa,” Positions, East Asia Cultures Critique, 17(1): 207–237. | + | Uhl, [[Christian]], 2009, “Displacing [[Japan]]: Takeuchi Yoshimi’s {{Wiki|Lu Xun}} in Light of Nishida’s [[Philosophy]], and Vice Versa,” Positions, {{Wiki|East Asia}} Cultures Critique, 17(1): 207–237. |
− | Wargo, Robert J., 2005, The Logic of Nothingness: An Essay on Nishida Kitarō, Honolulu, University of Hawai’i Press. | + | Wargo, Robert J., 2005, The [[Logic]] of [[Nothingness]]: An Essay on Nishida Kitarō, [[Honolulu]], {{Wiki|University}} of [[Hawai’i]] Press. |
− | Weinmayr, Elmar, 2005, | + | Weinmayr, Elmar, 2005, “[[Thinking]] in Transition: Nishida Kitarō and {{Wiki|Martin Heidegger}},” [[Philosophy East and West]], 55(2): 232–256. |
− | Wilkinson, Robert, 2009, Nishida and Western Philosophy, Surry, England and Burlington VT: Ashgate. | + | Wilkinson, Robert, 2009, Nishida and {{Wiki|Western Philosophy}}, Surry, [[England]] and Burlington VT: Ashgate. |
− | Yusa, Michiko, 2002, Zen & Philosophy: An Intellectual Biography of Nishida Kitarō, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. | + | Yusa, Michiko, 2002, [[Zen]] & [[Philosophy]]: An [[Intellectual]] {{Wiki|Biography}} of Nishida Kitarō, [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University}} of [[Hawai’i]] Press. |
Latest revision as of 00:12, 12 February 2020
Nishida Kitarō
First published Fri Feb 25, 2005; substantive revision Thu Oct 22, 2015
Nishida Kitarō was the most significant and influential Japanese philosopher of the twentieth-century. His work is path-breaking in several respects: it established in Japan the creative discipline of philosophy as practiced in Europe and the Americas; it enriched that discipline by infusing Anglo-European philosophy with Asian sources of thought; it provided a new basis for philosophical treatments of East Asian Buddhist thought; and it produced novel theories of self and world with rich implications for contemporary philosophizing.
Nishida’s work is also frustrating for its repetitive and often obscure style, exceedingly abstract formulations, and detailed but frequently dead-end investigations. Nishida once said of his work, “I have always been a miner of ore; I have never managed to refine it” (Nishida 1958, Preface). A concise presentation of his achievements therefore will require extensive selection, interpretation and clarification.
This article presents his work in a roughly chronological order. We may understand his philosophical project overall as an attempt to restore to experience and consciousness the rigor, necessity and universality accorded to logic.
This project developed in a direction quite opposite to that of psychologism, which would reduce logic to the contingencies of the individual mind or brain. It also differed from efforts to establish pure logic as a self-explanatory realm in that Nishida insisted on the starting point of experience, a priority he shared with Husserl’s phenomenology and William James’ radical empiricism.
We might characterize his philosophy in general as a phenomenological metaphysics for its universalizing of first-person experience. It can also be considered an ontology of logical forms for its investigations of their experiential basis, with one qualification: although Nishida proposed a unitary source of such forms, that source is neither exclusionary nor positive; in other words the source itself cannot be described monistically as a single, more basic form or thing.
Nishida eventually called this source “mu” (nothingness), a notion he found particularly prominent in the traditions of the East. His interests led him to develop a philosophy of culture, and his status as Japan’s premier philosopher led government officials to call upon him for justification of Japanese expansionism in the late 1930s and early 40s. His last work recapitulated his non-dualistic account of world and self, but also reinterpreted the meaning of death.
1. Biography
2. Theory of Experience and Consciousness
2.1 Pure Experience
2.2 Self-Awareness
3. Theory of Universals and the Logic of Place
3.1 Absolute Nothingness
3.2 Analogies to the Logic of Place
4. Theory of the Historical World
4.1 Enactive Intuition
4.2 Theory of Relations: Self and Other, One and Many
5. Nishida’s Theology: the Finite Self meets the Absolute
6. Political Theory: Religion, Culture, and Nations
7. Methods in Nishida’s Thought
8. The Unity and Development of Nishida’s Philosophy
8.1 The Attempt to Unify the Varying Themes
8.2 Stages in Nishida’s Thought
9. The Place of Asian Philosophies in Nishida’s Thought
10. Critiques of Nishida’s Philosophy
11. Nishida’s Influence
Bibliography
Nishida’s works
Secondary Literature
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries
1. Biography
Nishida was born on May 19, 1870 in the village of Unoke on the Sea of Japan just north of the city of Kanazawa. His birthplace, later incorporated into the town of Kahoku, is the site today of archives and a monumental museum, perhaps the world’s largest architectural structure dedicated to a single philosopher.
Nishida grew up in the early years of the Meiji era (1868–1912), when Japan had reopened to the world after two and a half centuries of relative isolation and was undergoing a revolutionary Europeanization of its political, educational and cultural institutions. As it touched Nishida’s early years, this “modernization” came in the form of both a rigid, often oppressive school atmosphere that demanded obeisance to the emperor, and a liberating exposure to the progressive ideas of the Japanese “Enlightenment” that had introduced western philosophy to Japan.
In high school in Kanazawa he studied Chinese Confucian, Neo-Confucian and Daoist classics, learned to read English and German, excelled in mathematics, and attempted briefly to penetrate works of Hegel and Kant.
He formed a life-long friendship with fellow student D.T. Suzuki, and with him dropped out of high school in 1890. Admitted into Tokyo Imperial University as a “limited status” student the following year, Nishida studied Kant, Hegel and Schopenhauer under the first philosophy professors in Japan.
After graduating in 1894 with a thesis on Hume’s theory of causation, he married and held teaching positions at several provincial high schools and universities. During the next decade, despite the demands of family life and teaching German among other subjects, he published a few philosophical essays but was more intent on formal meditation practice under Zen masters in Kyoto.
He began composing what later appeared as An Inquiry into the Good in 1905 and on the basis of that work secured a position at Kyoto Imperial University in 1910, becoming Professor of Philosophy there in 1914.
Nishida concentrated on the philosophical books that made their way into Japan and for the next decade wrote numerous essays that reworked ideas from the Neo-Kantians, Royce, Bergson, Hermann Lotze and, to a lesser extent, Husserl.
These essays were collected into books that investigated a wide range of topics, including art and morality, from the perspective of a theory of consciousness and the will. Nishida’s fame began to spread in the 1920s.
He was instrumental in securing positions at Kyoto University for Tanabe Hajime, Watsuji Tetsurō, and Kuki Shuzō, and attracted students such as Nishitani Keiji, Miki Kiyoshi and Tosaka Jun, who all became significant philosophers in Japan.
He developed his signature theory of place (basho) in the mid 1920s, and continued to elaborate it after he became professor emeritus and moved to Kamakura in 1929. In the early 1930s his interests turned to the nature of human actions and interactions in the historical and social world, and eventually to the meaning of culture and nationhood.
Because of his prestige as Japan’s premier philosopher, government officials—among them his former student and then Prime Minister Konoe Fumimaro—appealed to him to justify Japanese nationalism. Nishida complied by addressing the issues, if not legitimizing Japan’s expansionism. Yet he considered much of that work a distraction. He lectured on “The Problem of Japanese Culture” in 1938; when published two years later the book quickly sold some 60,000 copies. He delivered an invited address to the emperor in 1941 that advocated academic freedom and a place for each nation in the global world, with each developing its own global perspective.[1] Addresses on the “Principles for the New World Order” and on “The Body (or Essence) of the Nation” (kokutai) followed. During this time Nishida’s critics on the right considered his political writings either too abstract or insufficiently supportive of the government; after the Second World War his leftist critics found them profusely nationalistic. Despite his failing health and the bombing of cities all around him, Nishida persisted in his philosophical investigations, using for example Descartes’ Cogito and Leibniz’s Preestablished Harmony as points of departure. He completed the seminal essay, “The Logic of Place and the Religious Worldview,” just two months before his death on June 7, 1945. Publication of his collected works in 19 volumes began two years later. An extant photograph shows dozens of people camped out all night long awaiting the issue of the first volume on July 20, 1947.
Nishida’s private life, reflected only faintly in his philosophical work, nevertheless left its stamp on its tenor. His perseverance through turmoil explains perhaps some of the intensity of his writing. Comprehending reality for him was an emotive as well as intellectual achievement; his calligraphy and poetry, renowned in their own right, evince an acute awareness of transience and transcendence. Nishida experienced the death of his first wife and four of his eight children; upon the passing of his first son he wrote this waka poem:
Having lived
healthily
till twenty-three
how could he disappear
like a dream
(Yusa 2002, 314–18).
Three years later he was able to write
The bottom of my soul has such depth;
Neither joy nor the waves of sorrow can reach it
(Nishida 1958, frontispiece).
2. Theory of Experience and Consciousness
2.1 Pure Experience
Starting with An Inquiry Into the Good, Nishida’s early work calls into question two basic presuppositions of most modern epistemology: the assumptions that experience is individual and subjective, and that it leads to knowledge only via a corrective process with input from the mind or other individuals.
For Nishida, experience in its original form is not the exercise of individuals equipped with sensory and mental abilities who contact an exterior world; rather it precedes the differentiation into subject experiencing and object experienced, and the individual is formed out of it. “The moment of seeing a color or hearing a sound” is prior not only to the thought that the color or sound is the activity of an external object or that one is sensing it, but also to the judgment of what the color or sound might be (Nishida 1990a, 3).
“Pure experience” names not only the basic form of every sensuous and every intellectual experience but also the fundamental form of reality, indeed the “one and only reality” from which all differentiated phenomena are to be understood. Cognitive activities such as thinking or judging, willing, and intellectual intuition are all derivative forms of pure experience but still manifest it insofar as they are in action —when thinking, willing, etc. are going on.
The experience of a running horse, for example, underlies the judgment that the horse is running, and the activity of judging is an exercise of pure experience prior to a subsequent judgment that “I am now judging.” Objective phenomena likewise derive from pure experience; when unified they are called “nature,” while “spirit” names the activity of unifying. Pure experience launches the dynamic process of reality that differentiates into subjective and objective phenomena on their way to a higher unity, and the recapture of our unitary foundation is what Nishida means by the Good.
Nishida would deny that his position is a kind of idealism, either subjective or transcendental, because no subjective mind, human or divine, is the origin of what is taken as reality, and no personified or ego-aware spirit is its beginning or end. His notion of pure experience clearly shows the influence of William James, Ernst Mach, and others, but it differs from their notions as well as from twentieth-century expositions of pre-reflective experience by its emphasis on the non-individuated character and the seamless development of such experience. It is the pre-individual basis of a systematic and all-comprehensive process. If we call his view a “theory” of experience, we should be aware that from his standpoint the theory is a natural outgrowth of unitary experience and not a reflection on it as proceeding from a different source. The question of how pure experience grounds reflective knowledge would occupy Nishida in works composed after An Inquiry Into the Good.
The directness, relative simplicity, and systematic approach of this book made it perhaps the most accessible and popular of his works; and many commentators have tended to emphasize it more than later writings, despite Nishida’s own misgivings about its latent psychologism. Indeed Nishida’s initial position anticipates several developments in his later thought. For example, the early statements of experience prior to a subject experiencing and an object experienced are re-formulated in the late 1920s as “seeing without a seer, hearing without a hearer.”
The nullification of the self in pure experience is later expressed as seeing the self from the perspective of the world, where world is understood phenomenologically as a determining horizon of experience. The notion of the individual as determined by the universal concealed within (Nishida 1990a, 18) pre-figures Nishida’s later adaptation of Hegel’s concrete universal; the later works speak of the individual as the self-determination of the universal. Finally, the ways in which pure experience can be said to be most concrete, to enfold all reality and indicate its undifferentiated ground, reflect methods that characterize Nishida’s philosophy as a whole.
2.2 Self-Awareness
The question of how reflective thought is grounded in pure experience finds a tentative answer in Nishida’s next essays. How can pure experience develop into reflective thought that would seem to interrupt and interpret it from an external vantage point? The self-reflection known as self-consciousness or self-awareness (jikaku) provides an answer.
There is a form of consciousness that inherently reflects or mirrors itself within itself, so that there is no difference between that which reflects and what is reflected. In self-awareness, immediate experiencing and reflection are unified. In epistemological terms, knower and known are the same, and this instance of unity serves as the prototype of all knowledge.
Two points may prevent a misunderstanding of Nishida’s position here. First, his talk of self-awareness and self-reflection does not imply the pre-given existence of some personal self that at times may be self-conscious.
Secondly, if consciousness is not placed in a pre-given self, it also is not placed in the objective world as a complex of brain cells or as the effect of material objects on the mind or brain. As in modern phenomenology, consciousness for Nishida means simply that which makes manifest or, to use a visual metaphor, that which illuminates.
To emphasize its non-objectifiable character, Nishida later will place consciousness “in” nothingness, that is, consider it a “form” of nothingness, and will eventually consider this a form of relative or oppositional nothingness, a non-being with respect to beings. In the meantime, he formulated it as the activity that precedes but ultimately unifies self and world. Knowledge of things in the world begins with the differentiation of unitary consciousness into knower and known and ends with self and things becoming one again.
Such unification takes form not only in knowing but in the valuing (of truth) that directs knowing, the willing that directs action, and the feeling or emotive reach that directs sensing. In this stage of his work Nishida, influenced by Fichte and Schopenhauer, considered “absolute will” as the preeminent form of self-awareness and saw it as the source of acts of moral decision and of the creation and appreciation of art. Since the activity of the will eludes reflection, however, Nishida eventually abandoned this formulation of a unitary source.
3. Theory of Universals and the Logic of Place
Nishida’s epistemological motivation gradually gave way to an examination of common ontological assumptions that underlie epistemology in the Western philosophical tradition. Not content merely to expose such assumptions, however, Nishida formulated a novel ontology of experience and self-awareness that would give them logical necessity.
Considering what is taken as the ordinary consciousness of objects, Nishida’s analysis questions both the notion of consciousness and that of objects. We can explicate Nishida’s first concern, with the ontology of consciousness, in the following way:
If the basic form of consciousness did not have the reflexivity of self-awareness, then the “consciousness” of objects would be blind, as it were, like a mechanical or neurological reaction to stimuli with no awareness whatsoever, and no way to account for awareness.
The problem appears in attempts to define consciousness in a non-circular way. A definition of consciousness as a state of awareness or sentience, for example, or a state in which there is something it feels like to be in that state, merely replaces consciousness with its synonyms. In a sense, awareness is irreducible, but it has a logical structure that accounts for its connection to a world of objects.
Structurally, awareness mirrors itself in itself, in a manner analogous to the way an infinite set mirrors itself in its equivalent subsets, or to the way an ideal map mirrors itself in all accurate representations of that map.[2] (Note that the English awareness can be used without the word self but the Japanese word that translates as self-awareness is an inseparable compound, ji-kaku.) If such self-awareness is to have logical necessity, it cannot be explained as a contingent property of a particular mind or consciousness that sometimes reflects on itself, that is, as a second order consciousness of being conscious of something.
Similarly, if self-awareness is to be an awareness of more than merely oneself, it cannot be interior to the self alone. Modern epistemology’s solution was to split the world in two, mind and nature, and then to see the mind as a mirror of nature, and ideas as representations of real objects. Nishida’s solution was to see the world as mirroring itself in all the things “in the world.”
Whatever is “in the world” is a mirroring of the world. In this sense it is the world that is “self-aware” or self-reflexive; and there is no outside to it. An individual’s “self-awareness” is a partial mirroring of the world; Nishida later described the individual self as a focal point of the world.
While he was still thinking in terms of consciousness, however, Nishida avoided pinpointing awareness and spoke of the world as a field of consciousness to indicate the extension of the term beyond the individual self. This field is similar to Kant’s Bewußtsein überhaupt, in that it functions as the condition for the possibility of particular acts of consciousness, but unlike Kant’s notion that turns everything into an object of consciousness, its reflexive structure allows it to take itself into account without making it another object.
We may use Nishida’s own terms to explain his second concern, the way that objects ordinarily function in judgments.
In what Nishida alternatively called the logic of objects or subjective logic, objects of consciousness are made the grammatical subject of propositions or judgments, and are specified by predicating properties of the subject. Eventually a subject is reached that cannot itself be predicated of anything else, recalling Aristotle’s hypokeimenon or individual substance that can be subject but never predicate.
Even when modern epistemology eschewed or at least modified Aristotle’s notion of substance as a substrate for contingent properties, it appealed to substances in the sense that they define the primary subject of a judgment, that is, the judgment’s topic and grammatical subject.
Similar to phenomenologists, Nishida wanted to account for the consciousness that posits such substances and underlies the subject of a judgment. Essays in From That Which Acts to That Which Sees (1927) and subsequent works invert Aristotle’s notion of the hypokeimenon and propose that consciousness is the “transcendental predicate” that can never be a subject; in other words consciousness in act can never be made an object of consciousness that could become a grammatical subject.
Nishida is aware of the paradox of such formulations that would make consciousness the subject of sentences that describe it, and he sometimes resorts to explicitly paradoxical descriptions such as “seeing without a seer” and “seeing the form of the formless, hearing the voice of the voiceless.”
But he again also uses the straightforward metaphor, the “field of consciousness,” to indicate its non-subjective and non-objectifiable character. Consciousness cannot be grasped as the property of an individual substance nor as anything like a substance or underlying substrate itself. It functions as the field that is the opening of world and self.
If judgments describe things and states of affairs and thus would give us access to reality by setting themselves over against that reality, we must step back as it were and consider a wider reality that includes judgments. In other words, we must place judgments that predicate universals of things into a wider field of predication, that is, in the “transcendental predicate” of consciousness. Here Nishida might have further developed a phenomenology of the agency of predication, but instead he moves to a more logical account of its scope and developed what he called a predicate logic.[3] He thinks of universals as fields of possibility that becomes specified or determined (more accurately, that determine themselves) in their particular instantiations. There is a necessary hierarchy of concreteness among universals that Nishida expresses as the order of topoi or places (basho).
Most abstract are the universals that serve as predicates in particular judgments. Judging or predication in turn takes place in the topos of consciousness, which is further concretized as the universal or topos of reflexive self-awareness wherein acts of seeing, knowing, desiring and willing take place. And just as the world of self-awareness enfolds the world of nature described in judgments, it in turn is enfolded in the topos (Nishida calls it “the intelligible world”) within which the creative self pursues ideal values like truth, beauty and goodness. Here Nishida echoes the medieval, seemingly all-inclusive transcendentalia that transcend all categories. In his terms, all predication would be a mirroring of the transcendentals of being and of the one (unum), the true (verum), and the good (bonum). But those transcendentals, insofar as they themselves all elude predication, actually point to a more inclusive and undifferentiated topos, absolute nothingness.
In summary, Nishida initially formulated his logic of place or topos to counter Neo-Kantian epistemology that took knowledge to be the subject’s form-ruled construction of an objective world. He sought not only to undermine the distinctions between subjective and objective but also to place both sides within a more comprehensive and concrete conception.
That is, while he first construed knowledge on the model of self-awareness in which self reflects itself within itself, he also felt compelled to find a locus of non-differentiation behind the distinction between such awareness and things seen from its vantage point.
As non-differentiated and inclusive, that locus is field-like, a metaphor that Nishida at first replaced with the notion of topos or “place” (basho). Then he placed the topos of self-awareness in the even more inclusive and concrete value-forming world. That world of creative activity anticipates what Nishida eventually considered the ultimate topos that defies description, predication, or determination by something beyond or different from it. His logic of place offered an alternative to the logic of substances presupposed in much traditional metaphysics.
The logical schema of topoi is paralleled by an ontological account. Nishida articulated the topoi also in terms of what we may call a me-ontology, from the Greek meon or non-being. The topos of being describes the world of nature. The topos of relative nothingness comprises the field of consciousness that is no-thing with respect to the things of which it is conscious.
This nothingness however is still opposed to being, and so differs from the absolute nothingness that underlies both sides of the opposition. Here and elsewhere Nishida plays on the word for absolute in Japanese, zettai, which literally means breaking through or overcoming opposition. His premise is that the meaning of “to be” is “to be within”; the ultimate “within” is the topos of absolute nothingness.
3.1 Absolute Nothingness
The topos of absolute nothingness is the ultimate “within which” all reality takes place. It can be understood as an alternative to a transcendent determiner of the world as conceptualized, for example, in medieval philosophy’s notion of God, Fichte’s transcendental ego, or Husserl’s transcendental subjectivity.
Nishida did use the language of transcendence to explain absolute nothingness, saying it transcended the opposition between being and non-being for example; but such language did not indicate any thing, power, or consciousness beyond the world.
Absolute nothingness is infinitely determinable and its determinates form the actual world, but this “self-determination” occurs “without anything that does the determining,” like an agency without an agent.
Equally paradoxical are the positive descriptions Nishida gives it, in spite of the implicit claim that it defies description. Rather than a mere absence of being, meaning, or function, absolute nothingness is active and creative in forming the actual world; and it manifests or awakens to itself through self-awareness.
It is the foundation of the world and of the self which is a focal point of the world; but it is an uncommon kind of foundation in that it functions through self-negation. It cannot be called “absolute” unless it negates any particular determination of it and simultaneously enfolds them all. It is the universal of universals. Nishida was not able to combine these various descriptions into one coherent notion, but they partially converge in the sense of an undifferentiated whole that includes all its differentiations.
3.2 Analogies to the Logic of Place
Nishida intended his theory of place or topos to provide a logical foundation for his previous philosophy of experience and self-awareness. Several overlapping models help make sense of this logic. Nishida drew upon some models explicitly, for example, Plato’s notion of the receptacle (chora) of ideas in the Timeus and Aristotle’s adaptation in his notion of topos in On the Soul.
Another model Nishida used early on was the notion of fields in modern physics and relativity theory, in which space-time is a field inseparable from the physical objects within it and determining how (when and where) they exist. Analogously, for Nishida, all perceived and conceptualized objects are “in” the “field of consciousness” (Nishida borrowed the term from William James).
Another early model was the logic of universals that serve as predicates. Particulars or individuals are placed within universals to specify their difference from other particulars or individuals, and less extensive universals are placed within more extensive ones, until one reaches the ultimate, boundless universal called nothingness.
This “transcendental predicate” cannot become the subject matter of any description or proposition in positive terms, but it is ultimately entailed by every specification.
Other analogies, although not explicitly mentioned by Nishida, nevertheless serve to clarify his logic at least in part. A model of interpretation is relevant: every text has its context, which in turn may be made a text or thematized by appealing to a further context. There is no final context that can be specified without referring to yet another context.
For Nishida this relation would not be settled by invoking the notion of an infinite regress; rather it indicates the necessity of an ultimate context of a different order, one that allows the distinction between a specific text and its context. This ultimately unspecifiable context in Nishida’s terms is called absolute nothingness.
The analysis of successful physical theories provides yet another model. Each of Nishida’s successive topoi serves as a level of analysis that resolves contradictions on less comprehensive levels, as Einstein’s relativity theory encompasses Newtonian theory and resolves contradictions in it. But for Nishida the final level that holds differences or contradictions together is ultimately unanalyzable absolute nothingness.
Despite Nishida’s relative ignorance of modern logic and his identification of predicates with universals, we may also find parallels to his logic of place in mathematical logic: an axiomatic system is a topos that, according to Gödel’s theorem, is not self-explanatory or self-generating since it contains undecidable propositions, and there is no final system with a self-explanatory foundation. Nishida’s absolute nothingness is the place beyond discursive determination.
Discourse analysis also suggests parallels: it analyzes how a discourse is framed or directed to an audience with certain interests, but the analysis too has its own frame that does not terminate in any definitive or final frame. Foundationalist theories of knowledge and reality might seem to provide a model of Nishida’s logic of place, but in Nishida the metaphor of grounding gives way to that of placing, locating, or encompassing, and in any case the ultimate place is more an Abgrund or void than a positive ground.
4. Theory of the Historical World
It is clear that Nishida proposed his various topoi not as static contexts terminating in an ultimate genus, but rather as a dynamic process of contextualization or world-formation. This always implied the temporality of the “self-aware” world, and not merely time as a dimension of the physical world.
Nevertheless, Nishida did not explicitly take account of the historical nature of the world until the early 1930s, after his critics, in particular his younger colleague, Tanabe Hajime, and his former students, Miki Kiyoshi and Tosaka Jun, turned his attention to the historical dimension of reality and human action.
The critics suggested that Nishida ignored the world determined by individual human action by replacing individual human subjectivity with trans-individual experience or consciousness and eventually shifting human agency to the world as a universal. In response, Nishida began to articulate the world as a dialectical universal.
The basic idea is that the world is a place of mediation between acting individuals. It is not a transcendent topos that one-sidedly determines individuals but a topos that arises with them through their creative interactions. There are two sides of this idea to consider: the world and the interacting individuals.
We conceptualize the formation of the world as history, but must think of history in terms of the logic of place and not simply as a temporal process. At any moment the world in process mirrors the indeterminacy or openness of absolute nothingness and contains the conditions for novelty and future possibilities; however it also encompasses everything that has already been determined. In Nishida’s words, the historical world proceeds “from the created to the creating.”
And it so proceeds not in a linear fashion, as if viewed from some point outside the world, but rather “in” every moment or, conversely, out of an “eternal now” or “absolute present” that describes the topos of its continual creation. This present in its absolute presence is the place where history can happen precisely because it enfolds the past though is not entirely determined by the past and it holds the future as infinite possibility. It is eternal or absolute in the sense that it contains infinite time by negating (fixed) time (NKZ VIII, 76ff.). Viewed in terms of the absolute present—the ever-present juncture between a determined past and an open future—the world appears as a “continuity of discontinuities.”
Similarly, we conceptualize the historical world sometimes as produced out of nature by human work and activity, sometimes as producing the individuals who interact in it, but we should think of it primarily as the mediating place of interactive creation. Individuals create their identities through their interactions in the world, and that world is continually created with them. (Nishida’s idea of a mediating place finds a distant analogue in Einstein’s theory of gravitational space, where space is not independent of the physical objects in it but rather is shaped by them). The historical world forms itself through the actions of embodied individuals who mutually form each other. Adapting a phenomenological perspective, Nishida argues that the historical world as the most concrete topos of our reality must be the starting point for understanding the more abstract world of life and even more abstract natural world.
Gradually Nishida came to recognize the importance of embodiment for human interaction and communication, and introduced the notion of the expressive or historical body. The body is not primarily a physical object and product of the natural world, but a historical subject and co-creator of the world. Insofar as the many historical bodies of the one world differ from each another, they too form a “discontinuous continuity.” Nishida was fond of calling this type of totality, which holds together differences without sublating them into a higher unity, a “self-identity of contradictories.”
Two parts of Nishida’s theory deserve further explication: his novel conception of enactive intuition and his explanation of the relations between self & other and one & many. 4.1 Enactive Intuition
In attempting to explain the formation and working of the historical world, Nishida coined the term “action-oriented intuition” or “enactive intuition” (kōi-teki chokkan). His texts suggest a reciprocity between action and intuition, so that we could also speak of “intuition-oriented action” or simply of “action-intuition.” Here again Nishida sought to discover the topos or common space that underlies a distinction, this time between intuition or seeing as a more or less passive reception of the world and its objects, and action as the human-engendered production of the world. Hence, this is another case of his “self-identity of contradictories.” The common space is the enactive or performative intuition exemplified by artistic creation.
For example, we might ordinarily conceive of the artist as a pre-given entity who views, is inspired by, and utilizes pre-given things in the world around her as she then goes about making her work. The production of the work would then be a causative process contributing in turn to the production of the historical world. We might also understand the work as an objectification of the artist, an expression of her inner spirit that externalizes and actualizes it. Nishida envisioned an alternative, however.
For Nishida, the artist takes in or intuits the world and transforms or enacts it, both of which are but two moments in a single unfolding—not only of the world but of the artist as well. Both artist and work are formed mutually and are reflected in one another. Whereas this mutual formation can be described in terms of a causative process taking time, with the person first intuiting or internalizing and then acting or externalizing, Nishida described it in terms of the place or topos wherein intuiting entails acting and acting entails intuiting, and wherein the difference between internal and external collapses. Granted, the work can take on a life of its own as an object of appreciation or criticism, but it always carries its reference to the artist, as the identity of the artist likewise cannot be separated from her work.
Artistic creation is only one example of such poiesis, as Nishida called it. Scientific experimentation also provides an example of enactive intuition insofar as experiments require the performance of a body acting and understanding through instruments (NKZ VIII, 326). Enactive or performative intuition is operative in praxis or political-social action as well, insofar as it grasps the world as including the self. Nishida emphasized that enactive intuition is a bodily achievement, the performance of an embodied individual who in turn is formed by the world; again, both body and world must be conceived as historical. While enactive intuition pertains to the dialectical way the individual historical body forms and is formed by the world, the way the world forms is described by the phrase “from the created to the creating.” 4.2 Theory of Relations: Self and Other, One and Many Self and Other
We can shift the focus from the action of the individual historical body to the interaction between distinct individuals, once again with the world as the mediating space of mutual formation. In fact, Nishida maintains that the individual, precisely as distinct, entails a plurality of interrelated individuals. The relation between “I and Thou” was the first part that Nishida considered, although he continued to intertwine that relation with an internal relation in self-awareness. Where his previous analysis of individual self-awareness described it as a self-reflection of the universal of self-awareness, his description now incorporated the dimension of recognition. My recognition of you as not me makes me who I am, and your recognition of me as not-you makes you who you are. Each is a relative other to the self.
That Hegelian analysis is incomplete, however, without the recognition of the absolute other in the self’s interior. This other, recalling Nishida’s notion of absolute, does not exclude the self; rather it constitutes self-identity as continually negating what it has been. My personal self-awareness arises not when I recognize my identity through memory, for example, nor simply when I encounter an other I; rather it arises in experiencing the groundlessness of my own existence, in recognizing what is absolutely other to a substantial self-same self. Recognizing the absolute other within constitutes not simply a reflexive self-awareness but a self-awakening, a realizing of the “true self.”
Nishida’s term for self-awareness is jikaku, which can also be translated as self-awakening, a Buddhist reading he undoubtedly intends. Nishida allows for the Buddhist view that there is actually no self to awaken by referring to the self-awakening of absolute nothingness; its awakening is the awakening of the “true self.” Absolute nothingness in action, as it were, entails a negation (of a substantial, self-same self) and an affirmation (of the true self). In the manner of self-negation, I am one with you while not being the same as you. Not only between us does a “continuity of absolute discontinuities” obtain, but also within each of us, insofar as our identity is in continual formation. In the end, then, Nishida denies the substantiality of the self and rejects both the radical alterity of other persons and the transcendence of an absolute other, in the guise of God for example. One and Many
Eventually Nishida saw that the “I-You” relation does not exhaust the discontinuous continuity of our being. We must also take into account the third party, the relative other, “he” or “she,” who forms at least an implicit reference to every “I-you” interaction. Nishida seems intent not so much on explaining alterity, however, as preserving interdependent individuality, which of course still requires difference. He has in mind the individuation of all phenomena but begins with the prototype of individuality, the self-aware human person, who is more concretely an individual than other single living beings, not to speak of individuated atoms or particles at the most abstract level. What determines individuality at the most concrete level is the one historical world that functions dialectically as the place or medium of interaction among innumerable individuals. The world is one yet many; individuals are many yet one in their mutual determination. (Nishida uses the Buddhist connective soku to indicate the relation between one and many and to emphasize their inherent reversibility. Soku translates roughly as “and at the same time”: “one and at the same time many”, “many and at the same time one.” Otherwise, however, his terminology in this part of his philosophy is often more Hegelian than Buddhist.)
Nishida’s own formulations once again make use of the pattern of an undifferentiated whole differentiating or determining itself, in this case as distinct individuals. Although the topological account of a self- or immanently determining historical world seems to invoke more spatial than temporal notions, the description of this topos as the space wherein individuals interact and mutually determine one another is meant to accommodate the temporal dimension as well. The world is formed in conjunction with the individual embodied selves who interact in it; like Einstein’s space-time, it is not independent of the things “in” it and does not preexist them. But for Nishida the realization or awareness of individual selves entails the realization or awareness of the world as well. As mentioned earlier, the world too is “self-aware” (jikaku-teki) not only in the sense of being self-reflexive but also in the sense of realizing and recognizing itself via its individual selves who are its “focal points.” Here we see another instance of Nishida’s way of universalizing first-person experience. In the discussions of the one and the many, however, Nishida relatively neglected the notion of self-awakening––the other, Buddhist-tinged reading of jikaku that is such an important part of the I-You relation. 5. Nishida’s Theology: the Finite Self meets the Absolute
Toward the end of his life, perhaps thinking of the significance of death for understanding individuality, perhaps re-considering the theme of self-awakening as a kind of death and re-birth, Nishida delved deeper into the relation between the individual finite human self and the absolute or God. In his view, this relation logically defines the place of religion. Experientially it comes to the fore in death. We will consider the meaning of death first, then the nature of God or the absolute in relation to the finite self.
The theme of personal death is absent in Nishida’s early work on pure experience and self-awareness, and mentioned only abstractly in essays on the historical world and the self, for example: “In absolute dialectics, mediation as absolute negation is mediation as absolute death, living by dying absolutely” (NKZ VII, 314). In the last completed essay, “The Logic of Place and the Religious Worldview” (1945), Nishida is more experiential. Death is not an event at the end of one’s life but penetrates life at each and every moment. It is the ever-present opening, so to speak, where one’s utter finitude can come to light. Insofar as this is the finitude of the individual self, it also implies a logic of individuation where the role of other relative selves is diminished. “I am myself by knowing my own death” (NKZ XI, 420) is both a declaration of existential self-awareness and a statement of what makes me uniquely me. What makes me an individual is not merely my differences from others nor my sameness with some essential core; it is precisely what most makes me not me, what negates me, in any moment of action. In this context, death signifies the self-negation of the finite self.
If death is an ever-present opening, the other side of that opening, so to speak, is the absolute. To die is to stand vis-à-vis the absolute. In the discussion of the “I-You” relation, this term appeared as the absolute other in one’s interior; here it shifts to the absolute in contradistinction to finite beings. Nishida calls it God as well, but makes clear that he is not referring to a personal, transcendent being. If transcendence is involved, it is a going beyond by going within. He also implies that it is not synonymous with absolute nothingness. If relative nothingness as opposed to being is implied, it is in the verbal sense of self-negating. The absolute arises through its own self-negation and inclusion of the relative self. It does not die in the sense that relative beings do, for it embraces all others whereas they, by being individual, exclude others. God cannot be wholly transcendent to or exclusive of the self or the world. Even Nishida’s early work, An Inquiry Into the Good , had spoken of God in a way that undermined the notion of a transcendent being outside the world; it conceived of God as the infinite activity of unification at work behind the articulations of spirit and nature out of pure experience.
In his final essay, Nishida admits that his notion of an absolute totally embracing the relative, even in its diabolical forms, is more in tune with a Mahayana Buddhist tradition than with the Christian sources that inspired him. To express the relation between a God and the relative finite self, Nishida introduces a new term, “inverse correlation”(gyaku taiō). This relation is another instance of opposites held together in a unity, a kind of “self-identity of contradictories,” but this time not a symmetrical one. The more one faces one’s death, the negation of one’s life as an individual, the more acutely one is self-aware as an individual. The closer the finite self approaches God the stronger the difference between them becomes. This peculiar kind of relation implies that God and the relative self are inseparable but asymmetrically co-dependent. God or the absolute embraces and never excludes the human or relative, and the relative self never coincides with or dissolves into God. Nishida’s inverse correlation is perhaps comparable to some theological notions of non-reciprocal dependence, where for example it is said that God is my being yet I am not God’s being. But in Nishida’s case, insofar as the distinction entails an undifferentiated source of their difference, an absolute nothingness, the more that source is contacted the stronger the distinction holds. 6. Political Theory: Religion, Culture, and Nations
Nishida’s discussion of the absolute and the finite self does not neglect the notion of religion and its relation to culture and the nation-state. These themes already formed an integral part of his theory of the historical world but became all the more pressing in a time of world war. The concern with death was perhaps as much a political as a personal matter for Nishida, whose health in 1945 was quickly failing. In one respect, he distanced himself from his milieu where everyday life was dominated by an authoritarian state. In his last completed essay, he focuses on the individual in relation to an absolute that in no way is subject to an absolutist state. His notion of the essentiality of religion is remarkably individualistic, removed from all social contingencies. He locates the core of religion in the heart of the individual: religious awareness arises in one’s knowing one’s own death.
On the other hand, Nishida recognizes that religion is a social and cultural phenomenon, and that the contemporary individual is a subject of a state. He seems however to reverse any implied priority of culture over religion and state over individual: it is because culture is religious in its core that we find religion in every culture; and obedience to the nation must be based on true religious awareness. To be sure, writing under a totalitarian government in 1945, Nishida couches his statements carefully in language that would deter his imprisonment on grounds of lèse majesté. He also says, for example, that insofar as the individual self is historically formed it must be understood as a nationally identified self; and further that it is selfish merely to seek one’s own peace of mind. In the end, Nishida remains ambiguous about the extent to which individuals are, or should be, formed by the will of the state, and whether religion can or should criticize the state or society.
To say that culture is essentially religious means that it too is an “affirmation of the self-negating absolute” (NKZ XI, 458). Religion and culture are each framed in the singular here, as something essential to all religions and cultures in the plural. At this level culture and religion function almost as regulative ideas. They are not the result but the telos of the one world forming its self-identity. Nishida’s formulations recapitulate much of his theory of the historical world. As the various ethnic peoples in the world become aware of themselves as constituents of a global world, that is, as they become “world-historical” nations, they mirror the formation of the historical world. As self-aware and globally historical, the world will be mirrored variously in each nation.
If we hear Hegelian echoes in these formulations, we should also note Nishida’s difference from Hegel: the formation of the “world-historical” world does not imply a hierarchy of cultures evolving as forms of increasing rationality; and it is exemplified in the everyday, as Nishida says, not the exceptional. Nishida’s global world seems more open to a genuine pluralism of cultures, world religions and national identities. Each can retain its uniqueness but to do so each must become self-aware by becoming aware of the plurality, by relativizing or negating itself. This self-negation creates the space in which true intercultural encounter can take place. Nishida implies that the proper relation between cultures is parallel to that between “I and Thou.” In simpler language: “A true world culture will be formed only by various cultures preserving their own respective viewpoints, but simultaneously developing themselves through global mediation” (NKZ VII, pp. 452–3).
Nevertheless a special place is accorded the nation of Japan. The Japanese nation is in a position to foster not only an awareness of the East but also a global awareness on the part of every nation. For Japan is the nation in Asia that has best retained Asian traditions while adapting Western technology and values. In the new world order Japan can stand for Asia, and stand against the domination of the West. Nishida’s language, perhaps deliberately ambiguous to avoid his incarceration, ostensibly wavers as to whether this special mission describes Japan’s calling, what it can be for the world, or refers to its current practice in its war-time struggle with other nations. A charitable reading of Nishida’s statements on the special place of Japan interprets them as advocating that his country overcome its outdated vision of itself as a colonizing nation, and embrace a global conception of itself as a nation interacting with other nations in a world of mutually defining equals.[4] A more critical reading interprets these statements as falsely absolutizing the particular nation of Japan, suggesting that Japan embraces other nations of the East which is abstractly opposed to the West. Similar challenges face us in the twenty-first century not only in a world of continuing imperialism and contesting nations with different religious and cultural traditions but also in single nations of multicultural composition. 7. Methods in Nishida’s Thought
Nishida composed essays on interrelated themes rather than sequential and tightly edited books. Major essays were subsequently collected and published as books, but often do not form chapters of a single coherent work. Instead of investigating a problem in a series of straightforward linear arguments, he tended to write in spirals that kept circling back on previous formulations and reworking them in new contexts. His style is akin to the manner in which one repeatedly practices a traditional Japanese art like calligraphy, poetry or even Zen mediation: working at a particular activity or expression, getting better and better at it without erasing one’s previous attempts. It is possible, however, to discern four methods that pervade his philosophy and make it easier for the reader to follow the train of his thought.
First is Nishida’s way of taking the more inclusive as the more concrete, and the more restricted as the more abstract. This makes sense insofar as abstraction involves removal of parts, but Nishida also uses this method to reverse the usual order of things in explanatory schemas or hierarchies. As mentioned earlier, the historical world lived by human beings, for example, is more concrete than the material world studied by physics since the historical, human world comprehends (in both senses of the word) the merely physical and can never be reduced to it. Between these two worlds is the biological realm of life forms, less concrete than the human world but more concrete than the physical world.
Second is Nishida’s recourse to the explanatory schema of wholes that reflect themselves in their parts. Here Nishida adapts the idea of self-representative systems presented in Josiah Royce and Richard Dedekind’s idea of an infinite system reflected in its parts. For Nishida, if there are no parts outside a whole, its evident differentiation must be explained. After his first major book, An Inquiry into the Good, Nishida came to explain this differentiating development not in terms of a temporal process but as the self-reflective or self-mirroring structure of a whole. Knowledge, for example, is not a matter of two disparate realities, a knowing mind and a known object, conforming to one another, but a single concrete reality that “reflects itself in itself” on differing levels that give rise to the more abstract notions of knowing subject and known objects. And after Nishida described self-awareness (jikaku) as the activity of self reflecting itself within itself, he came to speak of other structural wholes, including place or topos and even the world itself, as “self-aware” (jikaku-teki) insofar as they reflected themselves within themselves.
Third is Nishida’s way of elaborating this “within” in terms of enfolding or enwrapping, as a whole enfolds or contains parts that partially reflect it , or as the universal of color encompasses that of red, for example. Nishida also referred to more limited realms as particularizations or “self-determinations” of more inclusive realms, but he often used the metaphor of wrapping to describe the manner of determination. The ultimate universal or enfolding whole has no determinate features; it is “nothingness” (mu).
The fourth method is Nishida’s way of treating oppositions and distinctions, emphasizing alternatively their undifferentiated ground or their irreducible relation. He often sought to return oppositions and distinctions to the non-differentiated condition that underlies them, ultimately to the nothingness that gives rise to (or determines itself as) various distinctions. Although terms translating as “ground” or “foundation” are found throughout his works, this emphasis undermines any recourse to a founding principle or entity wholly transcendent to, and thus ultimately different from, the world or reality. “Absolute nothingness” may be understood as the lack of any positively definable transcendent ground. When for example Nishida writes “absolute nothingness transcends all that is, but at the same time all that is arises through it” (NKZ IX, 6), we may interpret him as pointing to an undifferentiated source beyond the distinctions it gives rise to, a source that is necessarily entailed by their being brought together precisely as distinct from one another.
The emphasis on relation similarly undermines any attempt to reduce opposed or distinguished terms to some element common to both. In mid career Nishida used the language of dialectics to describe relations, while insisting that the opposed terms were not sublated into a higher unity. Later he used expressions like “the self-identity of absolute contradictories” to describe the way in which opposed terms are held together, the many and the one for example. His notion of an “inverse correlation” also reflects this method. Nishida’s emphasis on relation modifies his notion of self-reflective structures to make it clear that they maintain difference within a whole and are not simply self-replicating or recursive. This is noticeable in his last essay, for example, when he describes individual selves as focal points where world reflects itself in itself (NKZ XI, 378). His rejection of a positive foundation or substratum, and his insistence on irreducible but inseparable terms in relation, explain why the holistic tendency evident in his methodology does not devolve into a simple monism, and why many commentators refer to his philosophy as non-dualist instead. 8. The Unity and Development of Nishida’s Philosophy 8.1 The Attempt to Unify the Varying Themes
A grasp of both the unity and the development of Nishida’s thought is also crucial to understanding it. As should be obvious, Nishida’s thought underwent extensive changes over the course of four decades. Less evident is that the varying themes are united by a deepening of the same basic insights. The Preface to the third volume of his Philosophical Essays published in 1939 gives us his own view of the unity of his progression: “It is said that that I repeatedly discuss the same problems, and [indeed] from An Inquiry into the Good on my objective has been to see things and think things from the most direct and fundamental standpoint—to grasp all things from the standpoint of whence they come and whither they go.” (NKZ IX, 3). A Preface written three years earlier to the reprint of An Inquiry into the Good identifies some of the crucial connections in the changing thematic: the standpoint of pure experience articulated in that maiden work developed into that of absolute will, and later into the notion of place or topos, concretized further as a dialectical universal, which in turn gets expressed as action-intuition. “That which I called...the world of pure experience I have now come to think of as the world of historical reality. The world of enactive intuition—the world of poiesis—is none other than the world of pure experience” (Nishida 1990, xxxiii).
Since Nishida composed his essays in a language and for a culture that had known philosophy as a distinct discipline for little more than half a century, his view of that discipline is equally crucial for understanding the unity and progression of his thought. Although his view likewise evolved over the course of his life, it reveals one abiding feature: philosophy should be not only the articulation but also the awareness of the most fundamental unities of experience, knowledge, action, and ultimately self and world.
Relatively early in his career, when he was still under the sway of Fichte, the Neo-Kantians, and Bergson he defined philosophy as science [gakumon], i.e. unified conceptual knowledge, more specifically the first and universal science that “reflects on the basic concepts of the particular sciences in general and constructs of them one system of knowledge.” Yet “its object of study is not simply the fundamental concepts of reality. Basic normative notions such as truth, goodness and beauty must of course enter into philosophical study. Philosophy not only clarifies basic notions of reality, but must also elucidate the ideals of human life, the ‘ought’ itself. Philosophy is not simply a worldview; it is a view of human life.” Within his extended definition Nishida, commenting on Bergson, clarifies the role of intuition so crucial to his own thought: “‘intuition’ as such cannot be called philosophy. Even if its contents can derive from intuition, philosophy has its raison d’être when intuition takes the form of conceptual knowledge.” (NKZ 13, 254).
Then, later in his career, Nishida paradoxically formed concepts of the limits of such knowledge and formulated his philosophy of absolute nothingness that is ultimately mirrored in self-awareness. Such awareness became a task for philosophy or, more specifically, for the philosopher. Throughout his life Nishida’s own practice of philosophy attempted to realize an abiding insight expressed in the various terms he recounts in the Preface cited above. In that sense his thought is systematic, while not forming a closed system. It is a consistent attempt to re-conceptualize philosophy, to reframe the terms in which many philosophers think about self and world. This is what is meant by saying that Nishida would have us think from the perspective of the world rather than the “I.” 8.2 Stages in Nishida’s Thought
Many readers of Nishida have attempted to delineate stages in the development of his philosophy (Elberfeld 1999, 71ff.); others have rejected a division into discrete stages (Heisig 2001, 104). As a heuristic approach to a summary of his thought, we may broadly distinguish three stages. The first is defined by an overwhelming conviction that concrete reality is at base unitary and can be articulated from the standpoint of consciousness. We have seen that Nishida successively names its most basic form “pure experience,” “self-awareness,” and “absolute free will.” Each of these exemplifies the fundamental reality from which all else becomes manifest through a process of differentiation. In An Inquiry Into the Good (1911), pure experience describes the primal undifferentiated form that subsequently dirempts into differentiated forms: experiencing subject and experienced objects, intellectual intuition and reflective thought, objectified nature and objectifying spirit—all on their way to a higher unity. Intuition and Reflection in Self-Awareness (1917) shifts that idealistic description to epistemological questions. It explicates self-awareness as the form in which reflection and immediate experience or intuition are unified, the form that reflects itself within itself and gives rise not only to differentiating judgments but to differently experienced systems such as spirit and matter and to “worlds” such as art and religion. Eventually Nishida proposes that the most basic form of self-awareness is not a kind of knowing at all, but a willing or “absolute free will” evident in valuing and creating. He develops this proposal in Problems of Consciousness (1920) and Art and Morality (1923). Nishida later said his first attempts, formulated from the standpoint of consciousness, invited the charges of psychologism (Nishida 1990, xxxi), and mysticism (Nishida 1987, xxiii), and so he abandoned the language of pure experience and absolute will. It is clear, however, that his initial convictions persisted a good deal longer: the most concrete form of reality is undifferentiated, and consciousness as the manifestation of reality is inseparable from it.
The second stage, broadly speaking, is defined by the standpoint of place or topos (basho). This involves the attempts to articulate levels of differentiation and place them in more and more inclusive circles (to use one of Nishida’s metaphors) until one reaches the most concrete and comprehensive circle, a circle without circumference whose center is everywhere. Nishida calls each such circle a place or topos, which allow things to be and to be seen as what they are. The final topos places self-awareness in the world of action and expression which contextualizes it, and ultimately in absolute nothingness. Nishida refers to the ultimate topos, alluding to Buddhist doctrine, as “the form of the formless,” clearly replacing earlier attempts to describe the basic form of concrete reality in positive and subjectivistic terms such as pure experience, self-awareness and absolute free will, This stage is evident in essays in From That Which Acts to That Which Sees (1927) and The Self-aware System of Universals (1930), and extends to much of The Self-aware Determination of Nothingness (1932). A Hegelian language of dialectics gradually became more and more prominent in his formulations, as he turned his attention to the place of individuals interacting in the world. He wrote of individuals as the “self-determinations” of the universal of self-awareness; and of absolute nothingness as a dialectical universal.
The third stage sharpens the focus on the dialectical world as a place of mediation between interacting individuals as historically embodied selves. Nishida now conceptualizes the world as the historical manifestation of absolute nothingness. This stage represents what is for Nishida the most comprehensive and concrete standpoint, that of the historical world. The world unfolds “from the created to the creating,” not in a straightforward linear progression but out of an “absolute present” that in each moment holds together past determinations and decisions for the future. The historical world as such is a “self-identity of contradictories.” The self realizes itself not in knowing itself as distinct from other selves or things but through forms of self-negation. One form calls for the self to recognize the absolute other in its own core to relate truly to the Thou or other relative selves. Another form calls for one to give oneself over to things or “become one with” the things it would know—through “enactive intuition,” seeing them by interacting with them and interacting by seeing them from their own perspective. In this stage relations come to the fore: the relations between I and Thou, the one and the many, the expressive self and its expressions, the Japanese nation and other nations. Each of these relations constitutes a self-identity of contradictories and resists a monistic interpretation. This stage, understood heuristically, stretches from the final essays in The Self-aware Determination of Nothingness through The World of Action and The Dialectical World (collected as The Fundamental Problems of Philosophy, 1934), seven volumes of Philosophical Essays (1935–45) and several political writings, to Nishida last essay, “The Logic of Place and the Religious Worldview”(1945). The final essay returns to the theme of religious awareness and makes more explicit the Buddhist references, as well as the Christian, influence, latent in much of Nishida’s philosophy. The focus on death and finitude, while consistent with the idea of self-negation, suggests a shift of standpoint, but Nishida’s final reflections are too brief to be called a new stage in his philosophy. 9. The Place of Asian Philosophies in Nishida’s Thought
Because Nishida throughout his career cited Western philosophers far more often than Asian sources, it is easy to read his thought as an ongoing engagement with problems that have their origin in Western traditions. In addressing the concerns of Western thinkers he followed the path taken by nearly all Japanese professors of philosophy since the inception of the academic discipline in the 1880s. Yet his appropriation of ideas from Asian philosophies is also evident to the discerning reader, if more by way of allusion and affinity than by direct citation. It was not always necessary for him to name his Asian sources as explicitly, for he could appeal to the general education of Japanese readers who would be familiar with the classics of Asia and with the convention of appropriating ideas without directly referring to them. While commentators have long pointed out the debt of Nishida to Zen Buddhist practice and thought, they have only recently begun to identify other Asian sources of his philosophy by researching his vast library in Asian languages (Dalissier 2009b). In retrospect, it is clear that all along Nishida was infusing Western philosophy with Asian thought far more pervasively than the few references to Buddhism above might indicate.
In general, we can discern two ways that Nishida made use of Asian sources: anecdotally and systematically. Nishida’s writings are strewn with unacknowledged quotations or paraphrases of verses in classical Chinese sources, as well as allusions that may or may not identify their source in Indian, Chinese, or Japanese literature. This sort of allusion is anecdotal. Unobtrusively placed in the current of a discussion on a particular issue, the anecdotal allusions serve to clarify an idea, to provide a concrete example, or to insert a playful turn of phrase into otherwise ponderous prose. One example is the passage in the early work, Intuition and Reflection in Self-Consciousness, where Nishida argues that the will of the individual can freely express absolute will as the creative activity of the universe when the individual will operates spontaneously, without reflection or objectification. Nishida inserts a saying from the Zen Buddhist Record of Linji in the middle of a sentence to express this undivided spontaneity: “To think of the infinite behind the finite, or of noumenon behind actuality, is to enter the realm of objectified knowledge. In the immediate, lived experience of willing, however, the finite is immediately infinite, actuality is immediately noumenon, one walks when needing to walk and sits when needing to sit, and there is no interval for conceptual analysis” (NKZ II, 299; see Nishida 1987b, 147). Nishida also incorporates Confucian phrases, often without identifying them as such. In his first book, An Inquiry Into the Good, for example, arguing that logical reasons are often not sufficient to motivate good conduct, he alludes to a maxim of Confucius: “The saying Do not do unto others what you would not have others do unto you, is nearly meaningless without the motivation of sympathy” (Nishida 1990, 113; NKZ I, 132).
Nishida makes use of Asian philosophies systematically both in key notions such as nothingness and in the methods that characterize his thinking. The notion of absolute nothingness recalls Indian ideas as well as Chinese Daoist and Buddhist expressions. Indeed, Nishida once suggested that we can distinguish traditional Eastern and Western philosophies by the East’s prioritizing of nothingness and the West’s reliance on being (NKZ VII, 429–30; Nishida 1970b, 237). He explicitly mentions the profound idea of nothingness developed in Indian religion (Nishida 1970b, 239), and we can find a precedent to his notion of absolute nothingness as beyond being and nonbeing in the Hymn of Creation in book ten of the Rg Veda: “nonbeing existed not, nor being” (Radhakrishnan 1957, 23). Nishida also had in mind the Chinese Daoist classics attributed to Laozi and Zhuangzi, where “the Way (or Dao) was clearly said to be ‘nonbeing’” (Nishida 1970b, 242). The Japanese term Nishida uses is mu (wu in Chinese), a sinogram that in Chinese literature usually functions simply as a negation of being or having and in this respect fails to convey Nishida’s full sense of nothingness that does not reduce to a lack of being. Nevertheless, philosophical Daoist literature provided a precedent that Nishida could draw upon. In chapter 40 of Laozi’s Daodejing we find the statement, “The myriad things are born from being. Being is born from nonbeing.” Reminiscent of Nishida’s absolute nothingness as a creative source, the Daodejing refers to the generative power of nonbeing and to the non-nameable Dao or Way that gives rise to the myriad things. And suggestive of Nishida’s sense of absolute nothingness as the most inclusive and undifferentiated place, the text known by its legendary author’s name, the Zhuangzi, refers to a Dao that has never known boundaries but preserves the possibility of distinctions. Taken up by Chinese Buddhism, wu not only referred to non-existence but also served as a variant of the Mahayana Buddhist notion of emptiness (śūnyatā), a negation of the self-subsistence of individual beings and an affirmation of their interdependence. Nishida drew upon such Buddhist and Daoist precedents in formulating his critique of substantialist metaphysics and his notion of absolute nothingness as an all-encompassing, ultimate frame of reference that is creative yet not transcendent to the world.
Systematic use of Asian philosophies is also apparent in Nishida’s methods. Where his arguments seek higher forms of inclusion rather than rejection of opposing views, he harks back to Chinese Buddhist schemes of explanation that absorb and contextualize rival doctrines rather than exclude them. Nishida’s manner of contextualizing, in his theory of place or topos, draws from Chinese cosmological methods in which “to explain and infer is to locate within the pattern” (Graham 1989, 320; cited in Dalissier 2009b, 226). Yogacara Buddhist theories of consciousness as the primary reality and explanatory principle most likely influenced Nishida’s tendency in his early works to explain all reality in terms of consciousness. Later, his way of unifying opposites and defining things in terms of self-negation adapts a Buddhist prajñapāramitā logic of negation, in which individuated terms entail their negation and are understood as co-relational rather than exclusive.
Even where there is no evidence of direct influence, the affinity of some key notions and arguments with classical Indian Buddhist ideas is striking. It is possible for example to read Nishida’s development of the three topoi or places of being, relative nothingness, and absolute nothingness, as a deepening of awareness that resembles the progression of awareness, described in many Buddhist schemes, that allows one to see first through the realm of desire, then through the realm of forms, to the formless realm beyond discrimination (Stevens 2009, 71). Also suggestive of the convictions underlying Nishida’s philosophy are arguments of the Mādhyamaka school of Nāgārjuna pressing for the relationality of all existents, and exhortations to appreciate the “groundlessless of things” in the Vimalakīrti-nirdeśa Sūtra (Priest 2009, 472). 10. Critiques of Nishida’s Philosophy
Criticisms of Nishida’s thought were a significant part of its development during his lifetime, and continue to this day to inform debates about its meaning and relevance. Insofar as Nishida aimed at a comprehensive “system of self-awareness” (Nishida 1987b, 70)––ultimately the system of absolute nothingness determining itself as the historical world––his philosophy seems to preclude the possibility of radical internal critique. Nishida did not envision his system as closed to development or to an open future. But several key notions that he never abandoned leave scant room for acknowledging the incomprehensible: the notions of a universal that reflects itself clearly if not completely in its particulars, of a world that mirrors itself in its individuals, of more inclusive topoi that fully envelop less inclusive topoi, or of an absolute that is immanent in all relative selves. How does such a system account for fallibility, unpredictability, distortion or violence? And where does the author Nishida stand in relation to the system that he describes. Is the author too merely a reflection of the system?
In contrast to interpreting Nishida’s thought as presenting a system that would preempt problems, one can also read it as a series of attempts to clarify for himself the activity of living a philosophical life. From this perspective, critique appears as a constant feature of Nishida’s personal development. During his lifetime Nishida took his critics seriously and sometimes changed course because of their criticisms. Takahashi Satomi, while still a graduate student at the University of Tokyo, criticized Nishida’s notion of pure experience and spurred him to clarify it in an article published soon after An Inquiry Into the Good. His colleague at Kyoto University, Sōda Kiichiro, criticized the lack of clarity in his initial formulation of basho (place) in 1926 and prompted him to remove Neo-Kantian comparisons. More significantly, in the early 1930s his younger colleague Tanabe Hajime and his former student and Marxist philosopher Tosaka Jun criticized Nishida’s focus on consciousness and lack of attention to history and social being; Nishida subsequently developed his notions of the historical world and the historical body. In the last years of his life, he seemed to anticipate his death and recognize human finitude more strongly as an inevitable disruption of any comprehensive systematic account. Two years before his death in 1945, he wrote, “Our life and our existence are not our own. They are the determinations of absolute nothingness…. Philosophy begins with the self set on living truly. It is a way for the self to become self-aware and to live” (NKZ 10, 401, 472).[5] 11. Nishida’s Influence
Nishida is often called the father of the Kyoto School of philosophy because of his influence on a group of thinkers who were his students or younger colleagues. Best known outside Japan are his colleague and critic, Tanabe Hajime, frequently considered the School’s co-founder, and his student Nishitani Keiji. As a “school” the group comprises a rather fuzzy set that includes Marxist-leaning former students such as Miki Kiyoshi and Tosaka Jun, more nationalistic students like Kōyama Iwao and Kōsaka Masaaki, and lesser known but close disciples like Mutai Risaku and Shimomura Toratarō. Other colleagues, students and friends on the fringes of the School proper nevertheless show the impact of Nishida’s ideas: the Zen Buddhist scholar-teachers D. T. Suzuki and Hisamatsu Shin’ichi, the ethical theorist Watsuji Tetsurō, and Kuki Shūzō, the interpreter of Japanese aesthetics and culture. A third generation of the School includes Tanabe’s student Takeuchi Yoshinori, Nishitani’s student Ueda Shizuteru and Hisamatsu’s student Abe Masao, who have been especially effective in introducing Nishida’s philosophy in Europe and North America and in applying Nishida’s thought to inter-religious Buddhist-Christian dialogue.
Nishida’s investigations inspired current interpretations of Mahayana Buddhism, just as his thought was influenced by Buddhist ideas. For many people, his explication of pure experience and self-awareness re-interprets Zen awakening; his intertwining of self and world develops the Buddhist teaching of co-dependent origination; and his philosophy of nothingness articulates the notion of emptiness and the experience of mu (nothing). His philosophy has also presented to his Buddhist and Christian readers serious challenges, such as a notion of a non-dual relation between God and man, and an emphasis, unusual in Buddhism, on the embodied self in the historical world.
Nishida’s logic of place has been a resource for theoreticians working in various scientific fields, for example Imanishi Kinji in biology and ecology, Shimizu Hiroshi in complexity theory and information science, Nonaka Ikujiro in management theory, and Ko Hojo in the philosophy of chemistry. The architect Ando Tadao, and artists like the calligrapher Morita Shiryū have also drawn from Nishida’s philosophy, as has the psychotherapist Kimura Bin. Ultimately, Nishida himself is best considered an independent thinker, as the growing literature in Japanese and Western languages attests. Bibliography Nishida’s works
Note: Some of the works referenced below were published in Volumes 1-7 of the series Frontiers in Japanese Philosophy, James W. Heisig et al. (eds.), 2006–2010, Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion. A copy of the works listed below that are marked [*] can be found linked into the following webpage: Frontiers in Japanese Philosophy.
Nishida Kitarō Zenshū, 4th edition 1987–89, Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten. (Complete Works of Nishida Kitarō, in nineteen volumes, cited as NKZ followed by volume and page number.) –––, New Edition 2002–09, twenty four volumes, edited by A. Takeda, K. Riesenhueber, K. Kosaka & M. Fujita, Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten.
Representative Translations
1958. Intelligibility and the Philosophy of Nothingness: Three Philosophical Essays, Robert Shinzinger (trans.), Honolulu: East-West Center Press. 1960, reprint edition 1988. A Study of the Good, V.H. Viglielmo (trans.), Westport, Connecticut and London: Greenwood Press. 1970a. “Toward a Philosophy of Religion with the Concept of Preestablished Harmony as a Guide,” David Dilworth (trans.), The Eastern Buddhist, 3(1): 19–46. 1970b. Fundamental Problems of Philosophy, David Dilworth (trans.), Tokyo: Sophia University. 1970c. “Religious Consciousness and the Logic of the Prajñapāramitā Sūtra,” David Dilworth (trans.), Monumenta Nipponica, 25: 3–15. 1973. Art and Morality, David Dilworth and Valdo Viglielmo (trans.), Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. 1979. “Affective Feeling,” David Dilworth and Valdo Viglielmo (trans.), in Japanese Phenomenology (Analecta Husserliana VIII), Y. Nitta and H. Tatematsu (eds.), Dordrecht, Boston & London: D. Reidel Publishing Company. 1985. “La crisis de la cultura japonesa,” “El problema de la rasón de estado,” “Teoría dek kokutai,” in Estado y Filosofía, Agustin Jacinto Zavala (trans.), Michoacan, Mexico: El Colegio de Michoacan. 1986. “The Logic of Topos and the Religious Worldview,” Michiko Yusa (trans.), The Eastern Buddhist 19(2): 1–29 & 20(1): 81–119. 1987a. Last Writings: Nothingness and the Religious Worldview, David Dilworth (trans.), Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. 1987b. Intuition and Reflection in Self-Consciousness, Valdo H. Viglielmo, Takeuchi Toshinori and Joseph S. O’Leary (trans.), Albany: State University of New York Press. 1989. Über das Gute: Eine Philosophie der reinen Erfahrung, Peter Pörtner (trans.), Frankfurt am Mein and Leipzig. 1990a. An Inquiry Into the Good, Masao Abe and Christopher Ives (trans.), New Haven and London: Yale University Press. 1990b. “Selbstidentität und Kontinuität der Welt,” “Das künstlerische Schaffen als Gestaltungsakt der Geschichte,” E. Weinmayr (trans.), in Die Philsophie der Kyōto Schule, Ôhashi Ryōsuke (ed.), Freiburg & London: Karl Alber. 1990c. “Die Welt als dialektisches Allgemeines,” Matsudo Yukio (trans.), Die Welt als dialektisches Allgemeines: Eine Einführung in die Spätphilosophie von Kitarō Nishida, Berlin: Vista. 1991. La Culture Japonaise en Question, Pierre Lavelle (trans.), Paris: Publications Orientalistes de France. 1995. “La experiencia pura,” “Problemas de la cultura japonesa,” “Discurso ente el Tennō: Sobre la filosofía de la historia,” “Fundamentación filosófica de las matemáticas,” “Lógica del topos y cosmovisión religiosa,” Agustín Jacinto Zavala (trans.), in Textos de la filosofía japonesa moderna, Michoacán: El Colegio de Michoacán. 1996. L’io e il tu, R. Andolfato (trans.), Padova: Unipress. 1997. “Coincidentia Oppositorum and Love,” W. S. Yokoyama (trans.), The Eastern Buddhist, 30(1): 7–12. 1998. “The Historical Body,” “The World as Identity of Absolute Contradiction,” “Fundamental Principles of a New World Order,” “On the National Polity,” David Dilworth and Valdo Viglielmo (trans.), in Sourcebook for Modern Japanese Philosophy: Selected Documents, Westport, Connecticut and London: Greenwood Press. 1999a. Logik des Ortes: Der Anfang der modernen Philosophie in Japan, Rolf Elberfeld (trans.), Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. 1999b. “Une étude sur le bein,” Bernard Stevens (trans.), “Logique prédicative,” Jacynthe Tremblay (trans.), “Logique de lieu et vision religieuse du monde,” Yasuhiko Sugimura & Syvain Cardonnel (trans.), Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 97. 2001. “L’intuizione attiva (Kōiteki chokkan),” “Saggio sulla filosofia di Cartesio (Dekaruto tetsugaku ni tsuite),” in Il corpo e la conoscenza, Matteo Cestari (trans.), Venice: Libreria Editrice Cafoscarina. 2003a. L’Éveil à soi, Jacynthe Tremblay (trans.), Paris: CNRS Éditions. [[[Wikipedia:essays|essays]] of Nishida composed between 1931 and 1944]. 2003b. “On the Role of Religion,” Gereon Kopf (trans.), The Eastern Buddhist, 25(1–2): 229–39. 2005. “General Summary of The System of Self-Consciousness of the Universal,” Robert J. Wargo (trans), in The Logic of Nothingness: An Essay on Nishida Kitarō, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press, 2005. 2008. “L’Autodétermination du maintenant eternal,” Jacynthe Tremblay (trans.), Laval théologique et philosophique, 64(2): 245–76. 2008. “L’Intuition agissante,” Kuroda Akinobu (trans.), Laval théologique et philosophique, 64(2): 277–93. 2011. “Pure Experience,” “The Logic of Place,” “The Eternal in Art and Poetry,” “A Religious View of the World,” “My Logic,” Masao Abe, Christopher Ives, James Heisig, Michiko Yusa (trans.), in Japanese Philosophy: A Sourcebook, J. Heisig, T. Kasulis and J. Maraldo (eds.), Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. 2012a. Place & Dialectic: Two Essays by Nishida Kitarō, John W. Krummel and Shigenori Nagatomo (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2012b. “The Unsolved Issue of Consciousness,” J.W.M. Krummel (trans.), Philosophy East and West, 62(1): 44–59. 2012c. Ontology of Production: 3 Essays, William Haver (trans.), Durham and London: Duke University Press.
Secondary Literature
Abe, Masao, 1988, “Nishida’s Philosophy of ‘Place,’” International Philosophical Quarterly, 28: 355–371. –––, 1992, “‘Inverse Correspondence’ in the Philosophy of Nishida: The Emergence of the Notion,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 32(1): 325–344, –––, 1995, “The Problem of ‘Inverse Correspondence’ in the Philosophy of Nishida: Toward a Critical Understanding,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 35(4): 419–436. Arisaka, Yoko, 1996, “The Nishida Enigma: ‘The Principle of the New World Order’,” Monumenta Npponica, 51(1): 81–106. –––, 1999, “Beyond ‘East and West’: Nishida’s Universalism and Postcolonial Critique,” The Review of Politics, 59(3): 541–560. –––, 2001, “The Ontological Co-emergence of ‘Self and Other’ in Japanese Philosophy,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7): 197–208. Axtell, G.S., 1991, “Comparative Dialectics: Nishida Kitarō’s Logic of Place and Western Dialectical Thought,” Philosophy East and West, 41(2): 163–184. Baek, Jin, 2008, “From the ‘Topos of Nothingness’ to the ‘Space of Transparency’: Kitarō Nishida’s Notion of Shintai and Its Influence on Art and Architecture (Part 1),” Philosophy East and West, 58(1): 83–107. Botz-Bornstein, Thorsten, 2003, “Nishida and Wittgenstein: from ‘pure experience’ to Lebensform or new perspectives for a philosophy of intercultural communication,” Asian Philosophy, 13(1): 53–70 –––, 2004, “The ‘I’ and the ‘Thou’: A Dialogue between Nishida Kitarō and Mikhail Bakhtin,” Japan Review, 16: 259–284. Carter, Robert E., second edition 1998, The Nothingness Beyond God: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Nishida Kitarō, St. Paul: Paragon House. Cestari, Matteo, 1998, “The Knowing Body: Nishida’s Philosophy of Active Intuition,” The Eastern Buddhist, 31(2): 179–208. –––, 2006, “From Seeing to Acting: Rethinking Nishida Kitarō’s Practical Philosophy,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 6, Raquel Bouso and James W. Heisig (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Cheung Ching-yuen, 2009, “The Potential and Limits of Nishida Kitarō’s Philosophy,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Dalissier, Michel, 2006, “The Idea of the Mirror in Dōgen and Nishida,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2009a, Anfractuosité et unification. La philosophie de Nishida Kitarō, Geneva: Droz. –––, 2009b, “Nishida Kitarō and Chinese Philosophy,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2010, “Nishida Kitarō and Chinese Philosophy: Debt and Distance,” Japan Review, 22: 137–170. Davis, Bret W., 2006a, “Provocative Ambivalences in Japanese Philosophy of Religion: with a Focus on Nishida and Zen,” in Japanese Philosophy Abroad, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2006b, “Toward a World of Worlds: Nishida, the Kyoto School, and the Place of Cross-Cultural Dialogue”, in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2013, “Nishida’s Multicultural Worldview: Contemporary Significance and Immanent Critique,” Nishida Tetsugakkai Nempō, 10: 183–203. –––, 2014, “Ethical and Religious Alterity: Nishida after Levinas,” in Kitarō Nishida in der Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts, Elberfeld, Rolf, and Yōko Arisaka (eds.), Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber. Dilworth, David, 1969, “The Initial Formation of ‘Pure Experience’ in Nishida Kitarō and William James,” Moumenta Nipponica, 24(1–2): 93–111. –––, 1970, “Nishida’s Early Pantheistic Voluntarism,” Philosophy East and West, 20(1): 35–49. –––, 1973, “Nishida Kitarō: Nothingness as the Negative Space of Experiential Immediacy,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 13(4): 463–483. Elberfeld, Rolf, 1999, Kitarō Nishida (1870–1945): Das Verstehen der Kulturen: Moderne japanische Philosophie und die Frage nach der Interkulturalität, Amsterdam & Atlanta: Rodopi. Elberfeld, Rolf, and Yōko Arisaka (eds.), 2014, Kitarō Nishida in der Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts, Mit Texten Nishidas in deutscher Übersetzung, Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber. Elwood, Brian D, 1994, “The Problem of the Self in the Later Nishida and in Sartre,” Philosophy East and West, 44(2): 303–316. Feenberg, Andrew and Yoko Arisaka, 1990, “Experiential Ontology: The Origins of the Nishida Philosophy in the Doctrine of Pure Experience,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 30(2): 173–205. –––, 1999, “Experience and Culture: Nishida’s Path ‘To the Things Themselves,’” Philosophy East and West, 49(1): 28–44. Ghilardi, Marcello, 2008, “Between Aesthetics and Ethics: The Experience of Seeing in Nicholas Cusanus and Nishida Kitarō,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Girard, Frédéric, 2008, “Le Lieu chez Nishida Kitarō et l’espace bouddhique,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Goto-Jones, Christopher S, 2005, Political Philosophy in Japan: Nishida, the Kyoto School, and Co-Prosperity, London and New York: Routledge. Graupe, Silja, 2006, “The Locus of Science and its Place in Japanese Culture: Nishida on the Relationship of Science and Culture,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2007, The Basho of Economics: An Intercultural Analysis of the Process of Economics, New Brunswick, New Jersey: Ontos Verlag. –––, 2008, “Nishida and the Dynamic Nature of Knowledge: Why Economists Should Take Nishida Seriously,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Graham, A.C., 1981, Chuang-Tsu: The Inner Chapters, London and Boston: Unwin Publishers. –––, 1989, Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argumentation in Ancient China, LaSalle, IL: Open Court. Hashi, Hisaki, 2007, “The Significance of Einstein’s Theory of Relativity in Nishida’s ‘Logic of Field’,” Philosophy East and West, 57(4): 457–481. Haver, William, 2012, “Introduction,” in Ontology of Production: 3 Essays by Nishida Kitarō, Durham and London: Duke University Press. Heisig, James W. and John C. Maraldo (eds.), 1994, Rude Awakenings: Zen, The Kyoto School, and the Question of Nationalism, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. Heisig, James W. et. al. (eds.), 2006–2010, Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy, Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion. [*] Heisig, James W., Thomas P. Kasulis, and John C. Maraldo (eds.), 2011, Japanese Philosophy: A Sourcebook, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. Heisig, James W., 2000, “Non-I and Thou: Nishida, Buber, and the Moral Consequences of Self-actualization,” Philosophy East and West, 50(2) (April 2000): 179–207. –––, 2001, Philosophers of Nothingness, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. –––, 2004, “Nishida’s Medieval Bent,” Japanese Journal of Religious Studies, 31(1): 55–72. –––, 2012, “An Inquiry Into the Good and Nishida’s Missing Basho,” Comparative and Continental Philosophy, 4(2): 237–251. –––, 2015, “Nishida’s Philosophical Equivalents of Enlightenment and No-Self,” Bulletin of the Nanzan Institute for Religion and Culture, 39: 36–60. [Available online (PDF)] Huang, Wen-hong, 2009, “The Shift in Nishida’s Logic of Place,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Huh, Woo-Sung, 1990, “The Philosophy of History in the ‘Later’ Nishida: A Philosophic Turn,” Philosophy East and West, 40(3): 343–374. –––, 2009, “Thinking and Perceiving: Nishida and Park as Embodied Subjects?” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Jacinto Zavala, Agustin, 1989, Filosofía de la Transformación del Mundo, Michoacan, Mexico: El Colegio de Michoacan. –––, 1994, La fiosofía social de Nishida Kitarō: 1935–1945, two volumes, Michoacan: El Colegio de Michoacan. –––, 2009, “Aristotle and the Epistemology of Nishida Kitarō (1924–1928),” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 6, Raquel Bouso and James W. Heisig (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, (ed.), 2012, Alternatives Filosóicas: Investigaciones recientes sobre Nishida Kitarō, Michoacan, Mexico: El Colegio de Michoacan. Jiang, Tao, 2005, “The Problematic of Continuity: Nishida Kitarō and Aristotle,” Philosophy Esat and West, 55(3): 447–460. Kobayashi,Toshiaki, 2002, Denken des Fremden: Am Beispiel von Kitarō Nishida, Frankfurt am Mein: Stroemfeld Verlag. Kopf, Gereon, 2001, Beyond Personal Identity: Dōgen, Nishida, and a Phenomenology of No-Self, Richmond, Surrey: Curzon Press. –––, 2003, “On the Brink of Postmodernity: Recent Japanese Language Publications on the Philosophy of Nishida Kitarō,” Japanese Journal of Religious Studies, 30(1–2): 133–156. –––, 2004, “Between Identity and Difference: Three Ways of Reading Nishida’s Non-Dualism,” Japanese Journal of Religious Studies, 31(1): 73–103. Kracht, Klaus, 1984, “Nishida Kitarō as a Philosopher of the State,”in Europe Interprets Japan, Gordon Daniels (ed.), Tenterden, Kent: Paul Norbury Publications. –––, 1997, “Zum Verständnis der Nishida-Philosophie unter dem Aspekt des Verhänisses von Form und Inhalt,” Japonica Humboldtina, 1: 199–217. –––, 2001–2002,“Nishida und die Politik,” Japonica Humboldtina, 5: 205–250; 6: 183–249. Krummel, John W. M., 2012, “Basho , World, and Dialectics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Nishida Kitarō,” in Place & Dialectic: Two Essays by Nishida Kitarō, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. –––, 2015, Nishida Kitarō’s Chiasmatic Chorology: Place of Dialectic, Dialectic of Place, Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press. Lam, Win-keung, 2006, “Redefining Philosophy Through Assimilation: Nishida Kitarō and Mou Zong-san,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Lange, Elena Louisa, 2014, “Waren-und Subsstanzfetisch–Zum Verhältnis von Intention und Explikation in Nishida Kitarōs ‘Ort’,” in Begriff und Bild der modernen japanischen Philosophie, R. C. Steineck, E. L. Lange and P. Kaufmann (eds.), Stuttgart–Bad Cannstatt: Frommann–Holzboog. Laozi, Daodejing, Roger Ames and David Hall (trans.), Dao De Jing: A Philosophical Translation, New York: Ballantine Books, 2003. Lavelle, Pierre, 1994, “The Political Thought of Nishida Kitarō,” Monumenta Nipponica, 49(2): 139–165. Mafli, Paul, 1996, Nishida Kitarōs Denkweg, Munich: Iudicium Verlag. Maraldo, John C., 1989, “Translating Nishida,” Philosophy East and West, 39(4): 465–496. –––, 1995, “The Problem of World Culture: Towards an Appropriation of Nishida’s Philosophy of Nation and Culture,”The Eastern Buddhist, 28(2): 183–197. –––, 2003, “Rethinking God: Heidegger in the Light of Absolute Nothing, Nishida in the Shadow of Onto-Theology,” in Religious Experience and the End of Metaphysics, Jeffrey Bloechl (ed.), Indiana University Press. –––, 2006a, “Self-Mirroring and Self-Awareness: Dedekind, Royce, and Nishida,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2006b, “The War Over the Kyoto School,” Monumenta Nipponica, 61(3): 375–406. –––, 2010, “Nothing Gives: Marion and Nishida on Gift-giving and God,” in Japanese and Continental Philosophy, Bret W. Davis and Brian Schroeder (eds.), Bloomington: Indiana University Press. –––, 2014, “Nishida’s Kōiteki chokkan and the Notion of Enaction in Cognitive Science,” in Kitarō Nishida in der Philosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts, Elberfeld, Rolf, and Yōko Arisaka (eds.), Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber. Nishitani, Keiji, 1991, Nishida Kitarō, Yamamoto Seisaku and James W. Heisig (trans.), Berkeley, Los Angeles, Oxford: University of California Press. Odagiri, Takushi, 2008, “From Self-Reflexivity to Contingency: Nishida Kitarō on Self-Knowledge,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2012, “On Nishida’s Rationality Thesis,” Philosophy East and West, 62(2): 197–222. Parkes, Graham, 1997, “The Putative Fascism of the Kyoto School and the Political Correctness of the Modern Academy,” Philosophy East and West, 47(3): 305–336. Peerenboom, R.P., “The Religious Foundation of Nishida’s Philosophy,” Asian Philosophy, 1(2): 161–1743. Priest, Graham, 2009, “The Structure of Emptiness,” Philosophy East and West, 59(4): 467–480. Putney, David, 1991, “Identity and the Unity of Experience: A Critique of Nishida’s Theory of Self,” Asian Philosophy, 1(2): 127–160. Radhakrishnan, Sarvepalli, and Charles Moore, 1957, Sourcebook in Indian Philosophy, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Raud, Rein, 2004, “‘Place’ and ‘Being-time’: Spatiotemporal Concepts in the Thought of Nishida Kitarō and Dōgen Kigen,” Philosophy East and West, 54(1): 29–51. Rigsby, Curtis A., 2009, “Nishida on God, Barth and Christianity,” Asian Philosophy, 19(2): 119–157. Sakabe, Megume, 2010, “Subject of the Absence and Absence of the Critique,” in Asian Aesthetics, Ken-ichi Sasaki (ed.), Kyoto: Kyoto University Press. Schultz, Lucy, 2012, “Nishida Kitarō, G.W.F. Hegel, and the Pursuit of the Concrete: A Dialectic of Dialectics,” Philosophy East and West, 62(3): 319–338. Shimizu, Takashi, 2008, “Quasi-Predicate Theory: A New Interpretation of Nishida,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Stehlin, Laurent, 2008, Mondes de soi et lieu des mondes chez Nishida Kitarō, Paris: Peter Lang AG. Steineck, Christian, 1998, “ Wirklichkeit und Interkulturalität bei Nishida Kitarō: Eine Kritik,” in Ogawa, Tadashi, Michael Lazarin and Guido Rappe (eds.), Interkulturelle Philosophie und Phänomenologie in Japan. Beiträge zum Gespräch über Grenzen hinweg, Munich: Iudicium Verlag. Stevens, Bernard, 1995, “Basho et khōra. Nishida en son lieu,” Etudes Phénoménologiques, 21: 81–109. –––, 1999, “La première esquisse du système nishidien,” Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 97: 9–18. –––, 2000, Topologie du néant: Une approche de l’école de Kyōto, Louvain-Paris:Éditions Peeters. –––, 2005, Invitation à la philosophie japnonaise: Autour de Nishida, Paris: CNRS Éditions. –––, 2008, “Husserl, Nishida et la ‘crise’: Hier et aujourd’hui,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 3, James W. Heisig and Uehara Mayuko (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Tremblay, Jacynthe, 1999, “Universel et individual dans la logique du basho de Nishida”, Revue Philosophique de Louvain, 97: 30–56. –––, 2006, “Nishida Kitarō: Approches actuelles et recherché future,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2007a, Introduction à la philosophie de Nishida, Paris: L’Harmattan. –––, 2007b, Auto-éveil et temporalité: Les défis posés par la philosophie de Nishida, Paris: L’Harmattan. –––, 2008, “Hidden Aspects of Temporality from Nishida to Watsuji,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 2, Victor Sōgen Hori and Melissa Anne-Marie Curley (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion and Culture. [*] –––, 2009a, “The Potential of Nishida’s ‘Encompassing’ Language,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2009b, “Nishida Kitarō’s Language and Structure of Thought in the ‘Logic of Basho’,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 6, Raquel Bouso and James W. Heisig (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Ueda, Shizuteru, 1993, “Pure Experience, Self-Awareness, ‘Basho,’” Etudes Phénoménologiques, 18: 63–86. –––, 1995a, “Nishida’s Thought,” The Eastern Buddhist, 28(1): 29–47. –––, 1995b, “The Difficulty of Understanding Nishida’s Philosophy,” The Eastern Buddhist, 28(2): 175–182. Uehara Mayuko, 2006, “The Conceptualization and Translation of Jikaku and Jiko in Nishida Kitarō”, in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 1, James W. Heisig, (ed.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] –––, 2009, “Japanese Aspects of Nishida’s Basho: Seeing the ‘Form without Form’,” in Frontiers of Japanese Philosophy 4, Lam Wing-keung and Cheung Ching-yuen (eds.), Nagoya: Nanzan Institute for Religion & Culture. [*] Uhl, Christian, 2009, “Displacing Japan: Takeuchi Yoshimi’s Lu Xun in Light of Nishida’s Philosophy, and Vice Versa,” Positions, East Asia Cultures Critique, 17(1): 207–237. Wargo, Robert J., 2005, The Logic of Nothingness: An Essay on Nishida Kitarō, Honolulu, University of Hawai’i Press. Weinmayr, Elmar, 2005, “Thinking in Transition: Nishida Kitarō and Martin Heidegger,” Philosophy East and West, 55(2): 232–256. Wilkinson, Robert, 2009, Nishida and Western Philosophy, Surry, England and Burlington VT: Ashgate. Yusa, Michiko, 2002, Zen & Philosophy: An Intellectual Biography of Nishida Kitarō, Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press.
John C. Maraldo <jmaraldo@unf.edu>
Source
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nishida-kitaro/ [[Category:]]