Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Buddhist Psychology and Different Virtues"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " <poem> Part 2. Reflections and notes on Damien Keown's The Nature of Buddhist Ethics, 1992. Scholars have analyzed, contested and debated about the relation...")
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
{{DisplayImages|4060|914|1153|3998}}
 +
<poem>
 +
Part 2. Reflections and notes on  [[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Damien Keown's]]  The [[Nature]] of [[Buddhist Ethics]], 1992.
  
<poem>
+
[[Scholars]] have analyzed, contested and [[debated]] about the relationship between [[ethics]] and {{Wiki|psychology}} and in many cases with reference to [[Abhidharma]] or [[Buddhist]] [[scholasticism]]. In terms of [[Buddhist psychology]], the [[fundamental cause]] of [[suffering]] in [[life]] or living this “[[samsaric]] [[life]]” can be said precisely as the need to {{Wiki|purify}} the [[mind]] ([[citta]]) whose real [[essence]] is [[pure]] but it is been contaminated by all sorts of different [[mental states]] ([[caitta]]) and [[destructive emotions]] ([[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown]], 1992, 57). the [[abhidharmic]] {{Wiki|literature}}, it lies out the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[dharmas]] of [[Buddhist philosophy]]: [[dharmas]] are basic and impartite constituents of [[reality]], the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] reals or {{Wiki|ontologically}} grounded [[existents]].
Part 2. Reflections and notes on Damien Keown's The [[Nature]] of [[Buddhist Ethics]], 1992.
+
 
 +
[[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown]] [[thinks]] that the nearest to a {{Wiki|theoretical}} approach to [[moral]] [[philosophy]] within the [[Buddhist ethics]] is found in the [[abhidharma]] and therefore it is worth the [[attention]] to its analytic framework. He rejects King’s notion that [[abhidharmic]] [[ethical]] {{Wiki|theory}} is meaningless and confounding for the {{Wiki|western}} [[mind]] with its maze of [[Buddhist]] [[psychological]] {{Wiki|terminology}} ([[Wikipedia:Keown |Keown]], 1992, 59). [[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown]] argues that the difficulty of {{Wiki|terminology}} cannot be good enough a [[reason]] to ignore what this [[tradition]] offers and sheds light on the [[nature]] of [[Buddhist ethics]]. He holds that [[abhidharmic]] [[ethical]] classifications are “readily intelligible” in terms of the one of the oldest and most influential [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] in {{Wiki|western}} [[ethics]], namely – the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[virtues]] (59). According to [[abhidharma]], [[enlightenment]] is achieved through purifying the personal {{Wiki|continuum}} ([[santana]]) of all [[defilements]] ([[klesa]]).
 +
 
 +
So in the taxonomical [[traditions]] of the [[mind]] and [[mental states]]; in case of [[Theravada tradition]], there are fifty-two different types of [[mental states]] or qualities and without [[understanding]] the [[ethical]] functions of these states; it is impossible to provide an analysis of [[sila]] at its most basic level. In [[Sarvastivada]] [[tradition]], there are seventy-five [[dharmas]] and of which forty-seven are of [[psychological]] [[nature]]. Despite the variations in detail all schools [[acknowledge]] a similar classificatory rubrics, and the standard {{Wiki|classification}} is four-fold: {{Wiki|matter}} ([[rupa]]), [[mind]] ([[citta]]), [[mental states]] ([[caitta]]) and the [[unconditioned]] ([[nirvana]]). Only a third of these are related to [[ethics]], which falls under the third category and its [[relation]] to the fourth. [[Citta]] is the center of subjective [[consciousness]], which is viewed as an arsenal or storage of dispositional properties that take its [[form]] in [[mental]] predispositions. “It is the personal [[psychological]] factor responsible for the {{Wiki|unity}} and continuity of the [[human being]] (61)”.
 +
 
 +
[[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown]] point out that one important conclusion to be made from the [[abhidharma]] is that [[Buddhist ethics]] is {{Wiki|naturalistic}}. Why? Because the [[abhidharmic]] analysis of vices and [[virtues]] – since there are [[dharmas]] – are [[objective]] and real. They are not part of our [[mental]] construction, but are actually found within the [[Wikipedia:Psyche (psychology)|psyche]] (64). Now, the implication of this objectivisation is what [[Buddhist ethics]] necessarily rules out {{Wiki|relativism}}: what is ultimately good or bad is not determined by accidental factors but grounded in [[human nature]]. The [[dharma]]-theory of [[abhidharma]] commands its authority on the [[nature]] of [[human]] [[mind]] and [[mental phenomena]] within which [[ethics]] resides.
  
[[Scholars]] have analyzed, contested and [[debated]] about the relationship between [[ethics]] and {{Wiki|psychology}} and in many cases with reference to [[Abhidharma]] or [[Buddhist]] [[scholasticism]]. In terms of [[Buddhist psychology]], the [[fundamental cause]] of [[suffering]] in [[life]] or living this “[[samsaric]] [[life]]” can be said precisely as the need to {{Wiki|purify}} the [[mind]] ([[citta]]) whose real [[essence]] is [[pure]] but it is been contaminated by all sorts of different [[mental states]] ([[caitta]]) and [[destructive emotions]] (Keown, 1992, 57). In the [[abhidharmic]] {{Wiki|literature}}, it lies out the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[dharmas]] of [[Buddhist philosophy]]: [[dharmas]] are basic and impartite constituents of [[reality]], the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] reals or {{Wiki|ontologically}} grounded [[existents]]. Keown [[thinks]] that the nearest to a {{Wiki|theoretical}} approach to [[moral]] [[philosophy]] within the [[Buddhist ethics]] is found in the [[abhidharma]] and therefore it is worth the [[attention]] to its analytic framework. He rejects King’s notion that [[abhidharmic]] [[ethical]] {{Wiki|theory}} is meaningless and confounding for the {{Wiki|western}} [[mind]] with its maze of [[Buddhist]] [[psychological]] {{Wiki|terminology}} (Keown, 1992, 59). Keown argues that the difficulty of {{Wiki|terminology}} cannot be good enough a [[reason]] to ignore what this [[tradition]] offers and sheds light on the [[nature]] of [[Buddhist ethics]]. He holds that [[abhidharmic]] [[ethical]] classifications are “readily intelligible” in terms of the one of the oldest and most influential [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] in {{Wiki|western}} [[ethics]], namely – the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[virtues]] (59). According to [[abhidharma]], [[enlightenment]] is achieved through purifying the personal {{Wiki|continuum}} ([[santana]]) of all [[defilements]] ([[klesa]]). So in the taxonomical [[traditions]] of the [[mind]] and [[mental states]]; in case of [[Theravada tradition]], there are fifty-two different types of [[mental states]] or qualities and without [[understanding]] the [[ethical]] functions of these states; it is impossible to provide an analysis of [[sila]] at its most basic level. In [[Sarvastivada]] [[tradition]], there are seventy-five [[dharmas]] and of which forty-seven are of [[psychological]] [[nature]]. Despite the variations in detail all schools [[acknowledge]] a similar classificatory rubrics, and the standard {{Wiki|classification}} is four-fold: {{Wiki|matter}} ([[rupa]]), [[mind]] ([[citta]]), [[mental states]] ([[caitta]]) and the [[unconditioned]] ([[nirvana]]). Only a third of these are related to [[ethics]], which falls under the third category and its [[relation]] to the fourth. [[Citta]] is the center of subjective [[consciousness]], which is viewed as an arsenal or storage of dispositional properties that take its [[form]] in [[mental]] predispositions. “It is the personal [[psychological]] factor responsible for the {{Wiki|unity}} and continuity of the [[human being]] (61)”. Keown point out that one important conclusion to be made from the [[abhidharma]] is that [[Buddhist ethics]] is {{Wiki|naturalistic}}. Why? Because the [[abhidharmic]] analysis of vices and [[virtues]] – since there are [[dharmas]] – are [[objective]] and real. They are not part of our [[mental]] construction, but are actually found within the [[Wikipedia:Psyche (psychology)|psyche]] (64). Now, the implication of this objectivisation is what [[Buddhist ethics]] necessarily rules out {{Wiki|relativism}}: what is ultimately good or bad is not determined by accidental factors but grounded in [[human nature]]. The dharma-theory of [[abhidharma]] commands its authority on the [[nature]] of [[human]] [[mind]] and [[mental phenomena]] within which [[ethics]] resides.
+
        [[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown]] finds it important to distinguish [[moral]] [[virtues]] as opposed to [[intellectual]] [[virtues]] to the study of {{Wiki|concept}} of [[virtues]] in general, because [[virtues]] or vices may be either [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] or non-cognitive. And he proceeds to do so though he designates chapter eight as where he engages with this in detail (64). The {{Wiki|distinction}} he makes clear as [[intellectual]] vice is a [[form]] of [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] error” such as [[delusion]] or [[moha]], while [[moral]] vices [[forms]] of non-cognitive errors such [[craving]] and [[hatred]]. However, [[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown]] acknowledges about the difficulties of {{Wiki|distinction}} between the affective and the [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] in [[Buddhist psychology]], because [[cognition]] and [[feeling]] are {{Wiki|mental processes}} dependent on [[citta]]. The exact [[nature]] of their relationship ([[Vedana]] vs. [[Sanna]]) is troublesome (67).  
  
        Keown finds it important to distinguish [[moral]] [[virtues]] as opposed to [[intellectual]] [[virtues]] to the study of {{Wiki|concept}} of [[virtues]] in general, because [[virtues]] or vices may be either [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] or non-cognitive. And he proceeds to do so though he designates chapter eight as where he engages with this in detail (64). The {{Wiki|distinction}} he makes clear as [[intellectual]] vice is a [[form]] of “[[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] error” such as [[delusion]] or [[moha]], while [[moral]] vices [[forms]] of non-cognitive errors such [[craving]] and [[hatred]]. However, Keown acknowledges about the difficulties of {{Wiki|distinction}} between the affective and the [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] in [[Buddhist psychology]], because [[cognition]] and [[feeling]] are {{Wiki|mental processes}} dependent on [[citta]]. The exact [[nature]] of their relationship ([[Vedana]] vs. [[Sanna]]) is troublesome (67). Keown draws on {{Wiki|western}} thinkers to see how the [[debate]] between [[moral]] and [[emotions]] has taken its route in the [[west]], but argues that, contrary to {{Wiki|Socrates}} ([[virtue]] is reducible to [[knowledge]]) and general [[belief]] about [[Buddhism]], he posits that neither of the two: [[sila]] or [[panna]] are reducible to one another (72). Keown’s posits that the approach of reason-emotion bifurcation is artificial and seeks a “[[middle-way]]” between them. And that is the {{Wiki|Aristotelian}} [[tradition]] that he finds most congenial to [[Buddhist ethics]], i.e. they both [[view]] that [[reason]] and [[emotion]] are complementary rather than disjunctive (72). Keown doesn’t address this in detail here as reserves a whole chapter on that latter in the [[book]], but it seems plausible to say that [[virtue]] [[ethics]] is nearest to [[Buddhist ethics]]. However, from a [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|perspective}}, even though the conclusions might look similar and somewhat compatible, the arguments leading to that conclusion may differ greatly: for instance, the assumptions about the [[nature of mind]] and [[human]] [[condition]] etc.
+
[[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown]] draws on {{Wiki|western}} thinkers to see how the [[debate]] between [[moral]] and [[emotions]] has taken its route in the [[west]], but argues that, contrary to {{Wiki|Socrates}} ([[virtue]] is reducible to [[knowledge]]) and general [[belief]] about [[Buddhism]], he posits that neither of the two: [[sila]] or [[panna]] are reducible to one another (72). [[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown’s]]  posits that the approach of reason-emotion bifurcation is artificial and seeks a “[[middle-way]]” between them. And that is the {{Wiki|Aristotelian}} [[tradition]] that he finds most congenial to [[Buddhist ethics]], i.e. they both [[view]] that [[reason]] and [[emotion]] are complementary rather than disjunctive (72). [[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown]] doesn’t address this in detail here as reserves a whole chapter on that latter in the [[book]], but it seems plausible to say that [[virtue]] [[ethics]] is nearest to [[Buddhist ethics]]. However, from a [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|perspective}}, even though the conclusions might look similar and somewhat compatible, the arguments leading to that conclusion may differ greatly: for instance, the assumptions about the [[nature of mind]] and [[human]] [[condition]] etc.
  
Note: [Chapter four addresses on the [[subject]] of transcendency {{Wiki|hypothesis}} by [[King]] and Spiro to which Keown responses by arguing that the Raft [[Parable]] they are employing meant to prove or support their point about the position, their anthropological studies in [[Burma]] on Karmmatic and [[Nirvanic]] [[Buddhism]] is confounding. Keown tries to discredit their claim by arguing that [[sila]] and [[panna]] are [[essential]] in post-enlightenment [[existence]], that they are not disassociated. I will address this raft [[parable]] in detail with Keown's detailed [[exposition]] on the entangled [[nature]] of projna and [[karuna]] later. Chapter five follows on the same line about the role of [[ethics]] in [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|soteriological}} program as we discussed in the last meeting, “[[Nirvana]] and the [[Path]] lie in the same {{Wiki|continuum}}”. ]
+
Note: [Chapter four addresses on the [[subject]] of transcendency {{Wiki|hypothesis}} by [[King]] and Spiro to which [[Wikipedia:Keown |Keown]] responses by arguing that the Raft [[Parable]] they are employing meant to prove or support their point about the position, their anthropological studies in [[Burma]] on [[Karmmatic]] and [[Nirvanic]] [[Buddhism]] is confounding. [[Wikipedia:KDamien Keown|Keown]] tries to discredit their claim by arguing that [[sila]] and [[panna]] are [[essential]] in post-enlightenment [[existence]], that they are not disassociated. I will address this raft [[parable]] in detail with [[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown's]] detailed [[exposition]] on the entangled [[nature]] of [[prajna]] and [[karuna]] later. Chapter five follows on the same line about the role of [[ethics]] in [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|soteriological}} program as we discussed in the last meeting, “[[Nirvana]] and the [[Path]] lie in the same {{Wiki|continuum}}”. ]
  
 
  Works Cited
 
  Works Cited
  
Keown, Damien.
+
[[Wikipedia:Damien Keown|Keown, Damien]][[Wikipedia:|]].
  
 
     1992 The [[Nature]] of [[Buddhist Ethics]], {{Wiki|New York}}, Palgrave.  
 
     1992 The [[Nature]] of [[Buddhist Ethics]], {{Wiki|New York}}, Palgrave.  

Revision as of 09:19, 10 July 2014

14 vx.jpg
Ksitigarbha-es30.jpg
E486ab78 z.jpg
101nm1933 n.jpg

 Part 2. Reflections and notes on Damien Keown's The Nature of Buddhist Ethics, 1992.

Scholars have analyzed, contested and debated about the relationship between ethics and psychology and in many cases with reference to Abhidharma or Buddhist scholasticism. In terms of Buddhist psychology, the fundamental cause of suffering in life or living this “samsaric life” can be said precisely as the need to purify the mind (citta) whose real essence is pure but it is been contaminated by all sorts of different mental states (caitta) and destructive emotions (Keown, 1992, 57). the abhidharmic literature, it lies out the theory of dharmas of Buddhist philosophy: dharmas are basic and impartite constituents of reality, the ultimate reals or ontologically grounded existents.

Keown thinks that the nearest to a theoretical approach to moral philosophy within the Buddhist ethics is found in the abhidharma and therefore it is worth the attention to its analytic framework. He rejects King’s notion that abhidharmic ethical theory is meaningless and confounding for the western mind with its maze of Buddhist psychological terminology (Keown, 1992, 59). Keown argues that the difficulty of terminology cannot be good enough a reason to ignore what this tradition offers and sheds light on the nature of Buddhist ethics. He holds that abhidharmic ethical classifications are “readily intelligible” in terms of the one of the oldest and most influential concepts in western ethics, namely – the concept of virtues (59). According to abhidharma, enlightenment is achieved through purifying the personal continuum (santana) of all defilements (klesa).

So in the taxonomical traditions of the mind and mental states; in case of Theravada tradition, there are fifty-two different types of mental states or qualities and without understanding the ethical functions of these states; it is impossible to provide an analysis of sila at its most basic level. In Sarvastivada tradition, there are seventy-five dharmas and of which forty-seven are of psychological nature. Despite the variations in detail all schools acknowledge a similar classificatory rubrics, and the standard classification is four-fold: matter (rupa), mind (citta), mental states (caitta) and the unconditioned (nirvana). Only a third of these are related to ethics, which falls under the third category and its relation to the fourth. Citta is the center of subjective consciousness, which is viewed as an arsenal or storage of dispositional properties that take its form in mental predispositions. “It is the personal psychological factor responsible for the unity and continuity of the human being (61)”.

Keown point out that one important conclusion to be made from the abhidharma is that Buddhist ethics is naturalistic. Why? Because the abhidharmic analysis of vices and virtues – since there are dharmas – are objective and real. They are not part of our mental construction, but are actually found within the psyche (64). Now, the implication of this objectivisation is what Buddhist ethics necessarily rules out relativism: what is ultimately good or bad is not determined by accidental factors but grounded in human nature. The dharma-theory of abhidharma commands its authority on the nature of human mind and mental phenomena within which ethics resides.

         Keown finds it important to distinguish moral virtues as opposed to intellectual virtues to the study of concept of virtues in general, because virtues or vices may be either cognitive or non-cognitive. And he proceeds to do so though he designates chapter eight as where he engages with this in detail (64). The distinction he makes clear as intellectual vice is a form of “cognitive error” such as delusion or moha, while moral vices forms of non-cognitive errors such craving and hatred. However, Keown acknowledges about the difficulties of distinction between the affective and the cognitive in Buddhist psychology, because cognition and feeling are mental processes dependent on citta. The exact nature of their relationship (Vedana vs. Sanna) is troublesome (67).

Keown draws on western thinkers to see how the debate between moral and emotions has taken its route in the west, but argues that, contrary to Socrates (virtue is reducible to knowledge) and general belief about Buddhism, he posits that neither of the two: sila or panna are reducible to one another (72). Keown’s posits that the approach of reason-emotion bifurcation is artificial and seeks a “middle-way” between them. And that is the Aristotelian tradition that he finds most congenial to Buddhist ethics, i.e. they both view that reason and emotion are complementary rather than disjunctive (72). Keown doesn’t address this in detail here as reserves a whole chapter on that latter in the book, but it seems plausible to say that virtue ethics is nearest to Buddhist ethics. However, from a Buddhist perspective, even though the conclusions might look similar and somewhat compatible, the arguments leading to that conclusion may differ greatly: for instance, the assumptions about the nature of mind and human condition etc.

Note: [Chapter four addresses on the subject of transcendency hypothesis by King and Spiro to which Keown responses by arguing that the Raft Parable they are employing meant to prove or support their point about the position, their anthropological studies in Burma on Karmmatic and Nirvanic Buddhism is confounding. Keown tries to discredit their claim by arguing that sila and panna are essential in post-enlightenment existence, that they are not disassociated. I will address this raft parable in detail with Keown's detailed exposition on the entangled nature of prajna and karuna later. Chapter five follows on the same line about the role of ethics in Buddhist soteriological program as we discussed in the last meeting, “Nirvana and the Path lie in the same continuum”. ]

 Works Cited

Keown, Damien[[Wikipedia:|]].

    1992 The Nature of Buddhist Ethics, New York, Palgrave.

Source