Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Belief"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
Line 1: Line 1:
 
[[File:143kl.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:143kl.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 +
 +
 +
 +
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
[[Belief]] is the [[psychological]] state in which an individual holds a proposition or premise to be true. Dispositional and occurrent belief concerns the contextual activation of the [[belief]] into [[thoughts]] (reactive of propositions) or ideas (based on the [[belief's]] premise)
+
[[Belief]] is the [[psychological]] [[state]] in which an {{Wiki|individual}} holds a proposition or premise to be true.  
 +
 
 +
Dispositional and occurrent [[belief]] concerns the contextual activation of the [[belief]] into [[thoughts]] (reactive of propositions) or [[ideas]] (based on the [[belief's]] premise)
  
 
[[Belief]], [[knowledge]] and {{Wiki|epistemology}}
 
[[Belief]], [[knowledge]] and {{Wiki|epistemology}}
Line 7: Line 13:
 
The terms [[belief]] and [[knowledge]] are used differently in {{Wiki|philosophy}}.
 
The terms [[belief]] and [[knowledge]] are used differently in {{Wiki|philosophy}}.
  
{{Wiki|Epistemology}} is the [[philosophical]] study of [[knowledge]] and [[belief]]. The primary problem in epistemology is to understand exactly what is needed in order for us to have true knowledge. In a notion derived from Plato's dialogue Theaetetus, philosophy has traditionally defined knowledge as "justified true belief". The relationship between belief and knowledge is that a belief is knowledge if the belief is true, and if the believer has a justification (reasonable and necessarily plausible assertions/evidence/guidance) for believing it is true.
+
{{Wiki|Epistemology}} is the [[philosophical]] study of [[knowledge]] and [[belief]].  
 +
 
 +
The primary problem in epistemology is to understand exactly what is needed in order for us to have true [[knowledge]].  
 +
 
 +
In a notion derived from [[Plato's]] {{Wiki|dialogue}} Theaetetus, [[philosophy]] has [[traditionally]] defined [[knowledge]] as "[[justified true belief]]".  
 +
 
 +
The relationship between [[belief]] and [[knowledge]] is that a [[belief]] is [[knowledge]] if the [[belief]] is true, and if the believer has a {{Wiki|justification}} (reasonable and necessarily plausible assertions/evidence/guidance) for believing it is true.
 +
 
 +
A [[false belief]] is not considered to be [[knowledge]], even if it is {{Wiki|sincere}}.  
  
A false belief is not considered to be knowledge, even if it is sincere. A sincere believer in the flat earth theory does not know that the Earth is flat. Later epistemologists, for instance Gettier (1963)  and Goldman (1967), have questioned the "justified true belief" definition.
+
A {{Wiki|sincere}} believer in the flat [[earth]] {{Wiki|theory}} does not know that the [[Earth]] is flat. Later [[epistemologists]], for instance Gettier (1963)  and Goldman (1967), have questioned the "[[justified true belief]]" [[definition]].
Belief as a psychological theory
+
[[Belief]] as a [[psychological]] {{Wiki|theory}}
 
[[File:0437.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:0437.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
Mainstream psychology and related disciplines have traditionally treated belief as if it were the simplest form of mental representation and therefore one of the building blocks of conscious thought. Philosophers have tended to be more abstract in their analysis, and much of the work examining the viability of the belief concept stems from philosophical analysis.
+
Mainstream {{Wiki|psychology}} and related [[disciplines]] have [[traditionally]] treated [[belief]] as if it were the simplest [[form]] of [[mental]] [[representation]] and therefore one of the building blocks of [[conscious]] [[thought]].  
 +
 
 +
[[Philosophers]] have tended to be more abstract in their analysis, and much of the work examining the viability of the [[belief]] {{Wiki|concept}} stems from [[philosophical]] analysis.
  
The concept of [[belief]] presumes a subject (the believer) and an object of [[belief]] (the proposition). So, like other propositional attitudes, belief implies the existence of mental states and intentionality, both of which are hotly debated topics in the philosophy of mind, whose foundations and relation to brain states are still controversial.
+
The {{Wiki|concept}} of [[belief]] presumes a [[subject]] (the believer) and an [[object]] of [[belief]] (the proposition).  
  
Beliefs are sometimes divided into core beliefs (that are actively thought about) and dispositional [[beliefs]] (that may be ascribed to someone who has not thought about the issue). For example, if asked "do you believe tigers wear pink pajamas?" a person might answer that they do not, despite the fact they may never have thought about this situation before.  
+
So, like other propositional attitudes, [[belief]] implies the [[existence]] of [[mental states]] and {{Wiki|intentionality}}, both of which are hotly [[debated]] topics in the {{Wiki|philosophy of mind}}, whose foundations and [[relation]] to {{Wiki|brain}} states are still controversial.
  
That a belief is a mental state has been seen by some as contentious. While some  have argued that beliefs are represented in the mind as sentence-like constructs, others  have gone as far as arguing that there is no consistent or coherent mental representation that underlies our common use of the belief concept and that it is therefore obsolete and should be rejected.
+
[[Beliefs]] are sometimes divided into core [[beliefs]] (that are actively [[thought]] about) and dispositional [[beliefs]] (that may be ascribed to someone who has not [[thought]] about the issue).  
  
This has important implications for understanding the neuropsychology and neuroscience of belief. If the concept of belief is incoherent, then any attempt to find the underlying neural processes that support it will fail.
+
For example, if asked "do you believe [[tigers]] wear pink pajamas?" a [[person]] might answer that they do not, despite the fact they may never have [[thought]] about this situation before.
 +
 
 +
That a [[belief]] is a [[mental state]] has been seen by some as contentious.
 +
 
 +
While some  have argued that [[beliefs]] are represented in the [[mind]] as sentence-like constructs, others  have gone as far as arguing that there is no consistent or coherent [[mental]] [[representation]] that underlies our common use of the [[belief]] {{Wiki|concept}} and that it is therefore obsolete and should be rejected.
 +
 
 +
This has important implications for [[understanding]] the {{Wiki|neuropsychology}} and {{Wiki|neuroscience}} of [[belief]].  
 +
 
 +
If the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[belief]] is [[Wikipedia:Coherentism|incoherent]], then any attempt to find the underlying neural {{Wiki|processes}} that support it will fail.
 
[[File:0438.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:0438.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
Philosopher Lynne Rudder Baker has outlined four main contemporary approaches to belief in her controversial book Saving Belief:  
+
[[Philosopher]] Lynne Rudder Baker has outlined four main contemporary approaches to [[belief]] in her controversial [[book]] Saving [[Belief]]:  
 +
 
 +
    Our {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[understanding]] of [[belief]] is correct - Sometimes called the "[[mental]] sentence {{Wiki|theory}}," in this {{Wiki|conception}}, [[beliefs]] [[exist]] as coherent entities, and the way we talk about them in everyday [[life]] is a valid basis for [[scientific]] endeavour. Jerry Fodor is one of the [[principal]] defenders of this point of view.
 +
 
  
     Our common-sense understanding of belief is correct - Sometimes called the "mental sentence theory," in this conception, beliefs exist as coherent entities, and the way we talk about them in everyday life is a valid basis for scientific endeavour. Jerry Fodor is one of the principal defenders of this point of view.
+
     Our {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[understanding]] of [[belief]] may not be entirely correct, but it is close enough to make some useful predictions -  
    Our common-sense understanding of belief may not be entirely correct, but it is close enough to make some useful predictions - This view argues that we will eventually reject the idea of belief as we use it now, but that there may be a correlation between what we take to be a belief when someone says "I believe that snow is white" and how a future theory of psychology will explain this behaviour. Most notably, philosopher Stephen Stich has argued for this particular understanding of belief.
+
 
     Our common-sense understanding of belief is entirely wrong and will be completely superseded by a radically different theory that will have no use for the concept of belief as we know it - Known as eliminativism, this view, (most notably proposed by Paul and Patricia Churchland), argues that the concept of belief is like obsolete theories of times past such as the four humours theory of medicine, or the phlogiston theory of combustion. In these cases science hasn't provided us with a more detailed account of these theories, but completely rejected them as valid scientific concepts to be replaced by entirely different accounts. The Churchlands argue that our common-sense concept of belief is similar in that as we discover more about neuroscience and the brain, the inevitable conclusion will be to reject the belief hypothesis in its entirety.
+
This view argues that we will eventually reject the [[idea]] of [[belief]] as we use it now, but that there may be a correlation between what we take to be a [[belief]] when someone says "I believe that snow is white" and how a {{Wiki|future}} {{Wiki|theory}} of {{Wiki|psychology}} will explain this {{Wiki|behaviour}}.  
     Our common-sense understanding of belief is entirely wrong; however, treating people, animals, and even computers as if they had beliefs is often a successful strategy - The major proponents of this view, Daniel Dennett and Lynne Rudder Baker, are both eliminativists in that they hold that beliefs are not a scientifically valid concept, but they don't go as far as rejecting the concept of belief as a predictive device. Dennett gives the example of playing a computer at chess. While few people would agree that the computer held beliefs, treating the computer as if it did (e.g. that the computer believes that taking the opposition's queen will give it a considerable advantage) is likely to be a successful and predictive strategy. In this understanding of belief, named by Dennett the intentional stance, belief-based explanations of mind and behaviour are at a different level of explanation and are not reducible to those based on fundamental neuroscience, although both may be explanatory at their own level.
+
 
 +
Most notably, [[philosopher]] Stephen Stich has argued for this particular [[understanding]] of [[belief]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
     Our {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[understanding]] of [[belief]] is entirely wrong and will be completely superseded by a radically different {{Wiki|theory}} that will have no use for the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[belief]] as we know it -  
 +
 
 +
Known as eliminativism, this view, (most notably proposed by Paul and {{Wiki|Patricia Churchland}}), argues that the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[belief]] is like obsolete theories of times {{Wiki|past}} such as the four [[humours]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[medicine]], or the phlogiston {{Wiki|theory}} of combustion.  
 +
 
 +
In these cases [[science]] hasn't provided us with a more detailed account of these theories, but completely rejected them as valid [[scientific]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] to be replaced by entirely different accounts.  
 +
 
 +
The Churchlands argue that our {{Wiki|common-sense}} {{Wiki|concept}} of [[belief]] is similar in that as we discover more about {{Wiki|neuroscience}} and the {{Wiki|brain}}, the inevitable conclusion will be to reject the [[belief]] {{Wiki|hypothesis}} in its entirety.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
     Our {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[understanding]] of [[belief]] is entirely wrong; however, treating [[people]], [[animals]], and even computers as if they had [[beliefs]] is often a successful strategy -  
 +
 
 +
The major proponents of this view, {{Wiki|Daniel Dennett}} and Lynne Rudder Baker, are both eliminativists in that they hold that [[beliefs]] are not a {{Wiki|scientifically}} valid {{Wiki|concept}}, but they don't go as far as rejecting the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[belief]] as a predictive device.  
 +
 
 +
Dennett gives the example of playing a {{Wiki|computer}} at {{Wiki|chess}}.  
 +
 
 +
While few [[people]] would agree that the {{Wiki|computer}} held [[beliefs]], treating the {{Wiki|computer}} as if it did (e.g. that the {{Wiki|computer}} believes that taking the opposition's [[Wikipedia:Queen consort|queen]] will give it a considerable advantage) is likely to be a successful and predictive strategy.  
 +
 
 +
In this [[understanding]] of [[belief]], named by Dennett the intentional stance, belief-based explanations of [[mind]] and {{Wiki|behaviour}} are at a different level of explanation and are not reducible to those based on fundamental {{Wiki|neuroscience}}, although both may be explanatory at their [[own]] level.
 
[[File:0450.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:0450.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
How beliefs are formed
+
How [[beliefs]] are formed
 +
 
 +
{{Wiki|Psychologists}} study [[belief]] formation and the relationship between [[beliefs]] and [[actions]]. [[Beliefs]] [[form]] in a variety of ways:
 +
 
 +
    We tend to internalise the [[beliefs]] of the [[people]] around us during childhood.
 +
 
 +
{{Wiki|Albert Einstein}} is often quoted as having said that "{{Wiki|Common sense}} is the collection of prejudices acquired by age eighteen."
 +
 
 +
{{Wiki|Political}} [[beliefs]] depend most strongly on the {{Wiki|political}} [[beliefs]] most common in the {{Wiki|community}} where we live.
 +
 
 +
Most {{Wiki|individuals}} believe the [[religion]] they were [[taught]] in childhood.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
    [[People]] may adopt the [[beliefs]] of a {{Wiki|charismatic}} leader, even if those [[beliefs]] fly in the face of all previous [[beliefs]], and produce [[actions]] that are clearly not in their [[own]] [[self-interest]]. 
 +
 
 +
Is [[belief]] voluntary?
  
Psychologists study belief formation and the relationship between beliefs and actions. Beliefs form in a variety of ways:
+
[[Rational]] {{Wiki|individuals}} need to reconcile their direct [[reality]] with any said [[belief]]; therefore, if [[belief]] is not {{Wiki|present}} or possible, it reflects the fact that contradictions were necessarily overcome using [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] dissonance.
  
    We tend to internalise the beliefs of the people around us during childhood. Albert Einstein is often quoted as having said that "Common sense is the collection of prejudices acquired by age eighteen." Political beliefs depend most strongly on the political beliefs most common in the community where we live. Most individuals believe the religion they were taught in childhood.
+
     Advertising can [[form]] or change [[beliefs]] through repetition, [[shock]], and association with images of {{Wiki|sex}}, [[love]], [[beauty]], and other strong positive [[emotions]].  
    People may adopt the beliefs of a charismatic leader, even if those beliefs fly in the face of all previous beliefs, and produce actions that are clearly not in their own self-interest.  Is belief voluntary? Rational individuals need to reconcile their direct reality with any said belief; therefore, if belief is not present or possible, it reflects the fact that contradictions were necessarily overcome using cognitive dissonance.
+
     [[Physical]] [[trauma]], especially to the head, can radically alter a person's [[beliefs]].  
     Advertising can form or change beliefs through repetition, shock, and association with images of sex, love, beauty, and other strong positive emotions.  
 
     Physical trauma, especially to the head, can radically alter a person's beliefs.  
 
 
[[File:100 1617.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:100 1617.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
However, even educated people, well aware of the process by which beliefs form, still strongly cling to their beliefs, and act on those beliefs even against their own self-interest. In Anna Rowley's Leadership Theory, she states "You want your beliefs to change. It's proof that you are keeping your eyes open, living fully, and welcoming everything that the world and people around you can teach you." This means that peoples' beliefs should evolve as they gain new experiences.  
+
 
 +
However, even educated [[people]], well {{Wiki|aware}} of the process by which [[beliefs]] [[form]], still strongly [[cling]] to their [[beliefs]], and act on those [[beliefs]] even against their [[own]] [[self-interest]].  
 +
 
 +
In Anna Rowley's [[Leadership]] {{Wiki|Theory}}, she states "You want your [[beliefs]] to change.  
 +
 
 +
It's [[proof]] that you are keeping your [[eyes]] open, living fully, and welcoming everything that the [[world]] and [[people]] around you can teach you."  
 +
 
 +
This means that peoples' [[beliefs]] should evolve as they gain new [[experiences]].  
 
Belief-in
 
Belief-in
  
To "believe in" someone or something is a distinct concept from "believe-that." There are two types of belief-in:
+
To "believe in" someone or something is a {{Wiki|distinct}} {{Wiki|concept}} from "believe-that." There are two types of belief-in:
 +
 
 +
    Commendatory - an expression of [[confidence]] in a [[person]] or [[entity]], as in, "I believe in his ability to do the job."
 +
    Existential claim - to claim [[belief]] in the [[existence]] of an [[entity]] or [[phenomenon]] with the implied need to justify its claim to [[existence]].
 +
 
 +
It is often used when the [[entity]] is not real, or its [[existence]] is in [[doubt]].
 +
 
 +
"He believes in {{Wiki|witches}} and [[ghosts]]" or "many children believe in {{Wiki|Santa Claus}}" are typical examples.
 +
 
 +
Delusional [[beliefs]]
  
    Commendatory - an expression of confidence in a person or entity, as in, "I believe in his ability to do the job."
+
[[Delusions]] are defined as [[beliefs]] in psychiatric {{Wiki|diagnostic}} criteria  (for example in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of {{Wiki|Mental Disorders}}).  
    Existential claim - to claim belief in the existence of an entity or phenomenon with the implied need to justify its claim to existence. It is often used when the entity is not real, or its existence is in doubt. "He believes in witches and ghosts" or "many children believe in Santa Claus" are typical examples.  
 
  
Delusional beliefs
+
{{Wiki|Psychiatrist}} and historian G.E. Berrios has challenged the view that [[delusions]] are genuine [[beliefs]] and instead labels them as "[[empty]] {{Wiki|speech}} acts," where affected persons are motivated to express false or bizarre [[belief]] statements due to an underlying [[psychological]] {{Wiki|disturbance}}.
  
Delusions are defined as beliefs in psychiatric diagnostic criteria  (for example in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders). Psychiatrist and historian G.E. Berrios has challenged the view that delusions are genuine beliefs and instead labels them as "empty speech acts," where affected persons are motivated to express false or bizarre belief statements due to an underlying psychological disturbance. However, the majority of mental health professionals and researchers treat delusions as if they were genuine beliefs.
+
However, the majority of {{Wiki|mental health}} professionals and researchers treat [[delusions]] as if they were genuine [[beliefs]].
  
In Lewis Carroll's Through the Looking-Glass the White Queen says, "Why, sometimes I've believed as many as six impossible things before breakfast." This is often quoted in mockery of the common ability of people to entertain beliefs contrary to fact.
+
In Lewis Carroll's Through the Looking-Glass the White [[Queen]] says, "Why, sometimes I've believed as many as six impossible things before breakfast." This is often quoted in mockery of the common ability of [[people]] to entertain [[beliefs]] contrary to fact.
 
{{W}}
 
{{W}}
 
[[Category:Buddhist Terms]]
 
[[Category:Buddhist Terms]]

Revision as of 07:03, 26 February 2016

143kl.jpg



<poem> Belief is the psychological state in which an individual holds a proposition or premise to be true.

Dispositional and occurrent belief concerns the contextual activation of the belief into thoughts (reactive of propositions) or ideas (based on the belief's premise)

Belief, knowledge and epistemology

The terms belief and knowledge are used differently in philosophy.

Epistemology is the philosophical study of knowledge and belief.

The primary problem in epistemology is to understand exactly what is needed in order for us to have true knowledge.

In a notion derived from Plato's dialogue Theaetetus, philosophy has traditionally defined knowledge as "justified true belief".

The relationship between belief and knowledge is that a belief is knowledge if the belief is true, and if the believer has a justification (reasonable and necessarily plausible assertions/evidence/guidance) for believing it is true.

A false belief is not considered to be knowledge, even if it is sincere.

A sincere believer in the flat earth theory does not know that the Earth is flat. Later epistemologists, for instance Gettier (1963) and Goldman (1967), have questioned the "justified true belief" definition. Belief as a psychological theory

0437.jpg

Mainstream psychology and related disciplines have traditionally treated belief as if it were the simplest form of mental representation and therefore one of the building blocks of conscious thought.

Philosophers have tended to be more abstract in their analysis, and much of the work examining the viability of the belief concept stems from philosophical analysis.

The concept of belief presumes a subject (the believer) and an object of belief (the proposition).

So, like other propositional attitudes, belief implies the existence of mental states and intentionality, both of which are hotly debated topics in the philosophy of mind, whose foundations and relation to brain states are still controversial.

Beliefs are sometimes divided into core beliefs (that are actively thought about) and dispositional beliefs (that may be ascribed to someone who has not thought about the issue).

For example, if asked "do you believe tigers wear pink pajamas?" a person might answer that they do not, despite the fact they may never have thought about this situation before.

That a belief is a mental state has been seen by some as contentious.

While some have argued that beliefs are represented in the mind as sentence-like constructs, others have gone as far as arguing that there is no consistent or coherent mental representation that underlies our common use of the belief concept and that it is therefore obsolete and should be rejected.

This has important implications for understanding the neuropsychology and neuroscience of belief.

If the concept of belief is incoherent, then any attempt to find the underlying neural processes that support it will fail.

0438.jpg

Philosopher Lynne Rudder Baker has outlined four main contemporary approaches to belief in her controversial book Saving Belief:

   Our common-sense understanding of belief is correct - Sometimes called the "mental sentence theory," in this conception, beliefs exist as coherent entities, and the way we talk about them in everyday life is a valid basis for scientific endeavour. Jerry Fodor is one of the principal defenders of this point of view.


   Our common-sense understanding of belief may not be entirely correct, but it is close enough to make some useful predictions - 

This view argues that we will eventually reject the idea of belief as we use it now, but that there may be a correlation between what we take to be a belief when someone says "I believe that snow is white" and how a future theory of psychology will explain this behaviour.

Most notably, philosopher Stephen Stich has argued for this particular understanding of belief.


   Our common-sense understanding of belief is entirely wrong and will be completely superseded by a radically different theory that will have no use for the concept of belief as we know it - 

Known as eliminativism, this view, (most notably proposed by Paul and Patricia Churchland), argues that the concept of belief is like obsolete theories of times past such as the four humours theory of medicine, or the phlogiston theory of combustion.

In these cases science hasn't provided us with a more detailed account of these theories, but completely rejected them as valid scientific concepts to be replaced by entirely different accounts.

The Churchlands argue that our common-sense concept of belief is similar in that as we discover more about neuroscience and the brain, the inevitable conclusion will be to reject the belief hypothesis in its entirety.


   Our common-sense understanding of belief is entirely wrong; however, treating people, animals, and even computers as if they had beliefs is often a successful strategy - 

The major proponents of this view, Daniel Dennett and Lynne Rudder Baker, are both eliminativists in that they hold that beliefs are not a scientifically valid concept, but they don't go as far as rejecting the concept of belief as a predictive device.

Dennett gives the example of playing a computer at chess.

While few people would agree that the computer held beliefs, treating the computer as if it did (e.g. that the computer believes that taking the opposition's queen will give it a considerable advantage) is likely to be a successful and predictive strategy.

In this understanding of belief, named by Dennett the intentional stance, belief-based explanations of mind and behaviour are at a different level of explanation and are not reducible to those based on fundamental neuroscience, although both may be explanatory at their own level.

0450.jpg

How beliefs are formed

Psychologists study belief formation and the relationship between beliefs and actions. Beliefs form in a variety of ways:

   We tend to internalise the beliefs of the people around us during childhood. 

Albert Einstein is often quoted as having said that "Common sense is the collection of prejudices acquired by age eighteen."

Political beliefs depend most strongly on the political beliefs most common in the community where we live.

Most individuals believe the religion they were taught in childhood.


   People may adopt the beliefs of a charismatic leader, even if those beliefs fly in the face of all previous beliefs, and produce actions that are clearly not in their own self-interest.  

Is belief voluntary?

Rational individuals need to reconcile their direct reality with any said belief; therefore, if belief is not present or possible, it reflects the fact that contradictions were necessarily overcome using cognitive dissonance.

   Advertising can form or change beliefs through repetition, shock, and association with images of sex, love, beauty, and other strong positive emotions. 
   Physical trauma, especially to the head, can radically alter a person's beliefs. 
100 1617.jpg

However, even educated people, well aware of the process by which beliefs form, still strongly cling to their beliefs, and act on those beliefs even against their own self-interest.

In Anna Rowley's Leadership Theory, she states "You want your beliefs to change.

It's proof that you are keeping your eyes open, living fully, and welcoming everything that the world and people around you can teach you."

This means that peoples' beliefs should evolve as they gain new experiences. Belief-in

To "believe in" someone or something is a distinct concept from "believe-that." There are two types of belief-in:

   Commendatory - an expression of confidence in a person or entity, as in, "I believe in his ability to do the job."
   Existential claim - to claim belief in the existence of an entity or phenomenon with the implied need to justify its claim to existence. 

It is often used when the entity is not real, or its existence is in doubt.

"He believes in witches and ghosts" or "many children believe in Santa Claus" are typical examples.

Delusional beliefs

Delusions are defined as beliefs in psychiatric diagnostic criteria (for example in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders).

Psychiatrist and historian G.E. Berrios has challenged the view that delusions are genuine beliefs and instead labels them as "empty speech acts," where affected persons are motivated to express false or bizarre belief statements due to an underlying psychological disturbance.

However, the majority of mental health professionals and researchers treat delusions as if they were genuine beliefs.

In Lewis Carroll's Through the Looking-Glass the White Queen says, "Why, sometimes I've believed as many as six impossible things before breakfast." This is often quoted in mockery of the common ability of people to entertain beliefs contrary to fact.

Source

Wikipedia:Belief