Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Buddhist Philosophy and Its European Parallels"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
Line 8: Line 8:
 
The search for [[philosophical]] parallels is fraught with pit-falls. Some parallels are fruitful and significant, others incidental and fortuitous. I now propose to discuss the {{Wiki|European}} parallels to [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] in two articles, of which the first is devoted to the true, and the second to the spurious, parallels.
 
The search for [[philosophical]] parallels is fraught with pit-falls. Some parallels are fruitful and significant, others incidental and fortuitous. I now propose to discuss the {{Wiki|European}} parallels to [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] in two articles, of which the first is devoted to the true, and the second to the spurious, parallels.
  
As for my interpretation of the basic principles of [[Buddhism]], I have recently given it in some detail in [[Buddhist]] [[Thought]] in India.(1) Since my [[views]] differ to some extent from those of my predecessors, I will briefly sum them up so that the reader can see what kind of "[[Buddhism]]" I compare with {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophy]].
+
As for my interpretation of the basic {{Wiki|principles}} of [[Buddhism]], I have recently given it in some detail in [[Buddhist]] [[Thought]] in India.(1) Since my [[views]] differ to some extent from those of my predecessors, I will briefly sum them up so that the reader can see what kind of "[[Buddhism]]" I compare with {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophy]].
  
The basic [[teaching of the Buddha]] can be expressed in one sentence: The [[conditioned]] [[world]] as it appears to us is fundamentally and irreparably undesirable, and {{Wiki|salvation}} can be found only through escape to the [[Unconditioned]], also called "Nirvaa.na." Everything else is elaboration.
+
The basic [[teaching of the Buddha]] can be expressed in one sentence: The [[conditioned]] [[world]] as it appears to us is fundamentally and irreparably undesirable, and {{Wiki|salvation}} can be found only through escape to the [[Unconditioned]], also called "Nirvaa.na." Everything else is [[elaboration]].
  
 
All [[conditioned things]] are marred by having three "marks, " i.e., by being [[impermanent]], "ill," and "alien to our true self."(2) Much [[thought]] has gone into determining the full meaning of those marks. "Ill," for instance, comprises not only [[pain]] and [[suffering]], but also the unease which is nowadays known as "existential anxiety,"(3) and the mark of "{{Wiki|not-self}}" has given rise to interminable discussions.(4) [[Human beings]] fret against a [[world]] which is [[impermanent]], ill, and {{Wiki|not-self}} and are not content to live in it, because they believe that in the core of their own being they are [[eternal]], at ease, and in full control of everything.(5) This alienation of our [[empirical]] [[personality]] from our true being (i.e., from the "[[Tathaagata]]" within us(6) )is brought about by "craving."(7)
 
All [[conditioned things]] are marred by having three "marks, " i.e., by being [[impermanent]], "ill," and "alien to our true self."(2) Much [[thought]] has gone into determining the full meaning of those marks. "Ill," for instance, comprises not only [[pain]] and [[suffering]], but also the unease which is nowadays known as "existential anxiety,"(3) and the mark of "{{Wiki|not-self}}" has given rise to interminable discussions.(4) [[Human beings]] fret against a [[world]] which is [[impermanent]], ill, and {{Wiki|not-self}} and are not content to live in it, because they believe that in the core of their own being they are [[eternal]], at ease, and in full control of everything.(5) This alienation of our [[empirical]] [[personality]] from our true being (i.e., from the "[[Tathaagata]]" within us(6) )is brought about by "craving."(7)
  
If we want to return to our original state of [[purity]], we must first regenerate ourselves by developing five cardinal virtues,(8) of which [[wisdom]] is the last and most important. After these [[virtues]] have sufficiently matured, we can slowly attempt a break-through to the Unconditioned,(9) which, through the [[three doors]] of [[deliverance]], i.e., [[Emptiness]], the [[Signless]], and the Wishless,(10) leads to Nirvaa.na,(11) which is a state in which the [[self]] has become [[extinct]], in which none of this [[world]] is any longer extant, and which therefore transcends all words and concepts.(12) This is all quite simple to understand, though at times hard to believe. It is very much complicated, however, by being combined with an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|theory}} of "[[Dharma]]" which requires a tremendous [[intellectual]] effort.(13) This {{Wiki|theory}} distinguishes three levels of [[reality]]: [1] the one and single [[Dharma]], which is the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] and [[unconditioned reality]] of Nirvaa.na;[2] a multiplicity of [[dharmas]], or momentary and impersonal events, which, though [[illusory]] compared with the one single Dharma,(14) are more real than the things around us; and [3] the things of the {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[world]], which are mere [[verbal]] constructions, in that they are combinations of [[dharmas]] held together by words.(15) The [[Buddhist]] "dharma-theory is unique, and has no exact {{Wiki|equivalent}} anywhere else.(16)
+
If we want to return to our original state of [[purity]], we must first regenerate ourselves by developing five cardinal virtues,(8) of which [[wisdom]] is the last and most important. After these [[virtues]] have sufficiently matured, we can slowly attempt a break-through to the Unconditioned,(9) which, through the [[three doors]] of [[deliverance]], i.e., [[Emptiness]], the [[Signless]], and the Wishless,(10) leads to Nirvaa.na,(11) which is a state in which the [[self]] has become [[extinct]], in which none of this [[world]] is any longer extant, and which therefore {{Wiki|transcends}} all words and concepts.(12) This is all quite simple to understand, though at times hard to believe. It is very much complicated, however, by being combined with an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|theory}} of "[[Dharma]]" which requires a tremendous [[intellectual]] effort.(13) This {{Wiki|theory}} distinguishes three levels of [[reality]]: [1] the one and single [[Dharma]], which is the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] and [[unconditioned reality]] of Nirvaa.na;[2] a multiplicity of [[dharmas]], or momentary and {{Wiki|impersonal}} events, which, though [[illusory]] compared with the one single Dharma,(14) are more real than the things around us; and [3] the things of the {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[world]], which are mere [[verbal]] constructions, in that they are combinations of [[dharmas]] held together by words.(15) The [[Buddhist]] "dharma-theory is unique, and has no exact {{Wiki|equivalent}} anywhere else.(16)
  
So much for the {{Wiki|tenets}} of what I call "{{Wiki|archaic}}" [[Buddhism]]. They were probably formulated by the [[time]] of A'soka.(16a) Two centuries later the further elaboration of these [[ideas]] led to two {{Wiki|distinct}} schools, i.e., the "{{Wiki|scholastic}} [[Hiinayaana]]" and the "[[Mahaayaana]]," which, contrary to what is often said, did not significantly conflict in their [[doctrines]] but merely diverged in their range of [[interest]]. The "{{Wiki|scholastic}} [[Hiinayaana]]" [[concentrated]] on the [[conditioned]] [[dharmas]], systematized their {{Wiki|classification}}, defined more precisely their particular [[attributes]] and general marks, and worked out the relations pertaining among them.(18) The creative contributions of the [[Mahaayaana]], on the other hand, almost exclusively [[concern]] the [[Unconditioned]]. In particular, the notion of "[[Emptiness]]," which in "{{Wiki|archaic}}" [[Buddhism]] had been one of the avenues to Nirvaa.na, was now immensely enriched.(19) It was also buttressed by a searching analysis of the [[traditional]] {{Wiki|concept}} of the "[[own-being]]" of dharmas(20) and by a type of [[logic]] which in {{Wiki|Europe}} we would call "dialectical."(21) Equally applied to [[conditioned]] and [[unconditioned]] [[dharmas]], "[[emptiness]]" led to their identification. The result is a "monistic" {{Wiki|ontology}} which shows many analogies to {{Wiki|European}} [[metaphysical]] systems of the same type,(22) while the descriptions of the bafflement [[experienced]] by the {{Wiki|intellect}} when confronted with this one and unique [[Absolute]] resemble the position of the {{Wiki|Greek}} skeptics in many ways.(23)
+
So much for the {{Wiki|tenets}} of what I call "{{Wiki|archaic}}" [[Buddhism]]. They were probably formulated by the [[time]] of A'soka.(16a) Two centuries later the further [[elaboration]] of these [[ideas]] led to two {{Wiki|distinct}} schools, i.e., the "{{Wiki|scholastic}} [[Hiinayaana]]" and the "[[Mahaayaana]]," which, contrary to what is often said, did not significantly conflict in their [[doctrines]] but merely diverged in their range of [[interest]]. The "{{Wiki|scholastic}} [[Hiinayaana]]" [[concentrated]] on the [[conditioned]] [[dharmas]], systematized their {{Wiki|classification}}, defined more precisely their particular [[attributes]] and general marks, and worked out the relations pertaining among them.(18) The creative contributions of the [[Mahaayaana]], on the other hand, almost exclusively [[concern]] the [[Unconditioned]]. In particular, the notion of "[[Emptiness]]," which in "{{Wiki|archaic}}" [[Buddhism]] had been one of the avenues to Nirvaa.na, was now immensely enriched.(19) It was also buttressed by a searching analysis of the [[traditional]] {{Wiki|concept}} of the "[[own-being]]" of dharmas(20) and by a type of [[logic]] which in {{Wiki|Europe}} we would call "dialectical."(21) Equally applied to [[conditioned]] and [[unconditioned]] [[dharmas]], "[[emptiness]]" led to their identification. The result is a "{{Wiki|monistic}}" {{Wiki|ontology}} which shows many analogies to {{Wiki|European}} [[metaphysical]] systems of the same type,(22) while the descriptions of the bafflement [[experienced]] by the {{Wiki|intellect}} when confronted with this one and unique [[Absolute]] resemble the position of the {{Wiki|Greek}} skeptics in many ways.(23)
  
Of special [[interest]] for the theme of these articles is the chapter on "Tacit Assumptions,"(24) in which I compare [[Buddhist]] with contemporary [[mentality]], and try to establish that [[Buddhist]] thinkers made a number of tacit assumptions which are explicitly rejected by {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophers]]. The first, common to nearly all [[Indian]], as {{Wiki|distinct}} from {{Wiki|European}}, "[[scientific]]," [[thought]] treats the [[experiences]] of [[Yoga]] as the chief raw material for [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|reflection}}. Secondly, all "perennial"(25) (as against "{{Wiki|modern}}") [[philosophers]], agree on the hierarchical structure of the [[universe]], as shown in (a) the {{Wiki|distinction}} of a "triple [[world]]" and (b) of degrees of "[[reality]]," and (c) in the establishment of a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} of [[insights]] dependent on [[spiritual]] maturity. Thirdly, all [[religious]] (as against a-religious) [[philosophies]] (a) use "numinous" as {{Wiki|distinct}} from "profane" terms, and (b) treat [[revelation]] as the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] source of all valid knowledge.(26)
+
Of special [[interest]] for the theme of these articles is the [[chapter]] on "Tacit Assumptions,"(24) in which I compare [[Buddhist]] with contemporary [[mentality]], and try to establish that [[Buddhist]] thinkers made a number of tacit {{Wiki|assumptions}} which are explicitly rejected by {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophers]]. The first, common to nearly all [[Indian]], as {{Wiki|distinct}} from {{Wiki|European}}, "[[scientific]]," [[thought]] treats the [[experiences]] of [[Yoga]] as the chief raw material for [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|reflection}}. Secondly, all "perennial"(25) (as against "{{Wiki|modern}}") [[philosophers]], agree on the hierarchical {{Wiki|structure}} of the [[universe]], as shown in (a) the {{Wiki|distinction}} of a "triple [[world]]" and (b) of degrees of "[[reality]]," and (c) in the establishment of a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} of [[insights]] dependent on [[spiritual]] maturity. Thirdly, all [[religious]] (as against a-religious) [[philosophies]] (a) use "numinous" as {{Wiki|distinct}} from "profane" terms, and (b) treat [[revelation]] as the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] source of all valid knowledge.(26)
  
 
This is not how everyone sees it, and the doubting reader must be referred to the arguments of my [[book]].
 
This is not how everyone sees it, and the doubting reader must be referred to the arguments of my [[book]].
  
The cornerstone of my interpretation of [[Buddhism]] is the conviction shared by nearly everyone, that it is [[essentially]] a [[doctrine]] of {{Wiki|salvation}}, and that all its [[philosophical]] statements are subordinate to its {{Wiki|soteriological}} purpose. This implies, not only that many [[philosophical]] problems are dismissed as idle speculations,(27) but that each and every proposition must be considered in reference to its spiritual(28) [[intention]] and as a formulation of [[meditational]] [[experiences]] acquired in the course of the process of winning {{Wiki|salvation}}. While I cannot [[imagine]] any [[scholar]] wishing to challenge this {{Wiki|methodological}} postulate, I am {{Wiki|aware}} that, next to {{Wiki|D. T. Suzuki}}, I am almost alone in having applied it consistently.
+
The cornerstone of my interpretation of [[Buddhism]] is the conviction shared by nearly everyone, that it is [[essentially]] a [[doctrine]] of {{Wiki|salvation}}, and that all its [[philosophical]] statements are subordinate to its {{Wiki|soteriological}} {{Wiki|purpose}}. This implies, not only that many [[philosophical]] problems are dismissed as idle speculations,(27) but that each and every proposition must be considered in reference to its spiritual(28) [[intention]] and as a formulation of [[meditational]] [[experiences]] acquired in the course of the process of winning {{Wiki|salvation}}. While I cannot [[imagine]] any [[scholar]] wishing to challenge this {{Wiki|methodological}} postulate, I am {{Wiki|aware}} that, next to {{Wiki|D. T. Suzuki}}, I am almost alone in having applied it consistently.
  
Finally, any interpretation of [[Buddhism]] which goes beyond the indiscriminate [[accumulation]] of quotations and attempts actual1y to understand [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] involves an [[element]] of choice, in that one has to decide which one among the numerous presentations of the [[Buddha's]] [[doctrine]] should be regarded as the most [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]]. [[Buston]] favors the Buddhisn of the Paala period, Frauwallner the [[Yogaacaarins]], [[Oldenberg]] the Palii [[Canon]] (minus the [[Abhidhamma]]), [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] the {{Wiki|scholastic}} [[Hiinayaana]] and the later [[logicians]], {{Wiki|D. T. Suzuki}} the early [[Mahaayaana]] and [[Zen]], some {{Wiki|Chinese}} schools the Saddharmapu.n.dariika, and so on. With {{Wiki|Professor}} [[Murti]], I regard the [[Maadhyamikas]] as representing the central [[tradition]] of [[Buddhism]], and believe that with them [[Buddhist]] theorizing reached its full maturity. This preference colors much of what I have to say.
+
Finally, any interpretation of [[Buddhism]] which goes beyond the indiscriminate [[accumulation]] of quotations and attempts actual1y to understand [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] involves an [[element]] of choice, in that one has to decide which one among the numerous presentations of the [[Buddha's]] [[doctrine]] should be regarded as the most [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]]. [[Buston]] favors the Buddhisn of the Paala period, {{Wiki|Frauwallner}} the [[Yogaacaarins]], [[Oldenberg]] the Palii [[Canon]] (minus the [[Abhidhamma]]), [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] the {{Wiki|scholastic}} [[Hiinayaana]] and the later [[logicians]], {{Wiki|D. T. Suzuki}} the early [[Mahaayaana]] and [[Zen]], some {{Wiki|Chinese}} schools the Saddharmapu.n.dariika, and so on. With {{Wiki|Professor}} [[Murti]], I regard the [[Maadhyamikas]] as representing the central [[tradition]] of [[Buddhism]], and believe that with them [[Buddhist]] theorizing reached its full maturity. This preference colors much of what I have to say.
  
What, then, is the [[relation]] of these [[Buddhist teachings]] to {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophy]]? From the outset, I must admit that I do not believe in a clear-cut {{Wiki|distinction}} between "Eastern" and "{{Wiki|Western}}" [[mentality]]. Until about 1450, as branches of the same "[[perennial]] [[philosophy]], "(29) [[Indian]] and {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophers]] disagreed less among themselves than with many of the later developments of {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophy]]. The "[[perennial]] [[philosophy]]" is in this context defined as a [[doctrine]] which holds [1] that as far as worth-while [[knowledge]] is concerned not all men are {{Wiki|equal}}, but that there is a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} of persons, some of whom, through what they are, can know much more than others; [2] that there is a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} also of the levels of [[reality]], some of which are more "real," because more [[exalted]] than others; and [3] that the [[wise]] men of old have found a "[[wisdom]]" which is true, although it has no "[[empirical]]" basis in observations which can be made by everyone and everybody; and that in fact there is a rare and unordinary {{Wiki|faculty}} in some of us by which we can attain direct [[contact]] with actual reality--through the praj~naa (paaramitaa) of the [[Buddhists]], the {{Wiki|logos}} of Parmenides,(30) the sophia of Aristotle(31) and others, Spinoza's amor dei intellectualis, Hegel's Vernunft, and so on; and [4] that [[true teaching]] is based on an authority which legitimizes itself by the exemplary [[life]] and {{Wiki|charismatic}} quality of its exponents.
+
What, then, is the [[relation]] of these [[Buddhist teachings]] to {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophy]]? From the outset, I must admit that I do not believe in a clear-cut {{Wiki|distinction}} between "Eastern" and "{{Wiki|Western}}" [[mentality]]. Until about 1450, as branches of the same "[[perennial]] [[philosophy]], "(29) [[Indian]] and {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophers]] disagreed less among themselves than with many of the later developments of {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophy]]. The "[[perennial]] [[philosophy]]" is in this context defined as a [[doctrine]] which holds [1] that as far as worth-while [[knowledge]] is concerned not all men are {{Wiki|equal}}, but that there is a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} of persons, some of whom, through what they are, can know much more than others; [2] that there is a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} also of the levels of [[reality]], some of which are more "real," because more [[exalted]] than others; and [3] that the [[wise]] men of old have found a "[[wisdom]]" which is true, although it has no "[[empirical]]" basis in observations which can be made by everyone and everybody; and that in fact there is a rare and unordinary {{Wiki|faculty}} in some of us by which we can attain direct [[contact]] with actual reality--through the [[praj~naa]] (paaramitaa) of the [[Buddhists]], the {{Wiki|logos}} of Parmenides,(30) the [[sophia]] of Aristotle(31) and others, Spinoza's amor dei intellectualis, Hegel's Vernunft, and so on; and [4] that [[true teaching]] is based on an authority which legitimizes itself by the exemplary [[life]] and {{Wiki|charismatic}} quality of its exponents.
  
Within the [[perennial]] [[philosophy]] [[Indian]] [[thought]] is marked off by two special features: [1] the reliance on [[yoga]] as providing the basic raw material of worth-while experience,(32) and [2] the implicit [[belief]] in [[karma and rebirth]]. [[Yoga]], of course, has its counterpart in the [[West]] in the [[spiritual]] and ecstatic practices of contemplatives, and [[belief]] in [[reincarnation]] is nearly world-wide,(33) though rare among [[philosophers]] accorded {{Wiki|academic}} [[recognition]].
+
Within the [[perennial]] [[philosophy]] [[Indian]] [[thought]] is marked off by two special features: [1] the reliance on [[yoga]] as providing the basic raw material of worth-while experience,(32) and [2] the implicit [[belief]] in [[karma and rebirth]]. [[Yoga]], of course, has its counterpart in the [[West]] in the [[spiritual]] and {{Wiki|ecstatic}} practices of contemplatives, and [[belief]] in [[reincarnation]] is nearly world-wide,(33) though rare among [[philosophers]] accorded {{Wiki|academic}} [[recognition]].
  
Then, after 1450, the [[East]] fell asleep and lived on its inherited capital, until in the end innate {{Wiki|lethargy}} and [[aggression]] from the outside brought it to its {{Wiki|present}} impasse. In the [[West]], a large number of [[philosophers]] discarded the basic presuppositions of the "[[perennial]] [[philosophy]]," and developed by contrast what for want of a better term we may call a "sciential"(34) [[philosophy]]. That has the following features: [1] Natural [[science]], particularly that dealing with [[inorganic]] {{Wiki|matter}}, has a [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] value, tells us about the actual structure of the [[universe]], and provides the other branches of [[knowledge]] with an {{Wiki|ideal}} standard in that they are the more "[[scientific]]" the more they are capable of {{Wiki|mathematical}} formulation and the more they rely on repeatable and publicly verified observations. [2] Man is the [[highest]] of [[beings]] known to [[science]], and his power and convenience should be promoted at all costs. [3] [[Spiritual]] and [[magical]] forces cannot influence events, and [[life]] after [[death]] may be disregarded, because it is unproven by [[scientific]] methods. [4] In consequence, "[[life]]" means "man's" [[life]] in this [[world]], and the task is to ameliorate this [[life]] by a {{Wiki|social}} "technique" in [[harmony]] with the "{{Wiki|welfare}}" or "will" of "the [[people]]." [[Buddhists]] must [[view]] all these {{Wiki|tenets}} with the utmost distaste.
+
Then, after 1450, the [[East]] fell asleep and lived on its inherited capital, until in the end innate {{Wiki|lethargy}} and [[aggression]] from the outside brought it to its {{Wiki|present}} impasse. In the [[West]], a large number of [[philosophers]] discarded the basic presuppositions of the "[[perennial]] [[philosophy]]," and developed by contrast what for want of a better term we may call a "sciential"(34) [[philosophy]]. That has the following features: [1] Natural [[science]], particularly that dealing with [[inorganic]] {{Wiki|matter}}, has a [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] value, tells us about the actual {{Wiki|structure}} of the [[universe]], and provides the other branches of [[knowledge]] with an {{Wiki|ideal}} standard in that they are the more "[[scientific]]" the more they are capable of {{Wiki|mathematical}} formulation and the more they rely on repeatable and publicly verified observations. [2] Man is the [[highest]] of [[beings]] known to [[science]], and his power and convenience should be promoted at all costs. [3] [[Spiritual]] and [[magical]] forces cannot influence events, and [[life]] after [[death]] may be disregarded, because it is unproven by [[scientific]] methods. [4] In consequence, "[[life]]" means "man's" [[life]] in this [[world]], and the task is to ameliorate this [[life]] by a {{Wiki|social}} "technique" in [[harmony]] with the "{{Wiki|welfare}}" or "will" of "the [[people]]." [[Buddhists]] must [[view]] all these {{Wiki|tenets}} with the utmost distaste.
  
 
"Sciential" [[philosophy]] is an ideology which corresponds to a technological {{Wiki|civilization}}. It arises in its [[purity]] only to the extent that its {{Wiki|social}} [[substratum]] has freed itself from all pre-industrial [[influences]], and in the end it must lead to the elimination of even the last traces of what could properly be called "[[philosophy]]" in the original [[sense]] of "[[love]] of [[wisdom]]." For centuries it existed only blended with [[elements]] from the [[traditional]] "[[perennial]]" [[philosophy]]. As [[philosophies]], both the "[[perennial]]" and the "sciential" systems possess some [[degree]] of intellectuality, and up to a point they both use {{Wiki|reasoning}}. But considered in their [[purity]], as {{Wiki|ideal}} types, they differ in that the first is motivated by man's spiritual(35) needs, and aims at his {{Wiki|salvation}} from the [[world]] and its ways, whereas the second is motivated by his utilitarian needs, aims at his conquest of the [[world]], and is therefore greatly concerned with the natural and {{Wiki|social sciences}}. Between the [[two extremes]] there are, of course, numerous intermediary stages. They depend to some extent on the quality of the [[spirituality]] behind them, which is very high, say, in [[Buddhism]], slightly lower in {{Wiki|Plato}} and {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, and still quite marked in such men as {{Wiki|Spinoza}}, {{Wiki|Leibniz}}, {{Wiki|Berkeley}}, {{Wiki|Kant}}, Goethe, [[Hegel]], and Bergson. The general trend, however, has been a continuous loss of [[spiritual]] [[substance]] between 1450 and 1960, based on an increasing [[forgetfulness]] of age-old [[traditions]], an increasing unawareness of [[spiritual]] practices, and an increasing [[indifference]] to the [[spiritual]] [[life]] by the classes which dominate {{Wiki|society}}.
 
"Sciential" [[philosophy]] is an ideology which corresponds to a technological {{Wiki|civilization}}. It arises in its [[purity]] only to the extent that its {{Wiki|social}} [[substratum]] has freed itself from all pre-industrial [[influences]], and in the end it must lead to the elimination of even the last traces of what could properly be called "[[philosophy]]" in the original [[sense]] of "[[love]] of [[wisdom]]." For centuries it existed only blended with [[elements]] from the [[traditional]] "[[perennial]]" [[philosophy]]. As [[philosophies]], both the "[[perennial]]" and the "sciential" systems possess some [[degree]] of intellectuality, and up to a point they both use {{Wiki|reasoning}}. But considered in their [[purity]], as {{Wiki|ideal}} types, they differ in that the first is motivated by man's spiritual(35) needs, and aims at his {{Wiki|salvation}} from the [[world]] and its ways, whereas the second is motivated by his utilitarian needs, aims at his conquest of the [[world]], and is therefore greatly concerned with the natural and {{Wiki|social sciences}}. Between the [[two extremes]] there are, of course, numerous intermediary stages. They depend to some extent on the quality of the [[spirituality]] behind them, which is very high, say, in [[Buddhism]], slightly lower in {{Wiki|Plato}} and {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, and still quite marked in such men as {{Wiki|Spinoza}}, {{Wiki|Leibniz}}, {{Wiki|Berkeley}}, {{Wiki|Kant}}, Goethe, [[Hegel]], and Bergson. The general trend, however, has been a continuous loss of [[spiritual]] [[substance]] between 1450 and 1960, based on an increasing [[forgetfulness]] of age-old [[traditions]], an increasing unawareness of [[spiritual]] practices, and an increasing [[indifference]] to the [[spiritual]] [[life]] by the classes which dominate {{Wiki|society}}.
  
Leaving aside the [[relative]] [[merits]] of the "[[perennial]]" and the "sciential" approaches to [[philosophy]], all I want to establish at {{Wiki|present}} is their mutual incompatibility, which is borne out by their mutual {{Wiki|hostility}}. Our "sciential" [[philosophers]] are well {{Wiki|aware}} of this. We need only peruse the writings of empiricists, [[logical]] positivists, and {{Wiki|linguistic}} analysts, and it will become obvious that the [[animosity]] displayed toward a [[philosopher]] is almost a [[measure]] of his spirituality.(36) And, in a way, the moderns are quite right. For "[[perennial]]" and "sciential" [[philosophies]] represent two qualitatively different kinds of [[thinking]] which have almost nothing in common, except perhaps for a certain [[degree]] of [[respect]] for {{Wiki|rationality}}. Our contemporaries continually assure us that the [[spiritual]] [[philosophers]] of the {{Wiki|past}} are not "[[philosophers]]" at all, but dreamers, {{Wiki|mystics}}, poets, and so on. All we can conclude from this is that the [[word]] "[[philosophy]]" is being used in two quite disparate [[senses]]: [1] as the pursuit of "[[wisdom]]," and [2] as a "rigorous" {{Wiki|academic}} exercise without much ostensible purpose. The "[[wisdom]]" meant here is [[compounded]] of [[knowledge]] and a "good [[life]]," and to it apply the words of Proverbs: "Blessed is the man who has found [[wisdom]]. Her ways are good ways, and all her [[paths]] are [[peaceful]]. She is a [[tree of life]] to all that lay hold upon her."(37) It is not easy to how such words could be used of "[[philosophy]]" in the second [[sense]].
+
Leaving aside the [[relative]] [[merits]] of the "[[perennial]]" and the "sciential" approaches to [[philosophy]], all I want to establish at {{Wiki|present}} is their mutual incompatibility, which is borne out by their mutual {{Wiki|hostility}}. Our "sciential" [[philosophers]] are well {{Wiki|aware}} of this. We need only peruse the writings of empiricists, [[logical]] [[Wikipedia:Positivism|positivists]], and {{Wiki|linguistic}} analysts, and it will become obvious that the [[animosity]] displayed toward a [[philosopher]] is almost a [[measure]] of his spirituality.(36) And, in a way, the moderns are quite right. For "[[perennial]]" and "sciential" [[philosophies]] represent two qualitatively different kinds of [[thinking]] which have almost nothing in common, except perhaps for a certain [[degree]] of [[respect]] for {{Wiki|rationality}}. Our contemporaries continually assure us that the [[spiritual]] [[philosophers]] of the {{Wiki|past}} are not "[[philosophers]]" at all, but dreamers, {{Wiki|mystics}}, poets, and so on. All we can conclude from this is that the [[word]] "[[philosophy]]" is being used in two quite disparate [[senses]]: [1] as the pursuit of "[[wisdom]]," and [2] as a "rigorous" {{Wiki|academic}} exercise without much ostensible {{Wiki|purpose}}. The "[[wisdom]]" meant here is [[compounded]] of [[knowledge]] and a "good [[life]]," and to it apply the words of Proverbs: "Blessed is the man who has found [[wisdom]]. Her ways are good ways, and all her [[paths]] are [[peaceful]]. She is a [[tree of life]] to all that lay hold upon her."(37) It is not easy to how such words could be used of "[[philosophy]]" in the second [[sense]].
  
Having stated the general {{Wiki|principles}} on which the comparison of [[Buddhist]] and {{Wiki|European}} [[thought]] must be based, I now speak of the only three currents of {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophy]] which can significantly be compared with [[Buddhism]], i.e., [1] the {{Wiki|Greek}} Skeptics, [2] the wisdom-seeking {{Wiki|mystics}}, and [3] the monists and dialecticians.
+
Having stated the general {{Wiki|principles}} on which the comparison of [[Buddhist]] and {{Wiki|European}} [[thought]] must be based, I now speak of the only three currents of {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophy]] which can significantly be compared with [[Buddhism]], i.e., [1] the {{Wiki|Greek}} Skeptics, [2] the wisdom-seeking {{Wiki|mystics}}, and [3] the [[Wikipedia:Monism|monists]] and [[Wikipedia:Dialectician|dialecticians]].
  
[1] The {{Wiki|European}} system nearest to the [[Maadhyamikas]] is that of the {{Wiki|Greek}} Skeptics. In my Buddhism,(37a) I have shown their close similarity, both in [[intention]] and structure. They also agree in that the history of {{Wiki|skepticism}} exhibits the same tendency to deviate into a purely {{Wiki|theoretical}} [[intellectualism]] which has continually threatened the integrity of [[Buddhist]] [[thought]]. {{Wiki|Greek}} {{Wiki|Skepticism}} went through four stages, which R. G. Bury(38) has called the practical, the critical, the [[dialectical]], and the [[empirical]]. The parallel with [[Buddhism]] is closest in the first stage, i.e., with Pyrrho (360-275 B.C.).In the last, with Sextus Empiricus (A.D. 160-210), it is barely perceptible. Indeed, taking the later developments as his norm, Bury can affirm that Pyrrho "was probably not at all a full-blown Sceptic, but rather a moralist of an austere and [[ascetic]] type who cultivated insensibility to externals and {{Wiki|superiority}} to environment."(39) It was only in the New {{Wiki|Academy}}, with Arcesilas (315-241 B.C.), that {{Wiki|Skepticism}} "ceased to be purely practical and became mainly theoretical."(40) "Thus, while Pyrrho had renounced and Timon flouted the Dogmatists, Arcesilas started the practice of refuting them {{Wiki|scientifically}} and systematically, and earned thereby the abuse of Timon for his lapse from [[pure]] Pyrrhonism."(41) In fact, when we read Sextus Empiricus, we find that, although some of the original message has remained intact,(42) it has been overlaid by a vast technical apparatus accumulated over five centuries and by numerous concessions to {{Wiki|common sense}}. The bulk of Sextus' work is parasitical on the {{Wiki|dogmatic}} [[philosophers]], and seems to be motivated more by disputatiousness and the [[desire]] to score [[debating]] points than by a positive [[interest]] in [[mental]] [[repose]]. In many ways his [[attitude]] resembles that of the later [[Buddhist logicians]].
+
[1] The {{Wiki|European}} system nearest to the [[Maadhyamikas]] is that of the {{Wiki|Greek}} Skeptics. In my Buddhism,(37a) I have shown their close similarity, both in [[intention]] and {{Wiki|structure}}. They also agree in that the history of {{Wiki|skepticism}} exhibits the same tendency to deviate into a purely {{Wiki|theoretical}} [[intellectualism]] which has continually threatened the integrity of [[Buddhist]] [[thought]]. {{Wiki|Greek}} {{Wiki|Skepticism}} went through four stages, which R. G. Bury(38) has called the {{Wiki|practical}}, the critical, the [[dialectical]], and the [[empirical]]. The parallel with [[Buddhism]] is closest in the [[first stage]], i.e., with Pyrrho (360-275 B.C.).In the last, with {{Wiki|Sextus Empiricus}} (A.D. 160-210), it is barely perceptible. Indeed, taking the later developments as his norm, Bury can affirm that Pyrrho "was probably not at all a full-blown Sceptic, but rather a moralist of an [[austere]] and [[ascetic]] type who cultivated insensibility to externals and {{Wiki|superiority}} to environment."(39) It was only in the New {{Wiki|Academy}}, with Arcesilas (315-241 B.C.), that {{Wiki|Skepticism}} "ceased to be purely {{Wiki|practical}} and became mainly theoretical."(40) "Thus, while Pyrrho had renounced and Timon flouted the Dogmatists, Arcesilas started the practice of refuting them {{Wiki|scientifically}} and systematically, and earned thereby the abuse of Timon for his lapse from [[pure]] Pyrrhonism."(41) In fact, when we read {{Wiki|Sextus Empiricus}}, we find that, although some of the original message has remained intact,(42) it has been overlaid by a vast technical apparatus [[accumulated]] over five centuries and by numerous concessions to {{Wiki|common sense}}. The bulk of Sextus' work is parasitical on the {{Wiki|dogmatic}} [[philosophers]], and seems to be motivated more by disputatiousness and the [[desire]] to score [[debating]] points than by a positive [[interest]] in [[mental]] [[repose]]. In many ways his [[attitude]] resembles that of the later [[Buddhist logicians]].
  
At the [[time]] of {{Wiki|Cicero}}, halfway between Pyrrho and Sextus Empiricus, this loss of [[spiritual]] earnestness had not gone quite so far. Some of the statements which {{Wiki|Cicero}} makes in his Academica,(43) on behalf of or in response to the Skeptics, are indeed strikingly similar to the teachings of the [[Maadhyamikas]] and other later [[Buddhists]].
+
At the [[time]] of {{Wiki|Cicero}}, halfway between Pyrrho and {{Wiki|Sextus Empiricus}}, this loss of [[spiritual]] earnestness had not gone quite so far. Some of the statements which {{Wiki|Cicero}} makes in his Academica,(43) on behalf of or in response to the Skeptics, are indeed strikingly similar to the teachings of the [[Maadhyamikas]] and other later [[Buddhists]].
  
 
The Skeptics were [[people]] who "sanctioned nothing as proved" (qui nibil probarent(44)). "All those things you talk about are hidden, closely concealed (occultata) and enfolded in thick clouds of {{Wiki|darkness}}, so that no [[human]] {{Wiki|intellect}} has sufficiently powerful [[sight]] to be able to penetrate to [[heaven]] and get inside the earth."(45) Though "it is possibly the case that when exposed and uncovered they change their [[character]]" (quia possit fieri ut patefacta et detecta mutentur).(46) The Skeptics "have a [[Wikipedia:Habit (psychology)|habit]] of concealing (occultandi) their opinion, and do not usually disclose it to any one except those that had lived with them right up to old age."(47) And the opponent says, "What pray are those {{Wiki|holy}} secrets (mysteria) of yours, or why should your school conceal (celatis) its [[doctrine]] as something disgraceful?"(48)
 
The Skeptics were [[people]] who "sanctioned nothing as proved" (qui nibil probarent(44)). "All those things you talk about are hidden, closely concealed (occultata) and enfolded in thick clouds of {{Wiki|darkness}}, so that no [[human]] {{Wiki|intellect}} has sufficiently powerful [[sight]] to be able to penetrate to [[heaven]] and get inside the earth."(45) Though "it is possibly the case that when exposed and uncovered they change their [[character]]" (quia possit fieri ut patefacta et detecta mutentur).(46) The Skeptics "have a [[Wikipedia:Habit (psychology)|habit]] of concealing (occultandi) their opinion, and do not usually disclose it to any one except those that had lived with them right up to old age."(47) And the opponent says, "What pray are those {{Wiki|holy}} secrets (mysteria) of yours, or why should your school conceal (celatis) its [[doctrine]] as something disgraceful?"(48)
Line 48: Line 48:
 
[2] Secondly, there is a close similarity with those [[ascetic]], other-worldly, and "[[mystical]]" thinkers who assigned a decisive importance to "[[spiritual experience]]." They are represented by four main trends:
 
[2] Secondly, there is a close similarity with those [[ascetic]], other-worldly, and "[[mystical]]" thinkers who assigned a decisive importance to "[[spiritual experience]]." They are represented by four main trends:
  
(a) First, there are the [[Wisdom]] speculations of the Near [[East]] between 200 B.C. and A.D. 300. Their {{Wiki|conception}} of chochma and sophia is closely analogous to that of [[praj~naapaaramitaa]], and some of the similarities are really quite startling.(59)
+
(a) First, there are the [[Wisdom]] speculations of the Near [[East]] between 200 B.C. and A.D. 300. Their {{Wiki|conception}} of chochma and [[sophia]] is closely analogous to that of [[praj~naapaaramitaa]], and some of the similarities are really quite startling.(59)
(b) Next, the kindred [[Gnostic]] and {{Wiki|Neo-Platonic}} modes of [[thought]], especially the later Neo-Platonists, like {{Wiki|Proclus}} and Damascius,(60) and also their {{Wiki|Christian}} [[form]] in Origenes and in Dionysius Areopagita, who in some passages of his [[Mystical]] Theology(61) gives what may well be called a {{Wiki|Christian}} version of the [[Heart]] [[Suutra]].
+
(b) Next, the kindred [[Gnostic]] and {{Wiki|Neo-Platonic}} modes of [[thought]], especially the later Neo-Platonists, like {{Wiki|Proclus}} and Damascius,(60) and also their {{Wiki|Christian}} [[form]] in Origenes and in {{Wiki|Dionysius}} Areopagita, who in some passages of his [[Mystical]] Theology(61) gives what may well be called a {{Wiki|Christian}} version of the [[Heart]] [[Suutra]].
(c) Thirdly, there are the great {{Wiki|mystics}} of the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries, such as Meister Eckhart,(62) Ruysbroeck, and Suso. Their kinship with [[Buddhism]] has been noted so often that I can be quite brief. Ruysbroeck says of the "God-seeing man" that "his [[spirit]] is undifferentiated and without {{Wiki|distinction}}, and therefore [[feels]] nothing without the {{Wiki|unity}}." Among {{Wiki|Western}} contemplatives, [[suunyataa]] corresponds to the "desert of the Godhead," to Ruysbroeck's "idle [[emptiness]]," to Eckhart's still wilderness where no one is at home, to the "naked orison," the "naked intent stretching unto [[God]]," which becomes possible with entire self-surrender, and also to the fathomless [[Wikipedia:Abyss (religion)|abyss]] of Ruysbroeck and Tauler.(63) This "[[Wikipedia:Abyss (religion)|abyss]]" is wholeheartedly welcomed by those steeped in self-negation and self-naughting, but, later on, less [[selfless]] [[people]] like B. Pascal(64) and Ch. Baudelaire(65) felt rather ambivalent when confronted with it, since they were clearly none too enchanted with the implication of being "separated from all created things." The Theologia Germanica(66) (ca, 1425), as is well known, contains many formulations with a distinctly [[Buddhist]] flavor. The most striking similarity lies, of course, in the [[constant]] emphasis on "I-hood and [[selfhood]]," on "I, me, and mine" as the source of all alienation from true [[reality]], and on the need to undo that "{{Wiki|blindness}} and folly."(67) But this is not all. On re-reading the [[book]] I have been astounded to find how close it is in so many ways to [[Buddhist]] [[mentality]], in spite of its author's "{{Wiki|cautious}} limitation of his speculations to what is compatible with the Church,"(68) and some minor concessions to [[theism]], especially in the later parts. Apart from the [[subject]] of satkaayad.r.s.ti this is true of what is said about the Godhead (= Nirvaa.na), the "deified man" (= the [[bodhisattva]]), activated by both "[[cognition]]" and a "[[love]]" wherein "there neither is nor can remain any I, Me, Mine, Thou, Thine, and the like, "(69) non-attainment, (70) the perverted [[views]], (71) self-deception (= avidyaa),(72) [[Suchness]], (73) [[faith]], (74) the One, (75) [[emptiness]], (76) [[desire]], (77) and so on--in fact, quite an impressive list.
+
(c) Thirdly, there are the great {{Wiki|mystics}} of the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries, such as Meister Eckhart,(62) Ruysbroeck, and Suso. Their kinship with [[Buddhism]] has been noted so often that I can be quite brief. Ruysbroeck says of the "God-seeing man" that "his [[spirit]] is undifferentiated and without {{Wiki|distinction}}, and therefore [[feels]] nothing without the {{Wiki|unity}}." Among {{Wiki|Western}} contemplatives, [[suunyataa]] corresponds to the "desert of the Godhead," to Ruysbroeck's "idle [[emptiness]]," to [[Wikipedia: Meister Eckhart|Eckhart's]] still wilderness where no one is at home, to the "naked orison," the "naked intent stretching unto [[God]]," which becomes possible with entire [[self-surrender]], and also to the fathomless [[Wikipedia:Abyss (religion)|abyss]] of Ruysbroeck and Tauler.(63) This "[[Wikipedia:Abyss (religion)|abyss]]" is wholeheartedly welcomed by those steeped in self-negation and self-naughting, but, later on, less [[selfless]] [[people]] like B. Pascal(64) and Ch. Baudelaire(65) felt rather ambivalent when confronted with it, since they were clearly none too enchanted with the implication of being "separated from all created things." The Theologia Germanica(66) (ca, 1425), as is well known, contains many formulations with a distinctly [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|flavor}}. The most striking similarity lies, of course, in the [[constant]] {{Wiki|emphasis}} on "I-hood and [[selfhood]]," on "I, me, and mine" as the source of all alienation from true [[reality]], and on the need to undo that "{{Wiki|blindness}} and folly."(67) But this is not all. On re-reading the [[book]] I have been astounded to find how close it is in so many ways to [[Buddhist]] [[mentality]], in spite of its author's "{{Wiki|cautious}} limitation of his speculations to what is compatible with the Church,"(68) and some minor concessions to [[theism]], especially in the later parts. Apart from the [[subject]] of satkaayad.r.s.ti this is true of what is said about the Godhead (= Nirvaa.na), the "deified man" (= the [[bodhisattva]]), activated by both "[[cognition]]" and a "[[love]]" wherein "there neither is nor can remain any I, Me, Mine, Thou, Thine, and the like, "(69) non-attainment, (70) the perverted [[views]], (71) self-deception (= avidyaa),(72) [[Suchness]], (73) [[faith]], (74) the One, (75) [[emptiness]], (76) [[desire]], (77) and so on--in fact, quite an impressive list.
(d) Toward the end of the seventeenth century, shortly after {{Wiki|Galileo}}, {{Wiki|European}} [[mysticism]] of this type lost its [[intellectual]] {{Wiki|distinction}}, and faded away into the "Quietism" of Molinos and Mme Guyon. In the aftermath of the {{Wiki|French}} {{Wiki|revolution}}, many of the basic laws of the [[spiritual]] [[life]] were rediscovered by great poets who were also fine thinkers, such as Blake, Shelley, Wordsworth, and Coleridge in {{Wiki|England}}. Though often vitiated by a fatal rift between {{Wiki|theory}} and practice, their [[thought]] offers many parallels to [[Buddhist]] [[thinking]]. To this generation of rebels against the [[Goddess]] of [[Reason]] belonged {{Wiki|Arthur Schopenhauer}}, whose [[thought]], partly under [[Indian]] influence, exhibits numerous, and almost miraculous, coincidences with the basic {{Wiki|tenets}} of [[Buddhist]] philosophy.(78) The term "parallel" implies that two lines run parallel at more than one point, and the [[degree]] of [[affinity]] [[existing]] between {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} and [[Buddhism]] will give us a standard by which to judge other alleged "parallels."
+
(d) Toward the end of the seventeenth century, shortly after {{Wiki|Galileo}}, {{Wiki|European}} [[mysticism]] of this type lost its [[intellectual]] {{Wiki|distinction}}, and faded away into the "Quietism" of Molinos and Mme Guyon. In the aftermath of the {{Wiki|French}} {{Wiki|revolution}}, many of the basic laws of the [[spiritual]] [[life]] were rediscovered by great poets who were also fine thinkers, such as Blake, Shelley, Wordsworth, and Coleridge in {{Wiki|England}}. Though often vitiated by a fatal rift between {{Wiki|theory}} and practice, their [[thought]] offers many parallels to [[Buddhist]] [[thinking]]. To this generation of rebels against the [[Goddess]] of [[Reason]] belonged {{Wiki|Arthur Schopenhauer}}, whose [[thought]], partly under [[Indian]] influence, exhibits numerous, and almost miraculous, coincidences with the basic {{Wiki|tenets}} of [[Buddhist]] philosophy.(78) The term "parallel" implies that two lines run parallel at more than one point, and the [[degree]] of [[affinity]] [[existing]] between {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} and [[Buddhism]] will give us a standard by which to [[judge]] other alleged "parallels."
  
As he himself said, {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} continued the triple [[tradition]] of "quietism, i.e. the giving up of all willing, [[asceticism]], i.e. intentional {{Wiki|mortification}} of one's own will, and [[mysticism]], i.e. [[consciousness]] of the [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] of one's own inner being with that of all [[beings]], or with the kernel of the world."(79) He shows that [[life]] in the [[world]] is meaningless, [[essentially]] [[suffering]], and bound to disappoint the {{Wiki|hope}} that our [[desires]] might be fulfilled. He [[attributes]] this [[suffering]] to "the will to live," which is the {{Wiki|equivalent}} of t.r.s.naa, and which "involves us in a [[delusion]]." He looks for {{Wiki|salvation}} from this [[world]] by way of a "{{Wiki|denial}} of the will to live," which is a "consequence of the dawning of better knowledge,"(80) and by an [[asceticism]] and self-renunciation exemplified in "the [[lives]] of [[saints]], penitents, sama.nas, sannyaasins, and so on."(81) We may add his {{Wiki|atheism}}, his {{Wiki|denial}} of an {{Wiki|immaterial}}, substantially [[unchanging]], [[soul]], his [[belief]] in [[reincarnation]], his [[stress]] on [[compassion]] as the basis of [[morality]], his [[indifference]] to the "achievements" or "rhythm" of [[human]] history,(82) as well as his [[insight]] into impermanence(83) and into the [[reasons]] why Nirvaa.na can be described only negatively, and yet it is not nothing.(84)
+
As he himself said, {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} continued the triple [[tradition]] of "quietism, i.e. the giving up of all willing, [[asceticism]], i.e. intentional {{Wiki|mortification}} of one's own will, and [[mysticism]], i.e. [[consciousness]] of the [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] of one's own inner being with that of all [[beings]], or with the kernel of the world."(79) He shows that [[life]] in the [[world]] is meaningless, [[essentially]] [[suffering]], and [[bound]] to disappoint the {{Wiki|hope}} that our [[desires]] might be fulfilled. He [[attributes]] this [[suffering]] to "the will to live," which is the {{Wiki|equivalent}} of t.r.s.naa, and which "involves us in a [[delusion]]." He looks for {{Wiki|salvation}} from this [[world]] by way of a "{{Wiki|denial}} of the will to live," which is a "consequence of the dawning of better knowledge,"(80) and by an [[asceticism]] and self-renunciation exemplified in "the [[lives]] of [[saints]], penitents, sama.nas, sannyaasins, and so on."(81) We may add his {{Wiki|atheism}}, his {{Wiki|denial}} of an {{Wiki|immaterial}}, substantially [[unchanging]], [[soul]], his [[belief]] in [[reincarnation]], his [[stress]] on [[compassion]] as the basis of [[morality]], his [[indifference]] to the "achievements" or "rhythm" of [[human]] history,(82) as well as his [[insight]] into impermanence(83) and into the [[reasons]] why Nirvaa.na can be described only negatively, and yet it is not nothing.(84)
  
 
It is only on two points that he differs from [[Buddhism]].
 
It is only on two points that he differs from [[Buddhism]].
  
(A) He fails to appreciate the importance of [[disciplined]] [[meditation]]. Educated non-Catholic Germans of the nineteenth century were quite unfamiliar with the [[tradition]] of [[spiritual]] contemplation. On the other hand, for [[relaxation]] they habitually visited [[art]] galleries and went for walks in the countryside. It is no wonder, therefore, that {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} sees the foretaste of "the [[exalted]] [[peace]]" of Nirvaa.na, not in [[Wikipedia:trance|trances]] (dhyaana), but in "[[pure]] esthetic contemplation." Although the contemplation of [[beauty]] has some analogy to the [[conditions]] prevailing in [[trance]], it is on the whole an undisciplined {{Wiki|faculty}}, and its results are rather fleeting and have little power to transmute the [[personality]]. In this [[respect]], the {{Wiki|German}} bourgeois town-dweller was a lesser man than the [[Indian]] man in the {{Wiki|forest}}.
+
(A) He fails to appreciate the importance of [[disciplined]] [[meditation]]. Educated non-Catholic Germans of the nineteenth century were quite unfamiliar with the [[tradition]] of [[spiritual]] contemplation. On the other hand, for [[relaxation]] they habitually visited [[art]] galleries and went for walks in the countryside. It is no {{Wiki|wonder}}, therefore, that {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} sees the foretaste of "the [[exalted]] [[peace]]" of Nirvaa.na, not in [[Wikipedia:trance|trances]] (dhyaana), but in "[[pure]] esthetic contemplation." Although the contemplation of [[beauty]] has some analogy to the [[conditions]] prevailing in [[trance]], it is on the whole an undisciplined {{Wiki|faculty}}, and its results are rather fleeting and have little power to transmute the [[personality]]. In this [[respect]], the {{Wiki|German}} bourgeois town-dweller was a lesser man than the [[Indian]] man in the {{Wiki|forest}}.
(B) Secondly, {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} teaches that the Will is the [[Thing-in-itself]], whereas in [[Buddhism]] "[[craving]]" operates within the [[conditioned]] and [[phenomenal world]], and the [[unconditioned]] noumenon lies in Nirvaa.na, which is quite [[calm]] as the result of the abolition of [[craving]]. Unacquainted with the practice of [[yoga]], {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} did not know that at the bottom of every [[mind]] there is a [[calm]] quietude which is the prototype of Nirvaa.na. His central [[metaphysical]] {{Wiki|thesis}} is, however, incompatible, not only with [[Buddhism]], but also with his own {{Wiki|soteriological}} aspirations. It is, indeed, not only hard to see how any [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] act can ever reach the [[Thing-in-itself]], but it also remains incomprehensible how [[thought]] can ever have the strength to stand up against the Will, and, what is more, how as a part of the purely [[illusory]] [[phenomenal world]] it can possibly overcome and effectively "deny" it.(85) This was early [[recognized]] by Nietzsche(86) and J. Bahnsen(87) (1881), Schopenhauer's immediate successors, and led them, respectively, into [[nihilism]] and a [[pessimism]] unrelieved by the {{Wiki|hope}} of escape.
+
(B) Secondly, {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} teaches that the Will is the [[Thing-in-itself]], whereas in [[Buddhism]] "[[craving]]" operates within the [[conditioned]] and [[phenomenal world]], and the [[unconditioned]] {{Wiki|noumenon}} lies in Nirvaa.na, which is quite [[calm]] as the result of the abolition of [[craving]]. Unacquainted with the practice of [[yoga]], {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} did not know that at the bottom of every [[mind]] there is a [[calm]] quietude which is the prototype of Nirvaa.na. His central [[metaphysical]] {{Wiki|thesis}} is, however, incompatible, not only with [[Buddhism]], but also with his own {{Wiki|soteriological}} [[aspirations]]. It is, indeed, not only hard to see how any [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] act can ever reach the [[Thing-in-itself]], but it also remains incomprehensible how [[thought]] can ever have the strength to stand up against the Will, and, what is more, how as a part of the purely [[illusory]] [[phenomenal world]] it can possibly overcome and effectively "deny" it.(85) This was early [[recognized]] by Nietzsche(86) and J. Bahnsen(87) (1881), Schopenhauer's immediate successors, and led them, respectively, into [[nihilism]] and a [[pessimism]] unrelieved by the {{Wiki|hope}} of escape.
(C) Furthermore, [[Buddhism]] has a {{Wiki|distinct}} [[affinity]] with the "monistic" [[traditions]] of {{Wiki|European}} [[thought]]. The Eleatic emphasis on the One(88) implied devaluation, depreciation, and at times even rejection of the plural and multiple [[world]]. However they may phrase it, all monistic systems are in tune with the [[feeling]] which Shelley formulated in the famous verse:
+
(C) Furthermore, [[Buddhism]] has a {{Wiki|distinct}} [[affinity]] with the "{{Wiki|monistic}}" [[traditions]] of {{Wiki|European}} [[thought]]. The Eleatic {{Wiki|emphasis}} on the One(88) implied devaluation, depreciation, and at times even rejection of the plural and multiple [[world]]. However they may [[phrase]] it, all {{Wiki|monistic}} systems are in tune with the [[feeling]] which Shelley formulated in the famous verse:
  
 
         [[Life]], like a dome of many-coloured glass
 
         [[Life]], like a dome of many-coloured glass
Line 67: Line 67:
 
{{Wiki|Parmenides}} (ca. 480 B.C., nearly the [[Buddha's]] contemporary) and his successors assume a radical difference between [[appearance]] and [[reality]], between surface and depth, between what we see (phainomena) and what we can only think (noumena), between opinion and [[truth]]. For {{Wiki|Parmenides}}, opinion (d.r.s.ti) is derived from the [[senses]], which are deceptive and the basis of false [[information]]. [[Truth]] is derived from the {{Wiki|logos}}, which has for its [[object]] Being (that which is and has no other [[attributes]] but to be). Being is, [[non-being]] is not; and that which Is can never not be, either now or later (as in change). Nothing that Is can either arise or perish.(90)
 
{{Wiki|Parmenides}} (ca. 480 B.C., nearly the [[Buddha's]] contemporary) and his successors assume a radical difference between [[appearance]] and [[reality]], between surface and depth, between what we see (phainomena) and what we can only think (noumena), between opinion and [[truth]]. For {{Wiki|Parmenides}}, opinion (d.r.s.ti) is derived from the [[senses]], which are deceptive and the basis of false [[information]]. [[Truth]] is derived from the {{Wiki|logos}}, which has for its [[object]] Being (that which is and has no other [[attributes]] but to be). Being is, [[non-being]] is not; and that which Is can never not be, either now or later (as in change). Nothing that Is can either arise or perish.(90)
  
All monistic systems are remarkably {{Wiki|uniform}}, and they are all equally beset by at least four unavoidable difficulties. They must, first of all, try to guard against the misunderstanding that the One might be a datum within the [[world]], or a part of the conglomeration. Both [[East]] and [[West]] acutely felt the difficulties of finding an adequate [[verbal]] expression for the [[essentially]] [[transcendent]] and elusive [[reality]] of the One, and both made many attempts to circumvent them by the use of paradoxes, absurdities, contradictions, [[Wikipedia:Tautology(logic)|tautologies]], riddles, negations, and other devices. Secondly, the monists must attempt to maintain the [[simplicity]] of the One by redefining the meaning of predication in regard to it. In this context, {{Wiki|scholastic}} [[philosophers]] explained that [[God]] is each of his predicates, whereas creatures have them, and that the predicates of [[God]] are not different from one another, since otherwise he would not be simple. "The [[absolute]] [[essence]] is not in one [[respect]] different from what it is in another; what it is, it is in the {{Wiki|totality}} of its being."(91) Everything plural is itself and in addition something else, and only the completely free can be itself [[pure]] and simple.
+
All {{Wiki|monistic}} systems are remarkably {{Wiki|uniform}}, and they are all equally beset by at least four unavoidable difficulties. They must, first of all, try to guard against the {{Wiki|misunderstanding}} that the One might be a datum within the [[world]], or a part of the conglomeration. Both [[East]] and [[West]] acutely felt the difficulties of finding an adequate [[verbal]] expression for the [[essentially]] [[transcendent]] and elusive [[reality]] of the One, and both made many attempts to circumvent them by the use of [[Wikipedia:paradox|paradoxes]], absurdities, contradictions, [[Wikipedia:Tautology(logic)|tautologies]], riddles, negations, and other devices. Secondly, the [[Wikipedia:Monism|monists]] must attempt to maintain the [[simplicity]] of the One by redefining the meaning of predication in regard to it. In this context, {{Wiki|scholastic}} [[philosophers]] explained that [[God]] is each of his predicates, whereas creatures have them, and that the predicates of [[God]] are not different from one another, since otherwise he would not be simple. "The [[absolute]] [[essence]] is not in one [[respect]] different from what it is in another; what it is, it is in the {{Wiki|totality}} of its being."(91) Everything plural is itself and in addition something else, and only the completely free can be itself [[pure]] and simple.
  
A third problem concerns the [[relation]] between the One and Being. The old Eleatic school, which flourished between 540 and 300 B.C.,(92) identifies the two. One must bear in [[mind]], however, that in doing so it uses a special {{Wiki|archaic}}, pre-Atistotelian type of logic(93) which, among other things, employs "the [[principle]] of [[unlimited]] predication." This means that a predicate is either predicated without limitation of the [[subject]] or it is not valid at all. This [[logic]] only [[knows]] statements of the type "All A are all B," which predicate the entire P of the entire S, without any qualification as to [[time]], part, or [[respect]], without any {{Wiki|distinction}} being made between total and partial [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] of S and P, or between their partial and total difference. The Eleatics also "assumed that one speaks only in one [[sense]] (monachos) of 'one' and 'being.'"(94) The victory of {{Wiki|Aristotelian logic}} changed all that. {{Wiki|Plotinus}} describes the One expressly as "beyond being"; for Meister Eckhart, who said that "in the {{Wiki|Kingdom}} of [[Heaven]] all is in all, all is one, and all is ours," [[Pure]] Being, as the most general, becomes the richest of all terms;(95) and [[Hegel]], again, treats "being" as the initial and minimal [[definition]] of the [[Absolute]], which is later enriched by many further "[[attributes]]." The Theologia Germanica(96) says that "he who finds [[satisfaction]] in [[God]], his [[satisfaction]] is the One, and is all in the One. And he to whom the One is not all and all not the One, and to Whom something and nothing are not one and the same, cannot find [[satisfaction]] in [[God]]." The [[Buddhist]] [[non-dual]] One was in the same way by many devices transferred beyond all [[logical]] categories.
+
A third problem concerns the [[relation]] between the One and Being. The old Eleatic school, which flourished between 540 and 300 B.C.,(92) identifies the two. One must bear in [[mind]], however, that in doing so it uses a special {{Wiki|archaic}}, pre-Atistotelian type of logic(93) which, among other things, employs "the [[principle]] of [[unlimited]] predication." This means that a predicate is either predicated without limitation of the [[subject]] or it is not valid at all. This [[logic]] only [[knows]] statements of the type "All A are all B," which predicate the entire P of the entire S, without any qualification as to [[time]], part, or [[respect]], without any {{Wiki|distinction}} being made between total and partial [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] of S and P, or between their partial and total difference. The Eleatics also "assumed that one speaks only in one [[sense]] (monachos) of 'one' and 'being.'"(94) The victory of {{Wiki|Aristotelian logic}} changed all that. {{Wiki|Plotinus}} describes the One expressly as "beyond being"; for {{Wiki|Meister Eckhart}}, who said that "in the {{Wiki|Kingdom}} of [[Heaven]] all is in all, all is one, and all is ours," [[Pure]] Being, as the most general, becomes the richest of all terms;(95) and [[Hegel]], again, treats "being" as the initial and minimal [[definition]] of the [[Absolute]], which is later enriched by many further "[[attributes]]." The Theologia Germanica(96) says that "he who finds [[satisfaction]] in [[God]], his [[satisfaction]] is the One, and is all in the One. And he to whom the One is not all and all not the One, and to Whom something and nothing are not one and the same, cannot find [[satisfaction]] in [[God]]." The [[Buddhist]] [[non-dual]] One was in the same way by many devices transferred beyond all [[logical]] categories.
  
And, fourthly, monists must come to some [[decision]] on the {{Wiki|status}} of [[appearance]]. It may well be that not all of them have, like most [[Buddhists]], regarded [[appearance]] as a mere [[illusion]], and it is probably true that' "there is never any suggestion in {{Wiki|Plotinus}} that all things except the One are [[illusions]] or fleeting appearances."(97) But this is a {{Wiki|distinction}} without much of a difference, because also in the Plotinian system the sensory and material [[world]] has an extremely low [[degree]] of [[reality]], and is afflicted by a great loss of the original [[reality]], near its point of [[extinction]]. In the same way, in the Hegelian system the natural [[world]] is a state of estrangement from the [[Absolute]] [[Spirit]]. In Eckhart, "all creatures, insofar as they are creatures, as they are in themselves (quod sunt in et per se), are not even an [[illusion]], but they are a [[pure]] nothing."(98) And, for {{Wiki|Spinoza}}, "a {{Wiki|temporal}} [[existence]] insofar as it is purely {{Wiki|temporal}} is the same as [[non-existence]], and is perishing in proportion to its fragmentariness and exclusiveness; [[existence]] in every range insofar as it gains content move already towards an {{Wiki|ideal}} of [[perfection]] which is one with {{Wiki|eternity}} itself."(99)
+
And, fourthly, [[Wikipedia:Monism|monists]] must come to some [[decision]] on the {{Wiki|status}} of [[appearance]]. It may well be that not all of them have, like most [[Buddhists]], regarded [[appearance]] as a mere [[illusion]], and it is probably true that' "there is never any suggestion in {{Wiki|Plotinus}} that all things except the One are [[illusions]] or fleeting appearances."(97) But this is a {{Wiki|distinction}} without much of a difference, because also in the Plotinian system the sensory and material [[world]] has an extremely low [[degree]] of [[reality]], and is afflicted by a great loss of the original [[reality]], near its point of [[extinction]]. In the same way, in the Hegelian system the natural [[world]] is a state of estrangement from the [[Absolute]] [[Spirit]]. In [[Wikipedia: Meister Eckhart|Eckhart]], "all creatures, insofar as they are creatures, as they are in themselves (quod sunt in et per se), are not even an [[illusion]], but they are a [[pure]] nothing."(98) And, for {{Wiki|Spinoza}}, "a {{Wiki|temporal}} [[existence]] insofar as it is purely {{Wiki|temporal}} is the same as [[non-existence]], and is perishing in proportion to its fragmentariness and exclusiveness; [[existence]] in every range insofar as it gains content move already towards an {{Wiki|ideal}} of [[perfection]] which is one with {{Wiki|eternity}} itself."(99)
  
The background of all "monistic" views(100) is a [[religious]] [[contempt]] for the [[world]] of ordinary [[experience]], for that which is not One or not He who Is. That [[world]] is held to be unsatisfactory---partly [[emotionally]] as a source of [[suffering]], and partly [[logically]] as self-contradictory, and as therefore either non-existing(101) or unable to abide in the state in which it is. In this way {{Wiki|monism}} is apt to beget the [[dialectics]] out of itself, as in Zeno, [[Hegel]], and {{Wiki|Bradley}}, to [[name]] only a few. In the case of Zeno of Elea (ca. 460 B.C.), whom {{Wiki|Aristotle}} called the founder of the [[dialectics]], the "paradoxes" (aporiai) he devised aimed at defending by indirect proofs the [[view]] of {{Wiki|Parmenides}}, which held local {{Wiki|movement}} to be impossible in the [[ultimate reality]] of the true [[world of being]]. All Zeno did was to show that, on assuming {{Wiki|movement}}, the consequences which follow are contradictory and untenable,(102) and that, therefore, the [[information]] derived from sense-data is patently false, since selfcontradictions are the marks of false [[appearance]].
+
The background of all "{{Wiki|monistic}}" views(100) is a [[religious]] [[contempt]] for the [[world]] of ordinary [[experience]], for that which is not One or not He who Is. That [[world]] is held to be unsatisfactory---partly [[emotionally]] as a source of [[suffering]], and partly [[logically]] as self-contradictory, and as therefore either non-existing(101) or unable to abide in the state in which it is. In this way {{Wiki|monism}} is apt to beget the [[dialectics]] out of itself, as in Zeno, [[Hegel]], and {{Wiki|Bradley}}, to [[name]] only a few. In the case of Zeno of Elea (ca. 460 B.C.), whom {{Wiki|Aristotle}} called the founder of the [[dialectics]], the "[[Wikipedia:paradox|paradoxes]]" (aporiai) he devised aimed at defending by indirect proofs the [[view]] of {{Wiki|Parmenides}}, which held local {{Wiki|movement}} to be impossible in the [[ultimate reality]] of the true [[world of being]]. All Zeno did was to show that, on assuming {{Wiki|movement}}, the {{Wiki|consequences}} which follow are contradictory and untenable,(102) and that, therefore, the [[information]] derived from sense-data is patently false, since selfcontradictions are the marks of false [[appearance]].
  
Zeno's [[dialectics]] has had many successors. Among them, {{Wiki|Bradley}} seems nearer to the [[Maadhyamikas]] than either [[Hegel]] or Marx. Both [[Hegel]] and Marx make two assumptions which must irritate [[Buddhists]]. The first is the insistence on [[human]] history, (103) which [[Buddhists]] hold to be utterly pointless. The second is the [[constant]] introduction of the tripartite scheme of {{Wiki|thesis}}, {{Wiki|antithesis}}, and synthesis, which postulates a relentless "progress" from one state to the other, culminating in the tyranny of the Prussian state or of the U.S.S.R. On the other hand, {{Wiki|Bradley}} is, next to {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}}, the nearest representative in {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|Europe}} of at least one side of [[Buddhist]] [[thought]]. Even the procedure of [[Appearance]] and [[Reality]] is the same as that of the Maadhyamikakaarikaa, in that one currently accepted category after the other is taken up and shown to be self-contradictory and untenable. Nor can I agree with {{Wiki|Professor}} Murti's(l04) claim that they differ greatly "in their notion of the Real and its [[relation]] to [[appearance]]." In fact, they both treat the Real as {{Wiki|ineffable}}, and "at once [[transcendent]] and immanent."(105) If {{Wiki|Bradley}} takes care not to exclude entirely the [[appearance]] from the Real, and seeks somehow to identify the two,(106) then this is not a "rather inconsistent contention,"(107) but the exact {{Wiki|equivalent}} of the [[Maadhyamika]] position ("[[Form]] is [[emptiness]], " etc.). Both these [[books]] are [[essentially]] polemical treatises and their message seems to be [[identical]].
+
Zeno's [[dialectics]] has had many successors. Among them, {{Wiki|Bradley}} seems nearer to the [[Maadhyamikas]] than either [[Hegel]] or Marx. Both [[Hegel]] and Marx make two {{Wiki|assumptions}} which must irritate [[Buddhists]]. The first is the insistence on [[human]] history, (103) which [[Buddhists]] hold to be utterly pointless. The second is the [[constant]] introduction of the tripartite scheme of {{Wiki|thesis}}, {{Wiki|antithesis}}, and {{Wiki|synthesis}}, which postulates a relentless "progress" from one state to the other, culminating in the tyranny of the Prussian state or of the U.S.S.R. On the other hand, {{Wiki|Bradley}} is, next to {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}}, the nearest representative in {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|Europe}} of at least one side of [[Buddhist]] [[thought]]. Even the procedure of [[Appearance]] and [[Reality]] is the same as that of the Maadhyamikakaarikaa, in that one currently accepted category after the other is taken up and shown to be self-contradictory and untenable. Nor can I agree with {{Wiki|Professor}} Murti's(l04) claim that they differ greatly "in their notion of the Real and its [[relation]] to [[appearance]]." In fact, they both treat the Real as {{Wiki|ineffable}}, and "at once [[transcendent]] and immanent."(105) If {{Wiki|Bradley}} takes care not to exclude entirely the [[appearance]] from the Real, and seeks somehow to identify the two,(106) then this is not a "rather inconsistent contention,"(107) but the exact {{Wiki|equivalent}} of the [[Maadhyamika]] position ("[[Form]] is [[emptiness]], " etc.). Both these [[books]] are [[essentially]] polemical treatises and their message seems to be [[identical]].
  
 
  part two of this essay: Spurious Parallels to [[Buddhist Philosophy]]
 
  part two of this essay: Spurious Parallels to [[Buddhist Philosophy]]
Line 109: Line 109:
 
(27) [[Sections]] 1 and 3 of the second article.
 
(27) [[Sections]] 1 and 3 of the second article.
 
(28) For a [[definition]], see below, p. 14, note 35.
 
(28) For a [[definition]], see below, p. 14, note 35.
(29) This term. was originally invented by Catholics to describe the [[philosophy]] of St. Thomas and {{Wiki|Aristotle}}. It was then taken over by {{Wiki|Aldous Huxley}} and others, and my [[definition]] is akin to that of {{Wiki|Ananda Coomaraswamy}}. A. Huxley in his famous [[book]] of 1946 'envisaged only the [[mystical]] school, whereas here i include the [[intellectual]] and speculative trends, i.e., {{Wiki|Plato}} and {{Wiki|Aristotle}} as well as the {{Wiki|German}} {{Wiki|idealists}}. The only [[people]] before 1450 who are excluded are those who, like the Lokaayatikas in [[India]], were deliberately antispiritual, but not necessarily the Epicureans who were anticlerical but no foes of a [[tranquil]] and [[serene]] [[life]].
+
(29) This term. was originally invented by Catholics to describe the [[philosophy]] of St. Thomas and {{Wiki|Aristotle}}. It was then taken over by {{Wiki|Aldous Huxley}} and others, and my [[definition]] is akin to that of {{Wiki|Ananda Coomaraswamy}}. A. Huxley in his famous [[book]] of 1946 'envisaged only the [[mystical]] school, whereas here i include the [[intellectual]] and speculative trends, i.e., {{Wiki|Plato}} and {{Wiki|Aristotle}} as well as the {{Wiki|German}} {{Wiki|idealists}}. The only [[people]] before 1450 who are excluded are those who, like the Lokaayatikas in [[India]], were deliberately antispiritual, but not necessarily the [[Wikipedia:Epicureanism|Epicureans]] who were anticlerical but no foes of a [[tranquil]] and [[serene]] [[life]].
 
(30) Being for him is "one" [[kata]] ton logon (when seen by [[reason]]) , "many" [[kata]] t(-+e) aisth(-+e)in (when seen by [[perception]]) . {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, [[Metaphysics]], I.986(b)33-34.
 
(30) Being for him is "one" [[kata]] ton logon (when seen by [[reason]]) , "many" [[kata]] t(-+e) aisth(-+e)in (when seen by [[perception]]) . {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, [[Metaphysics]], I.986(b)33-34.
(31) "In his [[Metaphysics]], {{Wiki|Aristotle}} has taken great [[pains]] to describe the subjective counterpart of "being as being," e.g., in [[Book]] I.981(b)-983(a).
+
(31) "In his [[Metaphysics]], {{Wiki|Aristotle}} has taken great [[pains]] to describe the [[subjective]] counterpart of "being as being," e.g., in [[Book]] I.981(b)-983(a).
 
(32) "Notre philosophie est n‚e de la curiosit? et du besoin de savoir, d'expliquer le monde d'une fa‡on coh‚rente. En Inde la philosophie est l'interpretation rationelle de l'exp‚rience mystique." So Constantin Regamey, on page 251 of what is one of the most notable contributions so far made to comparative [[philosophy]], i.e., "Tendences et m‚thodes de la philosophie indienne compar‚es celles de la philosophie occidentale, " Revue de Th‚ologie et de Philosophie, IV (1951), 245-262. Regamey also shows how this difference in the point de d‚part leads to a radical divergence in the criteria of [[absolute truth]]. (33) Joseph Head and S. L. Cranson, eds., [[Reincarnation]]: An East-West {{Wiki|Anthology}} ({{Wiki|New York}}: The Julian Press, Inc., 1961).
 
(32) "Notre philosophie est n‚e de la curiosit? et du besoin de savoir, d'expliquer le monde d'une fa‡on coh‚rente. En Inde la philosophie est l'interpretation rationelle de l'exp‚rience mystique." So Constantin Regamey, on page 251 of what is one of the most notable contributions so far made to comparative [[philosophy]], i.e., "Tendences et m‚thodes de la philosophie indienne compar‚es celles de la philosophie occidentale, " Revue de Th‚ologie et de Philosophie, IV (1951), 245-262. Regamey also shows how this difference in the point de d‚part leads to a radical divergence in the criteria of [[absolute truth]]. (33) Joseph Head and S. L. Cranson, eds., [[Reincarnation]]: An East-West {{Wiki|Anthology}} ({{Wiki|New York}}: The Julian Press, Inc., 1961).
(34) The opponents of the [[perennial]] [[philosophy]] prefer to describe themselves as "[[scientific]]." There can be nothing more unscientific, however, than the drawing of extravagant and presumptuous conclusions about the [[mind]], [[soul]], and [[spirit]] of man, and about his [[destiny]] and the purpose of his [[life]], from a few observations about the expansion of gases, the distribution of moths, and the reflections of the [[Wikipedia:astronomical objects|celestial bodies]] in little pieces of glass. If I were reduced to that part of myself which can be seen in bits of glass, I would certainly [[feel]] that most of my being was omitted. Why should this not be true also of other things apart from my own dear [[self]]?
+
(34) The opponents of the [[perennial]] [[philosophy]] prefer to describe themselves as "[[scientific]]." There can be nothing more unscientific, however, than the drawing of extravagant and presumptuous conclusions about the [[mind]], [[soul]], and [[spirit]] of man, and about his [[destiny]] and the {{Wiki|purpose}} of his [[life]], from a few observations about the expansion of gases, the distribution of moths, and the reflections of the [[Wikipedia:astronomical objects|celestial bodies]] in little pieces of glass. If I were reduced to that part of myself which can be seen in bits of glass, I would certainly [[feel]] that most of my being was omitted. Why should this not be true also of other things apart from my own dear [[self]]?
(35) I have defined the [[word]] "[[spiritual]]" in my [[Buddhism]] (3rd ed., {{Wiki|Oxford}}: Bruno Cassirer, 1957) on page 11. The quintessence of the [[spiritual]] [[life]], shorn of its usual accretions, was admirably formulated by Petrus Damiani in the eleventh century in two exceedingly fine poems which have recently been reprinted in F. J. E. Raby, ed., The {{Wiki|Oxford}} [[Book]] of {{Wiki|Medieval}} Latin Verse ({{Wiki|Oxford}}: Clarendon Press, 1959), pp. 185-189. The second has also been translated into English in Frederick Brittain, ed., The Penguin [[Book]] of Latin Verse (Harmondsworth, {{Wiki|England}}: Penguin [[Books]], Ltd., 1962), pp. 176-180.
+
(35) I have defined the [[word]] "[[spiritual]]" in my [[Buddhism]] (3rd ed., {{Wiki|Oxford}}: Bruno Cassirer, 1957) on page 11. The quintessence of the [[spiritual]] [[life]], shorn of its usual accretions, was admirably formulated by Petrus Damiani in the eleventh century in two exceedingly fine poems which have recently been reprinted in F. J. E. Raby, ed., The {{Wiki|Oxford}} [[Book]] of {{Wiki|Medieval}} {{Wiki|Latin}} Verse ({{Wiki|Oxford}}: Clarendon Press, 1959), pp. 185-189. The second has also been translated into English in Frederick Brittain, ed., The Penguin [[Book]] of {{Wiki|Latin}} Verse (Harmondsworth, {{Wiki|England}}: Penguin [[Books]], Ltd., 1962), pp. 176-180.
 
(36) To mention just two easily accessible sources: In Bertrand Russell's A History of {{Wiki|Western}} Philorophy ({{Wiki|New York}}: Simon and Schuster, 1945) this [[attitude]] is expressed with some urbanity, and in J. O. Urmson, ed., The Concise {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of {{Wiki|Western Philosophy}} ({{Wiki|London}}: Hutchinson, 1960) with blunt rudeness (e.g., the article on {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} is sheer personal abuse).
 
(36) To mention just two easily accessible sources: In Bertrand Russell's A History of {{Wiki|Western}} Philorophy ({{Wiki|New York}}: Simon and Schuster, 1945) this [[attitude]] is expressed with some urbanity, and in J. O. Urmson, ed., The Concise {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of {{Wiki|Western Philosophy}} ({{Wiki|London}}: Hutchinson, 1960) with blunt rudeness (e.g., the article on {{Wiki|Schopenhauer}} is sheer personal abuse).
 
(37) Cf. III:13-18.
 
(37) Cf. III:13-18.
 
(37a) Op. cit., pp. 140-142.
 
(37a) Op. cit., pp. 140-142.
(38) R. G. Bury, trans., Sextus Empiricus, 4 vols. Vol. I, Outlines of {{Wiki|Pyrrhonism}} ({{Wiki|New York}}: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1333),p. xxx.
+
(38) R. G. Bury, trans., {{Wiki|Sextus Empiricus}}, 4 vols. Vol. I, Outlines of {{Wiki|Pyrrhonism}} ({{Wiki|New York}}: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1333),p. xxx.
 
(39) Ibid., p. xxx; Cf. also p. xxxi.
 
(39) Ibid., p. xxx; Cf. also p. xxxi.
 
(40) Ibid., p. xxxii.
 
(40) Ibid., p. xxxii.
 
(41) Ibid., p. xxxiii.
 
(41) Ibid., p. xxxiii.
(42) E.g., in what the skeptik(-+e) ag(-+o)g(-+e) ("{{Wiki|sceptical}} procedure") ([[Book]] I. Chap. 4) has to say about ataraxia (='[[samatha]]) as the end of [[life]] (I. 25-30), or about the [[svabhaava]] (physis or peri t(-+o)n ex(-+o)then hypokeimen(-+o)n) (I. 15, 22, 93, 163) , the [[relativity]] of everything (I. 135), or on non-assertion (I. 192-193) , non-determination (I. 197) , and non-apprehension (I. 200).
+
(42) E.g., in what the skeptik(-+e) ag(-+o)g(-+e) ("{{Wiki|sceptical}} procedure") ([[Book]] I. Chap. 4) has to say about {{Wiki|ataraxia}} (='[[samatha]]) as the end of [[life]] (I. 25-30), or about the [[svabhaava]] (physis or peri t(-+o)n ex(-+o)then hypokeimen(-+o)n) (I. 15, 22, 93, 163) , the [[relativity]] of everything (I. 135), or on non-assertion (I. 192-193) , non-determination (I. 197) , and non-apprehension (I. 200).
 
(43) {{Wiki|Cicero}}, De Natura Deorum; Academica, H. Rackham, ed. and trans. ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: Harvad {{Wiki|University}} Press, 1961). (44) Ibid., pp. 488-489; Academica, II (Lucullus). vi.17.
 
(43) {{Wiki|Cicero}}, De Natura Deorum; Academica, H. Rackham, ed. and trans. ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: Harvad {{Wiki|University}} Press, 1961). (44) Ibid., pp. 488-489; Academica, II (Lucullus). vi.17.
 
(45) Ibid., pp. 624-625; Academica, II (Lucullus). xxxix.122.
 
(45) Ibid., pp. 624-625; Academica, II (Lucullus). xxxix.122.
Line 139: Line 139:
 
(58) Ibid., p. 499; Academica, II (Lucullus). viii.24.
 
(58) Ibid., p. 499; Academica, II (Lucullus). viii.24.
 
(59) For some details, see my review of H. Ringgren, [[Word]] and [[Wisdom]], in {{Wiki|Oriental}} [[Art]], I, No. 4 (Spring, 1949), 196-197.
 
(59) For some details, see my review of H. Ringgren, [[Word]] and [[Wisdom]], in {{Wiki|Oriental}} [[Art]], I, No. 4 (Spring, 1949), 196-197.
(60) Some useful material has been collected by R. Gnoli in La Parola del [[passato]], I (1961), fasc. LXXVII, 153-159. See also J. Rahder's suggestions on '[[suunyataa]] in Indogaku Bukky(-+o)gaku Kenkyuu (Journal of [[Indian]] and [[Buddhist Studies]]). IX, No. 2 (1961), 754. On the other hand, I can see no [[merit]] in E. Benz's attempt to establish a direct link by claiming that {{Wiki|Plotinus}}' [[teacher]], Ammonios "[[Sakkas]]," was either a member of the [[Indian]] dynasty of the "Saki," or a "[[Sakya]]" (Sakiya, [[Sakka]]), i.e., a [[Buddhist monk]]. Orientalia Romana, I (1958), 18-20 (Instituto Italiano per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente. Serie Orientale Roma, XVII).
+
(60) Some useful material has been collected by R. Gnoli in La Parola del [[passato]], I (1961), fasc. LXXVII, 153-159. See also J. Rahder's suggestions on '[[suunyataa]] in Indogaku Bukky(-+o)gaku Kenkyuu (Journal of [[Indian]] and [[Buddhist Studies]]). IX, No. 2 (1961), 754. On the other hand, I can see no [[merit]] in E. Benz's attempt to establish a direct link by claiming that {{Wiki|Plotinus}}' [[teacher]], Ammonios "[[Sakkas]]," was either a member of the [[Indian]] {{Wiki|dynasty}} of the "Saki," or a "[[Sakya]]" (Sakiya, [[Sakka]]), i.e., a [[Buddhist monk]]. Orientalia Romana, I (1958), 18-20 (Instituto Italiano per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente. Serie Orientale Roma, XVII).
 
(61) I.e., 1.2, II.1, III.1, chaps. 4 and 5. The translations are apt to obscure the parallel, which becomes strikingly obvious as soon as the {{Wiki|Greek}} text is consulted.
 
(61) I.e., 1.2, II.1, III.1, chaps. 4 and 5. The translations are apt to obscure the parallel, which becomes strikingly obvious as soon as the {{Wiki|Greek}} text is consulted.
(62) Cf. Daisetz T. Suzuki, "Meister Eckhart and [[Buddhism]]," in [[Mysticism]], {{Wiki|Christian}} and [[Buddhist]] ({{Wiki|London}}: George Alien & Unwin Ltd., 1957), pp. 7-35.
+
(62) Cf. Daisetz T. Suzuki, "{{Wiki|Meister Eckhart}} and [[Buddhism]]," in [[Mysticism]], {{Wiki|Christian}} and [[Buddhist]] ({{Wiki|London}}: George Alien & Unwin Ltd., 1957), pp. 7-35.
 
(63) For a good description, see Tauler, "{{Wiki|Sermon}} on St. {{Wiki|John the Baptist}}," in The Inner Wary: 36 Sermons for {{Wiki|Festivals}}. [[New translation]], edited with Introduction by Arthur Wollaston Hutton ({{Wiki|London}}: Methuen & Co., Ltd., 1901), pp. 97-99. Cf. St. John of the Cross, Noche Oscura, Vol. I, [[Book]] 2, chap. 17.
 
(63) For a good description, see Tauler, "{{Wiki|Sermon}} on St. {{Wiki|John the Baptist}}," in The Inner Wary: 36 Sermons for {{Wiki|Festivals}}. [[New translation]], edited with Introduction by Arthur Wollaston Hutton ({{Wiki|London}}: Methuen & Co., Ltd., 1901), pp. 97-99. Cf. St. John of the Cross, Noche Oscura, Vol. I, [[Book]] 2, chap. 17.
 
(64) E.g., L. Brunschvicg, ed., Pens‚es (14th ed., {{Wiki|Paris}}: Hachette, 1927), p. 350.
 
(64) E.g., L. Brunschvicg, ed., Pens‚es (14th ed., {{Wiki|Paris}}: Hachette, 1927), p. 350.
Line 157: Line 157:
 
(76) Ibid., pp. 144, 219-220.
 
(76) Ibid., pp. 144, 219-220.
 
(77) Ibid., p. 115, liebheyt.
 
(77) Ibid., p. 115, liebheyt.
(78) Cf. R. Fussell, The [[Nature]] and Purpose of the [[Ascetic]] {{Wiki|Ideal}} (Kandy, [[Ceylon]]: [[Buddhist]] Publication {{Wiki|Society}}, 1960). H. v. Glasenapp, [[Die]] Philosophie der Inder (Stuttgart: Alfre Kroener Verlag, 1958), pp. 428-429.
+
(78) Cf. R. Fussell, The [[Nature]] and Purpose of the [[Ascetic]] {{Wiki|Ideal}} ({{Wiki|Kandy}}, [[Ceylon]]: [[Buddhist]] Publication {{Wiki|Society}}, 1960). H. v. Glasenapp, [[Die]] Philosophie der Inder (Stuttgart: Alfre Kroener Verlag, 1958), pp. 428-429.
 
(79) E. F. J. Payne, trans., The [[World]] as Will and [[Representation]] (WWR), 2 vols. ([[Indian]] Hills, {{Wiki|Colorado}}: The Falcon's Wing Press, 1958), p. 613. Vol. II.
 
(79) E. F. J. Payne, trans., The [[World]] as Will and [[Representation]] (WWR), 2 vols. ([[Indian]] Hills, {{Wiki|Colorado}}: The Falcon's Wing Press, 1958), p. 613. Vol. II.
 
(80) WWR, Vol. II, p. 608.
 
(80) WWR, Vol. II, p. 608.
Line 172: Line 172:
 
(91) {{Wiki|Plotinus}}, Enneads, VI.viii.10.
 
(91) {{Wiki|Plotinus}}, Enneads, VI.viii.10.
 
(92) Also the Megarics and Antisthenes belonged to it. Pyrrho appears to have started with the Megaric position.
 
(92) Also the Megarics and Antisthenes belonged to it. Pyrrho appears to have started with the Megaric position.
(93) S. Ranulf, Der eleatische Satz vom Widerpruch (Kopenhagen: Gyldendal, 1924). The {{Wiki|archaic}} [[character]] of {{Wiki|Parmenides}}' [[thinking]] is also shown in his [[belief]] that Being is a mass which,.as a well-rounded [[sphere]], fills [[space]]. Also the well-known works of Prant1, Apelt, Maier, E. Hoffmann ([[Die]] Sprache und [[die]] archaisthe Logik [Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1925]), and Cornford are helpful in this connection.
+
(93) S. Ranulf, Der eleatische Satz vom Widerpruch (Kopenhagen: Gyldendal, 1924). The {{Wiki|archaic}} [[character]] of {{Wiki|Parmenides}}' [[thinking]] is also shown in his [[belief]] that Being is a {{Wiki|mass}} which,.as a well-rounded [[sphere]], fills [[space]]. Also the well-known works of Prant1, Apelt, Maier, E. Hoffmann ([[Die]] Sprache und [[die]] archaisthe Logik [Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1925]), and Cornford are helpful in this connection.
 
(94) {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, [[Physics]], 185(b)33. In many passages ([[Metaphysics]], Gamma 2, 4, E 1, Z 1, K 3), {{Wiki|Aristotle}} points out that Being is said pollach(-+o)s (in many [[senses]]).
 
(94) {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, [[Physics]], 185(b)33. In many passages ([[Metaphysics]], Gamma 2, 4, E 1, Z 1, K 3), {{Wiki|Aristotle}} points out that Being is said pollach(-+o)s (in many [[senses]]).
 
(95) See R. Otto, [[Mysticism]] [[East]] and [[West]] ({{Wiki|London}}: Marmillan and Company, 1932), pp. 21-26.
 
(95) See R. Otto, [[Mysticism]] [[East]] and [[West]] ({{Wiki|London}}: Marmillan and Company, 1932), pp. 21-26.
Line 179: Line 179:
 
(98) For useful quotations see 11. Otto, op. cit., pp. 91-96.
 
(98) For useful quotations see 11. Otto, op. cit., pp. 91-96.
 
(99) According to Harold F. Hallett, Aeternitas ({{Wiki|Oxford}}: Clarendon Press, 1930), p. 45.
 
(99) According to Harold F. Hallett, Aeternitas ({{Wiki|Oxford}}: Clarendon Press, 1930), p. 45.
(100) It may be objected that the comparison of all this with [[Buddhism]] applies more to the "monistic" [[Mahaayaana]] than to the "pluralistic" [[Hiinayaana]] theories. But the difference should not be overstressed. As the [[Theravaada]] had a latent {{Wiki|idealism}} and an implicit bias toward a mentalistic interpretation of [[physical]] [[reality]] (%tienne Lamotte, L'enseignement de Vimalakiirti. BibliothŠque du Mus‚on, Vol. 51 [Louvain: Institut Orientaliste, Universite Catholique de Louvain, 1962], pp. 52-60), so it teaches also the one [[Dhamma]] side by side with the multiple [[dhammas]] (see [[Buddhaghosa]] on ekam hi saccam, na dutiiyam atthi, in [[Visuddhimagga]] of Buddhaghosaacariya, H. C. Warren, ed; rev. by Dh. [[Kosambi]], Harvard {{Wiki|Oriental}} Series, Vol. 41 ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: {{Wiki|Harvard University}} Press, 1950), pp. 422, 421.
+
(100) It may be objected that the comparison of all this with [[Buddhism]] applies more to the "{{Wiki|monistic}}" [[Mahaayaana]] than to the "pluralistic" [[Hiinayaana]] theories. But the difference should not be overstressed. As the [[Theravaada]] had a latent {{Wiki|idealism}} and an implicit bias toward a mentalistic interpretation of [[physical]] [[reality]] (%tienne [[Wikipedia:Étienne Lamotte|Lamotte]], L'enseignement de [[Vimalakiirti]]. BibliothŠque du Mus‚on, Vol. 51 [Louvain: Institut Orientaliste, Universite Catholique de Louvain, 1962], pp. 52-60), so it teaches also the one [[Dhamma]] side by side with the multiple [[dhammas]] (see [[Buddhaghosa]] on ekam hi saccam, na dutiiyam [[atthi]], in [[Visuddhimagga]] of Buddhaghosaacariya, H. C. Warren, ed; rev. by Dh. [[Kosambi]], {{Wiki|Harvard}} {{Wiki|Oriental}} Series, Vol. 41 ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: {{Wiki|Harvard University}} Press, 1950), pp. 422, 421.
 
(101) A purely [[intellectual]] {{Wiki|contradiction}} reduces [[thought]] to nothing. It results in nonsense. He who [[thinks]] a {{Wiki|contradiction}} [[thinks]] nothing at all.
 
(101) A purely [[intellectual]] {{Wiki|contradiction}} reduces [[thought]] to nothing. It results in nonsense. He who [[thinks]] a {{Wiki|contradiction}} [[thinks]] nothing at all.
 
(102) Or, in other words, that his Pythagorean opponents cannot assert the [[reality]] of {{Wiki|movement}} without coming into conflict with their own premises. These opponents assumed that a line consists of indivisible points in juxtaposition, and the counter-arguments of Hobbes ( Works, I. 110), Bergson, and {{Wiki|Aristotle}} take no notice of the historical situation. The contradictions involved can be seen succinctly in [[Hegel]], History of [[Philosophy]], Haldane, trans., 1892, I. 273-274; cf. [[Logic]], I. 191-193, II. 143 sq.; F. Engels, Herrn Eugen Dhrings Umw„lzung der Wissenschaft, 3rd ed. (Stuttgart: J. H. W. Dietz, 1894), 120; E. {{Wiki|Conze}}, [[Philosophy]] (see note 87), p. 21).
 
(102) Or, in other words, that his Pythagorean opponents cannot assert the [[reality]] of {{Wiki|movement}} without coming into conflict with their own premises. These opponents assumed that a line consists of indivisible points in juxtaposition, and the counter-arguments of Hobbes ( Works, I. 110), Bergson, and {{Wiki|Aristotle}} take no notice of the historical situation. The contradictions involved can be seen succinctly in [[Hegel]], History of [[Philosophy]], Haldane, trans., 1892, I. 273-274; cf. [[Logic]], I. 191-193, II. 143 sq.; F. Engels, Herrn Eugen Dhrings Umw„lzung der Wissenschaft, 3rd ed. (Stuttgart: J. H. W. Dietz, 1894), 120; E. {{Wiki|Conze}}, [[Philosophy]] (see note 87), p. 21).

Revision as of 18:31, 3 January 2015

Buddha-face.jpg
Medi837392.jpeg
Keha45.jpg
10fdf73 n.jpg
DharmaChakra414.jpg
Mo es.jpg
Kuh0118.JPG
BZmwjrge.jpg
30a18cf9 o.jpg
2655414 n.jpg
Su 06A.jpg
IMG c61-vi.jpg
Cundi bodhisattva05.jpg
Sd.jpg
Vimāna46.jpg

By Edward Conze
Philosophy East and West 13, p.9-23, no.1, January 1963.



The search for philosophical parallels is fraught with pit-falls. Some parallels are fruitful and significant, others incidental and fortuitous. I now propose to discuss the European parallels to Buddhist thought in two articles, of which the first is devoted to the true, and the second to the spurious, parallels.

As for my interpretation of the basic principles of Buddhism, I have recently given it in some detail in Buddhist Thought in India.(1) Since my views differ to some extent from those of my predecessors, I will briefly sum them up so that the reader can see what kind of "Buddhism" I compare with European philosophy.

The basic teaching of the Buddha can be expressed in one sentence: The conditioned world as it appears to us is fundamentally and irreparably undesirable, and salvation can be found only through escape to the Unconditioned, also called "Nirvaa.na." Everything else is elaboration.

All conditioned things are marred by having three "marks, " i.e., by being impermanent, "ill," and "alien to our true self."(2) Much thought has gone into determining the full meaning of those marks. "Ill," for instance, comprises not only pain and suffering, but also the unease which is nowadays known as "existential anxiety,"(3) and the mark of "not-self" has given rise to interminable discussions.(4) Human beings fret against a world which is impermanent, ill, and not-self and are not content to live in it, because they believe that in the core of their own being they are eternal, at ease, and in full control of everything.(5) This alienation of our empirical personality from our true being (i.e., from the "Tathaagata" within us(6) )is brought about by "craving."(7)

If we want to return to our original state of purity, we must first regenerate ourselves by developing five cardinal virtues,(8) of which wisdom is the last and most important. After these virtues have sufficiently matured, we can slowly attempt a break-through to the Unconditioned,(9) which, through the three doors of deliverance, i.e., Emptiness, the Signless, and the Wishless,(10) leads to Nirvaa.na,(11) which is a state in which the self has become extinct, in which none of this world is any longer extant, and which therefore transcends all words and concepts.(12) This is all quite simple to understand, though at times hard to believe. It is very much complicated, however, by being combined with an ontological theory of "Dharma" which requires a tremendous intellectual effort.(13) This theory distinguishes three levels of reality: [1] the one and single Dharma, which is the ultimate and unconditioned reality of Nirvaa.na;[2] a multiplicity of dharmas, or momentary and impersonal events, which, though illusory compared with the one single Dharma,(14) are more real than the things around us; and [3] the things of the common-sense world, which are mere verbal constructions, in that they are combinations of dharmas held together by words.(15) The Buddhist "dharma-theory is unique, and has no exact equivalent anywhere else.(16)

So much for the tenets of what I call "archaic" Buddhism. They were probably formulated by the time of A'soka.(16a) Two centuries later the further elaboration of these ideas led to two distinct schools, i.e., the "scholastic Hiinayaana" and the "Mahaayaana," which, contrary to what is often said, did not significantly conflict in their doctrines but merely diverged in their range of interest. The "scholastic Hiinayaana" concentrated on the conditioned dharmas, systematized their classification, defined more precisely their particular attributes and general marks, and worked out the relations pertaining among them.(18) The creative contributions of the Mahaayaana, on the other hand, almost exclusively concern the Unconditioned. In particular, the notion of "Emptiness," which in "archaic" Buddhism had been one of the avenues to Nirvaa.na, was now immensely enriched.(19) It was also buttressed by a searching analysis of the traditional concept of the "own-being" of dharmas(20) and by a type of logic which in Europe we would call "dialectical."(21) Equally applied to conditioned and unconditioned dharmas, "emptiness" led to their identification. The result is a "monistic" ontology which shows many analogies to European metaphysical systems of the same type,(22) while the descriptions of the bafflement experienced by the intellect when confronted with this one and unique Absolute resemble the position of the Greek skeptics in many ways.(23)

Of special interest for the theme of these articles is the chapter on "Tacit Assumptions,"(24) in which I compare Buddhist with contemporary mentality, and try to establish that Buddhist thinkers made a number of tacit assumptions which are explicitly rejected by modern European philosophers. The first, common to nearly all Indian, as distinct from European, "scientific," thought treats the experiences of Yoga as the chief raw material for philosophical reflection. Secondly, all "perennial"(25) (as against "modern") philosophers, agree on the hierarchical structure of the universe, as shown in (a) the distinction of a "triple world" and (b) of degrees of "reality," and (c) in the establishment of a hierarchy of insights dependent on spiritual maturity. Thirdly, all religious (as against a-religious) philosophies (a) use "numinous" as distinct from "profane" terms, and (b) treat revelation as the ultimate source of all valid knowledge.(26)

This is not how everyone sees it, and the doubting reader must be referred to the arguments of my book.

The cornerstone of my interpretation of Buddhism is the conviction shared by nearly everyone, that it is essentially a doctrine of salvation, and that all its philosophical statements are subordinate to its soteriological purpose. This implies, not only that many philosophical problems are dismissed as idle speculations,(27) but that each and every proposition must be considered in reference to its spiritual(28) intention and as a formulation of meditational experiences acquired in the course of the process of winning salvation. While I cannot imagine any scholar wishing to challenge this methodological postulate, I am aware that, next to D. T. Suzuki, I am almost alone in having applied it consistently.

Finally, any interpretation of Buddhism which goes beyond the indiscriminate accumulation of quotations and attempts actual1y to understand Buddhist thought involves an element of choice, in that one has to decide which one among the numerous presentations of the Buddha's doctrine should be regarded as the most authentic. Buston favors the Buddhisn of the Paala period, Frauwallner the Yogaacaarins, Oldenberg the Palii Canon (minus the Abhidhamma), Stcherbatsky the scholastic Hiinayaana and the later logicians, D. T. Suzuki the early Mahaayaana and Zen, some Chinese schools the Saddharmapu.n.dariika, and so on. With Professor Murti, I regard the Maadhyamikas as representing the central tradition of Buddhism, and believe that with them Buddhist theorizing reached its full maturity. This preference colors much of what I have to say.

What, then, is the relation of these Buddhist teachings to European philosophy? From the outset, I must admit that I do not believe in a clear-cut distinction between "Eastern" and "Western" mentality. Until about 1450, as branches of the same "perennial philosophy, "(29) Indian and European philosophers disagreed less among themselves than with many of the later developments of European philosophy. The "perennial philosophy" is in this context defined as a doctrine which holds [1] that as far as worth-while knowledge is concerned not all men are equal, but that there is a hierarchy of persons, some of whom, through what they are, can know much more than others; [2] that there is a hierarchy also of the levels of reality, some of which are more "real," because more exalted than others; and [3] that the wise men of old have found a "wisdom" which is true, although it has no "empirical" basis in observations which can be made by everyone and everybody; and that in fact there is a rare and unordinary faculty in some of us by which we can attain direct contact with actual reality--through the praj~naa (paaramitaa) of the Buddhists, the logos of Parmenides,(30) the sophia of Aristotle(31) and others, Spinoza's amor dei intellectualis, Hegel's Vernunft, and so on; and [4] that true teaching is based on an authority which legitimizes itself by the exemplary life and charismatic quality of its exponents.

Within the perennial philosophy Indian thought is marked off by two special features: [1] the reliance on yoga as providing the basic raw material of worth-while experience,(32) and [2] the implicit belief in karma and rebirth. Yoga, of course, has its counterpart in the West in the spiritual and ecstatic practices of contemplatives, and belief in reincarnation is nearly world-wide,(33) though rare among philosophers accorded academic recognition.

Then, after 1450, the East fell asleep and lived on its inherited capital, until in the end innate lethargy and aggression from the outside brought it to its present impasse. In the West, a large number of philosophers discarded the basic presuppositions of the "perennial philosophy," and developed by contrast what for want of a better term we may call a "sciential"(34) philosophy. That has the following features: [1] Natural science, particularly that dealing with inorganic matter, has a cognitive value, tells us about the actual structure of the universe, and provides the other branches of knowledge with an ideal standard in that they are the more "scientific" the more they are capable of mathematical formulation and the more they rely on repeatable and publicly verified observations. [2] Man is the highest of beings known to science, and his power and convenience should be promoted at all costs. [3] Spiritual and magical forces cannot influence events, and life after death may be disregarded, because it is unproven by scientific methods. [4] In consequence, "life" means "man's" life in this world, and the task is to ameliorate this life by a social "technique" in harmony with the "welfare" or "will" of "the people." Buddhists must view all these tenets with the utmost distaste.

"Sciential" philosophy is an ideology which corresponds to a technological civilization. It arises in its purity only to the extent that its social substratum has freed itself from all pre-industrial influences, and in the end it must lead to the elimination of even the last traces of what could properly be called "philosophy" in the original sense of "love of wisdom." For centuries it existed only blended with elements from the traditional "perennial" philosophy. As philosophies, both the "perennial" and the "sciential" systems possess some degree of intellectuality, and up to a point they both use reasoning. But considered in their purity, as ideal types, they differ in that the first is motivated by man's spiritual(35) needs, and aims at his salvation from the world and its ways, whereas the second is motivated by his utilitarian needs, aims at his conquest of the world, and is therefore greatly concerned with the natural and social sciences. Between the two extremes there are, of course, numerous intermediary stages. They depend to some extent on the quality of the spirituality behind them, which is very high, say, in Buddhism, slightly lower in Plato and Aristotle, and still quite marked in such men as Spinoza, Leibniz, Berkeley, Kant, Goethe, Hegel, and Bergson. The general trend, however, has been a continuous loss of spiritual substance between 1450 and 1960, based on an increasing forgetfulness of age-old traditions, an increasing unawareness of spiritual practices, and an increasing indifference to the spiritual life by the classes which dominate society.

Leaving aside the relative merits of the "perennial" and the "sciential" approaches to philosophy, all I want to establish at present is their mutual incompatibility, which is borne out by their mutual hostility. Our "sciential" philosophers are well aware of this. We need only peruse the writings of empiricists, logical positivists, and linguistic analysts, and it will become obvious that the animosity displayed toward a philosopher is almost a measure of his spirituality.(36) And, in a way, the moderns are quite right. For "perennial" and "sciential" philosophies represent two qualitatively different kinds of thinking which have almost nothing in common, except perhaps for a certain degree of respect for rationality. Our contemporaries continually assure us that the spiritual philosophers of the past are not "philosophers" at all, but dreamers, mystics, poets, and so on. All we can conclude from this is that the word "philosophy" is being used in two quite disparate senses: [1] as the pursuit of "wisdom," and [2] as a "rigorous" academic exercise without much ostensible purpose. The "wisdom" meant here is compounded of knowledge and a "good life," and to it apply the words of Proverbs: "Blessed is the man who has found wisdom. Her ways are good ways, and all her paths are peaceful. She is a tree of life to all that lay hold upon her."(37) It is not easy to how such words could be used of "philosophy" in the second sense.

Having stated the general principles on which the comparison of Buddhist and European thought must be based, I now speak of the only three currents of European philosophy which can significantly be compared with Buddhism, i.e., [1] the Greek Skeptics, [2] the wisdom-seeking mystics, and [3] the monists and dialecticians.

[1] The European system nearest to the Maadhyamikas is that of the Greek Skeptics. In my Buddhism,(37a) I have shown their close similarity, both in intention and structure. They also agree in that the history of skepticism exhibits the same tendency to deviate into a purely theoretical intellectualism which has continually threatened the integrity of Buddhist thought. Greek Skepticism went through four stages, which R. G. Bury(38) has called the practical, the critical, the dialectical, and the empirical. The parallel with Buddhism is closest in the first stage, i.e., with Pyrrho (360-275 B.C.).In the last, with Sextus Empiricus (A.D. 160-210), it is barely perceptible. Indeed, taking the later developments as his norm, Bury can affirm that Pyrrho "was probably not at all a full-blown Sceptic, but rather a moralist of an austere and ascetic type who cultivated insensibility to externals and superiority to environment."(39) It was only in the New Academy, with Arcesilas (315-241 B.C.), that Skepticism "ceased to be purely practical and became mainly theoretical."(40) "Thus, while Pyrrho had renounced and Timon flouted the Dogmatists, Arcesilas started the practice of refuting them scientifically and systematically, and earned thereby the abuse of Timon for his lapse from pure Pyrrhonism."(41) In fact, when we read Sextus Empiricus, we find that, although some of the original message has remained intact,(42) it has been overlaid by a vast technical apparatus accumulated over five centuries and by numerous concessions to common sense. The bulk of Sextus' work is parasitical on the dogmatic philosophers, and seems to be motivated more by disputatiousness and the desire to score debating points than by a positive interest in mental repose. In many ways his attitude resembles that of the later Buddhist logicians.

At the time of Cicero, halfway between Pyrrho and Sextus Empiricus, this loss of spiritual earnestness had not gone quite so far. Some of the statements which Cicero makes in his Academica,(43) on behalf of or in response to the Skeptics, are indeed strikingly similar to the teachings of the Maadhyamikas and other later Buddhists.

The Skeptics were people who "sanctioned nothing as proved" (qui nibil probarent(44)). "All those things you talk about are hidden, closely concealed (occultata) and enfolded in thick clouds of darkness, so that no human intellect has sufficiently powerful sight to be able to penetrate to heaven and get inside the earth."(45) Though "it is possibly the case that when exposed and uncovered they change their character" (quia possit fieri ut patefacta et detecta mutentur).(46) The Skeptics "have a habit of concealing (occultandi) their opinion, and do not usually disclose it to any one except those that had lived with them right up to old age."(47) And the opponent says, "What pray are those holy secrets (mysteria) of yours, or why should your school conceal (celatis) its doctrine as something disgraceful?"(48)

"It is the wise man (sapiens) that we are investigating,"(49) and it is on him that "all this enquiry turns."(50) He "avoids being taken in and sees to it that he is nor deceived."(51) They hold that "nothing can be perceived,"(52) or grasped (comprehendi, anupalabdhi),(53) and the "wise man will restrain all acts of assent" (adsensus, abhinive'sa).(54) There is also a reference to the "perversity" (pravitas) of seeing the non-real as real,(55) and to arguments against the senses, which are said to be "full of darkness,"(56) and against "everything that is approved in common experience" (consuetudo = sa^mv.rti).(57) And, as though he had read the Praj~naapaaramitaa, an opponent points out that "as for wisdom herself, if she does not know whether she is wisdom or not, how in the first place will she make good her claim to the name of wisdom? Next, how will she venture with confidence to plan or execute any undertaking when there will be nothing certain for her to act upon?"(58)

[2] Secondly, there is a close similarity with those ascetic, other-worldly, and "mystical" thinkers who assigned a decisive importance to "spiritual experience." They are represented by four main trends:

(a) First, there are the Wisdom speculations of the Near East between 200 B.C. and A.D. 300. Their conception of chochma and sophia is closely analogous to that of praj~naapaaramitaa, and some of the similarities are really quite startling.(59)
(b) Next, the kindred Gnostic and Neo-Platonic modes of thought, especially the later Neo-Platonists, like Proclus and Damascius,(60) and also their Christian form in Origenes and in Dionysius Areopagita, who in some passages of his Mystical Theology(61) gives what may well be called a Christian version of the Heart Suutra.
(c) Thirdly, there are the great mystics of the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries, such as Meister Eckhart,(62) Ruysbroeck, and Suso. Their kinship with Buddhism has been noted so often that I can be quite brief. Ruysbroeck says of the "God-seeing man" that "his spirit is undifferentiated and without distinction, and therefore feels nothing without the unity." Among Western contemplatives, suunyataa corresponds to the "desert of the Godhead," to Ruysbroeck's "idle emptiness," to Eckhart's still wilderness where no one is at home, to the "naked orison," the "naked intent stretching unto God," which becomes possible with entire self-surrender, and also to the fathomless abyss of Ruysbroeck and Tauler.(63) This "abyss" is wholeheartedly welcomed by those steeped in self-negation and self-naughting, but, later on, less selfless people like B. Pascal(64) and Ch. Baudelaire(65) felt rather ambivalent when confronted with it, since they were clearly none too enchanted with the implication of being "separated from all created things." The Theologia Germanica(66) (ca, 1425), as is well known, contains many formulations with a distinctly Buddhist flavor. The most striking similarity lies, of course, in the constant emphasis on "I-hood and selfhood," on "I, me, and mine" as the source of all alienation from true reality, and on the need to undo that "blindness and folly."(67) But this is not all. On re-reading the book I have been astounded to find how close it is in so many ways to Buddhist mentality, in spite of its author's "cautious limitation of his speculations to what is compatible with the Church,"(68) and some minor concessions to theism, especially in the later parts. Apart from the subject of satkaayad.r.s.ti this is true of what is said about the Godhead (= Nirvaa.na), the "deified man" (= the bodhisattva), activated by both "cognition" and a "love" wherein "there neither is nor can remain any I, Me, Mine, Thou, Thine, and the like, "(69) non-attainment, (70) the perverted views, (71) self-deception (= avidyaa),(72) Suchness, (73) faith, (74) the One, (75) emptiness, (76) desire, (77) and so on--in fact, quite an impressive list.
(d) Toward the end of the seventeenth century, shortly after Galileo, European mysticism of this type lost its intellectual distinction, and faded away into the "Quietism" of Molinos and Mme Guyon. In the aftermath of the French revolution, many of the basic laws of the spiritual life were rediscovered by great poets who were also fine thinkers, such as Blake, Shelley, Wordsworth, and Coleridge in England. Though often vitiated by a fatal rift between theory and practice, their thought offers many parallels to Buddhist thinking. To this generation of rebels against the Goddess of Reason belonged Arthur Schopenhauer, whose thought, partly under Indian influence, exhibits numerous, and almost miraculous, coincidences with the basic tenets of Buddhist philosophy.(78) The term "parallel" implies that two lines run parallel at more than one point, and the degree of affinity existing between Schopenhauer and Buddhism will give us a standard by which to judge other alleged "parallels."

As he himself said, Schopenhauer continued the triple tradition of "quietism, i.e. the giving up of all willing, asceticism, i.e. intentional mortification of one's own will, and mysticism, i.e. consciousness of the identity of one's own inner being with that of all beings, or with the kernel of the world."(79) He shows that life in the world is meaningless, essentially suffering, and bound to disappoint the hope that our desires might be fulfilled. He attributes this suffering to "the will to live," which is the equivalent of t.r.s.naa, and which "involves us in a delusion." He looks for salvation from this world by way of a "denial of the will to live," which is a "consequence of the dawning of better knowledge,"(80) and by an asceticism and self-renunciation exemplified in "the lives of saints, penitents, sama.nas, sannyaasins, and so on."(81) We may add his atheism, his denial of an immaterial, substantially unchanging, soul, his belief in reincarnation, his stress on compassion as the basis of morality, his indifference to the "achievements" or "rhythm" of human history,(82) as well as his insight into impermanence(83) and into the reasons why Nirvaa.na can be described only negatively, and yet it is not nothing.(84)

It is only on two points that he differs from Buddhism.

(A) He fails to appreciate the importance of disciplined meditation. Educated non-Catholic Germans of the nineteenth century were quite unfamiliar with the tradition of spiritual contemplation. On the other hand, for relaxation they habitually visited art galleries and went for walks in the countryside. It is no wonder, therefore, that Schopenhauer sees the foretaste of "the exalted peace" of Nirvaa.na, not in trances (dhyaana), but in "pure esthetic contemplation." Although the contemplation of beauty has some analogy to the conditions prevailing in trance, it is on the whole an undisciplined faculty, and its results are rather fleeting and have little power to transmute the personality. In this respect, the German bourgeois town-dweller was a lesser man than the Indian man in the forest.
(B) Secondly, Schopenhauer teaches that the Will is the Thing-in-itself, whereas in Buddhism "craving" operates within the conditioned and phenomenal world, and the unconditioned noumenon lies in Nirvaa.na, which is quite calm as the result of the abolition of craving. Unacquainted with the practice of yoga, Schopenhauer did not know that at the bottom of every mind there is a calm quietude which is the prototype of Nirvaa.na. His central metaphysical thesis is, however, incompatible, not only with Buddhism, but also with his own soteriological aspirations. It is, indeed, not only hard to see how any cognitive act can ever reach the Thing-in-itself, but it also remains incomprehensible how thought can ever have the strength to stand up against the Will, and, what is more, how as a part of the purely illusory phenomenal world it can possibly overcome and effectively "deny" it.(85) This was early recognized by Nietzsche(86) and J. Bahnsen(87) (1881), Schopenhauer's immediate successors, and led them, respectively, into nihilism and a pessimism unrelieved by the hope of escape.
(C) Furthermore, Buddhism has a distinct affinity with the "monistic" traditions of European thought. The Eleatic emphasis on the One(88) implied devaluation, depreciation, and at times even rejection of the plural and multiple world. However they may phrase it, all monistic systems are in tune with the feeling which Shelley formulated in the famous verse:

        Life, like a dome of many-coloured glass
        Stains the white radiance of eternity
        Until death tramples it to fragments.(89)

Parmenides (ca. 480 B.C., nearly the Buddha's contemporary) and his successors assume a radical difference between appearance and reality, between surface and depth, between what we see (phainomena) and what we can only think (noumena), between opinion and truth. For Parmenides, opinion (d.r.s.ti) is derived from the senses, which are deceptive and the basis of false information. Truth is derived from the logos, which has for its object Being (that which is and has no other attributes but to be). Being is, non-being is not; and that which Is can never not be, either now or later (as in change). Nothing that Is can either arise or perish.(90)

All monistic systems are remarkably uniform, and they are all equally beset by at least four unavoidable difficulties. They must, first of all, try to guard against the misunderstanding that the One might be a datum within the world, or a part of the conglomeration. Both East and West acutely felt the difficulties of finding an adequate verbal expression for the essentially transcendent and elusive reality of the One, and both made many attempts to circumvent them by the use of paradoxes, absurdities, contradictions, tautologies, riddles, negations, and other devices. Secondly, the monists must attempt to maintain the simplicity of the One by redefining the meaning of predication in regard to it. In this context, scholastic philosophers explained that God is each of his predicates, whereas creatures have them, and that the predicates of God are not different from one another, since otherwise he would not be simple. "The absolute essence is not in one respect different from what it is in another; what it is, it is in the totality of its being."(91) Everything plural is itself and in addition something else, and only the completely free can be itself pure and simple.

A third problem concerns the relation between the One and Being. The old Eleatic school, which flourished between 540 and 300 B.C.,(92) identifies the two. One must bear in mind, however, that in doing so it uses a special archaic, pre-Atistotelian type of logic(93) which, among other things, employs "the principle of unlimited predication." This means that a predicate is either predicated without limitation of the subject or it is not valid at all. This logic only knows statements of the type "All A are all B," which predicate the entire P of the entire S, without any qualification as to time, part, or respect, without any distinction being made between total and partial identity of S and P, or between their partial and total difference. The Eleatics also "assumed that one speaks only in one sense (monachos) of 'one' and 'being.'"(94) The victory of Aristotelian logic changed all that. Plotinus describes the One expressly as "beyond being"; for Meister Eckhart, who said that "in the Kingdom of Heaven all is in all, all is one, and all is ours," Pure Being, as the most general, becomes the richest of all terms;(95) and Hegel, again, treats "being" as the initial and minimal definition of the Absolute, which is later enriched by many further "attributes." The Theologia Germanica(96) says that "he who finds satisfaction in God, his satisfaction is the One, and is all in the One. And he to whom the One is not all and all not the One, and to Whom something and nothing are not one and the same, cannot find satisfaction in God." The Buddhist non-dual One was in the same way by many devices transferred beyond all logical categories.

And, fourthly, monists must come to some decision on the status of appearance. It may well be that not all of them have, like most Buddhists, regarded appearance as a mere illusion, and it is probably true that' "there is never any suggestion in Plotinus that all things except the One are illusions or fleeting appearances."(97) But this is a distinction without much of a difference, because also in the Plotinian system the sensory and material world has an extremely low degree of reality, and is afflicted by a great loss of the original reality, near its point of extinction. In the same way, in the Hegelian system the natural world is a state of estrangement from the Absolute Spirit. In Eckhart, "all creatures, insofar as they are creatures, as they are in themselves (quod sunt in et per se), are not even an illusion, but they are a pure nothing."(98) And, for Spinoza, "a temporal existence insofar as it is purely temporal is the same as non-existence, and is perishing in proportion to its fragmentariness and exclusiveness; existence in every range insofar as it gains content move already towards an ideal of perfection which is one with eternity itself."(99)

The background of all "monistic" views(100) is a religious contempt for the world of ordinary experience, for that which is not One or not He who Is. That world is held to be unsatisfactory---partly emotionally as a source of suffering, and partly logically as self-contradictory, and as therefore either non-existing(101) or unable to abide in the state in which it is. In this way monism is apt to beget the dialectics out of itself, as in Zeno, Hegel, and Bradley, to name only a few. In the case of Zeno of Elea (ca. 460 B.C.), whom Aristotle called the founder of the dialectics, the "paradoxes" (aporiai) he devised aimed at defending by indirect proofs the view of Parmenides, which held local movement to be impossible in the ultimate reality of the true world of being. All Zeno did was to show that, on assuming movement, the consequences which follow are contradictory and untenable,(102) and that, therefore, the information derived from sense-data is patently false, since selfcontradictions are the marks of false appearance.

Zeno's dialectics has had many successors. Among them, Bradley seems nearer to the Maadhyamikas than either Hegel or Marx. Both Hegel and Marx make two assumptions which must irritate Buddhists. The first is the insistence on human history, (103) which Buddhists hold to be utterly pointless. The second is the constant introduction of the tripartite scheme of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, which postulates a relentless "progress" from one state to the other, culminating in the tyranny of the Prussian state or of the U.S.S.R. On the other hand, Bradley is, next to Schopenhauer, the nearest representative in modern Europe of at least one side of Buddhist thought. Even the procedure of Appearance and Reality is the same as that of the Maadhyamikakaarikaa, in that one currently accepted category after the other is taken up and shown to be self-contradictory and untenable. Nor can I agree with Professor Murti's(l04) claim that they differ greatly "in their notion of the Real and its relation to appearance." In fact, they both treat the Real as ineffable, and "at once transcendent and immanent."(105) If Bradley takes care not to exclude entirely the appearance from the Real, and seeks somehow to identify the two,(106) then this is not a "rather inconsistent contention,"(107) but the exact equivalent of the Maadhyamika position ("Form is emptiness, " etc.). Both these books are essentially polemical treatises and their message seems to be identical.

 part two of this essay: Spurious Parallels to Buddhist Philosophy

NOTES

(1) Buddhist Thought in India (London: George Alien & Unwin Ltd., 1962). Hereafter BThl.
(2) BThl, pp. 34-43.
(3) To be discussed in Section 2b of the second article, "Spurious Parallels to Buddhist Philosophy," to be published in the next issue of this Journal.
(4) About its relation to Hume's denial of a "self," see Section 3 of the second article.
(5) BThl, pp. 43-46.
(6) It is "A central peace, subsisting at the heart/Of endless agitation" (W. Wordsworth). See below, p. 18.
(7) See below, p.19.
(8) BThIl, pp. 47-55.
(9) Ibid., pp. 56-58.
(10) Ibid., pp. 59-69.
(11) Ibid., pp. 69-79.
(12) "The teachings of European mystics correspond to this doctrine in its general tone (see below, pp. 17-18), but only Schopenhauer matches it in many particulars (see below, pp. 18-20).
(13) BThI, pp. 92-106.
(14) Ibid., pp. 223-225 (see below, p. 22).
(15) Ibid., p. 97n.
(16) See Section 2a of the second article. (16a)274-236 B.C.
(17) BThI, pp. 119-191.
(18) Ibid., pp. 148-158.
(19) Ibid., pp. 242-249.
(20) Ibid., pp. 239-241 (see Section 1 of the second article).
(21) BThI, pp. 261--264; also below, pp. 22-23.
(22) See below, pp. 20-22.
(23) See below, pp. 15-17.
(24) BThI, pp. 17-30.
(25) For a definition, see below, pp. 12-13.
(26) BThI, p. 17.
(27) Sections 1 and 3 of the second article.
(28) For a definition, see below, p. 14, note 35.
(29) This term. was originally invented by Catholics to describe the philosophy of St. Thomas and Aristotle. It was then taken over by Aldous Huxley and others, and my definition is akin to that of Ananda Coomaraswamy. A. Huxley in his famous book of 1946 'envisaged only the mystical school, whereas here i include the intellectual and speculative trends, i.e., Plato and Aristotle as well as the German idealists. The only people before 1450 who are excluded are those who, like the Lokaayatikas in India, were deliberately antispiritual, but not necessarily the Epicureans who were anticlerical but no foes of a tranquil and serene life.
(30) Being for him is "one" kata ton logon (when seen by reason) , "many" kata t(-+e) aisth(-+e)in (when seen by perception) . Aristotle, Metaphysics, I.986(b)33-34.
(31) "In his Metaphysics, Aristotle has taken great pains to describe the subjective counterpart of "being as being," e.g., in Book I.981(b)-983(a).
(32) "Notre philosophie est n‚e de la curiosit? et du besoin de savoir, d'expliquer le monde d'une fa‡on coh‚rente. En Inde la philosophie est l'interpretation rationelle de l'exp‚rience mystique." So Constantin Regamey, on page 251 of what is one of the most notable contributions so far made to comparative philosophy, i.e., "Tendences et m‚thodes de la philosophie indienne compar‚es celles de la philosophie occidentale, " Revue de Th‚ologie et de Philosophie, IV (1951), 245-262. Regamey also shows how this difference in the point de d‚part leads to a radical divergence in the criteria of absolute truth. (33) Joseph Head and S. L. Cranson, eds., Reincarnation: An East-West Anthology (New York: The Julian Press, Inc., 1961).
(34) The opponents of the perennial philosophy prefer to describe themselves as "scientific." There can be nothing more unscientific, however, than the drawing of extravagant and presumptuous conclusions about the mind, soul, and spirit of man, and about his destiny and the purpose of his life, from a few observations about the expansion of gases, the distribution of moths, and the reflections of the celestial bodies in little pieces of glass. If I were reduced to that part of myself which can be seen in bits of glass, I would certainly feel that most of my being was omitted. Why should this not be true also of other things apart from my own dear self?
(35) I have defined the word "spiritual" in my Buddhism (3rd ed., Oxford: Bruno Cassirer, 1957) on page 11. The quintessence of the spiritual life, shorn of its usual accretions, was admirably formulated by Petrus Damiani in the eleventh century in two exceedingly fine poems which have recently been reprinted in F. J. E. Raby, ed., The Oxford Book of Medieval Latin Verse (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959), pp. 185-189. The second has also been translated into English in Frederick Brittain, ed., The Penguin Book of Latin Verse (Harmondsworth, England: Penguin Books, Ltd., 1962), pp. 176-180.
(36) To mention just two easily accessible sources: In Bertrand Russell's A History of Western Philorophy (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1945) this attitude is expressed with some urbanity, and in J. O. Urmson, ed., The Concise Encyclopedia of Western Philosophy (London: Hutchinson, 1960) with blunt rudeness (e.g., the article on Schopenhauer is sheer personal abuse).
(37) Cf. III:13-18.
(37a) Op. cit., pp. 140-142.
(38) R. G. Bury, trans., Sextus Empiricus, 4 vols. Vol. I, Outlines of Pyrrhonism (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1333),p. xxx.
(39) Ibid., p. xxx; Cf. also p. xxxi.
(40) Ibid., p. xxxii.
(41) Ibid., p. xxxiii.
(42) E.g., in what the skeptik(-+e) ag(-+o)g(-+e) ("sceptical procedure") (Book I. Chap. 4) has to say about ataraxia (='samatha) as the end of life (I. 25-30), or about the svabhaava (physis or peri t(-+o)n ex(-+o)then hypokeimen(-+o)n) (I. 15, 22, 93, 163) , the relativity of everything (I. 135), or on non-assertion (I. 192-193) , non-determination (I. 197) , and non-apprehension (I. 200).
(43) Cicero, De Natura Deorum; Academica, H. Rackham, ed. and trans. (Cambridge: Harvad University Press, 1961). (44) Ibid., pp. 488-489; Academica, II (Lucullus). vi.17.
(45) Ibid., pp. 624-625; Academica, II (Lucullus). xxxix.122.
(46) Ibid.
(47) Ibid., pp, 462-463; Academica, fragment No. 21.
(48) Ibid., pp, 542-543; Academica, II (Lucullus). xviii.60.
(49) Ibid., pp. 550-551; Academica, II (Lucullus). xx.66.
(50) Ibid., pp. 614-615; Academica, II (Lucullus). xxxvi.115.
(51) Ibid., pp. 550-551; Academica, II (Lucullus). xx.66.
(52) Ibid., pp. 550-551, 554-555, 608-609, 489-490, 542-543. They "do not deny that some truth exists, but deny that it can be perceived" (qui veri esse aliquid non negamus, percipi posse negamus). II. xxiii.73.
(53) Ibid., pp. 620-621; Academica, II (Lucullus). xxxviii.119.
(54) Ibid., pp. 554-555; Academica, II (Lucullus). xxi.68.
(55) Ibid., pp. 566-567; Academica, II (Lucullus). xxv.80.
(56) Ibid., p. 559; Academica, II (Lucullus). xxiii.73.
(57) Ibid., pp. 562-563; Academica, II (Lucullus). xxiv.75.
(58) Ibid., p. 499; Academica, II (Lucullus). viii.24.
(59) For some details, see my review of H. Ringgren, Word and Wisdom, in Oriental Art, I, No. 4 (Spring, 1949), 196-197.
(60) Some useful material has been collected by R. Gnoli in La Parola del passato, I (1961), fasc. LXXVII, 153-159. See also J. Rahder's suggestions on 'suunyataa in Indogaku Bukky(-+o)gaku Kenkyuu (Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies). IX, No. 2 (1961), 754. On the other hand, I can see no merit in E. Benz's attempt to establish a direct link by claiming that Plotinus' teacher, Ammonios "Sakkas," was either a member of the Indian dynasty of the "Saki," or a "Sakya" (Sakiya, Sakka), i.e., a Buddhist monk. Orientalia Romana, I (1958), 18-20 (Instituto Italiano per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente. Serie Orientale Roma, XVII).
(61) I.e., 1.2, II.1, III.1, chaps. 4 and 5. The translations are apt to obscure the parallel, which becomes strikingly obvious as soon as the Greek text is consulted.
(62) Cf. Daisetz T. Suzuki, "Meister Eckhart and Buddhism," in Mysticism, Christian and Buddhist (London: George Alien & Unwin Ltd., 1957), pp. 7-35.
(63) For a good description, see Tauler, "Sermon on St. John the Baptist," in The Inner Wary: 36 Sermons for Festivals. New translation, edited with Introduction by Arthur Wollaston Hutton (London: Methuen & Co., Ltd., 1901), pp. 97-99. Cf. St. John of the Cross, Noche Oscura, Vol. I, Book 2, chap. 17.
(64) E.g., L. Brunschvicg, ed., Pens‚es (14th ed., Paris: Hachette, 1927), p. 350.
(65) It is quite interesting to note, when reading Les Fleurs du Mal, the varying and conflicting connotations of such key terms as gouffre, abime, and vide.
(66) New York: Pantheon Books, Inc., 1949. London: Gollancz, 1950. This is the translation of S. Winkworth, revised by W. Trask, on the basis of J. Bernhart's translation into modern German: Theologia Germanica (New York: Pantheon Books, 1949).
(67) Chaps. 1-5, 20, 22, 24, 32, 34, 40, 44, 49, 51.
(68) Bernhart, op. cit., p. 101.
(69) Ibid., pp. 191-192, 197.
(70) Ibid., pp. 167, 180, 183.
(71) Ibid., pp. 119, 186.
(72) Ibid., p. 200.
(73) Ibid., pp. 206, 240.
(74) Ibid., p. 207.
(75) Ibid., pp. 197, 204-206, 218-219.
(76) Ibid., pp. 144, 219-220.
(77) Ibid., p. 115, liebheyt.
(78) Cf. R. Fussell, The Nature and Purpose of the Ascetic Ideal (Kandy, Ceylon: Buddhist Publication Society, 1960). H. v. Glasenapp, Die Philosophie der Inder (Stuttgart: Alfre Kroener Verlag, 1958), pp. 428-429.
(79) E. F. J. Payne, trans., The World as Will and Representation (WWR), 2 vols. (Indian Hills, Colorado: The Falcon's Wing Press, 1958), p. 613. Vol. II.
(80) WWR, Vol. II, p. 608.
(81) Quoted in Fussell, op. cit., p. 1. Sama.nas = recluses; sannyaasins = ascetics.
(82) WWR. Vol. II chap. 38.
(83) WWR, Bk. I, par. 3; Bk. III, par. 33.
(84) WWR, Vol. II, pp. 608, 612.
(85) For an exceedingly clear and lucid survey of the many inconsistencies in Schopenhauer': philosophy, I must refer to H. M. Wolf, Arthur Schopenhauer. Hundert Jahre Sp„ter (Bern and Muenchen: Francke Verlag, 1960).
(86) H. M. Wolf, op. tit., pp. 36, 70, 106-107.
(87) About his "miserabilism," see E. Conze, "The Objective Validity of the Principle o: Contradiction," Philozophy, X (1935), 216.
(88) But the panta ch(-+o)rei of Herakleitos fits none too well, because not everything flows Nirvaa.na, the most important thing of all, being excepted.
(89) Good parallels can be found in P. Damiani, "The Glories of Paradise," referred to above note 35.
(90) "It never was, and it never will be, since it Is, all of it together, only present in the Now, one and indivisible." (Diels-Kranz. Fr. 8 [Simpl. Phys. 145.I.3-6].)
(91) Plotinus, Enneads, VI.viii.10.
(92) Also the Megarics and Antisthenes belonged to it. Pyrrho appears to have started with the Megaric position.
(93) S. Ranulf, Der eleatische Satz vom Widerpruch (Kopenhagen: Gyldendal, 1924). The archaic character of Parmenides' thinking is also shown in his belief that Being is a mass which,.as a well-rounded sphere, fills space. Also the well-known works of Prant1, Apelt, Maier, E. Hoffmann (Die Sprache und die archaisthe Logik [Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1925]), and Cornford are helpful in this connection.
(94) Aristotle, Physics, 185(b)33. In many passages (Metaphysics, Gamma 2, 4, E 1, Z 1, K 3), Aristotle points out that Being is said pollach(-+o)s (in many senses).
(95) See R. Otto, Mysticism East and West (London: Marmillan and Company, 1932), pp. 21-26.
(96) Pp. 204-205. Italics mine.
(97) A. H. Armstrong, Plotinus (London: G. Alien & Unwin Ltd., 1953), p. 41. For the ambiguities in Plotinus' own thought, compare Armstrong p. 21 with p. 29.
(98) For useful quotations see 11. Otto, op. cit., pp. 91-96.
(99) According to Harold F. Hallett, Aeternitas (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930), p. 45.
(100) It may be objected that the comparison of all this with Buddhism applies more to the "monistic" Mahaayaana than to the "pluralistic" Hiinayaana theories. But the difference should not be overstressed. As the Theravaada had a latent idealism and an implicit bias toward a mentalistic interpretation of physical reality (%tienne Lamotte, L'enseignement de Vimalakiirti. BibliothŠque du Mus‚on, Vol. 51 [Louvain: Institut Orientaliste, Universite Catholique de Louvain, 1962], pp. 52-60), so it teaches also the one Dhamma side by side with the multiple dhammas (see Buddhaghosa on ekam hi saccam, na dutiiyam atthi, in Visuddhimagga of Buddhaghosaacariya, H. C. Warren, ed; rev. by Dh. Kosambi, Harvard Oriental Series, Vol. 41 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1950), pp. 422, 421.
(101) A purely intellectual contradiction reduces thought to nothing. It results in nonsense. He who thinks a contradiction thinks nothing at all.
(102) Or, in other words, that his Pythagorean opponents cannot assert the reality of movement without coming into conflict with their own premises. These opponents assumed that a line consists of indivisible points in juxtaposition, and the counter-arguments of Hobbes ( Works, I. 110), Bergson, and Aristotle take no notice of the historical situation. The contradictions involved can be seen succinctly in Hegel, History of Philosophy, Haldane, trans., 1892, I. 273-274; cf. Logic, I. 191-193, II. 143 sq.; F. Engels, Herrn Eugen Dhrings Umw„lzung der Wissenschaft, 3rd ed. (Stuttgart: J. H. W. Dietz, 1894), 120; E. Conze, Philosophy (see note 87), p. 21).
(103) Hegel said that "comprehended history forms both the memorial and the calvary of the absolute Spirit--that without which it would be Lifeless (!) Solitude." He seems to have a strange view of "life," as composed of a long series of senseless oppressions and massacres perpetrated in the name of some fatuous "ideal" or other.
(104) The Central Philosophy of Buddhism (London: George Alien & Unwin Ltd., 1955), p. 308.
(105) Murti, ibid,, p. 310.
(106) Appearance and Reality: A Metaphysical Study (9th impression, corrected, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1930),p. 404.
(107) Murti, op. cit., p. 309.

Source

www.thezensite.com