Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "BUDDHIST-CHRISTIAN PHENOMENOLOGY"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
Line 5: Line 5:
  
  
From Comparison to Collaboration Jacob W. Torbeck Loyola University Chicago Theology  
+
From Comparison to Collaboration Jacob W. Torbeck Loyola {{Wiki|University}} {{Wiki|Chicago}} {{Wiki|Theology}}
  
  
This paper appears in a form similar to the manner in which it delivered on March 27, 2015 at Boston College’s ‘Engaging Particularities’ XIII Conference.  For the sake of the conferences time constraints, this version has been substantially condensed from the initial full-length paper. Uncovering what Buddhism and Christianity might look like expressed in the native  
+
This paper appears in a [[form]] similar to the manner in which it delivered on March 27, 2015 at [[Boston]] College’s ‘Engaging Particularities’ XIII Conference.  For the [[sake]] of the conferences time constraints, this version has been substantially condensed from the initial full-length paper. Uncovering what [[Buddhism]] and [[Christianity]] might look like expressed in the native  
  
philosophical idiom of the other is an ongoing project.  Many comparative theologies have been  
+
[[philosophical]] idiom of the other is an ongoing project.  Many comparative theologies have been  
focused on the translation of concepts between idioms – a redescription of one in terms of the  
+
focused on the translation of [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] between idioms – a redescription of one in terms of the  
other -- an observation of similarities between faiths, such as sin and karma, heaven and nirvana,  
+
other -- an observation of similarities between [[faiths]], such as [[sin]] and [[karma]], [[heaven]] and [[nirvana]],  
or in comparative philosophy, angst (die Angst) and duhkha, nothingness (das Nichts) and  
+
or in comparative [[philosophy]], angst ([[die]] Angst) and [[duhkha]], [[nothingness]] (das Nichts) and  
shunyata.  Constructive projects have followed, mediating between various concepts and  
+
[[shunyata]].  Constructive projects have followed, mediating between various [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] and  
paradigms. These projects are thanks in part to exchanges that were taking place in philosophical  
+
[[paradigms]]. These projects are thanks in part to exchanges that were taking place in [[philosophical]]
circles in the early half of the 20th Century, when Nishida Kitaro, Tanabe Hajime, and Nishitani  
+
circles in the early half of the 20th Century, when [[Nishida Kitaro]], [[Tanabe]] Hajime, and [[Nishitani Keiji]], all in what would become known as the [[Kyoto School]], studied with [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]], and  
Keiji, all in what would become known as the Kyoto School, studied with Heidegger, and  
+
according to [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] himself, “understood immediately” what he meant by nothingness.1   
according to Heidegger himself, “understood immediately” what he meant by nothingness.1   
 
  
 
   
 
   
While this sort of translation has achieved admittedly interesting dialogue and  
+
While this sort of translation has achieved admittedly [[interesting]] {{Wiki|dialogue}} and  
 
opportunities for cross-fertilization in some instances, collaborative efforts, in many cases,  
 
opportunities for cross-fertilization in some instances, collaborative efforts, in many cases,  
 
remain nascent.2  My attempt in this paper is to suggest not merely a fruitful area for comparative  
 
remain nascent.2  My attempt in this paper is to suggest not merely a fruitful area for comparative  
philosophy or theology, but an outgrowth of comparison that offers a pathway to a shared  
+
[[philosophy]] or {{Wiki|theology}}, but an outgrowth of comparison that offers a pathway to a shared  
method of doing philosophical theology.  I envision this as a mutual approach that effects both  
+
method of doing [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|theology}}.  I envision this as a mutual approach that effects both  
meanings of “mutuality” in a movement of each toward the other, held in common by each.  To  
+
meanings of “mutuality” in a {{Wiki|movement}} of each toward the other, held in common by each.  [[To accomplish]] this, I will describe the [[beliefs]] of [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]] alongside [[Western]]
accomplish this, I will describe the beliefs of Yogācāra Buddhism alongside Western  
+
[[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], before following phenomenology’s “{{Wiki|theological}} turn” and [[offering]] speculation  
phenomenology, before following phenomenology’s “theological turn” and offering speculation  
+
on {{Wiki|future}} possibilities for collaboration.   
on future possibilities for collaboration.   
 
  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
What Analogue in Western Thought?  
+
What Analogue in [[Western]] [[Thought]]?  
  
  
Notable scholars of Buddhism have labeled Yogācāra as a kind of “idealism.”  Lambert  
+
Notable [[scholars]] of [[Buddhism]] have labeled [[Yogācāra]] as a kind of “[[idealism]].”  {{Wiki|Lambert Schmithausen}}, for example, employs it, as do Vallee [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Poussin]], {{Wiki|D.T. Suzuki}}, [[Edward Conze]], and  
Schmithausen, for example, employs it, as do Vallee Poussin, D.T. Suzuki, Edward Conze, and  
+
others.3  Against this characterization, [[Dan Lusthaus]] argues that the meanings of such an  
others.3  Against this characterization, Dan Lusthaus argues that the meanings of such an  
+
appellation are so numerous as to be without any real content.  By “[[idealism]],” do we mean to say  
appellation are so numerous as to be without any real content.  By “idealism,” do we mean to say  
+
merely that [[Yogācāra]] is not a kind of {{Wiki|materialism}}?  Or that it is a [[metaphysical idealism]] akin to  
merely that Yogācāra is not a kind of materialism?  Or that it is a metaphysical idealism akin to  
+
[[Vedanta]] (wherein “some supermental, non-material [[entity]] creates all that [[exists]].”)? An  
Vedanta (wherein “some supermental, non-material entity creates all that exists.”)? An  
+
[[epistemological]] [[idealism]], wherein the [[Wikipedia:Cognition|cognizing]] [[subject]] is the ground and limit of epistemology?  
epistemological idealism, wherein the cognizing subject is the ground and limit of epistemology?  
+
Or a critical [[epistemological]] [[idealism]], which brackets [[metaphysical]] or [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] implications,  
Or a critical epistemological idealism, which brackets metaphysical or ontological implications,  
+
claiming only that the [[subject]] unavoidable shapes an [[experience]] to such an extent that the [[self]]
claiming only that the subject unavoidable shapes an experience to such an extent that the self  
 
 
and other are inextricable?4  
 
and other are inextricable?4  
 
   
 
   
  
These are all inappropriate categories.  Yogācāra claims not that there is “only a mind,”  
+
These are all inappropriate categories.  [[Yogācāra]] claims not that there is “only a [[mind]],”  
but rather that the “mind only” is the obstacle to seeing things as they are.  Rather than  
+
but rather that the “[[mind only]]” is the [[obstacle]] to [[seeing]] things as they are.  Rather than  
understanding the knowing subject as the limit of epistemology, Yogācāra, as a Buddhism, quite  
+
[[understanding]] the [[knowing]] [[subject]] as the limit of epistemology, [[Yogācāra]], as a [[Buddhism]], quite  
explicitly seeks to deconstruct and/or rid the practitioner of the delusion of subjectivity-as
+
explicitly seeks to deconstruct and/or rid the [[practitioner]] of the [[delusion]] of subjectivity-as
selfhood.  Finally, in lieu of positing an Other that is essentially unknowable as Other, Yogācāra  
+
[[selfhood]].  Finally, in lieu of positing an Other that is [[essentially]] unknowable as Other, [[Yogācāra]]
hopes to enable practitioners to see the Other without a “mirror,” that is, without the obstructions  
+
[[Wikipedia:Hope|hopes]] to enable practitioners to see the Other without a “[[mirror]],” that is, without the obstructions  
 
we ourselves create, as no longer Other.   
 
we ourselves create, as no longer Other.   
 
   
 
   
The inappropriateness of the category of idealism notwithstanding, the stages of  
+
The inappropriateness of the category of [[idealism]] notwithstanding, the stages of  
Yogācārin analysis seem to follow paths similar to those of certain Western philosophers.   
+
[[Yogācārin]] analysis seem to follow [[paths]] similar to those of certain [[Western]] [[philosophers]].   
Theodore Stcherbatsky saw affinities between Yogācāra and Kantian critical philosophy, but the  
+
[[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Theodore Stcherbatsky]] saw affinities between [[Yogācāra]] and [[Wikipedia:Immanuel Kant|Kantian]] critical [[philosophy]], but the  
two thought systems come to different conclusions: Kant’s ‘thing-in-itself’ “is ultimately  
+
two [[thought]] systems come to different conclusions: [[Kant’s]] ‘[[thing-in-itself]]’ “is ultimately  
unknowable as it is in itself (that is, it is noumenal). For Yogācāra, the way things happen  
+
unknowable as it is in itself (that is, it is [[noumenal]]). For [[Yogācāra]], the way things happen  
  
 
    
 
    
(yathabhutham) is eminently knowable, and seeing things as they truly are is one of [its] goals.”5  
+
(yathabhutham) is eminently knowable, and [[seeing]] things as they truly are is one of [its] goals.”5  
In Kant, we intuit the things themselves, “but never actually perceive anything beyond our own  
+
In {{Wiki|Kant}}, we intuit the things themselves, “but never actually {{Wiki|perceive}} anything beyond our [[own]]
mental representations (Vorstellungen); for Yogācāra, eliminating precisely this sort of  
+
[[mental]] {{Wiki|representations}} (Vorstellungen); for [[Yogācāra]], eliminating precisely this sort of  
narcissistic cognitive closure (vijnapti-matra), so that one’s congnitions (jnana) are open to  
+
narcissistic [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] closure ([[vijnapti-matra]]), so that one’s congnitions ([[jnana]]) are open to  
everything beyond ourselfs, like a mirror (adarsa), is the cognitive shift (asraya-paravrtti)  
+
everything beyond ourselfs, like a [[mirror]] ([[adarsa]]), is the [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] shift (asraya-paravrtti)  
necessary to become Awakened (Bodhi).”6 Stcherbatsky seems unaware that the reaction against  
+
necessary to become [[Awakened]] (Bodhi).”6 [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] seems unaware that the {{Wiki|reaction}} against  
Kant in the phenomenological school of Husserl was much closer to Yogācāra than Kant ever  
+
{{Wiki|Kant}} in the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} school of [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] was much closer to [[Yogācāra]] than {{Wiki|Kant}} ever  
was, a movement that will be the subject of much of our comparative exercise.  
+
was, a {{Wiki|movement}} that will be the [[subject]] of much of our comparative exercise.  
  
  
Line 76: Line 73:
  
  
Through a close examination of Western phenomenologists in comparison with Yogācāra  
+
Through a close {{Wiki|examination}} of [[Western]] [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologists]] in comparison with [[Yogācāra]]
thought, Dan Lusthaus’s Buddhist Phenomenology argues for the understanding of Yogācāra as  
+
[[thought]], Dan [[Lusthaus’s]] [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} argues for the [[understanding]] of [[Yogācāra]] as  
Buddhist phenomenology, with the caveat that “Husserlian phenomenology and Yogācāra are  
+
[[Buddhist]] [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], with the caveat that “Husserlian [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] and [[Yogācāra]] are  
not isomorphic systems… Husserl, et al., do not provide us with an exact correlation to  
+
not {{Wiki|isomorphic}} systems… [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], et al., do not provide us with an exact correlation to  
Yogācāra.”7  Furthermore, we should not forget that Husserl himself continually changed his  
+
Yogācāra.”7  Furthermore, we should not forget that [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] himself continually changed his  
mind and developed his thought.  One cannot pin Husserl down to a static set of propositions –  
+
[[mind]] and developed his [[thought]].  One cannot pin [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] down to a static set of propositions –  
  
  
 
he must be identified, rather, with his method and the trajectory of his work.8 In addition, a  
 
he must be identified, rather, with his method and the trajectory of his work.8 In addition, a  
number of followers of Husserl, among which were Edith Stein and Martin Heidegger, departed  
+
number of followers of [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], among which were Edith Stein and {{Wiki|Martin Heidegger}}, departed  
in their own ways from doing phenomenology in the manner Husserl taught, creating within the  
+
in their [[own]] ways from doing [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] in the manner [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] [[taught]], creating within the  
discipline a multiplicity of phenomenological perspectives. An analogue to this is true of  
+
[[discipline]] a multiplicity of {{Wiki|phenomenological}} perspectives. An analogue to this is true of  
Yogācāra, as well. The development of Yogācāra as a broad category within Buddhism is such  
+
[[Yogācāra]], as well. The [[development]] of [[Yogācāra]] as a broad category within [[Buddhism]] is such  
that no one system can answer univocally to that name.9  Nevertheless, Lusthaus believes that  
+
that no one system can answer univocally to that name.9  Nevertheless, [[Lusthaus]] believes that  
phenomenology (in its varied forms) is the closest Western system of thought system to  
+
[[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] (in its varied [[forms]]) is the closest [[Western]] system of [[thought]] system to  
  
Yogācāra (in its varied forms), and thus offers a westerner a methodological advantage and a  
+
[[Yogācāra]] (in its varied [[forms]]), and thus offers a westerner a {{Wiki|methodological}} advantage and a  
hermeneutical lens that other perspectives lack.10  
+
[[Wikipedia:Hermeneutics|hermeneutical]] lens that other perspectives lack.10  
  
The great perceived potential for mutual approach is promising in comparative efforts to  
+
The great [[perceived]] potential for mutual approach is [[promising]] in comparative efforts to  
to build bridges (and erect shrines?) where a broadly shared perspective and language can help  
+
[[to build]] [[bridges]] (and erect [[shrines]]?) where a broadly shared {{Wiki|perspective}} and [[language]] can help  
us think together on the preoccupations Western phenomenology and Yogācāra have in common:  
+
us think together on the preoccupations [[Western]] [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] and [[Yogācāra]] have in common:  
“the whys and hows of human experience […] perception, sensation, cognition, noetic  
+
“the whys and hows of [[human experience]] […] [[perception]], [[sensation]], [[cognition]], noetic  
construction, embodied conditioning,” and overcoming “embodied ways of seeing the world.”11   
+
construction, [[embodied]] {{Wiki|conditioning}},” and [[overcoming]] “[[embodied]] ways of [[seeing]] the world.”11   
This approach would still involve the “translation” of Yogācāra Buddhism into Western  
+
This approach would still involve the “translation” of [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]] into [[Western]]
phenomenological language, and perhaps the converse as well.  Lusthaus believes that this sort  
+
{{Wiki|phenomenological}} [[language]], and perhaps the converse as well.  [[Lusthaus]] believes that this sort  
of translation has far fewer problems than with another system, e.g., German Idealism a la  
+
of translation has far fewer problems than with another system, e.g., [[German Idealism]] a la  
Hegel.  In demonstrating the translation already underway, I will weave together some of the  
+
[[Wikipedia:Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]].  In demonstrating the translation already underway, I will weave together some of the  
many points of connection between the Yogācāra school and phenomenologists from Edmund  
+
many points of [[connection]] between the [[Yogācāra school]] and [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologists]] from {{Wiki|Edmund Husserl}} to Jean-Luc Marion.  
Husserl to Jean-Luc Marion.  
 
  
“Buddhism contends that we habitually and incessantly misinterpret our experience,”  
+
“[[Buddhism]] contends that we habitually and incessantly misinterpret our [[experience]],”  
Lusthaus writes.12  This basic starting point was the impetus for Husserl as well. Husserl called  
+
[[Lusthaus]] writes.12  This basic starting point was the impetus for [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] as well. [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] called  
his method a transcendental idealism, by which he meant an “investigation of those conditions  
+
his method a [[transcendental]] [[idealism]], by which he meant an “[[investigation]] of those [[conditions]]
through which we experience and think that are not readily apparent while we are experiencing  
+
through which we [[experience]] and think that are not readily apparent while we are experiencing  
and thinking.”13  To move to the experience, Husserl hoped to ‘bracket’ presuppositions. He  
+
and thinking.”13  To move to the [[experience]], [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] hoped to ‘bracket’ presuppositions. He  
finds common ground here with the Yogācāra, in the “search for the cognitive roots of  
+
finds common ground here with the [[Yogācāra]], in the “search for the [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[roots]] of  
knowledge,” or the epistemic foundation.14  For Husserl, all philosophic concerns ultimately  
+
[[knowledge]],” or the {{Wiki|epistemic}} foundation.14  For [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], all [[philosophic]] concerns ultimately  
must rest on the epistemic foundation. The philosopher questions ‘why and how’ cognition is  
+
must rest on the {{Wiki|epistemic}} foundation. The [[philosopher]] questions ‘why and how’ [[cognition]] is  
possible, while the naïve (for the Buddhist, “unawakened” or “unenlightened”) viewpoint leaves  
+
possible, while the naïve (for the [[Buddhist]], “unawakened” or “unenlightened”) viewpoint leaves  
 
such things unquestioned.15   
 
such things unquestioned.15   
  
Husserl’s Hyle and the Yogācārin Worldview  
+
Husserl’s [[Hyle]] and the [[Yogācārin]] Worldview  
  
  
Yogācāra’s affinity to Husserl manifests itself in the problem of consciousness.  In  
+
[[Yogācāra’s]] [[affinity]] to [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] [[manifests]] itself in the problem of [[consciousness]].  In  
consciousness, we all the time encounter “non-genuine cognitive objects.”  For Husserl, these  
+
[[consciousness]], we all the time encounter “non-genuine [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[objects]].”  For [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], these  
objects are a ‘past’ objects (memories).  Lusthaus identifies this example as “strikingly  
+
[[objects]] are a ‘{{Wiki|past}}’ [[objects]] ([[memories]]).  [[Lusthaus]] identifies this example as “strikingly  
Yogacaric.  Yogacara also accepts only a present object as genuine, as real.  Objects from the  
+
[[Yogacaric]][[Yogacara]] also accepts only a {{Wiki|present}} [[object]] as genuine, as real.  [[Objects]] from the  
past and future are never immediately given, or even remotely given; they are, according to  
+
{{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}} are never immediately given, or even remotely given; they are, according to  
Yogacara, cognitive constructions (parikalpita), which is to say, they are mental fictions.”16  
+
[[Yogacara]], [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] constructions ([[parikalpita]]), which is to say, they are [[mental]] fictions.”16  
  
  
While Husserl and Yogācāra both regard the present moment alone as real, “the present is  
+
While [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] and [[Yogācāra]] both regard the {{Wiki|present}} [[moment]] alone as real, “the {{Wiki|present}} is  
never anything other than embodied history.”17  Husserl approaches this history through the  
+
never anything other than [[embodied]] history.”17  [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] approaches this history through the  
phenomenological method, which innovatively reflects on the present moment.  Yogācāra has as  
+
{{Wiki|phenomenological}} method, which innovatively reflects on the {{Wiki|present}} [[moment]][[Yogācāra]] has as  
its soteriological underpinning a theory of historical embodiment in karma and the alayavijnana  
+
its [[soteriological]] underpinning a {{Wiki|theory}} of historical [[embodiment]] in [[karma]] and the [[alayavijnana]]
(storehouse consciousness).  The two approaches can be viewed in parallel. On the one hand, a  
+
([[storehouse consciousness]]).  The two approaches can be viewed in parallel. On the one hand, a  
phenomenological movement from viewing the present as “mere presence” to “embodied
+
{{Wiki|phenomenological}} {{Wiki|movement}} from viewing the {{Wiki|present}} as “mere presence” to “[[embodied]]
history,” on the other, the uncovering and elimination of habitual (karmic) sedimentations, which  
+
history,” on the other, the uncovering and elimination of habitual ([[karmic]]) sedimentations, which  
float as seeds down the stream of consciousness.18  
+
float as [[seeds]] down the {{Wiki|stream}} of consciousness.18  
  
  
Alayavijnana, Edith Stein, and Other Consciousnesses   
+
[[Alayavijnana]], Edith Stein, and Other [[Consciousnesses]]  
 
   
 
   
  
“According to Yogācāra our mental experience is changing, altering (parinama, pravrtti)  
+
“According to [[Yogācāra]] our [[mental]] [[experience]] is changing, altering ([[parinama]], [[pravrtti]])  
every moment. In this fluctuating stream (vijnana-santana) we tend to posit two constants which  
+
every [[moment]]. In this fluctuating {{Wiki|stream}} ([[vijnana-santana]]) we tend to posit two constants which  
and through which we cognize and evaluate all that we experience.”19  First, the self (ātman) as  
+
and through which we {{Wiki|cognize}} and evaluate all that we experience.”19  First, the [[self]] ([[ātman]]) as  
unchanging witness, and ‘objective’ circumstances (dharmas).  In this stream of constant  
+
[[unchanging]] {{Wiki|witness}}, and ‘[[objective]]’ circumstances ([[dharmas]]).  In this {{Wiki|stream}} of [[constant]]
change, we grasp at physical objects because we have theories of them and ourselves by which  
+
change, we [[grasp]] at [[physical objects]] because we have theories of them and ourselves by which  
we give value and identity to ourselves by obtaining the objects onto which we project values  
+
we give value and [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] to ourselves by obtaining the [[objects]] onto which we project values  
 
and identities.20  
 
and identities.20  
  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
In a similar manner, Edith Stein writes, “We can take das Ich in a second sense as the  
+
In a similar manner, Edith Stein writes, “We can take das Ich in a second [[sense]] as the  
unity of a stream of consciousness.  We begin with das Ich as the subject of an actual experience.   
+
{{Wiki|unity}} of a [[stream of consciousness]].  We begin with das Ich as the [[subject]] of an actual [[experience]].   
However, when we reflect on this experience, we find that it is not isolated, but set against the  
+
However, when we reflect on this [[experience]], we find that it is not isolated, but set against the  
background of a stream of such experiences more or less clearly and distinctively given.  The Ich  
+
background of a {{Wiki|stream}} of such [[experiences]] more or less clearly and distinctively given.  The Ich  
of this experience was not always in it but shifted over or was drawn into it from another  
+
of this [[experience]] was not always in it but shifted over or was drawn into it from another  
experience, and so on.”21 That is, our stream of consciousness is dependently arisen.  She  
+
[[experience]], and so on.”21 That is, our [[stream of consciousness]] is [[dependently arisen]].  She  
continues, “Our uniform, isolated stream of consciousness is not our soul.  But . . . there is one  
+
continues, “Our {{Wiki|uniform}}, isolated [[stream of consciousness]] is not our [[soul]].  But . . . there is one  
basic experience given to us which, together with its persistent attributes, becomes apparent in  
+
basic [[experience]] given to us which, together with its persistent [[attributes]], becomes apparent in  
our experiences as the identical “bearer” of [those experiences].  This is the substantial soul.”22     
+
our [[experiences]] as the [[identical]] “bearer” of [those [[experiences]]].  This is the substantial soul.”22     
What she means here is something quite similar to the storehouse consciousness of the  
+
What she means here is something quite similar to the [[storehouse consciousness]] of the  
Yogācāra, understood by Paul Williams to be a “bearer” of karmic “seeds.”23 These seeds  
+
[[Yogācāra]], understood by [[Paul Williams]] to be a “bearer” of [[karmic]] “seeds.”23 These [[seeds]]
explain phenomenal existence in general,” and in particular, the link between experiences arising  
+
explain [[phenomenal existence]] in general,” and in particular, the link between [[experiences]] [[arising]]
  
  
from prior actions.24  This consciousness is described as belonging to an individual, always  
+
from prior actions.24  This [[consciousness]] is described as belonging to an {{Wiki|individual}}, always  
changing (flowing), and yet providing the principle of personal identity by linking actions in a  
+
changing (flowing), and yet providing the [[principle]] of personal [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] by linking [[actions]] in a  
causal chain (or stream).  Despite belonging to an individual, because of the dependent,  
+
[[causal chain]] (or {{Wiki|stream}}).  Despite belonging to an {{Wiki|individual}}, because of the dependent,  
“intersubjective” nature of the world, the karmic seeds actually engage with all relevant  
+
“intersubjective” [[nature]] of the [[world]], the [[karmic seeds]] actually engage with all relevant  
storehouse consciousnesses, in effect giving rise to common experience and the intersubjective  
+
[[storehouse]] [[consciousnesses]], in effect giving rise to common [[experience]] and the intersubjective  
phenomenal world itself.  The metaphor of “perfuming” used by the Yogācāra is quite evocative,  
+
[[phenomenal world]] itself.  The {{Wiki|metaphor}} of “perfuming” used by the [[Yogācāra]] is quite evocative,  
leading us to imagine a sort of continuous causality that looks less like the causal model evoked  
+
leading us to [[imagine]] a sort of continuous [[causality]] that looks less like the causal model evoked  
 
by billiard balls ricocheting around a table, and more like the very organic image we get of an  
 
by billiard balls ricocheting around a table, and more like the very organic image we get of an  
flower’s odor permeating the air, causing a new and different “perfuming” each time it gives rise  
+
flower’s {{Wiki|odor}} permeating the [[air]], causing a new and different “perfuming” each time it gives rise  
to a new experience.  Just as we can imagine this going on into the indefinite future, so too  
+
to a new [[experience]].  Just as we can [[imagine]] this going on into the indefinite {{Wiki|future}}, so too  
 
would it stretch back through history ad infinitum.25   
 
would it stretch back through history ad infinitum.25   
  
Dependent origination comes again to the fore in the “perfuming” by these karmic seeds,  
+
[[Dependent origination]] comes again to the fore in the “perfuming” by these [[karmic seeds]],  
as many experiences of phenomena could be said to be phenomena “of ‘foreign experience’ and  
+
as many [[experiences]] of [[phenomena]] could be said to be [[phenomena]] “of ‘foreign [[experience]]’ and  
correlatively the ‘perception of foreign experience,’”26  or in other words, an experiential  
+
correlatively the ‘[[perception]] of foreign experience,’”26  or in other words, an experiential  
awareness of foreign consciousness(es).  Stein addresses knowledge of foreign consciousnesses  
+
[[awareness]] of foreign consciousness(es).  Stein addresses [[knowledge]] of foreign [[consciousnesses]]
earlier in Empathy, when she talks of, among other examples, how “[a] child seeing another  
+
earlier in {{Wiki|Empathy}}, when she talks of, among other examples, how “[a] child [[seeing]] another  
crying cries, too,” speaking of transference of feeling as a kind of imitation resulting from the  
+
crying {{Wiki|cries}}, too,” {{Wiki|speaking}} of [[transference]] of [[feeling]] as a kind of imitation resulting from the  
  
  
action of another.  “If we had not first comprehended the foreign experience,” Stein says, “we  
+
[[action]] of another.  “If we had not first comprehended the foreign [[experience]],” Stein says, “we  
 
could not have brought it to givenness to ourselves at all.”27 She chooses the example of  
 
could not have brought it to givenness to ourselves at all.”27 She chooses the example of  
imitation of feeling to make the point that we not only observe the effects of others’ actions, but  
+
imitation of [[feeling]] to make the point that we not only observe the effects of others’ [[actions]], but  
these actions truly affect us, even in situations where they don’t impinge upon us physically.   
+
these [[actions]] truly affect us, even in situations where they don’t impinge upon us {{Wiki|physically}}.   
After a like fashion, it makes sense to the Yogācāra to speak of the minds of others, and to avoid  
+
After a like fashion, it makes [[sense]] to the [[Yogācāra]] to speak of the [[minds]] of others, and to avoid  
asserting any kind of solipsism; there are as many streams of consciousness as there are others,  
+
asserting any kind of {{Wiki|solipsism}}; there are as many streams of [[consciousness]] as there are others,  
and the scent of their karmic seeds is not limited to one storehouse, but permeates the  
+
and the {{Wiki|scent}} of their [[karmic seeds]] is not limited to one [[storehouse]], but permeates the  
surroundings and becomes constitutive of the intersubjective phenomenal world.28  
+
surroundings and becomes constitutive of the intersubjective [[phenomenal]] world.28  
 
   
 
   
On the nature of value, Edith Stein, in 1916, was merely concerned with writing a  
+
On the [[nature]] of value, Edith Stein, in 1916, was merely concerned with [[writing]] a  
descriptive account of how and why valuing occurs, and shared none of the soteriological aims  
+
descriptive account of how and why valuing occurs, and shared none of the [[soteriological]] aims  
of Yogācāra philosophy.  For the Yogācāra, “value” is connected with desire, and is indicative of  
+
of [[Yogācāra philosophy]].  For the [[Yogācāra]], “value” is connected with [[desire]], and is indicative of  
a subject-object dualism spoken of in terms of grahaka (the grasper) and grahya (the grasped).  
+
a subject-object [[dualism]] spoken of in terms of [[grahaka]] (the grasper) and [[grahya]] (the grasped).  
Escaping this problematic dualism through a realization or revelation of the emptiness of all  
+
Escaping this problematic [[dualism]] through a [[realization]] or [[revelation]] of the [[emptiness of all things]] is the goal of [[Yogācāra]] [[thought]] and practice.  Peter Oldmeadow, in observing this  
things is the goal of Yogācāra thought and practice.  Peter Oldmeadow, in observing this  
+
problem, notes similarities not primarily with [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] or Stein, but with {{Wiki|Martin Heidegger}}, who,  
problem, notes similarities not primarily with Husserl or Stein, but with Martin Heidegger, who,  
+
with the [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhists]], rejects [[dualisms]] of almost every kind.  
with the Yogācāra Buddhists, rejects dualisms of almost every kind.  
+
The Problem of [[Dualism]] in [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] and [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]].  
The Problem of Dualism in Heidegger and Yogācāra Buddhism.  
 
  
  
Heidegger, in his critique of the Western philosophical tradition, identifies the dualist  
+
[[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]], in his critique of the [[Western]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]], identifies the [[dualist]]
orientation as a cause of cultural and personal alienation.29  His insistence on breaking through  
+
orientation as a [[cause]] of {{Wiki|cultural}} and personal alienation.29  His insistence on breaking through  
the alienation of dualism has an almost soteriological trajectory, prima facie resonating with the  
+
the alienation of [[dualism]] has an almost [[soteriological]] trajectory, [[Wikipedia:Prima facie|prima facie]] resonating with the  
goals of Yogācāra philosophy.  In Heidegger’s work, the problem of dualism is linked to the  
+
goals of [[Yogācāra philosophy]].  In Heidegger’s work, the problem of [[dualism]] is linked to the  
  
  
question of ontology.  The enquiry into the meaning of being is never one that can be asked from  
+
question of {{Wiki|ontology}}.  The enquiry into the meaning of being is never one that can be asked from  
objectivity, however, and this very fact is the condition that makes Heidegger’s  
+
objectivity, however, and this very fact is the [[condition]] that makes Heidegger’s  
phenomenological method necessary.  Being “thrown” into a particular world, with its particular  
+
{{Wiki|phenomenological}} method necessary.  Being “thrown” into a particular [[world]], with its particular  
 
socio-historical constitution, we must engage a method of traveling back to “a more fundamental  
 
socio-historical constitution, we must engage a method of traveling back to “a more fundamental  
attunement with Being,” creating an openness, or a clearing, “where a more fundamental  
+
[[attunement]] with Being,” creating an [[openness]], or a clearing, “where a more fundamental  
  
presencing (as opposed to representation) of beings can occur.”30  Oldmeadow here identifies a  
+
presencing (as opposed to [[representation]]) of [[beings]] can occur.”30  Oldmeadow here identifies a  
point of connection with Yogācāra Buddhism, wherein the “fundamental mode of being, or  
+
point of [[connection]] with [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]], wherein the “fundamental mode of being, or  
awakened awareness, which ‘precedes’ dualistic appearance (dvaya-pratibhasa) must be  
+
[[awakened awareness]], which ‘precedes’ [[dualistic]] [[appearance]] (dvaya-pratibhasa) must be  
 
uncovered,” through a similar “going back.”31  
 
uncovered,” through a similar “going back.”31  
  
Dualistic appearances, which much be ultimately un-seen (or re-viewed) are of various  
+
[[Dualistic]] [[appearances]], which much be ultimately un-seen (or re-viewed) are of various  
 
kinds: subject/object, perceiver/perceived, knower/known, and absolute/phenomena, for  
 
kinds: subject/object, perceiver/perceived, knower/known, and absolute/phenomena, for  
example.  The final example might even be understood on the theological level as God/world, or  
+
example.  The final example might even be understood on the {{Wiki|theological}} level as God/world, or  
nirvana/samsara.32  This matter of un-seeing, however, should not be understood as placing  
+
nirvana/samsara.32  This {{Wiki|matter}} of un-seeing, however, should not be understood as placing  
reality under the umbrella of monism.  Rather than a radical unity, both Yogācāric and  
+
[[reality]] under the [[umbrella]] of {{Wiki|monism}}.  Rather than a radical {{Wiki|unity}}, both [[Yogācāric]] and  
Heideggerian phenomenology emphasize the intersubjective or dependently originated nature of  
+
Heideggerian [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] {{Wiki|emphasize}} the intersubjective or [[dependently originated]] [[nature]] of  
 
all things.33  
 
all things.33  
  
This process of un-seeing is conceived of in different, though perhaps complementary  
+
This process of un-seeing is [[conceived]] of in different, though perhaps complementary  
ways. In the West, “being” is taken for granted so as to be forgotten, so much so that even the  
+
ways. In the [[West]], “being” is taken for granted so as to be forgotten, so much so that even the  
forgetting has been forgotten. Thus Heidegger’s project can be said to be a “remembering” of  
+
{{Wiki|forgetting}} has been forgotten. Thus Heidegger’s project can be said to be a “remembering” of  
  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
Being and a rediscovery of the open horizon of possibilities.34  Buddhists approach a similar  
+
Being and a rediscovery of the open horizon of possibilities.34  [[Buddhists]] approach a similar  
soteriological goal from the starting point of the first noble truth.   
+
[[soteriological]] goal from the starting point of the [[first noble truth]].   
Because the aim of Buddhists is to escape duhkha and samsara, they come to discuss the  
+
Because the aim of [[Buddhists]] is to escape [[duhkha]] and [[samsara]], they come to discuss the  
existence of graspable, cravable things as a product of delusion, an unawakened state.35  The  
+
[[existence]] of graspable, cravable things as a product of [[delusion]], an unawakened state.35  The  
unawakened state takes the imagined nature to be real, having its own inherent being, which is  
+
unawakened [[state]] takes the [[imagined]] [[nature]] to be real, having its [[own]] [[inherent]] being, which is  
essentially what Heidegger rejects when he rejects the correspondence theory of ontological  
+
[[essentially]] what [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] rejects when he rejects the correspondence {{Wiki|theory}} of [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]]
realists.  The Yogācāra reject such theories as well, saying that the “apprehending subject and  
+
[[realists]].  The [[Yogācāra]] reject such theories as well, saying that the “apprehending [[subject]] and  
apprehending object are inseparable in experience . . . there is no ‘self’ or ‘world’ but only  
+
apprehending [[object]] are [[inseparable]] in [[experience]] . . . there is no ‘[[self]]’ or ‘[[world]]’ but only  
experience (cittamatra) or presence (abhasa).  ‘The appearance/ presencing (abhasata) of duality  
+
[[experience]] ([[cittamatra]]) or presence ([[abhasa]]).  ‘The [[appearance]]/ presencing (abhasata) of [[duality]]
(dyava) exists (asti) but the being of duality does not’ (Mahayanasutralamkara XI, 21).”36  This  
+
(dyava) [[exists]] ([[asti]]) but the being of [[duality]] does not’ ([[Mahayanasutralamkara]] XI, 21).”36  This  
is not to say that things are entirely not-existent, as if the Yogācāra were nihilists, but rather that  
+
is not to say that things are entirely not-existent, as if the [[Yogācāra]] were [[nihilists]], but rather that  
they exist as dependently originated, and never inseparable from our experience of them.  In  
+
they [[exist]] as [[dependently originated]], and never [[inseparable]] from our [[experience]] of them.  In  
other words, with the Western phenomenologists, “to the Yogācārins, to speak of a ‘world’
+
other words, with the [[Western]] [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologists]], “to the [[Yogācārins]], to speak of a ‘[[world]]’
independent of our experiencing it makes no sense.”37   
+
{{Wiki|independent}} of our experiencing it makes no sense.”37   
  
By positing “things,” the deluded creates in the consciousness the dualism of grahaka  
+
By positing “things,” the deluded creates in the [[consciousness]] the [[dualism]] of [[grahaka]]
and grahya, the latter of which will be desired as if they have their own inherent being, as a  
+
and [[grahya]], the [[latter]] of which will be [[desired]] as if they have their [[own]] [[inherent]] being, as a  
means of attaining some lasting satisfaction.  This inevitably causes duhka, as any apparent  
+
means of [[attaining]] some lasting [[satisfaction]].  This inevitably [[causes]] duhka, as any apparent  
independence or inherent being is illusory. Thus, Yogācāra’s methodical stance is a “re
+
{{Wiki|independence}} or [[inherent]] being is [[illusory]]. Thus, [[Yogācāra’s]] methodical stance is a “re
membering” of the dependent nature of things, an un-seeing of the world of objects, and the  
+
membering” of the [[dependent nature]] of things, an un-seeing of the [[world]] of [[objects]], and the  
move from delusion to enlightened awareness (jnana), in which the awakened is free of false  
+
move from [[delusion]] to [[enlightened awareness]] ([[jnana]]), in which the [[awakened]] is free of false  
 
epistemology and sees things as they are.38  
 
epistemology and sees things as they are.38  
While the soteriological trajectory of Yogācāra seems foreign to the thought of Husserl,  
+
While the [[soteriological]] trajectory of [[Yogācāra]] seems foreign to the [[thought]] of [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]],  
Heidegger in some senses has reintroduced a weak soteriological equation: being open to Being  
+
[[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] in some [[senses]] has reintroduced a weak [[soteriological]] equation: being open to Being  
  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
results in a more fundamental presencing (against representation) of beings, or in later thought,  
+
results in a more fundamental presencing (against [[representation]]) of [[beings]], or in later [[thought]],  
Gelassenheit, “releasement” from willing or grasping, enables aletheia, or the disclosure of the  
+
Gelassenheit, “releasement” from willing or [[grasping]], enables aletheia, or the disclosure of the  
mystery of Being.39  I say only “weak” soteriological principle, as it occurs in the shadow of his  
+
{{Wiki|mystery}} of Being.39  I say only “weak” [[soteriological]] [[principle]], as it occurs in the shadow of his  
critique of onto-theology.  Husserl’s methodological influence on philosophy was such that it  
+
critique of onto-theology.  Husserl’s {{Wiki|methodological}} influence on [[philosophy]] was such that it  
took very little time for (especially French) phenomenologists to begin to do what Husserl – who  
+
took very little time for (especially {{Wiki|French}}) [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologists]] to begin to do what [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] – who  
himself “bracketed” religious assumptions -- would not do:  apply his method to religious  
+
himself “bracketed” [[religious]] {{Wiki|assumptions}} -- would not do:  apply his method to [[religious]]
 
assumptions.40  
 
assumptions.40  
  
The Theological Turn, and a Path Toward Theological-Buddhological Collaboration.  
+
The {{Wiki|Theological}} Turn, and a [[Path]] Toward Theological-Buddhological Collaboration.  
 
   
 
   
Heidegger’s critique of onto-theology in some ways complicates any use of philosophy  
+
Heidegger’s critique of onto-theology in some ways complicates any use of [[philosophy]]
by Christians. In others, his critique enables Christianity to make use of phenomenology as a  
+
by [[Christians]]. In others, his critique enables [[Christianity]] to make use of [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] as a  
better theological method than Heidegger might think.  To the first point, Heidegger critiques the  
+
better {{Wiki|theological}} method than [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] might think.  To the first point, [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] critiques the  
notion of God or the divine conceived of as “Being.”  When asked in Zurich, in 1951, whether it  
+
notion of [[God]] or the [[divine]] [[conceived]] of as “Being.”  When asked in {{Wiki|Zurich}}, in 1951, whether it  
is “proper to posit Being and God as identical?” Heidegger responded,  
+
is “proper to posit Being and [[God]] as [[identical]]?” [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] responded,  
 
   
 
   
Being and God are not identical and I would never attempt to think the essence of God by means of being.  Some among you perhaps know that I come from theology, that I still guard an old love for it and that I am not without a certain understanding of it.  If I were yet to write a theology – to which I sometimes feel inclined – then the word Being would not occur in it.  Faith does not need the thought of Being. […] I believe that Being can never be thought as the ground and essence of God and of his manifestedness, to the extent that the latter can indeed meet man, flashes in the dimension of Being, which in no way signifies that Being might be regarded as a possible predicate for God.  On this point one would have to establish completely new distinctions and delimitations.41  
+
Being and [[God]] are not [[identical]] and I would never attempt to think the [[essence]] of [[God]] by means of being.  Some among you perhaps know that I come from {{Wiki|theology}}, that I still guard an old [[love]] for it and that I am not without a certain [[understanding]] of it.  If I were yet to write a {{Wiki|theology}} – to which I sometimes [[feel]] inclined – then the [[word]] Being would not occur in it.  [[Faith]] does not need the [[thought]] of Being. […] I believe that Being can never be [[thought]] as the ground and [[essence]] of [[God]] and of his manifestedness, to the extent that the [[latter]] can indeed meet man, flashes in the [[dimension]] of Being, which in no way {{Wiki|signifies}} that Being might be regarded as a possible predicate for [[God]].  On this point one would have to establish completely new {{Wiki|distinctions}} and delimitations.41  
 
   
 
   
Further, it seems to Heidegger that for a Christian to engage philosophy at all is absurd,   
+
Further, it seems to [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] that for a [[Christian]] to engage [[philosophy]] at all is absurd,   
The thinker speaks of the ‘manifestness of Being;’ but ‘Being’ is an untheological word.  Because revelation itself determines the manner of manifestness and because theology does not have to prove or interpret ‘Being,’ theology does not have to defend itself before philosophy. . . . The Christian experience is so completely different that is has no need to enter into competition with philosophy.  When theology holds fast to the view that philosophy is foolishness, the mystery character of revelation will be much better preserved.  Therefore, in the face of a final decision, the ways part.42  
+
The thinker speaks of the ‘manifestness of Being;’ but ‘Being’ is an untheological [[word]].  Because [[revelation]] itself determines the manner of manifestness and because {{Wiki|theology}} does not have to prove or interpret ‘Being,’ {{Wiki|theology}} does not have to defend itself before [[philosophy]]. . . . The [[Christian]] [[experience]] is so completely different that is has no need to enter into competition with [[philosophy]].  When {{Wiki|theology}} holds fast to the view that [[philosophy]] is [[foolishness]], the {{Wiki|mystery}} [[character]] of [[revelation]] will be much better preserved.  Therefore, in the face of a final [[decision]], the ways part.42  
 
   
 
   
  
Line 289: Line 284:
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
Jean-Luc Marion and others have interpreted the first kind of distinction as mitigating  
+
Jean-Luc Marion and others have interpreted the first kind of {{Wiki|distinction}} as mitigating  
against blasphemy or idolatry. “To ‘degrade’ the notion of ‘God,’ for example, to the ‘highest
+
against [[blasphemy]] or [[idolatry]]. “To ‘degrade’ the notion of ‘[[God]],’ for example, to the ‘[[highest]]
value’ constitutes a ‘blow’ against ‘God,’ inasmuch as it is first ‘the greatest blasphemy  
+
value’ constitutes a ‘blow’ against ‘[[God]],’ inasmuch as it is first ‘the greatest [[blasphemy]]
 
imaginable against Being.’”43 This maneuver is (in a manner discussed above) reminiscent of the  
 
imaginable against Being.’”43 This maneuver is (in a manner discussed above) reminiscent of the  
Yogācāra rejection of the reification of the absolute, and leads to, in Marion’s terms, a necessary  
+
[[Yogācāra]] rejection of the [[reification]] of the [[absolute]], and leads to, in Marion’s terms, a necessary  
retreat from the inevitable blasphemy and idolatry of metaphysics.44  If we take this point  
+
[[retreat]] from the inevitable [[blasphemy]] and [[idolatry]] of metaphysics.44  If we take this point  
seriously, our only recourse to discuss the kind of inherently religious thought of Yogācāra, or to  
+
seriously, our only recourse to discuss the kind of inherently [[religious]] [[thought]] of [[Yogācāra]], or to  
talk of a Christian (or even Jewish) philosophical approach, then, is to turn to a method that is at  
+
talk of a [[Christian]] (or even [[Wikipedia:Judaism|Jewish]]) [[philosophical]] approach, then, is to turn to a method that is at  
least in the phenomenological tradition.   
+
least in the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} [[tradition]].   
  
Levinas achieves this theological turn to some degree by arguing that encounter with the  
+
Levinas achieves this {{Wiki|theological}} turn to some [[degree]] by arguing that encounter with the  
faces belonging to foreign consciousnesses communicates an irreducible quality of infinity;  
+
faces belonging to foreign [[consciousnesses]] communicates an irreducible [[quality]] of [[infinity]];  
Michel Henry takes a different approach, arguing from his Christian faith that the Incarnation  
+
Michel Henry takes a different approach, arguing from his [[Christian]] [[faith]] that the [[Incarnation]]
means that God is an experience and a phenomenon that can thus be phenomenologically  
+
means that [[God]] is an [[experience]] and a [[phenomenon]] that can thus be [[phenomenologically]]
analyzed.45  A Buddhist may already consider this in some manner valid, since the Buddha was  
+
analyzed.45  A [[Buddhist]] may already consider this in some manner valid, since the [[Buddha]] was  
supposed to have been conceived from divinity, but (re)incarnated as a human man –  
+
supposed to have been [[conceived]] from [[divinity]], but (re)incarnated as a [[human]] man –  
accordingly, Yogācāra holds that the realizations of its phenomenological methods are the same  
+
accordingly, [[Yogācāra]] holds that the realizations of its {{Wiki|phenomenological}} [[methods]] are the same  
that brought Gautama Buddha to enlightenment.  If we can, as Lusthaus argues, consider  
+
that brought [[Gautama Buddha]] to [[enlightenment]].  If we can, as [[Lusthaus]] argues, consider  
Yogācāra a Buddhist phenomenology, then perhaps phenomenology, which Husserl once said  
+
[[Yogācāra]] a [[Buddhist]] [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], then perhaps [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], which [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] once said  
“makes ‘protestants out of catholics and catholics out of protestants,’” truly “open[s] up a space  
+
“makes ‘protestants out of [[catholics]] and [[catholics]] out of protestants,’” truly “open[s] up a [[space]]
of reflection in which religious themes and concerns obtain a new philosophical weight and  
+
of {{Wiki|reflection}} in which [[religious]] themes and concerns obtain a new [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|weight}} and  
 
urgency, so as to bridge or at least make problematic the apparently strict separation between  
 
urgency, so as to bridge or at least make problematic the apparently strict separation between  
reason and faith.”46  
+
[[reason]] and faith.”46  
 
   
 
   
  
This characterization brings us back to the central conceit of the paper, which I hope is  
+
This characterization brings us back to the central [[conceit]] of the paper, which I {{Wiki|hope}} is  
now apparent:  Phenomenology offers a bridge not only within traditions as means of reconciling  
+
now apparent:  {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} offers a bridge not only within [[traditions]] as means of reconciling  
reason and faith, but also as a method of mutual approach to the “religious themes and concerns”  
+
[[reason]] and [[faith]], but also as a method of mutual approach to the “[[religious]] themes and concerns”  
of Yogācāra Buddhism and Christianity.  The human person, notions of the sacred, spirituality,  
+
of [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]] and [[Christianity]].  The [[human]] [[person]], notions of the [[sacred]], [[spirituality]],  
and mystical experiences are all among the fertile grounds for collaborative exploration.  
+
and [[mystical]] [[experiences]] are all among the {{Wiki|fertile}} grounds for collaborative exploration.  
Comparative theology often takes as its method a process of importing concepts from an  
+
Comparative {{Wiki|theology}} often takes as its method a process of importing [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] from an  
outside tradition and letting those alien spiritual insights dialogue with the home tradition to  
+
outside [[tradition]] and letting those alien [[spiritual insights]] {{Wiki|dialogue}} with the home [[tradition]] to  
enrich meaning or uncover new possibilities within the home tradition.  While this method has  
+
enrich meaning or uncover new possibilities within the home [[tradition]].  While this method has  
admittedly produced immensely interesting results in certain cases, the end product is an often  
+
admittedly produced immensely [[interesting]] results in certain cases, the end product is an often  
piecemeal collection of semi-isolated re-articulated dogmata that remain problematic in relation  
+
piecemeal collection of semi-isolated re-articulated dogmata that remain problematic in [[relation]]
to the larger whole of their respective traditions.  Rather than suggest that the problemata render  
+
to the larger whole of their respective [[traditions]].  Rather than suggest that the problemata render  
the exercise worthless, I affirm the value of theological dialogue of this nature, and take its rough  
+
the exercise worthless, I affirm the value of {{Wiki|theological}} {{Wiki|dialogue}} of this [[nature]], and take its rough  
edges as a promise that there is more work to be done.  Nevertheless, in the limited realm where  
+
edges as a promise that there is more work to be done.  Nevertheless, in the limited [[realm]] where  
it is possible, between Yogacara Buddhism and Western religious phenomenology, I hope to  
+
it is possible, between [[Yogacara]] [[Buddhism]] and [[Western]] [[religious]] [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], I {{Wiki|hope}} to  
encourage a transcendence of “cross-fertilization” and a move towards a method of shared  
+
encourage a {{Wiki|transcendence}} of “cross-fertilization” and a move towards a method of shared  
 
discovery that has no need of “crossing over” or “crossing back” as both parties resolve to do the  
 
discovery that has no need of “crossing over” or “crossing back” as both parties resolve to do the  
work of theology together.   
+
work of {{Wiki|theology}} together.   
 
   
 
   
  
Line 337: Line 332:
  
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
Bornemark, Jonna, and Hans Ruin, eds., Phenomenology and Religion: New Frontiers. Stockholm: Södertörn University, 2010.  
+
Bornemark, Jonna, and Hans Ruin, eds., {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and [[Religion]]: New Frontiers. {{Wiki|Stockholm}}: Södertörn {{Wiki|University}}, 2010.  
 
   
 
   
Cobb, John B., Jr., and Christopher Ives, eds. The Emptying God: A Buddhist-Jewish-Christian Conversation. Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock, 1990.  
+
Cobb, John B., Jr., and Christopher Ives, eds. The Emptying [[God]]: A Buddhist-Jewish-Christian [[Conversation]]. Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock, 1990.  
  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
Dalton, Drew. "Phenomenology and the Divine: Understanding the French Theological Turn,” Lecture given at St. Anselm College, October, 2009.  Accessed December 1, 2014. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=deE2qoyVf-0   
+
Dalton, Drew. "{{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and the [[Divine]]: [[Understanding]] the {{Wiki|French}} {{Wiki|Theological}} Turn,” Lecture given at St. Anselm {{Wiki|College}}, October, 2009.  Accessed December 1, 2014. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=deE2qoyVf-0   
Dupuis, Jacques. Christianity and the Religions: From Confrontation to Dialogue. Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 2003.  
+
Dupuis, Jacques. [[Christianity]] and the [[Religions]]: From Confrontation to Dialogue. Maryknoll, NY: Orbis [[Books]], 2003.  
Janicaud, Dominique, et al. Phenomenology and the “Theological Turn”: The French Debate. New York: Fordham University Press, 2000.  
+
Janicaud, Dominique, et al. {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and the “{{Wiki|Theological}} Turn”: The {{Wiki|French}} [[Debate]]. [[New York]]: {{Wiki|Fordham University}} Press, 2000.  
Lusthaus, Dan. Buddhist Phenomenology: A philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Ch’eng Wei-shih lun. New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2002.  
+
[[Lusthaus, Dan]]. [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Phenomenology}}: A [[philosophical]] [[Investigation]] of [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]] and the Ch’eng [[Wei-shih]] [[lun]]. [[New York]]: RoutledgeCurzon, 2002.  
Marion, Jean-Luc. God Without Being: hors-texte.  Translated by Thomas A. Carlson. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012.   
+
Marion, Jean-Luc. [[God]] Without Being: hors-texte.  Translated by Thomas A. Carlson. {{Wiki|Chicago}}: [[University of Chicago Press]], 2012.   
May, Reinhard. Heidegger's Hidden Sources: East-Asian Influences on his Work. Translated by Graham Parkes. New York: Routledge, 1996.  
+
May, Reinhard. Heidegger's Hidden Sources: East-Asian [[Influences]] on his Work. Translated by Graham Parkes. [[New York]]: Routledge, 1996.  
Mochizuki, Shinko. “Pure Land Buddhism in China: A Doctrinal History, Chapter 2: The Earliest Period; Chapter 3: Hui-yuan of Mt.Lu; and Chapter 4: The Translation of TextsSpurious Scriptures,” in Pacific World Journal, Third Series Number 3 (Fall 2001): 241275.  
+
[[Mochizuki]], [[Shinko]]. “[[Pure Land Buddhism]] in [[China]]: A [[Doctrinal]] History, [[Chapter]] 2: The Earliest Period; [[Chapter]] 3: [[Hui-yuan]] of Mt.Lu; and [[Chapter]] 4: The Translation of TextsSpurious [[Scriptures]],” in Pacific [[World]] Journal, Third Series Number 3 (Fall 2001): 241275.  
Nishitani, Keiji. Religion and Nothingness, trans. Jan Van Bragt (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1983)  
+
Nishitani, Keiji. [[Religion]] and [[Nothingness]], trans. Jan Van Bragt ([[Berkeley]], CA: {{Wiki|University of California Press}}, 1983)  
Oldmeadow, Peter. “Approaches to the Problem of Dualism in Heidegger and Indian Yogācāra Buddhism.” In Religion and Retributive Logic: Essays in Honor of Professor Garry W. Trompf. Edited by Carol M. Cusack and Christopher Hartney, 267-287. Leiden, The Netherlands: Koninklijke Brill NV, 2010.  
+
Oldmeadow, Peter. “Approaches to the Problem of [[Dualism]] in [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] and [[Indian]] [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]].” In [[Religion]] and Retributive [[Logic]]: Essays in [[Honor]] of [[Professor]] Garry W. Trompf. Edited by Carol M. Cusack and Christopher Hartney, 267-287. [[Leiden]], The {{Wiki|Netherlands}}: Koninklijke Brill NV, 2010.  
Powers, John. Hermeneutics and Tradition in the Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra (Boston: Brill Academic Publishers, 1993)  
+
[[Powers]], John. {{Wiki|Hermeneutics}} and [[Tradition]] in the [[Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra]] ([[Boston]]: Brill {{Wiki|Academic}} Publishers, 1993)  
Powers, John. “Yogācāra: Indian Buddhist Origins.” In Transforming Consciousness: Yogācāra Thought in Modern China. Edited by John Makeham, 41-63. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.  
+
[[Powers]], John. “[[Yogācāra]]: [[Indian Buddhist]] Origins.” In [[Transforming]] [[Consciousness]]: [[Yogācāra]] [[Thought]] in {{Wiki|Modern}} [[China]]. Edited by John Makeham, 41-63. [[Oxford]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 2014.  
Sawicki, Marianne. “Husserl” in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Accessed December 1, 2014. http://www.iep.utm.edu/husserl/#H6  
+
Sawicki, Marianne. “[[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]]” in The [[Internet]] {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Philosophy]]. Accessed December 1, 2014. http://www.iep.utm.edu/husserl/#H6  
Schmithausen, Lambert. The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and Reflections. Tokyo: International Institute for Buddhist Studies of the ICPBS, 2014.  
+
[[Schmithausen]], Lambert. The Genesis of [[Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda]]: Responses and Reflections. [[Tokyo]]: International Institute for [[Buddhist Studies]] of the ICPBS, 2014.  
Stein, Edith. On the Problem of Empathy. Translated by Waltraut Stein. Washington, D.C.: ICS Publications, 1989.  
+
Stein, Edith. On the Problem of {{Wiki|Empathy}}. Translated by Waltraut Stein. {{Wiki|Washington, D.C}}.: ICS Publications, 1989.  
  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
Williams, Paul. “Catholicism and Buddhism,” in The Catholic Church and the World Religions. Edited by Gavin d’Costa, 141-177. London: T&T Clark, 2011. Williams, Paul. “Yogācāra.” In Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations, 2nd ed. 84102. New York: Routledge, 2009.  
+
[[Williams]], Paul. “{{Wiki|Catholicism}} and [[Buddhism]],” in The {{Wiki|Catholic Church}} and the [[World]] [[Religions]]. Edited by Gavin d’Costa, 141-177. [[London]]: T&T Clark, 2011. [[Williams]], Paul. “[[Yogācāra]].” In [[Mahayana Buddhism]]: The [[Doctrinal]] Foundations, 2nd ed. 84102. [[New York]]: Routledge, 2009.  
  
 
   
 
   
 
   
 
   
1 Peter Oldmeadow, “Approaches to the Problem of Dualism in Heidegger and Indian Yogācāra Buddhism,” in Religion and Retributive Logic: Essays in Honor of Professor Garry W. Trompf, eds. Carol M. Cusack and Christopher Hartney (Leiden, The Netherlands: Koninklijke Brill NV, 2010), 272; see also Keiji Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness, trans. Jan Van Bragt (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1983), passim, and Reinhard May, Heidegger's Hidden Sources: East-Asian Influences on his Work, trans. Graham Parkes (New York: Routledge, 1996), 25.  
+
1 Peter Oldmeadow, “Approaches to the Problem of [[Dualism]] in [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] and [[Indian]] [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]],” in [[Religion]] and Retributive [[Logic]]: Essays in [[Honor]] of [[Professor]] Garry W. Trompf, eds. Carol M. Cusack and Christopher Hartney ([[Leiden]], The {{Wiki|Netherlands}}: Koninklijke Brill NV, 2010), 272; see also {{Wiki|Keiji Nishitani}}, [[Religion]] and [[Nothingness]], trans. Jan Van Bragt ([[Berkeley]], CA: {{Wiki|University of California Press}}, 1983), passim, and Reinhard May, Heidegger's Hidden Sources: East-Asian [[Influences]] on his Work, trans. Graham Parkes ([[New York]]: Routledge, 1996), 25.  
 
   
 
   
2 One example of extraordinary dialogue can be found in John B. Cobb, Jr., and Christopher Ives, eds., The Emptying God: A Buddhist-Jewish-Christian Conversation (Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock, 1990).  The conversation is mature and fruitful, but still sadly, because of its format of open dialogue, occupies a realm somewhere on the margins of (published) theological collaboration, which tends to take the form of a collection of essays united by topic of interest but not in actual participatory discourse.  
+
2 One example of [[extraordinary]] {{Wiki|dialogue}} can be found in John B. Cobb, Jr., and Christopher Ives, eds., The Emptying [[God]]: A Buddhist-Jewish-Christian [[Conversation]] (Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock, 1990).  The [[conversation]] is mature and fruitful, but still sadly, because of its format of open {{Wiki|dialogue}}, occupies a [[realm]] somewhere on the margins of (published) {{Wiki|theological}} collaboration, which tends to take the [[form]] of a collection of {{Wiki|essays}} united by topic of [[interest]] but not in actual participatory [[discourse]].  
 
   
 
   
3 Dan Lusthaus, Buddhist Phenomenology: A philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Ch’eng Wei-shih lun (New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2002), v, 4.  Cf. Oldmeadow, 270.  
+
3 [[Dan Lusthaus]], [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Phenomenology}}: A [[philosophical]] [[Investigation]] of [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]] and the Ch’eng [[Wei-shih]] [[lun]] ([[New York]]: RoutledgeCurzon, 2002), v, 4.  Cf. Oldmeadow, 270.  
 
   
 
   
 
4 Ibid., 4-5.  
 
4 Ibid., 4-5.  
Line 376: Line 371:
 
6 Ibid.  
 
6 Ibid.  
 
   
 
   
7 Ibid., vi.  See also, Powers, “Yogācāra: Indian Buddhist Origins,” in John Makeham, Transforming Consciousness: Yogācāra Thought in Modern China (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 57.  Powers praises Lusthaus for providing an erudite overview of Yogācāra, but balks at the apparent lack of a method analogous to Husserls epoché in Yogācāra texts.   
+
7 Ibid., vi.  See also, [[Powers]], “[[Yogācāra]]: [[Indian Buddhist]] Origins,” in John Makeham, [[Transforming]] [[Consciousness]]: [[Yogācāra]] [[Thought]] in {{Wiki|Modern}} [[China]] ([[Oxford]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 2014), 57.  [[Powers]] praises [[Lusthaus]] for providing an erudite overview of [[Yogācāra]], but balks at the apparent lack of a method analogous to Husserls epoché in [[Yogācāra]] texts.   
 
   
 
   
8 Indeed, the continuously delayed Ideen II, compiled by Edith stein before 1920, only saw publication in 1952, after Husserl’s death, in part because he had moved on in his thought before the manuscript could be finished.  Cf. Marianne Sawicki, “Husserl,” in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://www.iep.utm.edu/husserl/#H6 <accessed Dec 1, 2014.>  
+
8 Indeed, the continuously delayed Ideen II, compiled by Edith stein before 1920, only saw publication in 1952, after Husserl’s [[death]], in part because he had moved on in his [[thought]] before the {{Wiki|manuscript}} could be finished.  Cf. Marianne Sawicki, “[[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]],” in The [[Internet]] {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Philosophy]], http://www.iep.utm.edu/husserl/#H6 <accessed Dec 1, 2014.>  
 
   
 
   
9 Lusthaus, 6-7.  
+
9 [[Lusthaus]], 6-7.  
 
   
 
   
 
10 Ibid., vii.  
 
10 Ibid., vii.  
Line 410: Line 405:
 
20 Ibid.  
 
20 Ibid.  
 
   
 
   
21 Edith Stein, On the Problem of Empathy, trans. Waltraut Stein (Washington, D.C.: ICS Publications, 1989), 38-39.  I have changed W. Stein’s rendering of “the ‘I’” back to das Ich, as the German renders better the disconnect between a mere personal referent and the conceptual “proper noun” that stands in for the perceiving self, experiencing subject, and moral agent.  
+
21 Edith Stein, On the Problem of {{Wiki|Empathy}}, trans. Waltraut Stein ({{Wiki|Washington, D.C}}.: ICS Publications, 1989), 38-39.  I have changed W. Stein’s rendering of “the ‘I’” back to das Ich, as the [[German]] renders better the disconnect between a mere personal referent and the {{Wiki|conceptual}} “proper {{Wiki|noun}}” that stands in for the perceiving [[self]], experiencing [[subject]], and [[moral]] agent.  
 
   
 
   
 
22 Ibid., 39-40.  
 
22 Ibid., 39-40.  
 
   
 
   
23 The Yogacara would strenuously object to any suggestion that this is some sort of self.   
+
23 The [[Yogacara]] would strenuously [[object]] to any suggestion that this is some sort of [[self]].   
24 Williams, “Yogācāra,” 97.  25 Williams, “Yogācāra,” 97.  
+
24 [[Williams]], “[[Yogācāra]],” 97.  25 [[Williams]], “[[Yogācāra]],” 97.  
 
   
 
   
 
26 Stein, 21.  
 
26 Stein, 21.  
Line 421: Line 416:
 
27 Ibid., 23.  
 
27 Ibid., 23.  
 
   
 
   
28 Williams, “Yogācāra,” 98.  
+
28 [[Williams]], “[[Yogācāra]],” 98.  
 
   
 
   
 
29 Oldmeadow, 269.  
 
29 Oldmeadow, 269.  
Line 429: Line 424:
 
31 Ibid.   
 
31 Ibid.   
 
   
 
   
32 Cf. Nagarjuna in the Perfection of Wisdom Sutras; & Ibid., 280-281.  
+
32 Cf. [[Nagarjuna]] in the [[Perfection of Wisdom Sutras]]; & Ibid., 280-281.  
 
   
 
   
 
33 Ibid., 270.  
 
33 Ibid., 270.  
Line 449: Line 444:
 
39 Ibid., 279, 286.  
 
39 Ibid., 279, 286.  
 
   
 
   
40 Cf. Dominique Janicaud, Phenomenology and the Theological Turn: The French Debate (New York: Fordham University Press, 2000).  
+
40 Cf. Dominique Janicaud, {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and the {{Wiki|Theological}} Turn: The {{Wiki|French}} [[Debate]] ([[New York]]: {{Wiki|Fordham University}} Press, 2000).  
 
   
 
   
41 Quoted in Jean-Luc Marion, God Without Being: Hors-Texte, trans. Thomas A. Carlson (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012), 61-62.  
+
41 Quoted in Jean-Luc Marion, [[God]] Without Being: Hors-Texte, trans. Thomas A. Carlson ({{Wiki|Chicago}}: [[University of Chicago Press]], 2012), 61-62.  
 
   
 
   
 
42 Quoted in Marion, 62.   
 
42 Quoted in Marion, 62.   
 
   
 
   
43 Quoting Heidegger, from, respectively, The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt (New York: Haper and Row, 1977), 105, and “The Letter on Humanism,” in Basic Writings, trans. Frank A. Capuzzi, ed. David Farrel Krell (New York: Harper and Row, 1973), 228, in Marion, 64.  Cf. Drew Dalton, "Phenomenology and the Divine: Understanding the French Theological Turn,” Lecture given October, 2009 at St. Anselm College, available online at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=deE2qoyVf-0 <accessed Dec 1, 2014>.  
+
43 Quoting [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]], from, respectively, The Question Concerning {{Wiki|Technology}} and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt ([[New York]]: Haper and Row, 1977), 105, and “The [[Letter]] on {{Wiki|Humanism}},” in Basic Writings, trans. Frank A. Capuzzi, ed. David Farrel Krell ([[New York]]: Harper and Row, 1973), 228, in Marion, 64.  Cf. Drew Dalton, "{{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and the [[Divine]]: [[Understanding]] the {{Wiki|French}} {{Wiki|Theological}} Turn,” Lecture given October, 2009 at St. Anselm {{Wiki|College}}, available online at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=deE2qoyVf-0 <accessed Dec 1, 2014>.  
 
   
 
   
44 Marion, 37.  The dependent origination, or emptiness, of God, a possible solution to how the conflict of God and the notion of inherent Being might be resolved, explored via the concept of Trinity, is discussed in Cobb & Ives, but won’t be taken up here. 45 See Dalton.  
+
44 Marion, 37.  The [[dependent origination]], or [[emptiness]], of [[God]], a possible {{Wiki|solution}} to how the conflict of [[God]] and the notion of [[inherent]] Being might be resolved, explored via the {{Wiki|concept}} of {{Wiki|Trinity}}, is discussed in Cobb & Ives, but won’t be taken up here. 45 See Dalton.  
 
   
 
   
46 Jonna Bornemark and Hans Ruin, eds., Phenomenology and Religion: New Frontiers (Stockholm: Södertörn University, 2010), 7.  
+
46 Jonna Bornemark and Hans Ruin, eds., {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and [[Religion]]: New Frontiers ({{Wiki|Stockholm}}: Södertörn {{Wiki|University}}, 2010), 7.  
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
  

Latest revision as of 21:45, 2 February 2020




From Comparison to Collaboration Jacob W. Torbeck Loyola University Chicago Theology


This paper appears in a form similar to the manner in which it delivered on March 27, 2015 at Boston College’s ‘Engaging Particularities’ XIII Conference. For the sake of the conferences time constraints, this version has been substantially condensed from the initial full-length paper. Uncovering what Buddhism and Christianity might look like expressed in the native

philosophical idiom of the other is an ongoing project. Many comparative theologies have been focused on the translation of concepts between idioms – a redescription of one in terms of the other -- an observation of similarities between faiths, such as sin and karma, heaven and nirvana, or in comparative philosophy, angst (die Angst) and duhkha, nothingness (das Nichts) and shunyata. Constructive projects have followed, mediating between various concepts and paradigms. These projects are thanks in part to exchanges that were taking place in philosophical circles in the early half of the 20th Century, when Nishida Kitaro, Tanabe Hajime, and Nishitani Keiji, all in what would become known as the Kyoto School, studied with Heidegger, and according to Heidegger himself, “understood immediately” what he meant by nothingness.1


While this sort of translation has achieved admittedly interesting dialogue and opportunities for cross-fertilization in some instances, collaborative efforts, in many cases, remain nascent.2 My attempt in this paper is to suggest not merely a fruitful area for comparative philosophy or theology, but an outgrowth of comparison that offers a pathway to a shared method of doing philosophical theology. I envision this as a mutual approach that effects both meanings of “mutuality” in a movement of each toward the other, held in common by each. To accomplish this, I will describe the beliefs of Yogācāra Buddhism alongside Western phenomenology, before following phenomenology’s “theological turn” and offering speculation on future possibilities for collaboration.


What Analogue in Western Thought?


Notable scholars of Buddhism have labeled Yogācāra as a kind of “idealism.” Lambert Schmithausen, for example, employs it, as do Vallee Poussin, D.T. Suzuki, Edward Conze, and others.3 Against this characterization, Dan Lusthaus argues that the meanings of such an appellation are so numerous as to be without any real content. By “idealism,” do we mean to say merely that Yogācāra is not a kind of materialism? Or that it is a metaphysical idealism akin to Vedanta (wherein “some supermental, non-material entity creates all that exists.”)? An epistemological idealism, wherein the cognizing subject is the ground and limit of epistemology? Or a critical epistemological idealism, which brackets metaphysical or ontological implications, claiming only that the subject unavoidable shapes an experience to such an extent that the self and other are inextricable?4


These are all inappropriate categories. Yogācāra claims not that there is “only a mind,” but rather that the “mind only” is the obstacle to seeing things as they are. Rather than understanding the knowing subject as the limit of epistemology, Yogācāra, as a Buddhism, quite explicitly seeks to deconstruct and/or rid the practitioner of the delusion of subjectivity-as selfhood. Finally, in lieu of positing an Other that is essentially unknowable as Other, Yogācāra hopes to enable practitioners to see the Other without a “mirror,” that is, without the obstructions we ourselves create, as no longer Other.

The inappropriateness of the category of idealism notwithstanding, the stages of Yogācārin analysis seem to follow paths similar to those of certain Western philosophers. Theodore Stcherbatsky saw affinities between Yogācāra and Kantian critical philosophy, but the two thought systems come to different conclusions: Kant’sthing-in-itself’ “is ultimately unknowable as it is in itself (that is, it is noumenal). For Yogācāra, the way things happen


(yathabhutham) is eminently knowable, and seeing things as they truly are is one of [its] goals.”5 In Kant, we intuit the things themselves, “but never actually perceive anything beyond our own mental representations (Vorstellungen); for Yogācāra, eliminating precisely this sort of narcissistic cognitive closure (vijnapti-matra), so that one’s congnitions (jnana) are open to everything beyond ourselfs, like a mirror (adarsa), is the cognitive shift (asraya-paravrtti) necessary to become Awakened (Bodhi).”6 Stcherbatsky seems unaware that the reaction against Kant in the phenomenological school of Husserl was much closer to Yogācāra than Kant ever was, a movement that will be the subject of much of our comparative exercise.


The Multiplicity of Phenomenologies


Through a close examination of Western phenomenologists in comparison with Yogācāra thought, Dan Lusthaus’s Buddhist Phenomenology argues for the understanding of Yogācāra as Buddhist phenomenology, with the caveat that “Husserlian phenomenology and Yogācāra are not isomorphic systems… Husserl, et al., do not provide us with an exact correlation to Yogācāra.”7 Furthermore, we should not forget that Husserl himself continually changed his mind and developed his thought. One cannot pin Husserl down to a static set of propositions –


he must be identified, rather, with his method and the trajectory of his work.8 In addition, a number of followers of Husserl, among which were Edith Stein and Martin Heidegger, departed in their own ways from doing phenomenology in the manner Husserl taught, creating within the discipline a multiplicity of phenomenological perspectives. An analogue to this is true of Yogācāra, as well. The development of Yogācāra as a broad category within Buddhism is such that no one system can answer univocally to that name.9 Nevertheless, Lusthaus believes that phenomenology (in its varied forms) is the closest Western system of thought system to

Yogācāra (in its varied forms), and thus offers a westerner a methodological advantage and a hermeneutical lens that other perspectives lack.10

The great perceived potential for mutual approach is promising in comparative efforts to to build bridges (and erect shrines?) where a broadly shared perspective and language can help us think together on the preoccupations Western phenomenology and Yogācāra have in common: “the whys and hows of human experience […] perception, sensation, cognition, noetic construction, embodied conditioning,” and overcomingembodied ways of seeing the world.”11 This approach would still involve the “translation” of Yogācāra Buddhism into Western phenomenological language, and perhaps the converse as well. Lusthaus believes that this sort of translation has far fewer problems than with another system, e.g., German Idealism a la Hegel. In demonstrating the translation already underway, I will weave together some of the many points of connection between the Yogācāra school and phenomenologists from Edmund Husserl to Jean-Luc Marion.

Buddhism contends that we habitually and incessantly misinterpret our experience,” Lusthaus writes.12 This basic starting point was the impetus for Husserl as well. Husserl called his method a transcendental idealism, by which he meant an “investigation of those conditions through which we experience and think that are not readily apparent while we are experiencing and thinking.”13 To move to the experience, Husserl hoped to ‘bracket’ presuppositions. He finds common ground here with the Yogācāra, in the “search for the cognitive roots of knowledge,” or the epistemic foundation.14 For Husserl, all philosophic concerns ultimately must rest on the epistemic foundation. The philosopher questions ‘why and how’ cognition is possible, while the naïve (for the Buddhist, “unawakened” or “unenlightened”) viewpoint leaves such things unquestioned.15

Husserl’s Hyle and the Yogācārin Worldview


Yogācāra’s affinity to Husserl manifests itself in the problem of consciousness. In consciousness, we all the time encounter “non-genuine cognitive objects.” For Husserl, these objects are a ‘pastobjects (memories). Lusthaus identifies this example as “strikingly Yogacaric. Yogacara also accepts only a present object as genuine, as real. Objects from the past and future are never immediately given, or even remotely given; they are, according to Yogacara, cognitive constructions (parikalpita), which is to say, they are mental fictions.”16


While Husserl and Yogācāra both regard the present moment alone as real, “the present is never anything other than embodied history.”17 Husserl approaches this history through the phenomenological method, which innovatively reflects on the present moment. Yogācāra has as its soteriological underpinning a theory of historical embodiment in karma and the alayavijnana (storehouse consciousness). The two approaches can be viewed in parallel. On the one hand, a phenomenological movement from viewing the present as “mere presence” to “embodied history,” on the other, the uncovering and elimination of habitual (karmic) sedimentations, which float as seeds down the stream of consciousness.18


Alayavijnana, Edith Stein, and Other Consciousnesses


“According to Yogācāra our mental experience is changing, altering (parinama, pravrtti) every moment. In this fluctuating stream (vijnana-santana) we tend to posit two constants which and through which we cognize and evaluate all that we experience.”19 First, the self (ātman) as unchanging witness, and ‘objective’ circumstances (dharmas). In this stream of constant change, we grasp at physical objects because we have theories of them and ourselves by which we give value and identity to ourselves by obtaining the objects onto which we project values and identities.20


In a similar manner, Edith Stein writes, “We can take das Ich in a second sense as the unity of a stream of consciousness. We begin with das Ich as the subject of an actual experience. However, when we reflect on this experience, we find that it is not isolated, but set against the background of a stream of such experiences more or less clearly and distinctively given. The Ich of this experience was not always in it but shifted over or was drawn into it from another experience, and so on.”21 That is, our stream of consciousness is dependently arisen. She continues, “Our uniform, isolated stream of consciousness is not our soul. But . . . there is one basic experience given to us which, together with its persistent attributes, becomes apparent in our experiences as the identical “bearer” of [those experiences]. This is the substantial soul.”22 What she means here is something quite similar to the storehouse consciousness of the Yogācāra, understood by Paul Williams to be a “bearer” of karmic “seeds.”23 These seeds explain phenomenal existence in general,” and in particular, the link between experiences arising


from prior actions.24 This consciousness is described as belonging to an individual, always changing (flowing), and yet providing the principle of personal identity by linking actions in a causal chain (or stream). Despite belonging to an individual, because of the dependent, “intersubjective” nature of the world, the karmic seeds actually engage with all relevant storehouse consciousnesses, in effect giving rise to common experience and the intersubjective phenomenal world itself. The metaphor of “perfuming” used by the Yogācāra is quite evocative, leading us to imagine a sort of continuous causality that looks less like the causal model evoked by billiard balls ricocheting around a table, and more like the very organic image we get of an flower’s odor permeating the air, causing a new and different “perfuming” each time it gives rise to a new experience. Just as we can imagine this going on into the indefinite future, so too would it stretch back through history ad infinitum.25

Dependent origination comes again to the fore in the “perfuming” by these karmic seeds, as many experiences of phenomena could be said to be phenomena “of ‘foreign experience’ and correlatively the ‘perception of foreign experience,’”26 or in other words, an experiential awareness of foreign consciousness(es). Stein addresses knowledge of foreign consciousnesses earlier in Empathy, when she talks of, among other examples, how “[a] child seeing another crying cries, too,” speaking of transference of feeling as a kind of imitation resulting from the


action of another. “If we had not first comprehended the foreign experience,” Stein says, “we could not have brought it to givenness to ourselves at all.”27 She chooses the example of imitation of feeling to make the point that we not only observe the effects of others’ actions, but these actions truly affect us, even in situations where they don’t impinge upon us physically. After a like fashion, it makes sense to the Yogācāra to speak of the minds of others, and to avoid asserting any kind of solipsism; there are as many streams of consciousness as there are others, and the scent of their karmic seeds is not limited to one storehouse, but permeates the surroundings and becomes constitutive of the intersubjective phenomenal world.28

On the nature of value, Edith Stein, in 1916, was merely concerned with writing a descriptive account of how and why valuing occurs, and shared none of the soteriological aims of Yogācāra philosophy. For the Yogācāra, “value” is connected with desire, and is indicative of a subject-object dualism spoken of in terms of grahaka (the grasper) and grahya (the grasped). Escaping this problematic dualism through a realization or revelation of the emptiness of all things is the goal of Yogācāra thought and practice. Peter Oldmeadow, in observing this problem, notes similarities not primarily with Husserl or Stein, but with Martin Heidegger, who, with the Yogācāra Buddhists, rejects dualisms of almost every kind. The Problem of Dualism in Heidegger and Yogācāra Buddhism.


Heidegger, in his critique of the Western philosophical tradition, identifies the dualist orientation as a cause of cultural and personal alienation.29 His insistence on breaking through the alienation of dualism has an almost soteriological trajectory, prima facie resonating with the goals of Yogācāra philosophy. In Heidegger’s work, the problem of dualism is linked to the


question of ontology. The enquiry into the meaning of being is never one that can be asked from objectivity, however, and this very fact is the condition that makes Heidegger’s phenomenological method necessary. Being “thrown” into a particular world, with its particular socio-historical constitution, we must engage a method of traveling back to “a more fundamental attunement with Being,” creating an openness, or a clearing, “where a more fundamental

presencing (as opposed to representation) of beings can occur.”30 Oldmeadow here identifies a point of connection with Yogācāra Buddhism, wherein the “fundamental mode of being, or awakened awareness, which ‘precedes’ dualistic appearance (dvaya-pratibhasa) must be uncovered,” through a similar “going back.”31

Dualistic appearances, which much be ultimately un-seen (or re-viewed) are of various kinds: subject/object, perceiver/perceived, knower/known, and absolute/phenomena, for example. The final example might even be understood on the theological level as God/world, or nirvana/samsara.32 This matter of un-seeing, however, should not be understood as placing reality under the umbrella of monism. Rather than a radical unity, both Yogācāric and Heideggerian phenomenology emphasize the intersubjective or dependently originated nature of all things.33

This process of un-seeing is conceived of in different, though perhaps complementary ways. In the West, “being” is taken for granted so as to be forgotten, so much so that even the forgetting has been forgotten. Thus Heidegger’s project can be said to be a “remembering” of


Being and a rediscovery of the open horizon of possibilities.34 Buddhists approach a similar soteriological goal from the starting point of the first noble truth. Because the aim of Buddhists is to escape duhkha and samsara, they come to discuss the existence of graspable, cravable things as a product of delusion, an unawakened state.35 The unawakened state takes the imagined nature to be real, having its own inherent being, which is essentially what Heidegger rejects when he rejects the correspondence theory of ontological realists. The Yogācāra reject such theories as well, saying that the “apprehending subject and apprehending object are inseparable in experience . . . there is no ‘self’ or ‘world’ but only experience (cittamatra) or presence (abhasa). ‘The appearance/ presencing (abhasata) of duality (dyava) exists (asti) but the being of duality does not’ (Mahayanasutralamkara XI, 21).”36 This is not to say that things are entirely not-existent, as if the Yogācāra were nihilists, but rather that they exist as dependently originated, and never inseparable from our experience of them. In other words, with the Western phenomenologists, “to the Yogācārins, to speak of a ‘worldindependent of our experiencing it makes no sense.”37

By positing “things,” the deluded creates in the consciousness the dualism of grahaka and grahya, the latter of which will be desired as if they have their own inherent being, as a means of attaining some lasting satisfaction. This inevitably causes duhka, as any apparent independence or inherent being is illusory. Thus, Yogācāra’s methodical stance is a “re membering” of the dependent nature of things, an un-seeing of the world of objects, and the move from delusion to enlightened awareness (jnana), in which the awakened is free of false epistemology and sees things as they are.38 While the soteriological trajectory of Yogācāra seems foreign to the thought of Husserl, Heidegger in some senses has reintroduced a weak soteriological equation: being open to Being


results in a more fundamental presencing (against representation) of beings, or in later thought, Gelassenheit, “releasement” from willing or grasping, enables aletheia, or the disclosure of the mystery of Being.39 I say only “weak” soteriological principle, as it occurs in the shadow of his critique of onto-theology. Husserl’s methodological influence on philosophy was such that it took very little time for (especially French) phenomenologists to begin to do what Husserl – who himself “bracketed” religious assumptions -- would not do: apply his method to religious assumptions.40

The Theological Turn, and a Path Toward Theological-Buddhological Collaboration.

Heidegger’s critique of onto-theology in some ways complicates any use of philosophy by Christians. In others, his critique enables Christianity to make use of phenomenology as a better theological method than Heidegger might think. To the first point, Heidegger critiques the notion of God or the divine conceived of as “Being.” When asked in Zurich, in 1951, whether it is “proper to posit Being and God as identical?” Heidegger responded,

Being and God are not identical and I would never attempt to think the essence of God by means of being. Some among you perhaps know that I come from theology, that I still guard an old love for it and that I am not without a certain understanding of it. If I were yet to write a theology – to which I sometimes feel inclined – then the word Being would not occur in it. Faith does not need the thought of Being. […] I believe that Being can never be thought as the ground and essence of God and of his manifestedness, to the extent that the latter can indeed meet man, flashes in the dimension of Being, which in no way signifies that Being might be regarded as a possible predicate for God. On this point one would have to establish completely new distinctions and delimitations.41

Further, it seems to Heidegger that for a Christian to engage philosophy at all is absurd, The thinker speaks of the ‘manifestness of Being;’ but ‘Being’ is an untheological word. Because revelation itself determines the manner of manifestness and because theology does not have to prove or interpret ‘Being,’ theology does not have to defend itself before philosophy. . . . The Christian experience is so completely different that is has no need to enter into competition with philosophy. When theology holds fast to the view that philosophy is foolishness, the mystery character of revelation will be much better preserved. Therefore, in the face of a final decision, the ways part.42



Jean-Luc Marion and others have interpreted the first kind of distinction as mitigating against blasphemy or idolatry. “To ‘degrade’ the notion of ‘God,’ for example, to the ‘highest value’ constitutes a ‘blow’ against ‘God,’ inasmuch as it is first ‘the greatest blasphemy imaginable against Being.’”43 This maneuver is (in a manner discussed above) reminiscent of the Yogācāra rejection of the reification of the absolute, and leads to, in Marion’s terms, a necessary retreat from the inevitable blasphemy and idolatry of metaphysics.44 If we take this point seriously, our only recourse to discuss the kind of inherently religious thought of Yogācāra, or to talk of a Christian (or even Jewish) philosophical approach, then, is to turn to a method that is at least in the phenomenological tradition.

Levinas achieves this theological turn to some degree by arguing that encounter with the faces belonging to foreign consciousnesses communicates an irreducible quality of infinity; Michel Henry takes a different approach, arguing from his Christian faith that the Incarnation means that God is an experience and a phenomenon that can thus be phenomenologically analyzed.45 A Buddhist may already consider this in some manner valid, since the Buddha was supposed to have been conceived from divinity, but (re)incarnated as a human man – accordingly, Yogācāra holds that the realizations of its phenomenological methods are the same that brought Gautama Buddha to enlightenment. If we can, as Lusthaus argues, consider Yogācāra a Buddhist phenomenology, then perhaps phenomenology, which Husserl once said “makes ‘protestants out of catholics and catholics out of protestants,’” truly “open[s] up a space of reflection in which religious themes and concerns obtain a new philosophical weight and urgency, so as to bridge or at least make problematic the apparently strict separation between reason and faith.”46


This characterization brings us back to the central conceit of the paper, which I hope is now apparent: Phenomenology offers a bridge not only within traditions as means of reconciling reason and faith, but also as a method of mutual approach to the “religious themes and concerns” of Yogācāra Buddhism and Christianity. The human person, notions of the sacred, spirituality, and mystical experiences are all among the fertile grounds for collaborative exploration. Comparative theology often takes as its method a process of importing concepts from an outside tradition and letting those alien spiritual insights dialogue with the home tradition to enrich meaning or uncover new possibilities within the home tradition. While this method has admittedly produced immensely interesting results in certain cases, the end product is an often piecemeal collection of semi-isolated re-articulated dogmata that remain problematic in relation to the larger whole of their respective traditions. Rather than suggest that the problemata render the exercise worthless, I affirm the value of theological dialogue of this nature, and take its rough edges as a promise that there is more work to be done. Nevertheless, in the limited realm where it is possible, between Yogacara Buddhism and Western religious phenomenology, I hope to encourage a transcendence of “cross-fertilization” and a move towards a method of shared discovery that has no need of “crossing over” or “crossing back” as both parties resolve to do the work of theology together.


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Bornemark, Jonna, and Hans Ruin, eds., Phenomenology and Religion: New Frontiers. Stockholm: Södertörn University, 2010.
 
Cobb, John B., Jr., and Christopher Ives, eds. The Emptying God: A Buddhist-Jewish-Christian Conversation. Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock, 1990.

 
 
Dalton, Drew. "Phenomenology and the Divine: Understanding the French Theological Turn,” Lecture given at St. Anselm College, October, 2009. Accessed December 1, 2014. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=deE2qoyVf-0
Dupuis, Jacques. Christianity and the Religions: From Confrontation to Dialogue. Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 2003.
Janicaud, Dominique, et al. Phenomenology and the “Theological Turn”: The French Debate. New York: Fordham University Press, 2000.
Lusthaus, Dan. Buddhist Phenomenology: A philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Ch’eng Wei-shih lun. New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2002.
Marion, Jean-Luc. God Without Being: hors-texte. Translated by Thomas A. Carlson. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012.
May, Reinhard. Heidegger's Hidden Sources: East-Asian Influences on his Work. Translated by Graham Parkes. New York: Routledge, 1996.
Mochizuki, Shinko. “Pure Land Buddhism in China: A Doctrinal History, Chapter 2: The Earliest Period; Chapter 3: Hui-yuan of Mt.Lu; and Chapter 4: The Translation of TextsSpurious Scriptures,” in Pacific World Journal, Third Series Number 3 (Fall 2001): 241275.
Nishitani, Keiji. Religion and Nothingness, trans. Jan Van Bragt (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1983)
Oldmeadow, Peter. “Approaches to the Problem of Dualism in Heidegger and Indian Yogācāra Buddhism.” In Religion and Retributive Logic: Essays in Honor of Professor Garry W. Trompf. Edited by Carol M. Cusack and Christopher Hartney, 267-287. Leiden, The Netherlands: Koninklijke Brill NV, 2010.
Powers, John. Hermeneutics and Tradition in the Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra (Boston: Brill Academic Publishers, 1993)
Powers, John. “Yogācāra: Indian Buddhist Origins.” In Transforming Consciousness: Yogācāra Thought in Modern China. Edited by John Makeham, 41-63. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.
Sawicki, Marianne. “Husserl” in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Accessed December 1, 2014. http://www.iep.utm.edu/husserl/#H6
Schmithausen, Lambert. The Genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and Reflections. Tokyo: International Institute for Buddhist Studies of the ICPBS, 2014.
Stein, Edith. On the Problem of Empathy. Translated by Waltraut Stein. Washington, D.C.: ICS Publications, 1989.

 
 
Williams, Paul. “Catholicism and Buddhism,” in The Catholic Church and the World Religions. Edited by Gavin d’Costa, 141-177. London: T&T Clark, 2011. Williams, Paul. “Yogācāra.” In Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations, 2nd ed. 84102. New York: Routledge, 2009.

 
 
1 Peter Oldmeadow, “Approaches to the Problem of Dualism in Heidegger and Indian Yogācāra Buddhism,” in Religion and Retributive Logic: Essays in Honor of Professor Garry W. Trompf, eds. Carol M. Cusack and Christopher Hartney (Leiden, The Netherlands: Koninklijke Brill NV, 2010), 272; see also Keiji Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness, trans. Jan Van Bragt (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1983), passim, and Reinhard May, Heidegger's Hidden Sources: East-Asian Influences on his Work, trans. Graham Parkes (New York: Routledge, 1996), 25.
 
2 One example of extraordinary dialogue can be found in John B. Cobb, Jr., and Christopher Ives, eds., The Emptying God: A Buddhist-Jewish-Christian Conversation (Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock, 1990). The conversation is mature and fruitful, but still sadly, because of its format of open dialogue, occupies a realm somewhere on the margins of (published) theological collaboration, which tends to take the form of a collection of essays united by topic of interest but not in actual participatory discourse.
 
3 Dan Lusthaus, Buddhist Phenomenology: A philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Ch’eng Wei-shih lun (New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2002), v, 4. Cf. Oldmeadow, 270.
 
4 Ibid., 4-5.
 
5 Ibid., v.
 
6 Ibid.
 
7 Ibid., vi. See also, Powers, “Yogācāra: Indian Buddhist Origins,” in John Makeham, Transforming Consciousness: Yogācāra Thought in Modern China (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 57. Powers praises Lusthaus for providing an erudite overview of Yogācāra, but balks at the apparent lack of a method analogous to Husserls epoché in Yogācāra texts.
 
8 Indeed, the continuously delayed Ideen II, compiled by Edith stein before 1920, only saw publication in 1952, after Husserl’s death, in part because he had moved on in his thought before the manuscript could be finished. Cf. Marianne Sawicki, “Husserl,” in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://www.iep.utm.edu/husserl/#H6 <accessed Dec 1, 2014.>
 
9 Lusthaus, 6-7.
 
10 Ibid., vii.
 
11 Ibid.
 
12 Ibid., 1.
 
13 Ibid., 11.
 
 
                                                          
 

 
 
                                                                                                                                                                                           14 Ibid.
 
15 Ibid., 13.
 
16 Ibid., 15.
 
17 Ibid., 25.
 
18 Ibid.
 
19 Ibid., 1.
 
20 Ibid.
 
21 Edith Stein, On the Problem of Empathy, trans. Waltraut Stein (Washington, D.C.: ICS Publications, 1989), 38-39. I have changed W. Stein’s rendering of “the ‘I’” back to das Ich, as the German renders better the disconnect between a mere personal referent and the conceptual “proper noun” that stands in for the perceiving self, experiencing subject, and moral agent.
 
22 Ibid., 39-40.
 
23 The Yogacara would strenuously object to any suggestion that this is some sort of self.
24 Williams, “Yogācāra,” 97. 25 Williams, “Yogācāra,” 97.
 
26 Stein, 21.
 
27 Ibid., 23.
 
28 Williams, “Yogācāra,” 98.
 
29 Oldmeadow, 269.
 
30 Ibid.
 
31 Ibid.
 
32 Cf. Nagarjuna in the Perfection of Wisdom Sutras; & Ibid., 280-281.
 
33 Ibid., 270.
 
34 Ibid., 277.
 
 

 
 
                                                                                                                                                                                           35 Ibid., 279.
 
36 Ibid., 284.
 
37 Ibid.
 
38 Ibid., 280-282.
 
39 Ibid., 279, 286.
 
40 Cf. Dominique Janicaud, Phenomenology and the Theological Turn: The French Debate (New York: Fordham University Press, 2000).
 
41 Quoted in Jean-Luc Marion, God Without Being: Hors-Texte, trans. Thomas A. Carlson (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012), 61-62.
 
42 Quoted in Marion, 62.
 
43 Quoting Heidegger, from, respectively, The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt (New York: Haper and Row, 1977), 105, and “The Letter on Humanism,” in Basic Writings, trans. Frank A. Capuzzi, ed. David Farrel Krell (New York: Harper and Row, 1973), 228, in Marion, 64. Cf. Drew Dalton, "Phenomenology and the Divine: Understanding the French Theological Turn,” Lecture given October, 2009 at St. Anselm College, available online at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=deE2qoyVf-0 <accessed Dec 1, 2014>.
 
44 Marion, 37. The dependent origination, or emptiness, of God, a possible solution to how the conflict of God and the notion of inherent Being might be resolved, explored via the concept of Trinity, is discussed in Cobb & Ives, but won’t be taken up here. 45 See Dalton.
 
46 Jonna Bornemark and Hans Ruin, eds., Phenomenology and Religion: New Frontiers (Stockholm: Södertörn University, 2010), 7.




Source