Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Buddhist Logic (Volume I) Stcherbatsky (Book Review by Radhika Abeysekera)"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
Line 7: Line 7:
  
  
Biography  
+
{{Wiki|Biography}}
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky who lived from 1866 to 1942 was a Russian known as a specialist in the study of Tibet and India. A professor at St. Petersburg University in Tsarist times, Stcherbatsky was elected to the Academy of Sciences of the Soviet Union in 1918. In 1928 he assumed direction of the Institute of Buddhist Culture in Leningrad. He became renowned for his translations of Tibetan and Sanskrit. He was also the author of a number of work in English including The conception of Buddhist Nirvana (Leningrad 1927), The central conception of Buddhism and the Meaning of the word Dhamma the second edition of which was published in Calcutta in 1956 and his two volumes of Buddhist Logic. His work has been translated to German, French and Japanese. Contemporary Soviet scholars note that his work remains unsurpassed to this date. Stcherbatsky died on March 18, 1942.  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] who lived from 1866 to 1942 was a {{Wiki|Russian}} known as a specialist in the study of [[Tibet]] and [[India]]. A [[professor]] at {{Wiki|St. Petersburg}} {{Wiki|University}} in Tsarist times, [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] was elected to the {{Wiki|Academy}} of [[Sciences]] of the {{Wiki|Soviet Union}} in 1918. In 1928 he assumed [[direction]] of the Institute of [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Culture}} in [[Wikipedia:Saint Petersburg|Leningrad]]. He became renowned for his translations of [[Tibetan]] and [[Sanskrit]]. He was also the author of a number of work in English [[including]] The {{Wiki|conception}} of [[Buddhist]] [[Nirvana]] ([[Wikipedia:Saint Petersburg|Leningrad]] 1927), The central {{Wiki|conception}} of [[Buddhism]] and the Meaning of the [[word]] [[Dhamma]] the second edition of which was published in [[Calcutta]] in 1956 and his two volumes of [[Buddhist Logic]]. His work has been translated to [[German]], {{Wiki|French}} and [[Japanese]]. Contemporary [[Soviet]] [[scholars]] note that his work remains [[unsurpassed]] to this date. [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] [[died]] on March 18, 1942.  
 
   
 
   
  
Line 15: Line 15:
 
   
 
   
  
There is a wide spread prejudice that positive philosophy is to be found only in Europe. It is also a prejudice that Aristotle, Plato Socrates and modern philosophers such as Kant, Hegel and Hume had no predecessor in this field in the East. This work considers a system of logic, but it is not Aristotelian. It is epistemological but not Kantian. It is philosophical but not Socratesan.  
+
There is a wide spread prejudice that positive [[philosophy]] is to be found only in {{Wiki|Europe}}. It is also a prejudice that {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, {{Wiki|Plato}} {{Wiki|Socrates}} and {{Wiki|modern}} [[philosophers]] such as {{Wiki|Kant}}, [[Wikipedia:Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]] and [[Hume]] had no predecessor in this field in the [[East]]. This work considers a system of [[logic]], but it is not {{Wiki|Aristotelian}}. It is [[epistemological]] but not [[Wikipedia:Immanuel Kant|Kantian]]. It is [[philosophical]] but not Socratesan.  
 
   
 
   
In his book Buddhists Logic (volume I) Stcherbatsky is addressing a system of logic and epistemology (knowledge based study) realized by the Gotama Buddha in 600 BC. A system of logic that predates Aristotle, Plato and Socrates. Of the three periods of growth and change in Buddhism Stcherbatsky has selected the most recent or third period and the philosophy expounded by two great Buddhists masters in the VI and VII century AD - the Masters Dignaaga and Dharmakirthi for his book  
+
In his [[book]] [[Buddhists]] [[Logic]] (volume I) [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] is addressing a system of [[logic]] and epistemology ([[knowledge]] based study) [[realized]] by the [[Gotama Buddha]] in 600 BC. A system of [[logic]] that predates {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, {{Wiki|Plato}} and {{Wiki|Socrates}}. Of the [[three periods]] of growth and change in [[Buddhism]] [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] has selected the most recent or third period and the [[philosophy]] expounded by two great [[Buddhists]] [[masters]] in the VI and VII century AD - the [[Masters]] [[Dignaaga]] and Dharmakirthi for his [[book]]
 
   
 
   
(Extracted from Page 1). Stcherbatsky claims that the logic in Buddhist philosophy contains more than just syllogism (deductive reasoning). It contains a theory of sense perceptions or more precisely a theory on the part of pure sensation in the whole content of our knowledge and on the reality of the external world as cognized by us in sensations and images. These problems are usually treated under the heading of epistemology. Therefore we may be justified in calling the Buddhist system a system of epistemological (knowledge based) logic. The Buddhists themselves call their science a doctrine of logical reason. It is a doctrine of truth through experience.  
+
(Extracted from Page 1). [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] claims that the [[logic]] in [[Buddhist philosophy]] contains more than just [[syllogism]] ([[deductive reasoning]]). It contains a {{Wiki|theory}} of [[sense perceptions]] or more precisely a {{Wiki|theory}} on the part of [[pure sensation]] in the whole content of our [[knowledge]] and on the [[reality]] of the [[external world]] as [[Wikipedia:Cognition|cognized]] by us in [[sensations]] and images. These problems are usually treated under the heading of epistemology. Therefore we may be justified in calling the [[Buddhist]] system a system of [[epistemological]] ([[knowledge]] based) [[logic]]. The [[Buddhists]] themselves call their [[science]] a [[doctrine]] of [[logical reason]]. It is a [[doctrine]] of [[truth]] through [[experience]].  
 
   
 
   
  
The ultimate aim of Buddhist logic is to explain the relation between a changing reality (internal and external) and the conditioned fabrications of thought. This doctrine of changing reality opposed the schools of realist such as Nyaya -Vaisesika and Mumamsa  
+
The [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] aim of [[Buddhist logic]] is to explain the [[relation]] between a changing [[reality]] (internal and external) and the [[conditioned]] [[fabrications]] of [[thought]]. This [[doctrine]] of changing [[reality]] opposed the schools of realist such as [[Nyaya]] -[[Vaisesika]] and Mumamsa  
for whom reality was static. Stcherbatsky feels that Buddhist logic was created in a spirit of opposition to the doctrines of these realists.  
+
for whom [[reality]] was static. [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] [[feels]] that [[Buddhist logic]] was created in a [[spirit]] of [[opposition]] to the [[doctrines]] of these [[realists]].  
 
   
 
   
In Part I and II of this book, Stcherbatsky analyses key Buddhists concepts using epistemic factors such as dialectics, syllogisms, contradiction, inference, judgment etc and then compares them to both Indian and European thought.  
+
In Part I and II of this [[book]], [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] analyses key [[Buddhists]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] using {{Wiki|epistemic}} factors such as [[dialectics]], [[syllogisms]], {{Wiki|contradiction}}, {{Wiki|inference}}, [[judgment]] etc and then compares them to both [[Indian]] and {{Wiki|European}} [[thought]].  
 
   
 
   
In part III of this book Stcherbatsky analyses the various methods of comparative philosophy specifically with Master Diganaaga‟s views of the various methods.  He shows the influence of Diganaaga on the logical fallacies of the Nyaaya - Vaisesika system. He also analyses the Buddhist theory of negation and judgment. He then compares the usage to both ancient Indian and European parallels.  
+
In part III of this [[book]] [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] analyses the various [[methods]] of comparative [[philosophy]] specifically with [[Master]] Diganaaga‟s [[views]] of the various [[methods]].  He shows the influence of Diganaaga on the [[logical]] fallacies of the [[Nyaaya]] - [[Vaisesika]] system. He also analyses the [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of {{Wiki|negation}} and [[judgment]]. He then compares the usage to both {{Wiki|ancient Indian}} and {{Wiki|European}} parallels.  
 
   
 
   
  
By using comparative philosophy and epistemic factors Stcherbatsky tries to show that the Buddhist logic is a positive philosophy comparable with any European philosophy and one that is more ancient than most found in the West.  
+
By using comparative [[philosophy]] and {{Wiki|epistemic}} factors [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] tries to show that the [[Buddhist logic]] is a positive [[philosophy]] comparable with any {{Wiki|European}} [[philosophy]] and one that is more [[ancient]] than most found in the [[West]].  
 
   
 
   
The History of Buddhism and an Introduction to Buddhist Logic  
+
The [[History of Buddhism]] and an Introduction to [[Buddhist Logic]]
 
   
 
   
The history of Buddhism in India may be divided into three periods. During all three periods the Buddhist concept of a dynamic flow of existence - a changing reality- remained steadfast.  
+
The [[history of Buddhism]] in [[India]] may be divided into [[three periods]]. During all [[three periods]] the [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|concept}} of a dynamic flow of [[existence]] - a changing [[reality]]- remained steadfast.  
 
   
 
   
During the first period three fundamental concepts of Buddhism were brought forward:  The concept of no permanent self or soul, the concept of impermanence or change and the concept of stress or suffering. These components were conditionally related in a law of casualty known as the doctrine of dependent origination.  
+
During the first period three fundamental [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of [[Buddhism]] were brought forward:  The {{Wiki|concept}} of no [[permanent]] [[self]] or [[soul]], the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[impermanence]] or change and the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[stress]] or [[suffering]]. These components were conditionally related in a law of casualty known as the [[doctrine of dependent origination]].  
  
 
   
 
   
The doctrine was summarized in what is known as the four noble truths.  
+
The [[doctrine]] was summarized in what is known as the [[four noble truths]].  
 
   
 
   
  
1-The existence of stress and suffering  2. The cause of suffering –grasping or clinging (Tanha) 3. The absence of suffering Nirvana or the final goal (Being the absence of grasping) 4. The path leading to the absence of suffering. – The Noble Eightfold Path.  
+
1-The [[existence]] of [[stress]] and [[suffering]] 2. The [[cause of suffering]] –[[grasping]] or [[clinging]] ([[Tanha]]) 3. The absence of [[suffering]] [[Nirvana]] or the final goal (Being the absence of [[grasping]]) 4. The [[path]] leading to the absence of [[suffering]]. – The [[Noble Eightfold Path]].  
 
   
 
   
The Goal or salvation was freedom from stress and suffering through self-purification. God played no part in this quest, which was essentially a path of salvation through selfpurification.  As the Buddhist doctrine had perceived reality and absolute reality and contained many key concepts such as the four noble truths and the doctrine of not self, impermanence and suffering it was known as a pluralistic system.   
+
The Goal or {{Wiki|salvation}} was freedom from [[stress]] and [[suffering]] through self-purification. [[God]] played no part in this quest, which was [[essentially]] a [[path]] of {{Wiki|salvation}} through selfpurification.  As the [[Buddhist doctrine]] had [[perceived reality]] and [[absolute reality]] and contained many key [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] such as the [[four noble truths]] and the [[doctrine]] of not [[self]], [[impermanence]] and [[suffering]] it was known as a pluralistic system.   
 
   
 
   
At the beginning of the fifth century, during the second period of Buddhism a radical change in Buddhists philosophy occurred. Buddhist philosophers changed the concept of the Buddha as being a perfect human - a fully enlightened Buddha - and made him a divine being. This new Buddhism gave up the idea of personal salvation where each  
+
At the beginning of the fifth century, during the second period of [[Buddhism]] a radical change in [[Buddhists]] [[philosophy]] occurred. [[Buddhist philosophers]] changed the {{Wiki|concept}} of the [[Buddha]] as being a {{Wiki|perfect}} [[human]] - a [[fully enlightened Buddha]] - and made him a [[divine being]]. This new [[Buddhism]] gave up the [[idea]] of personal {{Wiki|salvation}} where each  
  
person strived on his own with the help of the teachings and the teacher and instead replaced it with universal salvation with the help of the divine Buddha. The core philosophy was based on emptiness, which was a hybrid of the doctrine of no soul and impermanence. It also changed the philosophy from radical pluralism to radical monism where emptiness was the key concept of reality. This new Buddhism also condemned logic and gave predominance to mysticism.  
+
[[person]] strived on his [[own]] with the help of the teachings and the [[teacher]] and instead replaced it with [[universal]] {{Wiki|salvation}} with the help of the [[divine]] [[Buddha]]. The core [[philosophy]] was based on [[emptiness]], which was a hybrid of the [[doctrine]] of [[no soul]] and [[impermanence]]. It also changed the [[philosophy]] from radical [[pluralism]] to radical {{Wiki|monism}} where [[emptiness]] was the key {{Wiki|concept}} of [[reality]]. This new [[Buddhism]] also condemned [[logic]] and gave predominance to [[mysticism]].  
 
   
 
   
The third period of Buddhist philosophy, which begins in the sixth and seventh century, changed Buddhism further. The first outstanding feature of the third period was a revival of logic.  A further feature was that Buddhism became idealistic. It maintained that all existence is necessarily mental and that our ideas have no support in corresponding external reality. Consciousness became the focus of this third period.  
+
The third period of [[Buddhist philosophy]], which begins in the sixth and seventh century, changed [[Buddhism]] further. The first outstanding feature of the third period was a revival of [[logic]].  A further feature was that [[Buddhism]] became {{Wiki|idealistic}}. It maintained that all [[existence]] is necessarily [[mental]] and that our [[ideas]] have no support in [[corresponding]] [[external reality]]. [[Consciousness]] became the focus of this third period.  
 
   
 
   
Throughout the three periods of Buddhist evolution the doctrine of impermanence, the doctrine of no permanent self or soul and the doctrine of dependent origination remained in some form or other. Elucidating the system of philosophy in this third period is the object of Stcherbatsky‟s present work.  
+
Throughout the [[three periods]] of [[Buddhist]] [[evolution]] the [[doctrine]] of [[impermanence]], the [[doctrine]] of no [[permanent]] [[self]] or [[soul]] and the [[doctrine of dependent origination]] remained in some [[form]] or other. Elucidating the system of [[philosophy]] in this third period is the [[object]] of Stcherbatsky‟s {{Wiki|present}} work.  
 
   
 
   
Comparative philosophy to existing systems in India  
+
Comparative [[philosophy]] to [[existing]] systems in [[India]]
 
   
 
   
  
Stcherbatsky, Begins his book on Buddhist Logic by comparing Buddhist philosophy to those of other philosophies that existed at the time in India, namely the Materialists, Jainism, Sankhya System, The Yoga System, The Vedanta, the Mimamsa and The NyayaVaisesika system. Stcherbatsky explored the dialogue and contradiction used among the various schools to clarify and modify or strengthen their individual position. Stcherbatsky then compares the various schools to arrive at the similarities and differences of the various systems using Buddhism as the norm. For example he compares Buddhism with the materialist and summarizes as follows: “In the denial of a permanent self and an omnipotent creator God materialist fell in line with Buddhism. It diverged from Buddhism in denying kamma (The law of cause and effect) and Nirvana (absence from suffering)” (Page 15)  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]], Begins his [[book]] on [[Buddhist Logic]] by comparing [[Buddhist philosophy]] to those of other [[philosophies]] that existed at the time in [[India]], namely the {{Wiki|Materialists}}, [[Jainism]], [[Sankhya]] System, The [[Yoga]] System, The [[Vedanta]], the [[Mimamsa]] and The NyayaVaisesika system. [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] explored the {{Wiki|dialogue}} and {{Wiki|contradiction}} used among the various schools to clarify and modify or strengthen their {{Wiki|individual}} position. [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] then compares the various schools to arrive at the similarities and differences of the various systems using [[Buddhism]] as the norm. For example he compares [[Buddhism]] with the {{Wiki|materialist}} and summarizes as follows: “In the {{Wiki|denial}} of a [[permanent]] [[self]] and an omnipotent creator [[God]] {{Wiki|materialist}} fell in line with [[Buddhism]]. It diverged from [[Buddhism]] in denying [[kamma]] (The [[law of cause and effect]]) and [[Nirvana]] (absence from [[suffering]])” (Page 15)  
 
   
 
   
His comparisons of Buddhism to the other systems in existence followed this pattern. He also hi-lighted when other systems had changed resulting from Buddhism and dialogue and contradiction with Buddhist ideals. (Page 22) For example he says: “The Mimamsa was a business like religion. There was no religious emotion or moral evaluation. It was founded on the principle that you pay the Brahmin his fee and you had your reward. However, in the face of Buddhists logic and reasoning they were driven by necessity to defend this business religion and for strengthening the authority of the Vedas”.   
+
His comparisons of [[Buddhism]] to the other systems in [[existence]] followed this pattern. He also hi-lighted when other systems had changed resulting from [[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|dialogue}} and {{Wiki|contradiction}} with [[Buddhist]] ideals. (Page 22) For example he says: “The [[Mimamsa]] was a business like [[religion]]. There was no [[religious]] [[emotion]] or [[moral]] {{Wiki|evaluation}}. It was founded on the [[principle]] that you pay the [[Brahmin]] his fee and you had your reward. However, in the face of [[Buddhists]] [[logic and reasoning]] they were driven by necessity to defend this business [[religion]] and for strengthening the authority of the [[Vedas]]”.   
 
   
 
   
However, at this point in his book Stcherbatsky does not use logical reasoning or syllogisms or any other methodology to first defend the Buddhist philosophy.  Instead taking it as norm he outlines the similarities and differences of the other systems to Buddhist philosophy and the influence of Buddhism on them and the influence of these other religions on Buddhism. While he addresses the fact that dialogue and contradiction  
+
However, at this point in his [[book]] [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] does not use [[logical]] {{Wiki|reasoning}} or [[syllogisms]] or any other [[Wikipedia:scientific method|methodology]] to first defend the [[Buddhist philosophy]].  Instead taking it as norm he outlines the similarities and differences of the other systems to [[Buddhist philosophy]] and the influence of [[Buddhism]] on them and the influence of these other [[religions]] on [[Buddhism]]. While he addresses the fact that {{Wiki|dialogue}} and {{Wiki|contradiction}}
arose among the existing religions, which helped to formulate the various doctrines he does not prove or disprove Buddhist philosophy.  Comparative philosophy to European systems  
+
arose among the [[existing]] [[religions]], which helped to formulate the various [[doctrines]] he does not prove or disprove [[Buddhist philosophy]].  Comparative [[philosophy]] to {{Wiki|European}} systems  
 
   
 
   
  
Stcherbatsky then moves to Buddhist logic in China and Japan and Buddhist logic in Tibet and Mongolia. By this time Buddhism had become extinct in India but every remarkable work of the Indian Buddhists had been translated to Tibetan. The Indian Master Darmakirthi had given Buddhist logic to Tibet. Stcherbatsky compares Darmakirthi‟s logic in Tibet to Aristotle‟s European Logic. “The Tibetan logical literature he says corresponds to European medieval scholastic literature. The chief reasoning being the reducing of scientific thought to the three terms of a regular syllogism”.  (Page 55)  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] then moves to [[Buddhist logic]] in [[China]] and [[Japan]] and [[Buddhist logic]] [[in Tibet]] and [[Mongolia]]. By this time [[Buddhism]] had become [[extinct]] in [[India]] but every remarkable work of the [[Indian Buddhists]] had been translated to [[Tibetan]]. The [[Indian]] [[Master]] Darmakirthi had given [[Buddhist logic]] to [[Tibet]]. [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] compares Darmakirthi‟s [[logic]] [[in Tibet]] to Aristotle‟s {{Wiki|European}} [[Logic]]. “The [[Tibetan]] [[logical]] {{Wiki|literature}} he says corresponds to {{Wiki|European}} {{Wiki|medieval}} {{Wiki|scholastic}} {{Wiki|literature}}. The chief {{Wiki|reasoning}} being the reducing of [[scientific]] [[thought]] to the three terms of a regular [[syllogism]]”.  (Page 55)  
 
   
 
   
It is at this point in his book that Stcherbatsky analyses Buddhist logic using epistemic factors. He does this by categorizing Buddhist logic into its predominant characteristics. Starting with the theory of instantaneous being or the doctrine of impermanence he moves to the doctrine of dependent origination, sense perception and ultimate reality. He begins by looking at epistemic factors to reason the logic of the Buddhist philosophy. He then looks for European parallels.   
+
It is at this point in his [[book]] that [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] analyses [[Buddhist logic]] using {{Wiki|epistemic}} factors. He does this by categorizing [[Buddhist logic]] into its predominant [[characteristics]]. Starting with the {{Wiki|theory}} of instantaneous being or the [[doctrine]] of [[impermanence]] he moves to the [[doctrine of dependent origination]], [[sense perception]] and [[ultimate reality]]. He begins by [[looking at]] {{Wiki|epistemic}} factors to [[reason]] the [[logic]] of the [[Buddhist philosophy]]. He then looks for {{Wiki|European}} parallels.   
 
   
 
   
For example the doctrine of impermanence and no self or no soul in Buddhism is compared to the modern philosopher Bergson‟s writings. (Page 115) “Bergson makes a statement to the effect that there is no ego. ie no permanent substratum for mental phenomena, that existence means constant change or what does not change does not exist…. Instantaneous being (ever changing) they are connected only by casual laws. The comparison to Buddhism cannot be more complete. Buddhism is called the no ego doctrine, the doctrine of impermanence or instantaneous being and the doctrine of causation or dependent origination.”  
+
For example the [[doctrine]] of [[impermanence]] and [[no self]] or [[no soul]] in [[Buddhism]] is compared to the {{Wiki|modern}} [[philosopher]] Bergson‟s writings. (Page 115) “Bergson makes a statement to the effect that there is no [[ego]]. ie no [[permanent]] [[substratum]] for [[mental phenomena]], that [[existence]] means [[constant]] change or what does not change does not [[exist]]…. Instantaneous being (ever changing) they are connected only by [[casual]] laws. The comparison to [[Buddhism]] cannot be more complete. [[Buddhism]] is called the no [[ego]] [[doctrine]], the [[doctrine]] of [[impermanence]] or instantaneous being and the [[doctrine]] of [[causation]] or [[dependent origination]].”  
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky begins by analyzing the law of karma using critical thinking and dialectic (arriving at the truth by logical arguments). In short karma is a moral law of cause and effect that links intentional wholesome and unwholesome action to reactions. (Page 134) Stcherbatsky claims “The Buddha has revealed the law of karma”. He then adds, “the law of karma can not be proved experimentally. It is transcendental. But when critically examined it will be found to have no contradiction and therefore it can be believed even by critical minds”.  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] begins by analyzing the [[law of karma]] using critical [[thinking]] and [[dialectic]] (arriving at the [[truth]] by [[logical]] arguments). In short [[karma]] is a [[moral]] [[law of cause and effect]] that links intentional [[wholesome]] and [[unwholesome]] [[action]] to reactions. (Page 134) [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] claims “The [[Buddha]] has revealed the [[law of karma]]”. He then adds, “the [[law of karma]] can not be proved experimentally. It is [[transcendental]]. But when critically examined it will be found to have no {{Wiki|contradiction}} and therefore it can be believed even by critical [[minds]]”.  
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky  then addresses the doctrine of dependent origination and tries to validate its truth. (Page 119) He claims: “Among all the jewels of Buddhist philosophy the chief jewel is the theory of causation or the doctrine of dependent origination”.  Stcherbatsky then compares the doctrine of dependent origination to the theory of Universal Momentariness for validation. (Read from book page 119). Stcherbatsky then uses the mathematical proof of S. March as an epistemic factor to substantiate the logic and reasoning of the doctrine of dependent origination. (Read from book page 142)  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] then addresses the [[doctrine of dependent origination]] and tries to validate its [[truth]]. (Page 119) He claims: “Among all the [[jewels]] of [[Buddhist philosophy]] the chief [[jewel]] is the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[causation]] or the [[doctrine of dependent origination]]”[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] then compares the [[doctrine of dependent origination]] to the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[Universal]] [[Momentariness]] for validation. (Read from [[book]] page 119). [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] then uses the {{Wiki|mathematical}} [[proof]] of S. March as an {{Wiki|epistemic}} factor to substantiate the [[logic and reasoning]] of the [[doctrine of dependent origination]]. (Read from [[book]] page 142)  
 
   
 
   
  
After describing the doctrine of dependent origination as laid out in both the Mahayana and Theravada traditions Stcherbatsky looks for comparison in Europe. (Quote page 142) “The doctrine of dependent origination and its profound brilliance has fascinated the Western world. The reason for this lies partly in the fact that it seemed highly improbable, too improbable beside sheer logical possibility, that the Indians should have had at so early a date in the history of human thought a doctrine of causation so entirely modern, the same in principle as the one accepted in the most advanced modern science”.  
+
After describing the [[doctrine of dependent origination]] as laid out in both the [[Mahayana]] and [[Theravada]] [[traditions]] [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] looks for comparison in {{Wiki|Europe}}. (Quote page 142) “The [[doctrine of dependent origination]] and its profound [[brilliance]] has fascinated the [[Western world]]. The [[reason]] for this lies partly in the fact that it seemed highly improbable, too improbable beside sheer [[logical]] possibility, that the {{Wiki|Indians}} should have had at so early a date in the history of [[human]] [[thought]] a [[doctrine]] of [[causation]] so entirely {{Wiki|modern}}, the same in [[principle]] as the one accepted in the most advanced {{Wiki|modern science}}”.  
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky is acknowledging the fact that the Buddha pre dated philosophers such as Socrates and Plato by over a century and Aristotle by about two centuries  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] is [[acknowledging]] the fact that the [[Buddha]] pre dated [[philosophers]] such as {{Wiki|Socrates}} and {{Wiki|Plato}} by over a century and {{Wiki|Aristotle}} by about two centuries  
 
   
 
   
He also compares the standpoint of J.S. Mill for whom substance is nothing but permanent possibility of sensation, to Kant for whom substance is but a mental category and to Bertrand Russell for whom substance is not permanent bits of matter but brief events. (Page 142)  
+
He also compares the standpoint of J.S. Mill for whom [[substance]] is nothing but [[permanent]] possibility of [[sensation]], to {{Wiki|Kant}} for whom [[substance]] is but a [[mental]] category and to {{Wiki|Bertrand Russell}} for whom [[substance]] is not [[permanent]] bits of {{Wiki|matter}} but brief events. (Page 142)  
 
   
 
   
  
The Kantian idea that substance is a category forced upon us by the general reason and conducted by the reason on the basis of a manifold of sensibility, Stcherbatsky feels would not have been objected to by Buddhists since it implies the acceptance of a double reality, the ultimate reality of the things by themselves and the constructed reality of empirical things. (Page 142-143). Stcherbatsky then continues to analyze the standpoint of J.S. Mill and Russell from the point of view of the Buddhists.  
+
The [[Wikipedia:Immanuel Kant|Kantian]] [[idea]] that [[substance]] is a category forced upon us by the general [[reason]] and conducted by the [[reason]] on the basis of a manifold of {{Wiki|sensibility}}, [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] [[feels]] would not have been objected to by [[Buddhists]] since it implies the [[acceptance]] of a double [[reality]], the [[ultimate reality]] of the things by themselves and the [[constructed]] [[reality]] of [[empirical]] things. (Page 142-143). [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] then continues to analyze the standpoint of J.S. Mill and Russell from the point of view of the [[Buddhists]].  
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky concludes his comparison of the doctrine of dependent origination to Western thought with a quote from professor T.W. Rhys David‟s (Page 144 read quote)   
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] concludes his comparison of the [[doctrine of dependent origination]] to [[Western]] [[thought]] with a quote from [[professor]] T.W. Rhys David‟s (Page 144 read quote)   
 
   
 
   
“Buddhism stands alone among the religions of India in ignoring a soul.  The vigor and originality of this new departure are evident from the complete isolation in which Buddhism stands in this respect, from all other religious systems then existing in the world. And the very great difficulties which these European writers, who are still steeped in animistic preconceptions, find in appreciating, or even understanding the doctrine, may help to realize how difficult it must have been for the originator of it to take so decisive and so far reaching a step in philosophy and religion, at so early a period in the history of human thought.’  
+
“[[Buddhism]] stands alone among the [[religions]] of [[India]] in ignoring a [[soul]].  The [[vigor]] and originality of this new departure are evident from the complete isolation in which [[Buddhism]] stands in this [[respect]], from all other [[religious]] systems then [[existing]] in the [[world]]. And the very great difficulties which these {{Wiki|European}} writers, who are still steeped in {{Wiki|animistic}} preconceptions, find in appreciating, or even [[understanding]] the [[doctrine]], may help to realize how difficult it must have been for the originator of it to take so decisive and so far reaching a step in [[philosophy]] and [[religion]], at so early a period in the history of [[human]] [[thought]].’  
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky continues in this manner taking each of the concepts of Buddhist philosophy such as sense perception, ultimate reality etc and proving the logic and reasoning by using epistemic factors. He then compares the Buddhist philosophy to Western philosophers thought by looking for similarities. When he finds similarities he injects his views by saying that if questioned he is feels that Buddhist would agree to these similarities. Stcherbatsky quotes extensively from Kant  (160, 177, 200-202, 270-275 317-318 424, 436) and Bertrand Russel 131,142,-144, 165, 179, 180 455, 456) but also Hume, Reid (176) and M.H. Bergson  (151)  Bertrand Russel 131, . In doing so at times Stcherbatsky misrepresents the essence of the Buddhist doctrine.  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] continues in this manner taking each of the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of [[Buddhist philosophy]] such as [[sense perception]], [[ultimate reality]] etc and proving the [[logic and reasoning]] by using {{Wiki|epistemic}} factors. He then compares the [[Buddhist philosophy]] to [[Western]] [[philosophers]] [[thought]] by looking for similarities. When he finds similarities he injects his [[views]] by saying that if questioned he is [[feels]] that [[Buddhist]] would agree to these similarities. [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] quotes extensively from {{Wiki|Kant}} (160, 177, 200-202, 270-275 317-318 424, 436) and Bertrand Russel 131,142,-144, 165, 179, 180 455, 456) but also [[Hume]], Reid (176) and M.H. Bergson  (151)  Bertrand Russel 131, . In doing so at times [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] misrepresents the [[essence]] of the [[Buddhist doctrine]].  
 
   
 
   
  
For example Stcherbatsky compares the Buddhist doctrine of sensation of experiential wisdom to quotes from Kant on sense perception as follows – (Kant page 177) “Without sensation says the Buddhist our knowledge would be empty of reality. Without intuition says Kant all our knowledge would be without objects and it would therefore remain entirely empty.” However, in trying to find parallels between Buddhist philosophy and Western thought Stcherbatsky misinterprets Buddhist thought.  For example the Buddhists view of sense perception is tied very much to experiential wisdom and insight gained through intense development of the mind.  The Buddhist philosophy though profoundly analytical and logical does not limit itself to only reasoning.  It encourages experiential wisdom gained through cultivation of the mind through insight meditation. In this comparison Kant‟s quote on intuition is no parallel to the experiential wisdom or insights that Buddhist refers to as sense perceptions.  
+
For example [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] compares the [[Buddhist doctrine]] of [[sensation]] of [[experiential wisdom]] to quotes from {{Wiki|Kant}} on [[sense perception]] as follows – ({{Wiki|Kant}} page 177) “[[Without sensation]] says the [[Buddhist]] our [[knowledge]] would be [[empty]] of [[reality]]. Without [[intuition]] says {{Wiki|Kant}} all our [[knowledge]] would be without [[objects]] and it would therefore remain entirely [[empty]].” However, in trying to find parallels between [[Buddhist philosophy]] and [[Western]] [[thought]] [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] misinterprets [[Buddhist]] [[thought]].  For example the [[Buddhists]] view of [[sense perception]] is tied very much to [[experiential wisdom]] and [[insight]] gained through intense [[development]] of the [[mind]].  The [[Buddhist philosophy]] though profoundly analytical and [[logical]] does not limit itself to only {{Wiki|reasoning}}.  It encourages [[experiential wisdom]] gained through [[cultivation]] of the [[mind]] through [[insight meditation]]. In this comparison Kant‟s quote on [[intuition]] is no parallel to the [[experiential wisdom]] or [[insights]] that [[Buddhist]] refers to as [[sense perceptions]].  
 
   
 
   
 
Conclusion  
 
Conclusion  
 
   
 
   
In conclusion, Stcherbatsky „s book Buddhist logic is a serious attempt at comparative philosophy.  Stcherbatsky first outlines key doctrines found in the Buddhist philosophy.  He then uses epistemic factors such as syllogism, dialectic, dialogue and contradiction to support the doctrine.  And finally he finds comparisons in ancient Eastern and modern Western thought to try and bring understanding and acceptance to Buddhist logic.  Then, to make his work more comprehensive in part III of the book Stcherbatsky analyses syllogism, logical fallacy, negative judgment etc from the Buddhist point of view of Master Diganaaga and Dharmottara and compares them to the European parallel.   
+
In conclusion, [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] „s [[book]] [[Buddhist logic]] is a serious attempt at comparative [[philosophy]][[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] first outlines key [[doctrines]] found in the [[Buddhist philosophy]].  He then uses {{Wiki|epistemic}} factors such as [[syllogism]], [[dialectic]], {{Wiki|dialogue}} and {{Wiki|contradiction}} to support the [[doctrine]].  And finally he finds comparisons in [[ancient]] Eastern and {{Wiki|modern}} [[Western]] [[thought]] to try and bring [[understanding]] and [[acceptance]] to [[Buddhist logic]].  Then, to make his work more comprehensive in part III of the [[book]] [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] analyses [[syllogism]], [[logical]] [[fallacy]], negative [[judgment]] etc from the [[Buddhist point of view]] of [[Master]] Diganaaga and [[Dharmottara]] and compares them to the {{Wiki|European}} parallel.   
 
   
 
   
Stcherbatsky acknowledges the fact that while European logic has developed from the writings of Aristotle and Kant that a parallel Indian philosophy that is more ancient has developed independently. “As such” he says, “it is of highest historical interest to note cases when both systems have a common theory or conception.” Considering the fact that the Buddha pre dated philosophers such as Socrates and Plato by a century and Aristotle by about two centuries and that most Western spiritual systems are intrinsically in variance with Buddhists doctrine Stcherbatsky‟s work is comprehensive and commendable. The fact that Master Diganaaga‟s philosophy is complex, massive, solid and uniform makes Stcherbatsky‟s undertaking daunting and has resulted in two complex yet comprehensive volumes on Buddhist logic.  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] acknowledges the fact that while {{Wiki|European}} [[logic]] has developed from the writings of {{Wiki|Aristotle}} and {{Wiki|Kant}} that a parallel [[Indian philosophy]] that is more [[ancient]] has developed {{Wiki|independently}}. “As such” he says, “it is of [[highest]] historical [[interest]] to note cases when both systems have a common {{Wiki|theory}} or {{Wiki|conception}}.” Considering the fact that the [[Buddha]] pre dated [[philosophers]] such as {{Wiki|Socrates}} and {{Wiki|Plato}} by a century and {{Wiki|Aristotle}} by about two centuries and that most [[Western]] [[spiritual]] systems are intrinsically in variance with [[Buddhists]] [[doctrine]] Stcherbatsky‟s work is comprehensive and commendable. The fact that [[Master]] Diganaaga‟s [[philosophy]] is complex, massive, solid and {{Wiki|uniform}} makes Stcherbatsky‟s {{Wiki|undertaking}} daunting and has resulted in two complex yet comprehensive volumes on [[Buddhist logic]].  
 
   
 
   
  
However the following weaknesses need attention. First Stcherbatsky could strengthen his epistemic proof of Buddhist logic by using the documented teachings of modern day Arahanths. Stcherbatsky introduces his subject by attesting to the fact that “Buddhism contains a theory of sense perceptions or more precisely a theory on the part of pure sensation in the whole content of our knowledge and on the reality of the external world as cognized by us in sensations and images. These problems are usually treated under the heading of epistemology”.  As Buddhism is a doctrine of experience he could have used the teachings and writings of those who have reached the same spiritual goals and experiences that the Buddha did to strengthen his arguments. (A spiritual biography Venerable Acariya Mun Bhuridatta Thera,  and Ajahn Lee Dhammadaro)  
+
However the following weaknesses need [[attention]]. First [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] could strengthen his {{Wiki|epistemic}} [[proof]] of [[Buddhist logic]] by using the documented teachings of {{Wiki|modern}} day [[Arahanths]]. [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] introduces his [[subject]] by attesting to the fact that “[[Buddhism]] contains a {{Wiki|theory}} of [[sense perceptions]] or more precisely a {{Wiki|theory}} on the part of [[pure sensation]] in the whole content of our [[knowledge]] and on the [[reality]] of the [[external world]] as [[Wikipedia:Cognition|cognized]] by us in [[sensations]] and images. These problems are usually treated under the heading of epistemology”.  As [[Buddhism]] is a [[doctrine]] of [[experience]] he could have used the teachings and writings of those who have reached the same [[spiritual]] goals and [[experiences]] that the [[Buddha]] did to strengthen his arguments. (A [[spiritual]] {{Wiki|biography}} [[Venerable]] [[Acariya]] [[Mun Bhuridatta]] [[Thera]],  and [[Ajahn]] Lee Dhammadaro)  
  
  
Stcherbatsky could have also used the work of modern scientists. There are many instances where scientists have used modern methods, which collaborate the doctrine found in Buddhist logic. (Buddhism and Science - Buddhadasa Kirthisinghe).   
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] could have also used the work of {{Wiki|modern}} [[scientists]]. There are many instances where [[scientists]] have used {{Wiki|modern}} [[methods]], which collaborate the [[doctrine]] found in [[Buddhist logic]]. ([[Buddhism and Science]] - [[Buddhadasa]] Kirthisinghe).   
 
   
 
   
Second unlike in other reading that we have done there does not seem to be comparative philosophy as it relates to Western spiritual thought or Christian philosophy.  The comparisons being more to Western thought or the thinking of Western philosophers as opposed to Christian Philosophy.  
+
Second unlike in other reading that we have done there does not seem to be comparative [[philosophy]] as it relates to [[Western]] [[spiritual]] [[thought]] or [[Christian]] [[philosophy]].  The comparisons being more to [[Western]] [[thought]] or the [[thinking]] of [[Western]] [[philosophers]] as opposed to [[Christian]] [[Philosophy]].  
 
   
 
   
  
And third, and in my opinion where he fails most, is in his effort to find European comparisons for understanding. In doing so at times he stretches the truth and misrepresents Buddhists logic leading the reader to assume that at times he does not have a true understanding of the Buddhist concepts and Buddhist logic that he is writing about.
+
And third, and in my opinion where he fails most, is in his [[effort]] to find {{Wiki|European}} comparisons for [[understanding]]. In doing so at times he stretches the [[truth]] and misrepresents [[Buddhists]] [[logic]] leading the reader to assume that at times he does not have a true [[understanding]] of the [[Buddhist]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] and [[Buddhist logic]] that he is [[writing]] about.
  
  

Latest revision as of 10:51, 2 February 2020





Biography

Stcherbatsky who lived from 1866 to 1942 was a Russian known as a specialist in the study of Tibet and India. A professor at St. Petersburg University in Tsarist times, Stcherbatsky was elected to the Academy of Sciences of the Soviet Union in 1918. In 1928 he assumed direction of the Institute of Buddhist Culture in Leningrad. He became renowned for his translations of Tibetan and Sanskrit. He was also the author of a number of work in English including The conception of Buddhist Nirvana (Leningrad 1927), The central conception of Buddhism and the Meaning of the word Dhamma the second edition of which was published in Calcutta in 1956 and his two volumes of Buddhist Logic. His work has been translated to German, French and Japanese. Contemporary Soviet scholars note that his work remains unsurpassed to this date. Stcherbatsky died on March 18, 1942.


Overview


There is a wide spread prejudice that positive philosophy is to be found only in Europe. It is also a prejudice that Aristotle, Plato Socrates and modern philosophers such as Kant, Hegel and Hume had no predecessor in this field in the East. This work considers a system of logic, but it is not Aristotelian. It is epistemological but not Kantian. It is philosophical but not Socratesan.

In his book Buddhists Logic (volume I) Stcherbatsky is addressing a system of logic and epistemology (knowledge based study) realized by the Gotama Buddha in 600 BC. A system of logic that predates Aristotle, Plato and Socrates. Of the three periods of growth and change in Buddhism Stcherbatsky has selected the most recent or third period and the philosophy expounded by two great Buddhists masters in the VI and VII century AD - the Masters Dignaaga and Dharmakirthi for his book

(Extracted from Page 1). Stcherbatsky claims that the logic in Buddhist philosophy contains more than just syllogism (deductive reasoning). It contains a theory of sense perceptions or more precisely a theory on the part of pure sensation in the whole content of our knowledge and on the reality of the external world as cognized by us in sensations and images. These problems are usually treated under the heading of epistemology. Therefore we may be justified in calling the Buddhist system a system of epistemological (knowledge based) logic. The Buddhists themselves call their science a doctrine of logical reason. It is a doctrine of truth through experience.


The ultimate aim of Buddhist logic is to explain the relation between a changing reality (internal and external) and the conditioned fabrications of thought. This doctrine of changing reality opposed the schools of realist such as Nyaya -Vaisesika and Mumamsa for whom reality was static. Stcherbatsky feels that Buddhist logic was created in a spirit of opposition to the doctrines of these realists.

In Part I and II of this book, Stcherbatsky analyses key Buddhists concepts using epistemic factors such as dialectics, syllogisms, contradiction, inference, judgment etc and then compares them to both Indian and European thought.

In part III of this book Stcherbatsky analyses the various methods of comparative philosophy specifically with Master Diganaaga‟s views of the various methods. He shows the influence of Diganaaga on the logical fallacies of the Nyaaya - Vaisesika system. He also analyses the Buddhist theory of negation and judgment. He then compares the usage to both ancient Indian and European parallels.


By using comparative philosophy and epistemic factors Stcherbatsky tries to show that the Buddhist logic is a positive philosophy comparable with any European philosophy and one that is more ancient than most found in the West.

The History of Buddhism and an Introduction to Buddhist Logic

The history of Buddhism in India may be divided into three periods. During all three periods the Buddhist concept of a dynamic flow of existence - a changing reality- remained steadfast.

During the first period three fundamental concepts of Buddhism were brought forward: The concept of no permanent self or soul, the concept of impermanence or change and the concept of stress or suffering. These components were conditionally related in a law of casualty known as the doctrine of dependent origination.


The doctrine was summarized in what is known as the four noble truths.


1-The existence of stress and suffering 2. The cause of sufferinggrasping or clinging (Tanha) 3. The absence of suffering Nirvana or the final goal (Being the absence of grasping) 4. The path leading to the absence of suffering. – The Noble Eightfold Path.

The Goal or salvation was freedom from stress and suffering through self-purification. God played no part in this quest, which was essentially a path of salvation through selfpurification. As the Buddhist doctrine had perceived reality and absolute reality and contained many key concepts such as the four noble truths and the doctrine of not self, impermanence and suffering it was known as a pluralistic system.

At the beginning of the fifth century, during the second period of Buddhism a radical change in Buddhists philosophy occurred. Buddhist philosophers changed the concept of the Buddha as being a perfect human - a fully enlightened Buddha - and made him a divine being. This new Buddhism gave up the idea of personal salvation where each

person strived on his own with the help of the teachings and the teacher and instead replaced it with universal salvation with the help of the divine Buddha. The core philosophy was based on emptiness, which was a hybrid of the doctrine of no soul and impermanence. It also changed the philosophy from radical pluralism to radical monism where emptiness was the key concept of reality. This new Buddhism also condemned logic and gave predominance to mysticism.

The third period of Buddhist philosophy, which begins in the sixth and seventh century, changed Buddhism further. The first outstanding feature of the third period was a revival of logic. A further feature was that Buddhism became idealistic. It maintained that all existence is necessarily mental and that our ideas have no support in corresponding external reality. Consciousness became the focus of this third period.

Throughout the three periods of Buddhist evolution the doctrine of impermanence, the doctrine of no permanent self or soul and the doctrine of dependent origination remained in some form or other. Elucidating the system of philosophy in this third period is the object of Stcherbatsky‟s present work.

Comparative philosophy to existing systems in India


Stcherbatsky, Begins his book on Buddhist Logic by comparing Buddhist philosophy to those of other philosophies that existed at the time in India, namely the Materialists, Jainism, Sankhya System, The Yoga System, The Vedanta, the Mimamsa and The NyayaVaisesika system. Stcherbatsky explored the dialogue and contradiction used among the various schools to clarify and modify or strengthen their individual position. Stcherbatsky then compares the various schools to arrive at the similarities and differences of the various systems using Buddhism as the norm. For example he compares Buddhism with the materialist and summarizes as follows: “In the denial of a permanent self and an omnipotent creator God materialist fell in line with Buddhism. It diverged from Buddhism in denying kamma (The law of cause and effect) and Nirvana (absence from suffering)” (Page 15)

His comparisons of Buddhism to the other systems in existence followed this pattern. He also hi-lighted when other systems had changed resulting from Buddhism and dialogue and contradiction with Buddhist ideals. (Page 22) For example he says: “The Mimamsa was a business like religion. There was no religious emotion or moral evaluation. It was founded on the principle that you pay the Brahmin his fee and you had your reward. However, in the face of Buddhists logic and reasoning they were driven by necessity to defend this business religion and for strengthening the authority of the Vedas”.

However, at this point in his book Stcherbatsky does not use logical reasoning or syllogisms or any other methodology to first defend the Buddhist philosophy. Instead taking it as norm he outlines the similarities and differences of the other systems to Buddhist philosophy and the influence of Buddhism on them and the influence of these other religions on Buddhism. While he addresses the fact that dialogue and contradiction arose among the existing religions, which helped to formulate the various doctrines he does not prove or disprove Buddhist philosophy. Comparative philosophy to European systems


Stcherbatsky then moves to Buddhist logic in China and Japan and Buddhist logic in Tibet and Mongolia. By this time Buddhism had become extinct in India but every remarkable work of the Indian Buddhists had been translated to Tibetan. The Indian Master Darmakirthi had given Buddhist logic to Tibet. Stcherbatsky compares Darmakirthi‟s logic in Tibet to Aristotle‟s European Logic. “The Tibetan logical literature he says corresponds to European medieval scholastic literature. The chief reasoning being the reducing of scientific thought to the three terms of a regular syllogism”. (Page 55)

It is at this point in his book that Stcherbatsky analyses Buddhist logic using epistemic factors. He does this by categorizing Buddhist logic into its predominant characteristics. Starting with the theory of instantaneous being or the doctrine of impermanence he moves to the doctrine of dependent origination, sense perception and ultimate reality. He begins by looking at epistemic factors to reason the logic of the Buddhist philosophy. He then looks for European parallels.

For example the doctrine of impermanence and no self or no soul in Buddhism is compared to the modern philosopher Bergson‟s writings. (Page 115) “Bergson makes a statement to the effect that there is no ego. ie no permanent substratum for mental phenomena, that existence means constant change or what does not change does not exist…. Instantaneous being (ever changing) they are connected only by casual laws. The comparison to Buddhism cannot be more complete. Buddhism is called the no ego doctrine, the doctrine of impermanence or instantaneous being and the doctrine of causation or dependent origination.”

Stcherbatsky begins by analyzing the law of karma using critical thinking and dialectic (arriving at the truth by logical arguments). In short karma is a moral law of cause and effect that links intentional wholesome and unwholesome action to reactions. (Page 134) Stcherbatsky claims “The Buddha has revealed the law of karma”. He then adds, “the law of karma can not be proved experimentally. It is transcendental. But when critically examined it will be found to have no contradiction and therefore it can be believed even by critical minds”.

Stcherbatsky then addresses the doctrine of dependent origination and tries to validate its truth. (Page 119) He claims: “Among all the jewels of Buddhist philosophy the chief jewel is the theory of causation or the doctrine of dependent origination”. Stcherbatsky then compares the doctrine of dependent origination to the theory of Universal Momentariness for validation. (Read from book page 119). Stcherbatsky then uses the mathematical proof of S. March as an epistemic factor to substantiate the logic and reasoning of the doctrine of dependent origination. (Read from book page 142)


After describing the doctrine of dependent origination as laid out in both the Mahayana and Theravada traditions Stcherbatsky looks for comparison in Europe. (Quote page 142) “The doctrine of dependent origination and its profound brilliance has fascinated the Western world. The reason for this lies partly in the fact that it seemed highly improbable, too improbable beside sheer logical possibility, that the Indians should have had at so early a date in the history of human thought a doctrine of causation so entirely modern, the same in principle as the one accepted in the most advanced modern science”.

Stcherbatsky is acknowledging the fact that the Buddha pre dated philosophers such as Socrates and Plato by over a century and Aristotle by about two centuries

He also compares the standpoint of J.S. Mill for whom substance is nothing but permanent possibility of sensation, to Kant for whom substance is but a mental category and to Bertrand Russell for whom substance is not permanent bits of matter but brief events. (Page 142)


The Kantian idea that substance is a category forced upon us by the general reason and conducted by the reason on the basis of a manifold of sensibility, Stcherbatsky feels would not have been objected to by Buddhists since it implies the acceptance of a double reality, the ultimate reality of the things by themselves and the constructed reality of empirical things. (Page 142-143). Stcherbatsky then continues to analyze the standpoint of J.S. Mill and Russell from the point of view of the Buddhists.

Stcherbatsky concludes his comparison of the doctrine of dependent origination to Western thought with a quote from professor T.W. Rhys David‟s (Page 144 read quote)

Buddhism stands alone among the religions of India in ignoring a soul. The vigor and originality of this new departure are evident from the complete isolation in which Buddhism stands in this respect, from all other religious systems then existing in the world. And the very great difficulties which these European writers, who are still steeped in animistic preconceptions, find in appreciating, or even understanding the doctrine, may help to realize how difficult it must have been for the originator of it to take so decisive and so far reaching a step in philosophy and religion, at so early a period in the history of human thought.’

Stcherbatsky continues in this manner taking each of the concepts of Buddhist philosophy such as sense perception, ultimate reality etc and proving the logic and reasoning by using epistemic factors. He then compares the Buddhist philosophy to Western philosophers thought by looking for similarities. When he finds similarities he injects his views by saying that if questioned he is feels that Buddhist would agree to these similarities. Stcherbatsky quotes extensively from Kant (160, 177, 200-202, 270-275 317-318 424, 436) and Bertrand Russel 131,142,-144, 165, 179, 180 455, 456) but also Hume, Reid (176) and M.H. Bergson (151) Bertrand Russel 131, . In doing so at times Stcherbatsky misrepresents the essence of the Buddhist doctrine.


For example Stcherbatsky compares the Buddhist doctrine of sensation of experiential wisdom to quotes from Kant on sense perception as follows – (Kant page 177) “Without sensation says the Buddhist our knowledge would be empty of reality. Without intuition says Kant all our knowledge would be without objects and it would therefore remain entirely empty.” However, in trying to find parallels between Buddhist philosophy and Western thought Stcherbatsky misinterprets Buddhist thought. For example the Buddhists view of sense perception is tied very much to experiential wisdom and insight gained through intense development of the mind. The Buddhist philosophy though profoundly analytical and logical does not limit itself to only reasoning. It encourages experiential wisdom gained through cultivation of the mind through insight meditation. In this comparison Kant‟s quote on intuition is no parallel to the experiential wisdom or insights that Buddhist refers to as sense perceptions.

Conclusion

In conclusion, Stcherbatsky „s book Buddhist logic is a serious attempt at comparative philosophy. Stcherbatsky first outlines key doctrines found in the Buddhist philosophy. He then uses epistemic factors such as syllogism, dialectic, dialogue and contradiction to support the doctrine. And finally he finds comparisons in ancient Eastern and modern Western thought to try and bring understanding and acceptance to Buddhist logic. Then, to make his work more comprehensive in part III of the book Stcherbatsky analyses syllogism, logical fallacy, negative judgment etc from the Buddhist point of view of Master Diganaaga and Dharmottara and compares them to the European parallel.

Stcherbatsky acknowledges the fact that while European logic has developed from the writings of Aristotle and Kant that a parallel Indian philosophy that is more ancient has developed independently. “As such” he says, “it is of highest historical interest to note cases when both systems have a common theory or conception.” Considering the fact that the Buddha pre dated philosophers such as Socrates and Plato by a century and Aristotle by about two centuries and that most Western spiritual systems are intrinsically in variance with Buddhists doctrine Stcherbatsky‟s work is comprehensive and commendable. The fact that Master Diganaaga‟s philosophy is complex, massive, solid and uniform makes Stcherbatsky‟s undertaking daunting and has resulted in two complex yet comprehensive volumes on Buddhist logic.


However the following weaknesses need attention. First Stcherbatsky could strengthen his epistemic proof of Buddhist logic by using the documented teachings of modern day Arahanths. Stcherbatsky introduces his subject by attesting to the fact that “Buddhism contains a theory of sense perceptions or more precisely a theory on the part of pure sensation in the whole content of our knowledge and on the reality of the external world as cognized by us in sensations and images. These problems are usually treated under the heading of epistemology”. As Buddhism is a doctrine of experience he could have used the teachings and writings of those who have reached the same spiritual goals and experiences that the Buddha did to strengthen his arguments. (A spiritual biography Venerable Acariya Mun Bhuridatta Thera, and Ajahn Lee Dhammadaro)


Stcherbatsky could have also used the work of modern scientists. There are many instances where scientists have used modern methods, which collaborate the doctrine found in Buddhist logic. (Buddhism and Science - Buddhadasa Kirthisinghe).

Second unlike in other reading that we have done there does not seem to be comparative philosophy as it relates to Western spiritual thought or Christian philosophy. The comparisons being more to Western thought or the thinking of Western philosophers as opposed to Christian Philosophy.


And third, and in my opinion where he fails most, is in his effort to find European comparisons for understanding. In doing so at times he stretches the truth and misrepresents Buddhists logic leading the reader to assume that at times he does not have a true understanding of the Buddhist concepts and Buddhist logic that he is writing about.




Source