Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Cārvāka"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with "thumb|250px| <poem> '''Cārvāka''' (Sanskrit: चार्वाक), also known as Lokāyata, is a system of Indian philosophy that assumes v...")
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
[[File:20100814Manjusri-1.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:20100814Manjusri-1.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
'''Cārvāka''' (Sanskrit: चार्वाक), also known as Lokāyata, is a system of Indian philosophy that assumes various forms of philosophical skepticism and religious indifference. Etymologically, both words Cārvāka and Lokāyata mean "popular" or "agreeable" in Sanskrit.  
+
'''[[Cārvāka]]''' ([[Sanskrit]]: चार्वाक), also known as [[Lokāyata]], is a system of [[Indian philosophy]] that assumes various forms of [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|skepticism}} and [[religious]] [[indifference]]. Etymologically, both words [[Cārvāka]] and [[Lokāyata]] mean "popular" or "agreeable" in [[Sanskrit]].  
  
Cārvāka is classified as a heterodox Hindu (Nāstika) system. It is characterized as a materialistic and atheistic school of thought. While this branch of Indian philosophy is today not considered to be part of the six orthodox schools of Hindu philosophy, some describe it as an atheistic or materialistic philosophical movement within Hinduism.  
+
[[Cārvāka]] is classified as a heterodox [[Hindu]] (Nāstika) system. It is characterized as a materialistic and atheistic school of [[thought]]. While this branch of [[Indian philosophy]] is today not considered to be part of the six orthodox schools of {{Wiki|Hindu philosophy}}, some describe it as an atheistic or materialistic [[philosophical]] movement within [[Hinduism]].  
  
Cārvāka emerged as an alternative to the orthodox Hindu pro-Vedic Āstika schools, as well as a philosophical predecessor to subsequent or contemporaneous nāstika philosophies such as Ājīvika, Jainism and Buddhism (the latter two later spinning off into what may be described today as separate religions) in the classical period of Indian philosophy. As opposed to other schools, the first principle of Cārvāka philosophy was the rejection of inference as a means to establish metaphysical truths.  
+
[[Cārvāka]] emerged as an alternative to the orthodox [[Hindu]] pro-Vedic Āstika schools, as well as a [[philosophical]] predecessor to subsequent or contemporaneous nāstika [[philosophies]] such as [[Ājīvika]], [[Jainism]] and [[Buddhism]] (the latter two later spinning off into what may be described today as separate [[religions]]) in the classical period of [[Indian philosophy]]. As opposed to other schools, the first principle of [[Cārvāka]] [[philosophy]] was the rejection of inference as a means to establish [[metaphysical]] [[truths]].  
 
Name
 
Name
  
Etymologically, Cārvāka means "agreeable speech" (cāru – agreeable and vāk – speech) and Lokāyata signifies "prevalence in the world" (loka – world and āyata – prevalent).  
+
Etymologically, [[Cārvāka]] means "agreeable [[speech]]" (cāru – agreeable and vāk – [[speech]]) and [[Lokāyata]] signifies "prevalence in the [[world]]" ([[loka]] [[world]] and āyata – prevalent).  
  
The name Lokāyata can be traced to Kautilya's Arthashastra, which refers to three ānvīkṣikīs (logical philosophies) — Yoga, Samkhya and Lokāyata. However, Lokāyata in Arthashastra, does not stand for materialism because the Arthashastra refers to Lokāyata as a part of Vedic lore. Lokāyata here probably refers to logic or science of debate (disputatio, "criticism") and not to the materialist doctrine. Similarly, Saddaniti and Buddhaghosa in the 5th century connect the "Lokāyata" with the Vitandas (sophists).
+
The name [[Lokāyata]] can be traced to Kautilya's Arthashastra, which refers to three ānvīkṣikīs ([[logical]] [[philosophies]]) — [[Yoga]], {{Wiki|Samkhya}} and [[Lokāyata]]. However, [[Lokāyata]] in Arthashastra, does not stand for {{Wiki|materialism}} because the Arthashastra refers to [[Lokāyata]] as a part of {{Wiki|Vedic}} lore. [[Lokāyata]] here probably refers to [[logic]] or [[science]] of [[debate]] (disputatio, "criticism") and not to the {{Wiki|materialist}} [[doctrine]]. Similarly, Saddaniti and [[Buddhaghosa]] in the 5th century connect the "[[Lokāyata]]" with the Vitandas (sophists).
  
It is only from about the 6th century that the term Lokāyata was restricted to the school of the materialists or Lokyātikas. The name Cārvāka was first used in the 7th century by the philosopher Purandara, who referred to his fellow materialists as "the Cārvākas", and it was used by the 8th century philosophers Kamalaśīla and Haribhadra. Adi Shankara, on the other hand, always used Lokāyata, not Cārvāka. By the 8th century, the terms Cārvāka, Lokāyata, and Bārhaspatya were used interchangeably to signify materialism.  
+
It is only from about the 6th century that the term [[Lokāyata]] was restricted to the school of the {{Wiki|materialists}} or Lokyātikas. The name [[Cārvāka]] was first used in the 7th century by the [[philosopher]] Purandara, who referred to his fellow {{Wiki|materialists}} as "the Cārvākas", and it was used by the 8th century [[philosophers]] Kamalaśīla and Haribhadra. Adi Shankara, on the other hand, always used [[Lokāyata]], not [[Cārvāka]]. By the 8th century, the terms [[Cārvāka]], [[Lokāyata]], and Bārhaspatya were used interchangeably to signify {{Wiki|materialism}}.  
 
Origin
 
Origin
  
The earliest documented materialist in India is Ajita Kesakambali, a senior contemporary of the Buddha (sixth/fifth century BCE). The basic tenets of Cārvāka philosophy, of no soul and existence of four (not five) elements were probably inspired from him. Although materialist schools existed before Cārvāka, it was the only school which systematized materialist philosophy by setting them down in the form of aphorisms in the 6th century. There was a base text, a collection sūtras or aphorisms and several commentaries were written to explicate the aphorisms.  
+
The earliest documented {{Wiki|materialist}} in [[India]] is [[Ajita Kesakambali]], a senior contemporary of the [[Buddha]] (sixth/fifth century BCE). The basic tenets of [[Cārvāka]] [[philosophy]], of no [[soul]] and [[existence]] of four (not five) [[elements]] were probably inspired from him. Although {{Wiki|materialist}} schools existed before [[Cārvāka]], it was the only school which systematized {{Wiki|materialist}} [[philosophy]] by setting them down in the [[form]] of {{Wiki|aphorisms}} in the 6th century. There was a base text, a collection sūtras or {{Wiki|aphorisms}} and several commentaries were written to explicate the {{Wiki|aphorisms}}.  
E. W. Hopkins, in his The Ethics of India (1924) claims that Cārvāka philosophy was contemporaneous to Jainism and Buddhism, mentioning "the old Cārvāka or materialist of the 6th century BC". Rhys Davids assumes that lokāyata in ca. 500 BC came to mean "skepticism" in general without yet being organized as a philosophical school, and that the name of a villain in the epic Mahabharata, Cārvāka, was attached to the position in order to disparage it. The earliest positive statement of skepticism is preserved from the epic period, in the Ramayana, Ayodhya kanda, chapter 108, where Jabāli tries to persuade Rāma to accept the kingdom by using nāstika arguments (but Rāma then refutes him in chapter 109):  
+
E. W. Hopkins, in his The [[Ethics]] of [[India]] (1924) claims that [[Cārvāka]] [[philosophy]] was contemporaneous to [[Jainism]] and [[Buddhism]], mentioning "the old [[Cārvāka]] or {{Wiki|materialist}} of the 6th century BC". Rhys Davids assumes that [[lokāyata]] in ca. 500 BC came to mean "{{Wiki|skepticism}}" in general without yet [[being]] organized as a [[philosophical]] school, and that the name of a villain in the epic {{Wiki|Mahabharata}}, [[Cārvāka]], was attached to the position in [[order]] to disparage it. The earliest positive statement of {{Wiki|skepticism}} is preserved from the epic period, in the {{Wiki|Ramayana}}, [[Ayodhya]] kanda, chapter [[108]], where Jabāli tries to persuade Rāma to accept the kingdom by using nāstika arguments (but Rāma then refutes him in chapter 109):  
     O, the highly wise! Arrive at a conclusion, therefore, that there is nothing beyond this Universe. Give precedence to that which meets the eye and turn your back on what is beyond our knowledge. (2.108.17)
+
     O, the highly [[wise]]! Arrive at a conclusion, therefore, that there is [[nothing]] beyond this [[Universe]]. Give precedence to that which meets the [[eye]] and turn your back on what is beyond our [[knowledge]]. (2.108.17)
 
[[File:7Manjusri.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:7Manjusri.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
The Cārvāka school thus appears to have gradually grown out of generic skepticism in the Mauryan period, but its existence as an organized body cannot be ascertained for times predating the 6th century. The Barhaspatya sutras were likely also composed in Mauryan times, predating 150 BC, based on a reference in the Mahabhasya of Patanjali (7.3.45).  Cārvāka was a living philosophy up to the 12th century AD after which this system seems to have disappeared without leaving any trace. The reason for this sudden disappearance is not known.  
+
The [[Cārvāka]] school thus appears to have gradually grown out of generic {{Wiki|skepticism}} in the Mauryan period, but its [[existence]] as an organized [[body]] cannot be ascertained for times predating the 6th century. The Barhaspatya [[sutras]] were likely also composed in Mauryan times, predating 150 BC, based on a reference in the Mahabhasya of Patanjali (7.3.45).  [[Cārvāka]] was a living [[philosophy]] up to the 12th century AD after which this system seems to have disappeared without leaving any trace. The [[reason]] for this sudden [[disappearance]] is not known.  
 
Earliest descriptions
 
Earliest descriptions
  
Brihaspati is sometimes referred to as the founder of Cārvāka or Lokāyata philosophy. The earliest direct quote from Brihaspati's lost writings is found in the text Sarvasiddhantasamgraha, which is sometimes controversially attributed to Shankara. In the Sarvasiddhantasamgraha, the author quotes Brihaspati as follows:
+
Brihaspati is sometimes referred to as the founder of [[Cārvāka]] or [[Lokāyata]] [[philosophy]]. The earliest direct quote from Brihaspati's lost writings is found in the text Sarvasiddhantasamgraha, which is sometimes controversially attributed to Shankara. In the Sarvasiddhantasamgraha, the author quotes Brihaspati as follows:
“ Chastity and other such ordinances are laid down by clever weaklings; gifts of gold and land, the pleasure of invitations to dinner, are devised by indigent people with stomachs lean with hunger.
+
“ Chastity and other such ordinances are laid down by clever weaklings; gifts of gold and land, the [[pleasure]] of invitations to dinner, are devised by indigent [[people]] with stomachs lean with hunger.
The building of temples, houses for water-supply, tanks, wells, resting places, and the like, please only travelers, not others.
+
The building of [[temples]], houses for water-supply, tanks, wells, resting places, and the like, please only travelers, not others.
The Agnihotra ritual, the three Vedas, the triple staff, the ash-smearing, are the ways of gaining a livelihood for those who are lacking in intellect and energy.
+
The Agnihotra [[ritual]], the three [[Vedas]], the triple [[staff]], the ash-smearing, are the ways of gaining a [[livelihood]] for those who are lacking in {{Wiki|intellect}} and [[energy]].
The wise should enjoy the pleasures of this world through the more appropriate available means of agriculture, tending cattle, trade, political administration, etc.  ”
+
The [[wise]] should enjoy the [[pleasures]] of this [[world]] through the more appropriate available means of agriculture, tending cattle, trade, political administration, etc.  ”
Philosophy
+
[[Philosophy]]
  
The Cārvāka school of philosophy had a variety of atheistic and materialistic beliefs. They held perception to be the only valid source of knowledge.  
+
The [[Cārvāka]] school of [[philosophy]] had a variety of atheistic and materialistic [[beliefs]]. They held [[perception]] to be the only valid source of [[knowledge]].  
Epistemology
+
{{Wiki|Epistemology}}
  
In syllogism, the middle term, which is found in both the subject (minor term) and is invariably connected with the predicate (major term), is seen as the cause of knowledge. This invariable connection between middle term and predicate is unconditional and causes inference not by virtue of its existence, like the existence of the eye is the cause of perception, but by virtue of it being known. To the Cārvākas there were no reliable means by which this connection could be known and therefore the efficacy of inference as a means of knowledge could not be established.  
+
In [[syllogism]], the middle term, which is found in both the [[subject]] (minor term) and is invariably connected with the predicate (major term), is seen as the [[cause]] of [[knowledge]]. This invariable connection between middle term and predicate is unconditional and [[causes]] inference not by [[virtue]] of its [[existence]], like the [[existence]] of the [[eye]] is the [[cause]] of [[perception]], but by [[virtue]] of it [[being]] known. To the Cārvākas there were no reliable means by which this connection could be known and therefore the efficacy of inference as a means of [[knowledge]] could not be established.  
  
To prove that inference was not a reliable means of knowledge Cārvākas examined and refuted each of the various means of knowing the connection between the middle term and the predicate individually:
+
To prove that inference was not a reliable means of [[knowledge]] Cārvākas examined and refuted each of the various means of [[knowing]] the connection between the middle term and the predicate individually:
 
[[File:080720 1.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:080720 1.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
     External perception, or perception which involves the use of the senses, could not be the required means because although, it is possible that the actual contact of the senses and the object could produce the knowledge of the particular object, yet there can never be such contact in the case of the past or the future. Therefore if external perception were the means on knowing the connection then inference related to objects of the past and future could not happen.
+
     External [[perception]], or [[perception]] which involves the use of the [[senses]], could not be the required means because although, it is possible that the actual [[contact]] of the [[senses]] and the [[object]] could produce the [[knowledge]] of the particular [[object]], yet there can never be such [[contact]] in the case of the past or the future. Therefore if external [[perception]] were the means on [[knowing]] the connection then inference related to [[objects]] of the past and future could not happen.
  
     Internal perception, or perception which involves the mind could, not be the required means either, because one cannot establish that the mind has any power to act independently towards an external object and is thought to be dependent on the external senses.
+
     Internal [[perception]], or [[perception]] which involves the [[mind]] could, not be the required means either, because one cannot establish that the [[mind]] has any [[power]] to act independently towards an external [[object]] and is [[thought]] to be dependent on the external [[senses]].
  
 
     Nor could inference be the means, since if inference were the proof of inference, one would also require another inference to establish this inference, and so on, leading to the fallacy of an Ad infinitum regression.
 
     Nor could inference be the means, since if inference were the proof of inference, one would also require another inference to establish this inference, and so on, leading to the fallacy of an Ad infinitum regression.
  
     Nor could testimony be the means, since testimony can be classified as a type of inference. Moreover, there is no reason for one to believe word of another. Besides, if testimony were to be accepted as the only means of the knowledge of the invariable connection between middle term and predicate, then in the case of a man to whom the fact of the connection had not been pointed out by another person, there could be no inference.
+
     Nor could testimony be the means, since testimony can be classified as a type of inference. Moreover, there is no [[reason]] for one to believe word of another. Besides, if testimony were to be accepted as the only means of the [[knowledge]] of the invariable connection between middle term and predicate, then in the case of a man to whom the fact of the connection had not been pointed out by another [[person]], there could be no inference.
  
     Comparison (Upamana) could also be rejected as the means of the knowledge of the connection, since objective of using Upamana is to establish a different kind of knowledge than is being sought here, the relation of a name to something so named.
+
     Comparison (Upamana) could also be rejected as the means of the [[knowledge]] of the connection, since [[objective]] of using Upamana is to establish a different kind of [[knowledge]] than is [[being]] sought here, the relation of a name to something so named.
  
     Absence of a condition (Upadhi), which is given as the definition of an invariable connection to restrict too general a middle term, could itself not be used to establish inference because it is impossible to establish that all conditions required to restrict the middle term are known without recourse to inference and inference, as has been proven earlier, cannot establish itself.  
+
     Absence of a [[condition]] (Upadhi), which is given as the definition of an invariable connection to restrict too general a middle term, could itself not be used to establish inference because it is impossible to establish that all [[conditions]] required to restrict the middle term are known without recourse to inference and inference, as has been proven earlier, cannot establish itself.  
  
Metaphysics
+
[[Metaphysics]]
 
[[File:202345 n.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:202345 n.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
Since, none of the means of knowing were found to be worthy to establish the invariable connection between middle term and predicate, Cārvākas concluded that the inference could not be used to ascertain metaphysical truths. Thus, to Cārvākas, the step which the mind takes from the knowledge of something to infer the knowledge of something else, could be accounted for by the its being based on a former perception or by its being in error. Cases where inference was justified by the result, were seen only to be mere coincidences.  
+
Since, none of the means of [[knowing]] were found to be [[worthy]] to establish the invariable connection between middle term and predicate, Cārvākas concluded that the inference could not be used to ascertain [[metaphysical]] [[truths]]. Thus, to Cārvākas, the step which the [[mind]] takes from the [[knowledge]] of something to infer the [[knowledge]] of something else, could be accounted for by the its [[being]] based on a former [[perception]] or by its [[being]] in error. Cases where inference was justified by the result, were seen only to be mere coincidences.  
  
Therefore, Cārvākas denied metaphysical concepts like reincarnation, extracorporeal soul, efficacy of religious rites, other world (heaven and hell), fate and accumulation of merit or demerit through the performance of certain actions. Cārvākas also rejected the use of supernatural causes to describe natural phenomena. To them all natural phenomena was produced spontaneously from the inherent nature of things.  
+
Therefore, Cārvākas denied [[metaphysical]] concepts like [[reincarnation]], extracorporeal [[soul]], efficacy of [[religious]] [[rites]], other [[world]] ([[heaven]] and [[hell]]), [[fate]] and accumulation of [[merit]] or demerit through the performance of certain [[actions]]. Cārvākas also rejected the use of [[supernatural]] [[causes]] to describe natural [[phenomena]]. To them all natural [[phenomena]] was produced spontaneously from the inherent nature of things.  
  
     The fire is hot, the water cold, refreshing cool the breeze of morn;
+
     The [[fire]] is hot, the [[water]] cold, refreshing cool the breeze of morn;
 
     By whom came this variety ? from their own nature was it born.  
 
     By whom came this variety ? from their own nature was it born.  
  
Consciousness and Afterlife
+
[[Consciousness]] and [[Afterlife]]
  
Carvakas thought that body was formed out of four elements (instead of five) and that consciousness was an outcome of the mixture of these elements. Therefore, Carvakas did not believe in an afterlife. To them, all attributes that represented a person, such a thinness, fatness etc., resided in the body. To support the proposition of non-existence of any soul or consciousness in the afterlife Carvakas often quoted from Brihadaranyaka Upanishad.  
+
Carvakas [[thought]] that [[body]] was formed out of four [[elements]] (instead of five) and that [[consciousness]] was an outcome of the mixture of these [[elements]]. Therefore, Carvakas did not believe in an [[afterlife]]. To them, all attributes that represented a [[person]], such a thinness, fatness etc., resided in the [[body]]. To support the proposition of non-existence of any [[soul]] or [[consciousness]] in the [[afterlife]] Carvakas often quoted from Brihadaranyaka Upanishad.  
  
     Springing forth from these elements itself
+
     Springing forth from these [[elements]] itself
     solid knowledge is destroyed
+
     solid [[knowledge]] is destroyed
 
     when they are destroyed—
 
     when they are destroyed—
     after death no intelligence remains.  
+
     after [[death]] no {{Wiki|intelligence}} remains.  
  
Cārvāka believed that there was nothing wrong with sensual pleasure. Since it is impossible to have pleasure without pain, Cārvāka thought that wisdom lay in enjoying pleasure and avoiding pain as far as possible. Unlike many of the Indian philosophies of the time, Cārvāka did not believe in austerities or rejecting pleasure out of fear of pain and held such reasoning to be foolish.  
+
[[Cārvāka]] believed that there was [[nothing]] wrong with sensual [[pleasure]]. Since it is impossible to have [[pleasure]] without [[pain]], [[Cārvāka]] [[thought]] that [[wisdom]] lay in enjoying [[pleasure]] and avoiding [[pain]] as far as possible. Unlike many of the [[Indian]] [[philosophies]] of the time, [[Cārvāka]] did not believe in austerities or rejecting [[pleasure]] out of {{Wiki|fear}} of [[pain]] and held such {{Wiki|reasoning}} to be foolish.  
 
     The berries of paddy, rich with the finest white grains,
 
     The berries of paddy, rich with the finest white grains,
 
     What man, seeking his true interest, would fling away because covered with husk and dust?  
 
     What man, seeking his true interest, would fling away because covered with husk and dust?  
 
[[File:Manj01.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Manj01.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
Religion
+
[[Religion]]
  
Cārvākas rejected religious conceptions like afterlife, reincarnation, religious rites etc. They were extremely critical of the Vedas and thought that Vedas suffered from three faults - untruth, self-contradiction and tautology. To them, Vedas were just incoherent rhapsodies. They also held the belief that such texts were invented and made up by men and had no divine authority.  
+
Cārvākas rejected [[religious]] conceptions like [[afterlife]], [[reincarnation]], [[religious]] [[rites]] etc. They were extremely critical of the [[Vedas]] and [[thought]] that [[Vedas]] [[suffered]] from three faults - untruth, self-contradiction and tautology. To them, [[Vedas]] were just incoherent rhapsodies. They also held the [[belief]] that such texts were invented and made up by men and had no divine authority.  
  
     The Agnihotra, the three Vedas, the ascetic's three staves, and smearing one's self with ashes,
+
     The Agnihotra, the three [[Vedas]], the ascetic's three staves, and smearing one's [[self]] with ashes,
     Were made by Nature as the livelihood of those destitute of knowledge and manliness.  
+
     Were made by Nature as the [[livelihood]] of those destitute of [[knowledge]] and manliness.  
 
Criticism
 
Criticism
  
Buddhist philosophers reasoned that the Cārvāka proposition that inference could not be used as a form of evidence (Pramana) was absurd. If no arguments were given to prove this proposition, it would just be a bare assertion. Whereas, if some form of argumentation were given, it would result in absurdity, because inference was being used to disprove its own efficacy as evidence. Besides, when existence of any object, be it the authority of inference, was denied on the ground of it not being perceived, inference was itself admitted in proposing such an argument, with middle term being the non-perception.  
+
[[Buddhist]] [[philosophers]] reasoned that the [[Cārvāka]] proposition that inference could not be used as a [[form]] of evidence (Pramana) was absurd. If no arguments were given to prove this proposition, it would just be a bare assertion. Whereas, if some [[form]] of argumentation were given, it would result in absurdity, because inference was [[being]] used to disprove its own efficacy as evidence. Besides, when [[existence]] of any [[object]], be it the authority of inference, was denied on the ground of it not [[being]] [[perceived]], inference was itself admitted in proposing such an argument, with middle term [[being]] the [[non-perception]].  
 
Works
 
Works
 
[[File:304.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:304.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
No independent works on Cārvāka philosophy can be found except for a few sūtras composed by Brihaspati. The 8th century Tattvopaplavasimha of Jayarashi Bhatta (ca. 8th century) is often cited as the only extant authentic Cārvāka text, but which also shows Madhyamaka influence. Shatdarshan Samuchay and Sarvadarśanasaṅ̇graha of Vidyaranya are a few other works which elucidate Cārvāka thought.  
+
No independent works on [[Cārvāka]] [[philosophy]] can be found except for a few sūtras composed by Brihaspati. The 8th century Tattvopaplavasimha of Jayarashi Bhatta (ca. 8th century) is often cited as the only extant authentic [[Cārvāka]] text, but which also shows [[Madhyamaka]] [[influence]]. Shatdarshan Samuchay and Sarvadarśanasaṅ̇graha of Vidyaranya are a few other works which elucidate [[Cārvāka]] [[thought]].  
  
One of the most important references to the Cārvāka philosophy is the Sarva-darśana-saṅgraha (etymologically all-philosophy-collection), a famous work of 14th century Advaita Vedanta philosopher Mādhava Vidyāraṇya from South India, which starts with a chapter on the Cārvāka system. After invoking, in the Prologue of the book, the Hindu gods Shiva and Vishnu ("by whom the earth and rest were produced"), Vidyāraṇya asks, in the first chapter:  
+
One of the most important references to the [[Cārvāka]] [[philosophy]] is the Sarva-darśana-saṅgraha (etymologically all-philosophy-collection), a famous work of 14th century {{Wiki|Advaita Vedanta}} [[philosopher]] Mādhava Vidyāraṇya from {{Wiki|South India}}, which starts with a chapter on the [[Cārvāka]] system. After invoking, in the Prologue of the book, the [[Hindu]] [[gods]] {{Wiki|Shiva}} and [[Vishnu]] ("by whom the [[earth]] and rest were produced"), Vidyāraṇya asks, in the first chapter:  
“ ...but how can we attribute to the Divine Being the giving of supreme felicity, when such a notion has been utterly abolished by Charvaka, the crest-gem of the atheistic school, the follower of the doctrine of Brihaspati? The efforts of Charvaka are indeed hard to be eradicated, for the majority of living beings hold by the current refrain:
+
“ ...but how can we attribute to the Divine [[Being]] the giving of supreme [[felicity]], when such a notion has been utterly abolished by Charvaka, the crest-gem of the atheistic school, the follower of the [[doctrine]] of Brihaspati? The efforts of Charvaka are indeed hard to be eradicated, for the majority of [[living beings]] hold by the current refrain:
  
         While life is yours, live joyously;
+
         While [[life]] is yours, [[live]] joyously;
         None can escape Death's searching eye:
+
         None can escape Death's searching [[eye]]:
 
         When once this frame of ours they burn,
 
         When once this frame of ours they burn,
 
         How shall it e'er again return?  
 
         How shall it e'er again return?  
Line 93: Line 93:
 
 
  
Ain-i-Akbari, written by Abul Fazl, the famous historian of Akbar's court, mentions a symposium of philosophers of all faiths held in 1578 at Akbar's insistence. Some of the beliefs of Cārvāka are recorded from this symposium, in which, some Cārvāka philosophers are said to have participated.  
+
Ain-i-Akbari, written by Abul Fazl, the famous historian of Akbar's court, mentions a symposium of [[philosophers]] of all [[faiths]] held in 1578 at Akbar's insistence. Some of the [[beliefs]] of [[Cārvāka]] are recorded from this symposium, in which, some [[Cārvāka]] [[philosophers]] are said to have participated.  
  
Sanskrit poems and plays like the Naiṣadha-carita, Prabodha-candrodaya, Āgama-dambara, Vidvanmoda-taraṅgiṇī and Kādambarī contain representations of the Cārvāka thought. However, the authors of these works were thoroughly opposed to materialism and tried to portray the Cārvāka in unfavourable light. Therefore, their works should only be accepted critically.  
+
[[Sanskrit]] poems and plays like the Naiṣadha-carita, Prabodha-candrodaya, Āgama-dambara, Vidvanmoda-taraṅgiṇī and Kādambarī contain representations of the [[Cārvāka]] [[thought]]. However, the authors of these works were thoroughly opposed to {{Wiki|materialism}} and tried to portray the [[Cārvāka]] in unfavourable [[light]]. Therefore, their works should only be accepted critically.  
 
Loss of original works
 
Loss of original works
  
There was no continuity in the Cārvāka tradition after the 12th century. Whatever is written on Cārvāka post this is based on second-hand knowledge, learned from preceptors to disciples and no independent works on Cārvāka philosophy can be found.  Chatterjee and Datta explain that our understanding of Cārvāka philosophy is fragmentary, based largely on criticism of its ideas by other schools, and that it is not a living tradition:
+
There was no continuity in the [[Cārvāka]] [[tradition]] after the 12th century. Whatever is written on [[Cārvāka]] post this is based on second-hand [[knowledge]], learned from preceptors to [[disciples]] and no independent works on [[Cārvāka]] [[philosophy]] can be found.  Chatterjee and Datta explain that our understanding of [[Cārvāka]] [[philosophy]] is fragmentary, based largely on criticism of its ideas by other schools, and that it is not a living [[tradition]]:
  
     "Though materialism in some form or other has always been present in India, and occasional references are found in the Vedas, the Buddhistic literature, the Epics, as well as in the later philosophical works we do not find any systematic work on materialism, nor any organised school of followers as the other philosophical schools possess. But almost every work of the other schools states, for refutation, the materialistic views. Our knowledge of Indian materialism is chiefly based on these."  
+
     "Though {{Wiki|materialism}} in some [[form]] or other has always been present in [[India]], and occasional references are found in the [[Vedas]], the [[Buddhistic]] literature, the Epics, as well as in the later [[philosophical]] works we do not find any systematic work on {{Wiki|materialism}}, nor any organised school of followers as the other [[philosophical]] schools possess. But almost every work of the other schools states, for refutation, the materialistic [[views]]. Our [[knowledge]] of [[Indian]] {{Wiki|materialism}} is chiefly based on these."  
  
Representation of Cārvāka in Āstika, Buddhist and Jain Literature
+
Representation of [[Cārvāka]] in Āstika, [[Buddhist]] and [[Jain]] Literature
  
The Yogācāra Buddhists, Jains, Advaita Vedantins and Nyāya philosophers considered the Cārvākas as one of their opponents and tried to refute their views. These refutations are sources of Cārvāka philosophy since, they continued to be made even after all the authentic Cārvāka/Lokāyata texts had been lost. However, the representation of the Cārvāka thought in these works is not always firmly grounded in first hand knowledge of Cārvāka texts and should be viewed critically.  
+
The [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhists]], {{Wiki|Jains}}, [[Advaita]] Vedantins and [[Nyāya]] [[philosophers]] considered the Cārvākas as one of their opponents and tried to refute their [[views]]. These refutations are sources of [[Cārvāka]] [[philosophy]] since, they continued to be made even after all the authentic Cārvāka/Lokāyata texts had been lost. However, the representation of the [[Cārvāka]] [[thought]] in these works is not always firmly grounded in first hand [[knowledge]] of [[Cārvāka]] texts and should be viewed critically.  
  
Though Cārvākas accepted direct perception as the surest method to prove the truth of anything, they might also have accepted a limited usage of inference. The perception that Cārvākas had a rigid stance against the application of inference might have been a result of caricaturing of their arguments by their opponents. Debiprasad Chattopadhyaya quotes S. N. Dasgupta:
+
Though Cārvākas accepted direct [[perception]] as the surest method to prove the [[truth]] of anything, they might also have accepted a limited usage of inference. The [[perception]] that Cārvākas had a rigid stance against the application of inference might have been a result of caricaturing of their arguments by their opponents. Debiprasad Chattopadhyaya quotes S. N. Dasgupta:
  
     "Purandara (a Lokāyata philosopher) [...] admits the usefulness of inference in determining the nature of all worldly things where perceptual experience is available; but inference cannot be employed for establishing any dogma regarding the transcendental world, or life after death or the law of karma which cannot be available to ordinary perceptual experience."  
+
     "Purandara (a [[Lokāyata]] [[philosopher]]) [...] admits the usefulness of inference in determining the nature of all [[worldly]] things where perceptual [[experience]] is available; but inference cannot be employed for establishing any {{Wiki|dogma}} regarding the [[transcendental]] [[world]], or [[life]] after [[death]] or the [[law of karma]] which cannot be available to ordinary perceptual [[experience]]."  
  
Likewise, the charge of hedonism against Cārvāka might have been exaggerated.  Countering the argument that the Cārvākas opposed all that was good in the Vedic tradition, Dale Riepe says, "It may be said from the available material that Cārvākas hold truth, integrity, consistency, and freedom of thought in the highest esteem."  
+
Likewise, the charge of hedonism against [[Cārvāka]] might have been exaggerated.  Countering the argument that the Cārvākas opposed all that was good in the {{Wiki|Vedic}} [[tradition]], Dale Riepe says, "It may be said from the available material that Cārvākas hold [[truth]], integrity, [[consistency]], and freedom of [[thought]] in the highest esteem."  
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
 
{{W}}
 
{{W}}
 
[[Category:Buddhist Terms]]
 
[[Category:Buddhist Terms]]
 
[[Category:Cārvāka]]
 
[[Category:Cārvāka]]

Revision as of 19:53, 25 August 2013

20100814Manjusri-1.jpg

Cārvāka (Sanskrit: चार्वाक), also known as Lokāyata, is a system of Indian philosophy that assumes various forms of philosophical skepticism and religious indifference. Etymologically, both words Cārvāka and Lokāyata mean "popular" or "agreeable" in Sanskrit.

Cārvāka is classified as a heterodox Hindu (Nāstika) system. It is characterized as a materialistic and atheistic school of thought. While this branch of Indian philosophy is today not considered to be part of the six orthodox schools of Hindu philosophy, some describe it as an atheistic or materialistic philosophical movement within Hinduism.

Cārvāka emerged as an alternative to the orthodox Hindu pro-Vedic Āstika schools, as well as a philosophical predecessor to subsequent or contemporaneous nāstika philosophies such as Ājīvika, Jainism and Buddhism (the latter two later spinning off into what may be described today as separate religions) in the classical period of Indian philosophy. As opposed to other schools, the first principle of Cārvāka philosophy was the rejection of inference as a means to establish metaphysical truths.
Name

Etymologically, Cārvāka means "agreeable speech" (cāru – agreeable and vāk – speech) and Lokāyata signifies "prevalence in the world" (lokaworld and āyata – prevalent).

The name Lokāyata can be traced to Kautilya's Arthashastra, which refers to three ānvīkṣikīs (logical philosophies) — Yoga, Samkhya and Lokāyata. However, Lokāyata in Arthashastra, does not stand for materialism because the Arthashastra refers to Lokāyata as a part of Vedic lore. Lokāyata here probably refers to logic or science of debate (disputatio, "criticism") and not to the materialist doctrine. Similarly, Saddaniti and Buddhaghosa in the 5th century connect the "Lokāyata" with the Vitandas (sophists).

It is only from about the 6th century that the term Lokāyata was restricted to the school of the materialists or Lokyātikas. The name Cārvāka was first used in the 7th century by the philosopher Purandara, who referred to his fellow materialists as "the Cārvākas", and it was used by the 8th century philosophers Kamalaśīla and Haribhadra. Adi Shankara, on the other hand, always used Lokāyata, not Cārvāka. By the 8th century, the terms Cārvāka, Lokāyata, and Bārhaspatya were used interchangeably to signify materialism.
Origin

The earliest documented materialist in India is Ajita Kesakambali, a senior contemporary of the Buddha (sixth/fifth century BCE). The basic tenets of Cārvāka philosophy, of no soul and existence of four (not five) elements were probably inspired from him. Although materialist schools existed before Cārvāka, it was the only school which systematized materialist philosophy by setting them down in the form of aphorisms in the 6th century. There was a base text, a collection sūtras or aphorisms and several commentaries were written to explicate the aphorisms.
E. W. Hopkins, in his The Ethics of India (1924) claims that Cārvāka philosophy was contemporaneous to Jainism and Buddhism, mentioning "the old Cārvāka or materialist of the 6th century BC". Rhys Davids assumes that lokāyata in ca. 500 BC came to mean "skepticism" in general without yet being organized as a philosophical school, and that the name of a villain in the epic Mahabharata, Cārvāka, was attached to the position in order to disparage it. The earliest positive statement of skepticism is preserved from the epic period, in the Ramayana, Ayodhya kanda, chapter 108, where Jabāli tries to persuade Rāma to accept the kingdom by using nāstika arguments (but Rāma then refutes him in chapter 109):
    O, the highly wise! Arrive at a conclusion, therefore, that there is nothing beyond this Universe. Give precedence to that which meets the eye and turn your back on what is beyond our knowledge. (2.108.17)

7Manjusri.JPG

The Cārvāka school thus appears to have gradually grown out of generic skepticism in the Mauryan period, but its existence as an organized body cannot be ascertained for times predating the 6th century. The Barhaspatya sutras were likely also composed in Mauryan times, predating 150 BC, based on a reference in the Mahabhasya of Patanjali (7.3.45). Cārvāka was a living philosophy up to the 12th century AD after which this system seems to have disappeared without leaving any trace. The reason for this sudden disappearance is not known.
Earliest descriptions

Brihaspati is sometimes referred to as the founder of Cārvāka or Lokāyata philosophy. The earliest direct quote from Brihaspati's lost writings is found in the text Sarvasiddhantasamgraha, which is sometimes controversially attributed to Shankara. In the Sarvasiddhantasamgraha, the author quotes Brihaspati as follows:
“ Chastity and other such ordinances are laid down by clever weaklings; gifts of gold and land, the pleasure of invitations to dinner, are devised by indigent people with stomachs lean with hunger.
The building of temples, houses for water-supply, tanks, wells, resting places, and the like, please only travelers, not others.
The Agnihotra ritual, the three Vedas, the triple staff, the ash-smearing, are the ways of gaining a livelihood for those who are lacking in intellect and energy.
The wise should enjoy the pleasures of this world through the more appropriate available means of agriculture, tending cattle, trade, political administration, etc. ”
Philosophy

The Cārvāka school of philosophy had a variety of atheistic and materialistic beliefs. They held perception to be the only valid source of knowledge.
Epistemology

In syllogism, the middle term, which is found in both the subject (minor term) and is invariably connected with the predicate (major term), is seen as the cause of knowledge. This invariable connection between middle term and predicate is unconditional and causes inference not by virtue of its existence, like the existence of the eye is the cause of perception, but by virtue of it being known. To the Cārvākas there were no reliable means by which this connection could be known and therefore the efficacy of inference as a means of knowledge could not be established.

To prove that inference was not a reliable means of knowledge Cārvākas examined and refuted each of the various means of knowing the connection between the middle term and the predicate individually:

080720 1.jpg

    External perception, or perception which involves the use of the senses, could not be the required means because although, it is possible that the actual contact of the senses and the object could produce the knowledge of the particular object, yet there can never be such contact in the case of the past or the future. Therefore if external perception were the means on knowing the connection then inference related to objects of the past and future could not happen.

    Internal perception, or perception which involves the mind could, not be the required means either, because one cannot establish that the mind has any power to act independently towards an external object and is thought to be dependent on the external senses.

    Nor could inference be the means, since if inference were the proof of inference, one would also require another inference to establish this inference, and so on, leading to the fallacy of an Ad infinitum regression.

    Nor could testimony be the means, since testimony can be classified as a type of inference. Moreover, there is no reason for one to believe word of another. Besides, if testimony were to be accepted as the only means of the knowledge of the invariable connection between middle term and predicate, then in the case of a man to whom the fact of the connection had not been pointed out by another person, there could be no inference.

    Comparison (Upamana) could also be rejected as the means of the knowledge of the connection, since objective of using Upamana is to establish a different kind of knowledge than is being sought here, the relation of a name to something so named.

    Absence of a condition (Upadhi), which is given as the definition of an invariable connection to restrict too general a middle term, could itself not be used to establish inference because it is impossible to establish that all conditions required to restrict the middle term are known without recourse to inference and inference, as has been proven earlier, cannot establish itself.

Metaphysics

202345 n.jpg

Since, none of the means of knowing were found to be worthy to establish the invariable connection between middle term and predicate, Cārvākas concluded that the inference could not be used to ascertain metaphysical truths. Thus, to Cārvākas, the step which the mind takes from the knowledge of something to infer the knowledge of something else, could be accounted for by the its being based on a former perception or by its being in error. Cases where inference was justified by the result, were seen only to be mere coincidences.

Therefore, Cārvākas denied metaphysical concepts like reincarnation, extracorporeal soul, efficacy of religious rites, other world (heaven and hell), fate and accumulation of merit or demerit through the performance of certain actions. Cārvākas also rejected the use of supernatural causes to describe natural phenomena. To them all natural phenomena was produced spontaneously from the inherent nature of things.

    The fire is hot, the water cold, refreshing cool the breeze of morn;
    By whom came this variety ? from their own nature was it born.

Consciousness and Afterlife

Carvakas thought that body was formed out of four elements (instead of five) and that consciousness was an outcome of the mixture of these elements. Therefore, Carvakas did not believe in an afterlife. To them, all attributes that represented a person, such a thinness, fatness etc., resided in the body. To support the proposition of non-existence of any soul or consciousness in the afterlife Carvakas often quoted from Brihadaranyaka Upanishad.

    Springing forth from these elements itself
    solid knowledge is destroyed
    when they are destroyed—
    after death no intelligence remains.

Cārvāka believed that there was nothing wrong with sensual pleasure. Since it is impossible to have pleasure without pain, Cārvāka thought that wisdom lay in enjoying pleasure and avoiding pain as far as possible. Unlike many of the Indian philosophies of the time, Cārvāka did not believe in austerities or rejecting pleasure out of fear of pain and held such reasoning to be foolish.
    The berries of paddy, rich with the finest white grains,
    What man, seeking his true interest, would fling away because covered with husk and dust?

Manj01.jpg

Religion

Cārvākas rejected religious conceptions like afterlife, reincarnation, religious rites etc. They were extremely critical of the Vedas and thought that Vedas suffered from three faults - untruth, self-contradiction and tautology. To them, Vedas were just incoherent rhapsodies. They also held the belief that such texts were invented and made up by men and had no divine authority.

    The Agnihotra, the three Vedas, the ascetic's three staves, and smearing one's self with ashes,
    Were made by Nature as the livelihood of those destitute of knowledge and manliness.
Criticism

Buddhist philosophers reasoned that the Cārvāka proposition that inference could not be used as a form of evidence (Pramana) was absurd. If no arguments were given to prove this proposition, it would just be a bare assertion. Whereas, if some form of argumentation were given, it would result in absurdity, because inference was being used to disprove its own efficacy as evidence. Besides, when existence of any object, be it the authority of inference, was denied on the ground of it not being perceived, inference was itself admitted in proposing such an argument, with middle term being the non-perception.
Works

304.jpg

No independent works on Cārvāka philosophy can be found except for a few sūtras composed by Brihaspati. The 8th century Tattvopaplavasimha of Jayarashi Bhatta (ca. 8th century) is often cited as the only extant authentic Cārvāka text, but which also shows Madhyamaka influence. Shatdarshan Samuchay and Sarvadarśanasaṅ̇graha of Vidyaranya are a few other works which elucidate Cārvāka thought.

One of the most important references to the Cārvāka philosophy is the Sarva-darśana-saṅgraha (etymologically all-philosophy-collection), a famous work of 14th century Advaita Vedanta philosopher Mādhava Vidyāraṇya from South India, which starts with a chapter on the Cārvāka system. After invoking, in the Prologue of the book, the Hindu gods Shiva and Vishnu ("by whom the earth and rest were produced"), Vidyāraṇya asks, in the first chapter:
“ ...but how can we attribute to the Divine Being the giving of supreme felicity, when such a notion has been utterly abolished by Charvaka, the crest-gem of the atheistic school, the follower of the doctrine of Brihaspati? The efforts of Charvaka are indeed hard to be eradicated, for the majority of living beings hold by the current refrain:

        While life is yours, live joyously;
        None can escape Death's searching eye:
        When once this frame of ours they burn,
        How shall it e'er again return?



Ain-i-Akbari, written by Abul Fazl, the famous historian of Akbar's court, mentions a symposium of philosophers of all faiths held in 1578 at Akbar's insistence. Some of the beliefs of Cārvāka are recorded from this symposium, in which, some Cārvāka philosophers are said to have participated.

Sanskrit poems and plays like the Naiṣadha-carita, Prabodha-candrodaya, Āgama-dambara, Vidvanmoda-taraṅgiṇī and Kādambarī contain representations of the Cārvāka thought. However, the authors of these works were thoroughly opposed to materialism and tried to portray the Cārvāka in unfavourable light. Therefore, their works should only be accepted critically.
Loss of original works

There was no continuity in the Cārvāka tradition after the 12th century. Whatever is written on Cārvāka post this is based on second-hand knowledge, learned from preceptors to disciples and no independent works on Cārvāka philosophy can be found. Chatterjee and Datta explain that our understanding of Cārvāka philosophy is fragmentary, based largely on criticism of its ideas by other schools, and that it is not a living tradition:

    "Though materialism in some form or other has always been present in India, and occasional references are found in the Vedas, the Buddhistic literature, the Epics, as well as in the later philosophical works we do not find any systematic work on materialism, nor any organised school of followers as the other philosophical schools possess. But almost every work of the other schools states, for refutation, the materialistic views. Our knowledge of Indian materialism is chiefly based on these."

Representation of Cārvāka in Āstika, Buddhist and Jain Literature

The Yogācāra Buddhists, Jains, Advaita Vedantins and Nyāya philosophers considered the Cārvākas as one of their opponents and tried to refute their views. These refutations are sources of Cārvāka philosophy since, they continued to be made even after all the authentic Cārvāka/Lokāyata texts had been lost. However, the representation of the Cārvāka thought in these works is not always firmly grounded in first hand knowledge of Cārvāka texts and should be viewed critically.

Though Cārvākas accepted direct perception as the surest method to prove the truth of anything, they might also have accepted a limited usage of inference. The perception that Cārvākas had a rigid stance against the application of inference might have been a result of caricaturing of their arguments by their opponents. Debiprasad Chattopadhyaya quotes S. N. Dasgupta:

    "Purandara (a Lokāyata philosopher) [...] admits the usefulness of inference in determining the nature of all worldly things where perceptual experience is available; but inference cannot be employed for establishing any dogma regarding the transcendental world, or life after death or the law of karma which cannot be available to ordinary perceptual experience."

Likewise, the charge of hedonism against Cārvāka might have been exaggerated. Countering the argument that the Cārvākas opposed all that was good in the Vedic tradition, Dale Riepe says, "It may be said from the available material that Cārvākas hold truth, integrity, consistency, and freedom of thought in the highest esteem."

Source

Wikipedia:Cārvāka