Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Religion : Madhyamaka"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " Paul B. Donnelly Subject: Buddhism, Schools, Lineages, and Movements Online Publication Date: Jan 2017 Summary and Keywords Along with Yogacara, Madhyamaka (Midd...")
 
Line 8: Line 8:
  
  
Subject: Buddhism, Schools, Lineages, and Movements Online Publication Date: Jan 2017
+
[[Subject]]: [[Buddhism]], Schools, [[Lineages]], and Movements Online Publication Date: Jan 2017
  
  
Line 16: Line 16:
  
  
Along with Yogacara, Madhyamaka (Middle Way) is one of the two foundational doctrinal systems of Indian Mahayana Buddhism, which flourished from the 3rd century CE to the final disappearance of Buddhism from the subcontinent in the 12th- 13th centuries. Beginning in the 4th century, it spread to East Asia, where it became the foundation of an independent school of thought and influenced the other major Chinese Buddhist schools. It took root in Tibet beginning in the 7th century, where it served as the cornerstone of all the scholastically inclined Buddhist sects. Throughout the Mahayana Buddhist world, Madhyamaka has occupied a foundational position in doctrinal formulations and practices. Madhyamaka has tended to be regarded as either the supreme formulation of Mahayana thought, as was often the case in Tibet, or as complementary to Yogacara, which was more commonly held in China and Japan.
+
Along with [[Yogacara]], [[Madhyamaka]] ([[Middle Way]]) is one of the two foundational [[doctrinal]] systems of [[Indian Mahayana Buddhism]], which flourished from the 3rd century CE to the final [[disappearance]] of [[Buddhism]] from the subcontinent in the 12th- 13th centuries. Beginning in the 4th century, it spread to {{Wiki|East Asia}}, where it became the foundation of an {{Wiki|independent}} school of [[thought]] and influenced the other major [[Chinese Buddhist schools]]. It took [[root]] [[in Tibet]] beginning in the 7th century, where it served as the cornerstone of all the scholastically inclined [[Buddhist]] sects. Throughout the [[Mahayana]] [[Buddhist]] [[world]], [[Madhyamaka]] has occupied a foundational position in [[doctrinal]] formulations and practices. [[Madhyamaka]] has tended to be regarded as either the supreme formulation of [[Mahayana]] [[thought]], as was often the case [[in Tibet]], or as complementary to [[Yogacara]], which was more commonly held in [[China]] and [[Japan]].
  
  
The name “Middle Way” references a fundamental assumption in Buddhism that stakes a middle position between the idea that the self is an irreducible, enduring entity and one in which it is wholly reducible to the physical body and perishes after death. Though central Madhyamaka ideas, such as the doctrine of the Two Truths, Dependent Origination, and Emptiness, can be found in Nikaya Buddhism and in Mahayana sutras, it is in the treatises of Nagarjuna (2nd-3rd centuries CE) that we have a fully formed and distinct system of thought that can be called Madhyamaka. In earlier canonical works, and more explicitly in the Abhidharma, this notion of middle way applied exclusively to the self (Skt atmanlPaM atta) and conceptually constructed phenomena. In Mahayana sutras and in Nagarjuna works, the assertion is extended to the fundamental component parts of all existents, which are declared to be empty of intrinsic nature. In Abhidharma works, the self and other composite phenomena are said to be reducible to their fundamental parts, the dharmas (Pali dhamma), which, being irreducible, must have their own identifiable intrinsic mode of existence even if they exist dependently. According to Madhyamaka, a dharma cannot possess an intrinsic nature precisely because it exists dependently. Denying any intrinsic nature, Madhyamaka asserts that things exist only dependently, and this only in terms of conventional truth, and that ultimately, emptiness of intrinsic nature is the truth and reality of all things. Not surprisingly, such a position was contentious, and numerous interpreters attempted to elucidate this rather radical position. The question of which commentator or commentators are definitive has occupied many generations of Indian, East Asian, and Tibetan Buddhists, and the issue remains very much alive in modern scholarship on Madhyamaka. Though much of this scholarship has come from a philosophical perspective, the intent of Madhyamaka, like all Buddhist thought, is primarily soteriological in nature.  
+
The [[name]] “[[Middle Way]]” references a fundamental assumption in [[Buddhism]] that stakes a middle position between the [[idea]] that the [[self]] is an irreducible, enduring [[entity]] and one in which it is wholly reducible to the [[physical body]] and perishes after [[death]]. Though central [[Madhyamaka]] [[ideas]], such as the [[doctrine of the Two Truths]], [[Dependent Origination]], and [[Emptiness]], can be found in [[Nikaya Buddhism]] and in [[Mahayana sutras]], it is in the treatises of [[Nagarjuna]] (2nd-3rd centuries CE) that we have a fully formed and {{Wiki|distinct}} system of [[thought]] that can be called [[Madhyamaka]]. In earlier [[Wikipedia:canonical|canonical]] works, and more explicitly in the [[Abhidharma]], this notion of [[middle way]] applied exclusively to the [[self]] (Skt atmanlPaM [[atta]]) and conceptually [[constructed]] [[phenomena]]. In [[Mahayana sutras]] and in [[Nagarjuna]] works, the [[assertion]] is extended to the fundamental component parts of all [[existents]], which are declared to be [[empty]] of [[intrinsic nature]]. In [[Abhidharma]] works, the [[self]] and other composite [[phenomena]] are said to be reducible to their fundamental parts, the [[dharmas]] ([[Pali]] [[dhamma]]), which, being irreducible, must have their [[own]] identifiable intrinsic mode of [[existence]] even if they [[exist]] dependently. According to [[Madhyamaka]], a [[dharma]] cannot possess an [[intrinsic nature]] precisely because it [[exists]] dependently. Denying any [[intrinsic nature]], [[Madhyamaka]] asserts that things [[exist]] only dependently, and this only in terms of [[conventional truth]], and that ultimately, [[emptiness]] of [[intrinsic nature]] is the [[truth]] and [[reality of all things]]. Not surprisingly, such a position was contentious, and numerous interpreters attempted to elucidate this rather radical position. The question of which commentator or commentators are definitive has occupied many generations of [[Indian]], {{Wiki|East Asian}}, and [[Tibetan Buddhists]], and the issue remains very much alive in {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} on [[Madhyamaka]]. Though much of this {{Wiki|scholarship}} has come from a [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|perspective}}, the intent of [[Madhyamaka]], like all [[Buddhist]] [[thought]], is primarily [[soteriological]] in [[nature]].  
  
  
Keywords: Madhyamaka, Nagarjuna, emptiness (sunyata), dependent origination (pratityasamutpada), Mahayana, Abhidharma, intrinsic nature (svabhava), Two Truths
+
Keywords: [[Madhyamaka]], [[Nagarjuna]], [[emptiness]] ([[sunyata]]), [[dependent origination]] ([[pratityasamutpada]]), [[Mahayana]], [[Abhidharma]], [[intrinsic nature]] ([[svabhava]]), [[Two Truths]]
  
  
  
==Historical Background and Context of Madhyamaka==
+
==Historical Background and Context of [[Madhyamaka]]==
  
  
In numerous discourses, the Buddha refers to his teaching as a middle way1 between extreme and erroneous views about the putative self (Skt. atman2). An example of this is the frequently referenced Kaccayanagotta Sutta, in which the Buddha tells Kaccana that right view occupies a middle position between the two extreme conceptions of existence and nonexistence:
+
In numerous [[discourses]], the [[Buddha]] refers to his [[teaching]] as a middle way1 between extreme and erroneous [[views]] about the putative [[self]] (Skt. atman2). An example of this is the frequently referenced [[Kaccayanagotta Sutta]], in which the [[Buddha]] tells [[Kaccana]] that [[right view]] occupies a middle position between the two extreme conceptions of [[existence]] and [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]]:
This world, Kaccana, for the most part depends upon a duality—upon the notion of existence and the notion of nonexistence. But for one who sees the origin of the world as it really is with correct wisdom, there is no notion of nonexistence in regard to the world. And for one who sees the cessation of the world as it really is with correct wisdom, there is no notion of existence in regard to the world... “All exists”: Kaccana, this is one extreme. ‘All does not exist': this is the second extreme. Without veering towards either of these extremes, the Tathagata teaches a Dhamma by the middle.3
+
This [[world]], [[Kaccana]], for the most part depends upon a duality—upon the notion of [[existence]] and the notion of [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]]. But for one who sees the origin of the [[world]] as it really is with correct [[wisdom]], there is no notion of [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]] in regard to the [[world]]. And for one who sees the [[cessation]] of the [[world]] as it really is with correct [[wisdom]], there is no notion of [[existence]] in regard to the [[world]]... “All [[exists]]”: [[Kaccana]], this is one extreme. ‘All does not [[exist]]': this is the second extreme. Without veering towards either of these extremes, the [[Tathagata]] teaches a [[Dhamma]] by the middle.3
  
  
This passage is followed by an iteration of the teaching on the twelve links of dependent origination (pratityasamutpada), which describes the process of the origination of suffering from ignorance (avidya), and explains that the cessation of the first link leads to the cessation of “this whole mass of suffering.”4 Right view is the antidote to ignorance, and thus to suffering. The Sutta explicitly states that this middle view pertains to views about the self and to the cessation of suffering as its goal.
+
This passage is followed by an iteration of the [[teaching]] on the [[twelve links of dependent origination]] ([[pratityasamutpada]]), which describes the process of the origination of [[suffering]] from [[ignorance]] ([[avidya]]), and explains that the [[cessation]] of the first link leads to the [[cessation]] of “this whole {{Wiki|mass}} of suffering.”4 [[Right view]] is the antidote to [[ignorance]], and thus to [[suffering]]. The [[Sutta]] explicitly states that this [[middle view]] pertains to [[views]] about the [[self]] and to the [[cessation of suffering]] as its goal.
  
  
With the Abhidharma literature, we see the beginnings of categorization and standardization of concepts understood to be presented in the Suttas. Some early Buddhist traditions made this literature canonical, raising it to the status of “word of the Buddha” (buddhavacana), but others did not, and in some cases the latter integrated such material into the Sutta Pitaka. Interpretations of the Abhidharma texts led to a proliferation of systems of exposition, and the depth and complexity of the material provided fertile ground for the further explication of Buddhist doctrine. It is against this background that Madhyamaka as a distinct doctrinal system arose. Nagarjuna's arguments are predominantly directed against other Buddhists, presumably Abhidharmikas. As Siderits and Katsura in their translation of the Nagarjuna's Root Verses of the Middle Way (Mulamadhyamakakarika) point out, Nagarjuna's adversaries would have shared a core set of presuppositions, which establish the parameters of what Nagarjuna seeks to refute. These presuppositions can be summarized as follows.
+
With the [[Abhidharma]] {{Wiki|literature}}, we see the beginnings of categorization and standardization of [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] understood to be presented in the [[Suttas]]. Some early [[Buddhist traditions]] made this {{Wiki|literature}} [[Wikipedia:canonical|canonical]], raising it to the {{Wiki|status}} of “[[word of the Buddha]]” ([[buddhavacana]]), but others did not, and in some cases the [[latter]] integrated such material into the [[Sutta Pitaka]]. Interpretations of the [[Abhidharma texts]] led to a {{Wiki|proliferation}} of systems of [[exposition]], and the depth and complexity of the material provided {{Wiki|fertile}} ground for the further explication of [[Buddhist doctrine]]. It is against this background that [[Madhyamaka]] as a {{Wiki|distinct}} [[doctrinal]] system arose. [[Nagarjuna's]] arguments are predominantly directed against other [[Buddhists]], presumably [[Abhidharmikas]]. As [[Siderits]] and [[Katsura]] in their translation of the [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Root Verses of the Middle Way]] ([[Mulamadhyamakakarika]]) point out, [[Nagarjuna's]] adversaries would have shared a core set of presuppositions, which establish the parameters of what [[Nagarjuna]] seeks to refute. These presuppositions can be summarized as follows.
  
  
What really exists, in the last analysis, and in yogic realization, is in fact a dynamic flow of fundamental, irreducible entities called dharmas. All facts about things of the conventional world, and especially the self, can be explained entirely and ultimately in terms of dharmas and their relations with one another. What one can say about composite phenomena, such as the self, is only true conventionally. Only statements grounded at the level of dharmas can be ultimately true, because only dharmas have ultimate existence. An element of the assumptions about this ultimate existence is that dharmas possess their own intrinsic natures (svabhava), a unique property that is inherent to them and depends on nothing else. Nothing that lacks an intrinsic nature can be ultimate. The Buddhist goal of nirvana, the complete and final cessation of suffering, was held to be achieved through the realization of what is ultimately true about ourselves and the world. The erroneous belief that keeps us bound in samsara is the mistaken assumption that the self is ultimately real, when in fact it is a conceptual fiction that we superimpose upon an impersonal stream of mental and physical phenomena.
+
What really [[exists]], in the last analysis, and in [[yogic]] [[realization]], is in fact a dynamic flow of fundamental, irreducible entities called [[dharmas]]. All facts about things of the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[world]], and especially the [[self]], can be explained entirely and ultimately in terms of [[dharmas]] and their relations with one another. What one can say about composite [[phenomena]], such as the [[self]], is only true {{Wiki|conventionally}}. Only statements grounded at the level of [[dharmas]] can be ultimately true, because only [[dharmas]] have [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[existence]]. An [[element]] of the {{Wiki|assumptions}} about this [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[existence]] is that [[dharmas]] possess their [[own]] [[intrinsic natures]] ([[svabhava]]), a unique property that is [[inherent]] to them and depends on nothing else. Nothing that lacks an [[intrinsic nature]] can be [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]]. The [[Buddhist]] goal of [[nirvana]], the complete and final [[cessation of suffering]], was held to be achieved through the [[realization]] of what is ultimately true about ourselves and the [[world]]. The erroneous [[belief]] that keeps us [[bound]] in [[samsara]] is the mistaken assumption that the [[self]] is [[ultimately real]], when in fact it is a {{Wiki|conceptual}} {{Wiki|fiction}} that we superimpose upon an {{Wiki|impersonal}} {{Wiki|stream}} of [[mental and physical phenomena]].
  
  
===Nagarjuna and Mahayana===
+
===[[Nagarjuna]] and [[Mahayana]]===
  
  
Nagarjuna (2nd-3rd centuries CE) is generally regarded by later Buddhist traditions and modern scholarship as the founder of the Madhyamaka “school.”5 Traditional accounts also associate Nagarjuna with the rise of the Mahayana. In Tibetan traditions, Nagarjuna (along with Asanga) is called one of the two “Re-openers” of the Mahayana and is credited with the return of the Perfection of Wisdom texts to the world of humans by retrieving them from the realm of the Nagas, where they had been kept safe for centuries. He is revered as a patriarch in numerous Buddhist traditions in East Asia and Tibet, including Ch'an/Zen, Pure Land, Shingon, and the Tibetan Vajrayana.
+
[[Nagarjuna]] (2nd-3rd centuries CE) is generally regarded by later [[Buddhist traditions]] and {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} as the founder of the [[Madhyamaka]] “school.”5 [[Traditional]] accounts also associate [[Nagarjuna]] with the rise of the [[Mahayana]]. In [[Tibetan traditions]], [[Nagarjuna]] (along with [[Asanga]]) is called one of the two “Re-openers” of the [[Mahayana]] and is credited with the return of the [[Perfection of Wisdom]] texts to the [[world of humans]] by retrieving them from the [[realm]] of the [[Nagas]], where they had been kept safe for centuries. He is revered as a [[patriarch]] in numerous [[Buddhist traditions]] in {{Wiki|East Asia}} and [[Tibet]], [[including]] Ch'an/Zen, [[Pure Land]], [[Shingon]], and the [[Tibetan]] [[Vajrayana]].
  
  
The emergence of the Mahayana is characterized by the appearance of new texts, most notably the Perfection of Wisdom (Prajnaparamita) sutras, attributed to the Buddha. This genre of sutra focuses on the six, or ten, perfections of the Bodhisattva culminating in the perfection of wisdom itself called, among other things, the “mother of all the Buddhas.” These texts, which depict themselves as discourses of the Buddha, flatly reject the position that, while self was utterly illusory, the skandhas, the dynamic processes upon which a self was wrongly imputed, actually had an ontological status. In these sutras we read that the five skandhas do not exist, or are empty (sunya) Madhyamaka thought is traditionally understood as elucidating the meaning of such assertions in the Perfection of Wisdom sutras. In Nagarjuna's texts, arguments are made to demonstrate how and why this way of expressing the dharma is not only justified, but is in fact the actual and final intent of the Buddha's teachings.
+
The [[emergence]] of the [[Mahayana]] is characterized by the [[appearance]] of new texts, most notably the [[Perfection of Wisdom]] ([[Prajnaparamita]]) [[sutras]], attributed to the [[Buddha]]. This genre of [[sutra]] focuses on the six, or ten, [[perfections]] of the [[Bodhisattva]] culminating in the [[perfection of wisdom]] itself called, among other things, the “mother of all the [[Buddhas]].” These texts, which depict themselves as [[discourses]] of the [[Buddha]], flatly reject the position that, while [[self]] was utterly [[illusory]], the [[skandhas]], the dynamic {{Wiki|processes}} upon which a [[self]] was wrongly [[imputed]], actually had an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|status}}. In these [[sutras]] we read that the [[five skandhas]] do not [[exist]], or are [[empty]] ([[sunya]]) [[Madhyamaka]] [[thought]] is [[traditionally]] understood as elucidating the meaning of such assertions in the [[Perfection of Wisdom sutras]]. In [[Nagarjuna's]] texts, arguments are made to demonstrate how and why this way of expressing the [[dharma]] is not only justified, but is in fact the actual and final intent of the [[Buddha's teachings]].
  
  
===The Textual Foundations of Madhyamaka===
+
===The Textual Foundations of [[Madhyamaka]]===
  
  
In the Chinese Buddhist canon there are eight texts attributed to Nagarjuna, and in the Tibetan canon, there are 116. Studies of Chinese Madhyamaka have tended to focus on the Sanlun School and the influence of Madhyamaka on later syncretic schools such as Tiantai, Huayan, and Chan.6 The bulk of most modern scholarly interest in Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka has been on just a few of the Indian texts, in some cases in their Tibetan translations. Some disagreement remains about which of them can be reliably attributed to Nagarjuna, but there is a general consensus that the texts that the later Tibetan traditions group into the “analytic corpus” are genuine works of Nagarjuna. In addition to the analytic corpus (rigs tshogs), the Tibetan categorization includes the hymnic corpus (bstod tshogs) and the advice corpus (gtam tshogs).7 The analytic corpus includes the Root Verses of the Middle Way (Mulamadhyamakakorikd), the Sixty Stanzas on Analysis (Yuktisastika), the Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness
+
In the [[Chinese Buddhist canon]] there are eight texts attributed to [[Nagarjuna]], and in the [[Tibetan canon]], there are 116. Studies of {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Madhyamaka]] have tended to focus on the [[Sanlun School]] and the influence of [[Madhyamaka]] on later {{Wiki|syncretic}} schools such as [[Tiantai]], [[Huayan]], and Chan.6 The bulk of most {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholarly]] [[interest]] in [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Madhyamaka]] has been on just a few of the [[Indian]] texts, in some cases in their [[Tibetan]] translations. Some disagreement remains about which of them can be reliably attributed to [[Nagarjuna]], but there is a general consensus that the texts that the later [[Tibetan traditions]] group into the “analytic corpus” are genuine works of [[Nagarjuna]]. In addition to the analytic corpus ([[rigs tshogs]]), the [[Tibetan]] categorization includes the hymnic corpus ([[bstod tshogs]]) and the advice corpus (gtam tshogs).7 The analytic corpus includes the [[Root Verses of the Middle Way]] (Mulamadhyamakakorikd), the Sixty [[Stanzas]] on Analysis ([[Yuktisastika]]), the [[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
  
  
 
 
(Sunyatasaptati), the Dispeller of Objections (Vigrahavyavatanl), the Treatise on Pulverization (Vaidalyaprakarano), and the non-extant Proof of Conventions (Vyavaharasiddhi)? The Precious Garland (Ratnavall) is sometimes substituted in the place of the latter, but it is in fact a very different sort of text from the other five, much more in accord with the advice corpus, and is often placed in that category.
+
([[Sunyatasaptati]]), the Dispeller of Objections (Vigrahavyavatanl), the [[Treatise on Pulverization]] (Vaidalyaprakarano), and the [[non-extant]] [[Proof]] of Conventions ([[Vyavaharasiddhi]])? The [[Precious Garland]] (Ratnavall) is sometimes substituted in the place of the [[latter]], but it is in fact a very different sort of text from the other five, much more in accord with the advice corpus, and is often placed in that category.
The Root Verses of the Middle Way (MMK) was regarded by all the major commentators in India, China, and Tibet as Nagarjuna's magnum opus. Modern scholarship has accepted this and has used this text as the touchstone for determining the authenticity of the other works attributed to Nagarjuna. The Mulamadhyamakakarika consists of 447 verses in twenty-seven chapters, though some modern scholars argue that the text originally ended with chapter 25. Typical of the karika genre, the subject matter is presented in a terse style, leading to the composition of numerous commentaries in India, China, and Tibet to elucidate the meaning of the Mulamadhyamakakarika.
+
The [[Root Verses of the Middle Way]] (MMK) was regarded by all the major commentators in [[India]], [[China]], and [[Tibet]] as [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Wikipedia:Masterpiece|magnum opus]]. {{Wiki|Modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} has accepted this and has used this text as the touchstone for determining the authenticity of the other works attributed to [[Nagarjuna]]. The [[Mulamadhyamakakarika]] consists of 447 verses in twenty-seven chapters, though some {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]] argue that the text originally ended with [[chapter]] 25. Typical of the [[karika]] genre, the [[subject]] {{Wiki|matter}} is presented in a terse style, leading to the composition of numerous commentaries in [[India]], [[China]], and [[Tibet]] to elucidate the meaning of the [[Mulamadhyamakakarika]].
  
  
The Sixty Stanzas on Analysis (Yuktisastika) is a text consisting of sixty-one verses that explain Madhyamika analysis as the elimination of thinking in terms of existence and nonexistence of what is dependently originated (pratityasamutpada). The Sixty
+
The Sixty [[Stanzas]] on Analysis ([[Yuktisastika]]) is a text consisting of sixty-one verses that explain [[Madhyamika]] analysis as the elimination of [[thinking]] in terms of [[existence]] and [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]] of what is [[dependently originated]] ([[pratityasamutpada]]). The Sixty
Stanzas on Analysis makes the striking assertion that the world is a construction of ignorance, and nirvana is precisely the realization of this fact/ It is extant in both Chinese and Tibetan translations. The Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness (Sunyatasaptati) is a text of seventy-three verses that deals with the central Madhyamaka concept of emptiness (sunyata), accompanied by a commentary said to be authored by Nagarjuna himself. It exists only in Tibetan translation. The Dispeller of Objections (Vigrahavyavartint) is a seventy-verse text that answers objections to Nagarjuna's views expressed in his other works, especially the MMK. It is available in the original Sanskrit and also in Chinese and Tibetan translations. The Treatise on Pulverization (Vaidalyaprakarana') is a work that critiques the sixteen logical categories of Nyaya philosophy. It exists only in Tibetan translation. The Precious Garland (Ratnavalt) is a 500-verse work that is said to be advice given to a king. Among the minor analytic corpus texts, the Dispeller of Objections is often invoked to help clarify points in the MMK, especially on the issue of Nagarjuna's assertion that Madhyamikas have no philosophical thesis of their own. In the major English translations and the broader attempts to establish Nagarjuna's system, neither the Sixty Stanzas on Analysis nor the Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness has been much taken into account,10 despite the fact that the 7th-century Indian commentator Candrakirti held the Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness, along with the Dispeller of Objections, to form an appendix to the MMK.11
+
[[Stanzas]] on Analysis makes the striking [[assertion]] that the [[world]] is a construction of [[ignorance]], and [[nirvana]] is precisely the [[realization]] of this fact/ It is extant in both {{Wiki|Chinese}} and [[Tibetan]] translations. The [[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] ([[Sunyatasaptati]]) is a text of seventy-three verses that deals with the central [[Madhyamaka]] [[concept of emptiness]] ([[sunyata]]), accompanied by a commentary said to be authored by [[Nagarjuna]] himself. It [[exists]] only in [[Tibetan translation]]. The Dispeller of Objections (Vigrahavyavartint) is a seventy-verse text that answers objections to [[Nagarjuna's]] [[views]] expressed in his other works, especially the MMK. It is available in the original [[Sanskrit]] and also in {{Wiki|Chinese}} and [[Tibetan]] translations. The [[Treatise on Pulverization]] ([[Vaidalyaprakarana]]') is a work that critiques the sixteen [[logical]] categories of [[Nyaya philosophy]]. It [[exists]] only in [[Tibetan translation]]. The [[Precious Garland]] (Ratnavalt) is a 500-verse work that is said to be advice given to a [[king]]. Among the minor analytic corpus texts, the Dispeller of Objections is often invoked to help clarify points in the MMK, especially on the issue of [[Nagarjuna's]] [[assertion]] that [[Madhyamikas]] have no [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|thesis}} of their [[own]]. In the major English translations and the broader attempts to establish [[Nagarjuna's]] system, neither the Sixty [[Stanzas]] on Analysis nor the [[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] has been much taken into account,10 despite the fact that the 7th-century [[Indian]] commentator [[Candrakirti]] held the [[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]], along with the Dispeller of Objections, to [[form]] an appendix to the MMK.11
  
  
The hymns have received relatively little attention in Western scholarship despite their importance in the Tibetan traditions and many scholars' acceptance that at least some of these texts were likely written by the same author as the Mulamadhyakakarika.12 In Tibet, for the proponents of the more cataphatic “other-emptiness” (gzhan stong) doctrine, the hymns were revered as expressing Nagarjuna's final philosophical position and the definitive meaning of the Middle Way. For the most part, however, these texts and their message have not played a significant part in the understanding of Madhyamaka for Indian or Tibetan13 authors or for modern scholars.
+
[[The hymns]] have received relatively little [[attention]] in [[Western]] {{Wiki|scholarship}} despite their importance in the [[Tibetan traditions]] and many [[scholars]]' [[acceptance]] that at least some of these texts were likely written by the same author as the Mulamadhyakakarika.12 In [[Tibet]], for the proponents of the more {{Wiki|cataphatic}} “[[other-emptiness]]” ([[gzhan stong]]) [[doctrine]], the hymns were revered as expressing [[Nagarjuna's]] final [[philosophical]] position and the [[definitive meaning]] of the [[Middle Way]]. For the most part, however, these texts and their message have not played a significant part in the [[understanding]] of [[Madhyamaka]] for [[Indian]] or Tibetan13 authors or for {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]].
What Did Nagarjuna Mean by “Middle Way?”
+
What Did [[Nagarjuna]] Mean by “[[Middle Way]]?”
  
  
As mentioned above, the early Buddhist meaning of the idea that the Buddha's teaching is a middle way was that it staked out a position between the extreme views of “all exists” and “all does not exist.” These two views are often referred to as “eternalism” (sasvatadarsanam) and “annihilationism” (ucchedadarsanam), and they specifically refer to views about the self. An eternalist view of the self holds that the self abides through time and across lives, and an annihilationist view holds that personal existence is annihilated at death, thus rendering null questions of karmic reward or retribution. The meaning of right view, in the
+
As mentioned above, the early [[Buddhist]] meaning of the [[idea]] that the [[Buddha's teaching]] is a [[middle way]] was that it staked out a position between the extreme [[views]] of “all [[exists]]” and “all does not [[exist]].” These two [[views]] are often referred to as “{{Wiki|eternalism}}” (sasvatadarsanam) and “{{Wiki|annihilationism}}” (ucchedadarsanam), and they specifically refer to [[views]] about the [[self]]. An {{Wiki|eternalist}} view of the [[self]] holds that the [[self]] abides through time and across [[lives]], and an {{Wiki|annihilationist}} view holds that personal [[existence]] is {{Wiki|annihilated}} at [[death]], thus rendering null questions of [[karmic]] reward or retribution. The meaning of [[right view]], in the
Kaccayanagotta Sutta, is defined: “Without veering towards either of these extremes, the Tathagata teaches the Dhamma by the middle.”14 That Dhamma is the teaching of the twelve links of dependent origination.
+
[[Kaccayanagotta Sutta]], is defined: “Without veering towards either of these extremes, the [[Tathagata]] teaches the [[Dhamma]] by the middle.”14 That [[Dhamma]] is the [[teaching]] of the [[twelve links of dependent origination]].
  
  
Nagarjuna cites the Sanskrit parallel of this sutta but takes its implications further. In chapter fifteen of the MMK, he says, “In ‘The Instructing of Katyayana,' both ‘it exists' and ‘it does not exist' are denied by the Blessed One, who clearly perceives the existent and nonexistent.”15 Here, and throughout the MMK, Nagarjuna takes this sense of right view to apply not just to the self but to everything, including the skandhas, which are the basis for the mistaken assumption of an existent self that Abhidarmikas held to ultimately exist. Echoing numerous statements in the Perfection of Wisdom sutras, where it says that the five skandhas are as empty as the putative self, Nagarjuna argues in the MMK and other texts of the analytic corpus that any conceivable entity can be demonstrated to be empty, that is, not existent, nonexistent, both existent and nonexistent, neither existent or nonexistent.
+
[[Nagarjuna]] cites the [[Sanskrit]] parallel of this [[sutta]] but takes its implications further. In [[chapter]] fifteen of the MMK, he says, “In ‘The Instructing of [[Katyayana]],' both ‘it [[exists]]' and ‘it does not [[exist]]' are denied by the [[Blessed One]], who clearly [[perceives]] the [[existent]] and nonexistent.”15 Here, and throughout the MMK, [[Nagarjuna]] takes this [[sense]] of [[right view]] to apply not just to the [[self]] but to everything, [[including]] the [[skandhas]], which are the basis for the mistaken assumption of an [[existent]] [[self]] that [[Abhidarmikas]] held to ultimately [[exist]]. Echoing numerous statements in the [[Perfection of Wisdom sutras]], where it says that the [[five skandhas]] are as [[empty]] as the putative [[self]], [[Nagarjuna]] argues in the MMK and other texts of the analytic corpus that any conceivable [[entity]] can be demonstrated to be [[empty]], that is, not [[existent]], [[Wikipedia:Nothing|nonexistent]], both [[existent]] and [[Wikipedia:Nothing|nonexistent]], neither [[existent]] or [[Wikipedia:Nothing|nonexistent]].
  
  
In chapter after chapter, Nagarjuna subjects to analysis numerous things, from conditionality up through the Buddha, the Four Noble Truths, and nirvana. In every case, the object is revealed not to exist in any ultimate sense. Though he uses a number of common patterns of argumentation, underlying them all is a method that sets up all possible ways that the object could exist, and then refutes each possibility. For example, in chapter 1 Nagarjuna takes on the concept that things exist in the sense that they
+
In [[chapter]] after [[chapter]], [[Nagarjuna]] [[subjects]] to analysis numerous things, from [[conditionality]] up through the [[Buddha]], the [[Four Noble Truths]], and [[nirvana]]. In every case, the [[object]] is revealed not to [[exist]] in any [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[sense]]. Though he uses a number of common patterns of {{Wiki|argumentation}}, underlying them all is a method that sets up all possible ways that the [[object]] could [[exist]], and then refutes each possibility. For example, in [[chapter]] 1 [[Nagarjuna]] takes on the {{Wiki|concept}} that things [[exist]] in the [[sense]] that they
  
  
arise from causal conditions. He begins, “Not from itself, not from another, not from both, nor without a cause: never in any way is there any existing thing that has arisen.”16 The four possibilities for the arising of a thing are considered to exhaust the possibilities for a meaningful explanation of causation, and Nagarjuna rejects each one as incoherent. To come to this conclusion, Nagarjuna points out that dichotomous concepts like “self/other” are mutually dependent for their meaning, or existence. According to Abhidharmikas, for a thing to be real, it must have an intrinsic nature (svabhava), which makes it what it is. Nagarjuna denies the possibility of intrinsic nature, as well as the possibility of the nature of a thing arising from something else (parabhava), because “other” depends on “self.” Nagarjuna seeks to demonstrate that the Abhidharmikas' own positions are incoherent. The conclusion here is that conditions, regarded as real things by Abhidharmikas, are empty. “Therefore neither a product consisting of conditions nor one consisting of nonconditions exists; if the product does not exist, how can there be a condition or noncondition.”17 This discursive “emptying” of concepts that were widely accepted by scholastically inclined Buddhists of Nagarjuna's time is the main work of the MMK, and the conclusion that Nagarjuna reaches again and again is that when analyzed deeply, everything is revealed to lack any unique nature or essential nature of its own. Abhidarmikas insisted that the possession of such an intrinsic nature was necessary for something to exist in an ultimate sense; thus, from their perspective Nagarjuna seemed to be arguing that nothing really existed, and this was thought to be thoroughly incompatible with the teachings of the Buddha.
+
arise from [[causal conditions]]. He begins, “Not from itself, not from another, not from both, nor without a [[cause]]: never in any way is there any [[existing]] thing that has arisen.”16 The four possibilities for the [[arising]] of a thing are considered to exhaust the possibilities for a meaningful explanation of [[causation]], and [[Nagarjuna]] rejects each one as [[Wikipedia:Coherentism|incoherent]]. To come to this conclusion, [[Nagarjuna]] points out that {{Wiki|dichotomous}} [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] like “self/other” are mutually dependent for their meaning, or [[existence]]. According to [[Abhidharmikas]], for a thing to be real, it must have an [[intrinsic nature]] ([[svabhava]]), which makes it what it is. [[Nagarjuna]] denies the possibility of [[intrinsic nature]], as well as the possibility of the [[nature]] of a thing [[arising]] from something else ([[parabhava]]), because “other” depends on “[[self]].” [[Nagarjuna]] seeks to demonstrate that the [[Abhidharmikas]]' [[own]] positions are [[Wikipedia:Coherentism|incoherent]]. The conclusion here is that [[conditions]], regarded as real things by [[Abhidharmikas]], are [[empty]]. “Therefore neither a product consisting of [[conditions]] nor one consisting of nonconditions [[exists]]; if the product does not [[exist]], how can there be a [[condition]] or noncondition.”17 This discursive “emptying” of [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] that were widely accepted by scholastically inclined [[Buddhists]] of [[Nagarjuna's]] time is the main work of the MMK, and the conclusion that [[Nagarjuna]] reaches again and again is that when analyzed deeply, everything is revealed to lack any unique [[nature]] or [[essential nature]] of its [[own]]. [[Abhidarmikas]] insisted that the possession of such an [[intrinsic nature]] was necessary for something to [[exist]] in an [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[sense]]; thus, from their {{Wiki|perspective}} [[Nagarjuna]] seemed to be arguing that nothing really existed, and this was [[thought]] to be thoroughly incompatible with the [[teachings of the Buddha]].
  
  
It takes until chapter 24 of the MMK, “An Analysis of the Four Noble Truths,” before Nagarjuna responds to this not unreasonable concern. His response is to invoke the structure of the Two Truths, which Abhidarmikas accept, though in a completely different way, as discussed above. Nagarjuna's analyses have revealed that the arising and passing away of things in the phenomenal world, about which the Buddha taught, is possible only because those things lack intrinsic nature—they are neither existent, nonexistent, both, or neither.
+
It takes until [[chapter]] 24 of the MMK, “An Analysis of the [[Four Noble Truths]],” before [[Nagarjuna]] responds to this not unreasonable [[concern]]. His response is to invoke the {{Wiki|structure}} of the [[Two Truths]], which [[Abhidarmikas]] accept, though in a completely different way, as discussed above. [[Nagarjuna's]] analyses have revealed that the [[arising]] and passing away of things in the [[phenomenal world]], about which the [[Buddha]] [[taught]], is possible only because those things lack intrinsic nature—they are neither [[existent]], [[Wikipedia:Nothing|nonexistent]], both, or neither.
Exactly what that entails for the level of conventional truth/existence has been disputed by Nagarjuna's Indian and Chinese commentators, as well as modern interpreters. If nothing can be said to exist (or not, or both, or neither) in any ultimate sense, numerous questions obviously arise about ethics, the path, nirvana, and more. Nagarjuna's response to those who say that emptiness undermines all these things is to state that it is in fact the assumptions of existence/nonexistence, or existence by intrinsic nature, that would make the phenomenal world, knowledge of it, and the attainment of nirvana impossible. “All is possible when emptiness is possible. Nothing is possible when emptiness is impossible... If you look upon existents as real intrinsically, in that case you regard existents as being without cause and conditions.. Effect and cause, as well as agent, instrument and act, arising and ceasing, and fruit—all these you thereby deny.”18 Later commentators, both ancient and modern, however, have struggled with the full implications of the status of the phenomenal world after it has been emptied by Madhyamika analysis.19
+
Exactly what that entails for the level of [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] truth/existence has been disputed by [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Indian]] and {{Wiki|Chinese}} commentators, as well as {{Wiki|modern}} interpreters. If nothing can be said to [[exist]] (or not, or both, or neither) in any [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[sense]], numerous questions obviously arise about [[ethics]], the [[path]], [[nirvana]], and more. [[Nagarjuna's]] response to those who say that [[emptiness]] undermines all these things is to [[state]] that it is in fact the {{Wiki|assumptions}} of existence/nonexistence, or [[existence]] by [[intrinsic nature]], that would make the [[phenomenal world]], [[knowledge]] of it, and the [[attainment]] of [[nirvana]] impossible. “All is possible when [[emptiness]] is possible. Nothing is possible when [[emptiness]] is impossible... If you look upon [[existents]] as real intrinsically, in that case you regard [[existents]] as being without [[cause]] and [[conditions]].. Effect and [[cause]], as well as agent, instrument and act, [[arising]] and ceasing, and fruit—all these you thereby deny.”18 Later commentators, both [[ancient]] and {{Wiki|modern}}, however, have struggled with the full implications of the {{Wiki|status}} of the [[phenomenal world]] after it has been emptied by [[Madhyamika]] analysis.19
Emptiness, however, is not some ultimate nature of the sort imagined by the Abhidarmikas. It is just a useful way of talking, a convention, that steers a middle course between absolutism and nihilism. In probably the most famous verse of the MMK, Nagarjuna says, “Dependent Origination we declare to be emptiness. It [emptiness] is a dependent concept; just that is the middle path.”20 If everything is dependently originated, as the Buddha taught and Nagarjuna has argued, it follows that things cannot be accurately described as existing, not existing, both, or neither. Those concepts, and all others, are only conventional. As Mark Siderits has pithily put this, “The ultimate truth is that there is no ultimate truth.”21
+
[[Emptiness]], however, is not some [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[nature]] of the sort [[imagined]] by the [[Abhidarmikas]]. It is just a useful way of talking, a convention, that steers a middle course between [[absolutism]] and [[nihilism]]. In probably the most famous verse of the MMK, [[Nagarjuna says]], “[[Dependent Origination]] we declare to be [[emptiness]]. It [[[emptiness]]] is a dependent {{Wiki|concept}}; just that is the middle path.”20 If everything is [[dependently originated]], as the [[Buddha]] [[taught]] and [[Nagarjuna]] has argued, it follows that things cannot be accurately described as [[existing]], not [[existing]], both, or neither. Those [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], and all others, are only [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]. As [[Mark Siderits]] has pithily put this, “The [[ultimate truth]] is that there is no [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] truth.”21
  
  
===What is the Purpose of Madhyamaka?===
+
===What is the Purpose of [[Madhyamaka]]?===
  
  
A great deal of the modern scholarship on Madhyamaka approaches and engages with it as philosophy, but Buddhism has always been more than what we usually mean by this term. The Buddhist path is concerned with the eradication of existential suffering. Knowledge is for the sake of liberation from suffering and the cycle of birth and death (samsara). What then does Madhyamaka have to do with this? It is worthwhile to look at what the MMK states as its purpose. It is often the case that Indian treatises such as the MMK lay out the intended purpose of the text in the opening dedicatory verse:
+
A great deal of the {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} on [[Madhyamaka]] approaches and engages with it as [[philosophy]], but [[Buddhism]] has always been more than what we usually mean by this term. The [[Buddhist path]] is concerned with the eradication of [[existential]] [[suffering]]. [[Knowledge]] is for the [[sake]] of [[liberation]] from [[suffering]] and the [[cycle of birth and death]] ([[samsara]]). What then does [[Madhyamaka]] have to do with this? It is worthwhile to look at what the MMK states as its {{Wiki|purpose}}. It is often the case that [[Indian]] treatises such as the MMK lay out the intended {{Wiki|purpose}} of the text in the opening dedicatory verse:
  
  
I salute the Fully Enlightened One, the best of orators, who taught the doctrine of dependent origination, according to which there is neither cessation nor origination, neither annihilation nor the eternal, neither singularity nor plurality, neither the coming nor the going [of any dharma, for the purpose of nirvana characterized by] the auspicious cessation of hypostatization.22
+
I salute the [[Fully Enlightened One]], the best of orators, who [[taught]] the [[doctrine of dependent origination]], according to which there is neither [[cessation]] nor origination, neither {{Wiki|annihilation}} nor the eternal, neither [[singularity]] nor plurality, neither the coming nor the going [of any [[dharma]], for the {{Wiki|purpose}} of [[nirvana]] characterized by] the [[auspicious]] [[cessation]] of hypostatization.22
Nagarjuna identifies the Buddha's fundamental teaching to be dependent origination, characterized by the negation of four pairs of concepts. The purpose of this teaching, or the fruit of its realization, is said to be cessation of “hypostatization” (prapanca}, or the mental process of conceptualization or “thing-ification.”
+
[[Nagarjuna]] identifies the [[Buddha's]] fundamental [[teaching]] to be [[dependent origination]], characterized by the {{Wiki|negation}} of four pairs of [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. The {{Wiki|purpose}} of this [[teaching]], or the fruit of its [[realization]], is said to be [[cessation]] of “{{Wiki|hypostatization}}” ([[prapanca]]}, or the [[mental]] process of [[conceptualization]] or “thing-ification.”
  
  
In chapter 18, “An Analysis of the Self,” Nagarjuna says, “Liberation is attained through the destruction of actions and defilements; actions and defilements arise because of falsifying conceptualizations; those arise from hypostatization; but hypostatization is extinguished in emptiness. In the Sunyatasaptati, considered by Candrakirti to be a supplement for
+
In [[chapter]] 18, “An Analysis of the [[Self]],” [[Nagarjuna says]], “[[Liberation]] is [[attained]] through the destruction of [[actions]] and [[defilements]]; [[actions]] and [[defilements]] arise because of falsifying [[conceptualizations]]; those arise from {{Wiki|hypostatization}}; but {{Wiki|hypostatization}} is [[extinguished]] in [[emptiness]]. In the [[Sunyatasaptati]], considered by [[Candrakirti]] to be a supplement for
understanding the MMK, Nagarjuna says, “To imagine that things born by causes and conditions are real is called ignorance by the Teacher. From that the twelve members arise. But when one, by seeing correctly, has understood that things are empty one is not infatuated. That is the cessation of ignorance. Thereupon the twelve members stop.”
+
[[understanding]] the MMK, [[Nagarjuna says]], “To [[imagine]] that things born by [[causes and conditions]] are real is called [[ignorance]] by the [[Teacher]]. From that the twelve members arise. But when one, by [[seeing]] correctly, has understood that things are [[empty]] one is not infatuated. That is the [[cessation]] of [[ignorance]]. Thereupon the twelve members stop.”
  
  
The final verse of an Indian treatise of this sort can also conclude or restate the purport of all that came before it. Though the two 25
+
The final verse of an [[Indian]] treatise of this sort can also conclude or restate the purport of all that came before it. Though the two 25
major Indian commentators, Bhaviveka and Candrakirti, take the current twenty-seven-chapter version of the MMK to be entirely composed by Nagarjuna, some modern scholars have asserted that the final two chapters were later additions by another author. If this were so, the final verse of chapter 25, “An Analysis of Nirvana,” should be expected to tell us about the intent of the work. “This halting of cognizing everything, the halting of hypostatizing, is blissful. No Dharma whatsoever was ever taught by the Buddha to anyone.” This verse clearly echoes the dedicatory verse, though the translation here obscures this slightly in that the same phrase (prapancopasamah sivah) found in both verses is translated differently here. In the translation of the dedicatory verse this is rendered “the auspicious cessation of hypostatization.” The second part of the dedicatory verse is the salutation to the Buddha, who taught dependent origination characterized by the eight negations. In the final line of the verse at the end of chapter 25, having been through twenty-five chapters of negations, we hear that the Buddha did not teach any dharma at all, to anyone. Without taking a stand on whether or not this was the final verse of the original text, this statement does indeed sum up the text's work, though concluding on a far more radical point than the one on which it started, but for which Nagarjuna has argued thus far.
+
major [[Indian]] commentators, [[Bhaviveka]] and [[Candrakirti]], take the current twenty-seven-chapter version of the MMK to be entirely composed by [[Nagarjuna]], some {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]] have asserted that the final two chapters were later additions by another author. If this were so, the final verse of [[chapter]] 25, “An Analysis of [[Nirvana]],” should be expected to tell us about the intent of the work. “This halting of [[Wikipedia:Cognition|cognizing]] everything, the halting of hypostatizing, is [[blissful]]. No [[Dharma]] whatsoever was ever [[taught]] by the [[Buddha]] to anyone.” This verse clearly echoes the dedicatory verse, though the translation here obscures this slightly in that the same [[phrase]] (prapancopasamah sivah) found in both verses is translated differently here. In the translation of the dedicatory verse this is rendered “the [[auspicious]] [[cessation]] of {{Wiki|hypostatization}}.” The second part of the dedicatory verse is the salutation to the [[Buddha]], who [[taught]] [[dependent origination]] characterized by the [[eight negations]]. In the final line of the verse at the end of [[chapter]] 25, having been through twenty-five chapters of negations, we hear that the [[Buddha]] did not teach any [[dharma]] at all, to anyone. Without taking a stand on whether or not this was the final verse of the original text, this statement does indeed sum up the text's work, though concluding on a far more radical point than the one on which it started, but for which [[Nagarjuna]] has argued thus far.
  
  
Chapter 26 is an orthodox teaching on the twelve links of dependent origination, perhaps, as the commentator Bhaviveka suggests, in response to those who would take issue with the concluding verse of the nirvana chapter. It is also worth noting that Nagarjuna has used the doctrine of dependent origination as an argument for how things are in fact empty throughout the text up to this point, so perhaps this uncontroversial teaching of the twelve links helps us to see what he has meant by “dependent origination,” and links it back to the intrinsically soteriological purpose of Madhyamaka. “Upon the cessation of ignorance there is the nonarising of volitions. But the cessation of ignorance is due to meditation on just the knowledge of this. By reason of the cessation of one factor in the twelvefold chain, another successor factor fails to arise. Thus does the entire mass of suffering completely cease.”
+
[[Chapter]] 26 is an [[orthodox]] [[teaching]] on the [[twelve links of dependent origination]], perhaps, as the commentator [[Bhaviveka]] suggests, in response to those who would take issue with the concluding verse of the [[nirvana]] [[chapter]]. It is also worth noting that [[Nagarjuna]] has used the [[doctrine of dependent origination]] as an argument for how things are in fact [[empty]] throughout the text up to this point, so perhaps this uncontroversial [[teaching]] of the [[twelve links]] helps us to see what he has meant by “[[dependent origination]],” and links it back to the intrinsically [[soteriological]] {{Wiki|purpose}} of [[Madhyamaka]]. “Upon the [[cessation]] of [[ignorance]] there is the [[nonarising]] of [[Wikipedia:Volition (psychology)|volitions]]. But the [[cessation]] of [[ignorance]] is due to [[meditation]] on just the [[knowledge]] of this. By [[reason]] of the [[cessation]] of one factor in the twelvefold chain, another successor factor fails to arise. Thus does the [[entire mass of suffering]] completely cease.”
  
  
The twenty-seventh chapter is “An Analysis of Views,” in which Nagarjuna tackles the so-called indeterminate questions posed to the Buddha in some sutras. These are questions that the Buddha refused to answer, such as past and future existence of the person, the world, and so on. These questions were answered with silence, because they involved false presuppositions and thus could not be answered in a fashion that would be helpful to the questioner. Up until the final verse, most of what Nagarjuna has said would be acceptable to his Abhidharmika contemporaries, but the final verse says, “I salute Gautama, who, based on compassion, taught the true Dharma for the abandonment of all views.”28 In the dedicatory verse, the Buddha is praised as the teacher of dependent origination, which is described in terms of four pairs of dichotomous concepts, or views, all of which are negated. Here the purpose is stated as the abandonment of all views, the aforementioned, and presumably any and every possible view at all about the self and the world. Chapter 24, verse 18 quoted above, suggests that even emptiness, if taken to express a view, is to be ultimately abandoned.
+
The twenty-seventh [[chapter]] is “An Analysis of [[Views]],” in which [[Nagarjuna]] tackles the so-called {{Wiki|indeterminate}} questions posed to the [[Buddha]] in some [[sutras]]. These are questions that the [[Buddha]] refused to answer, such as {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}} [[existence]] of the [[person]], the [[world]], and so on. These questions were answered with [[silence]], because they involved false presuppositions and thus could not be answered in a fashion that would be helpful to the questioner. Up until the final verse, most of what [[Nagarjuna]] has said would be acceptable to his [[Abhidharmika]] contemporaries, but the final verse says, “I salute [[Gautama]], who, based on [[compassion]], [[taught]] the true [[Dharma]] for the [[abandonment]] of all views.”28 In the dedicatory verse, the [[Buddha]] is praised as the [[teacher]] of [[dependent origination]], which is described in terms of four pairs of {{Wiki|dichotomous}} [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], or [[views]], all of which are negated. Here the {{Wiki|purpose}} is stated as the [[abandonment]] of all [[views]], the aforementioned, and presumably any and every possible view at all about the [[self]] and the [[world]]. [[Chapter]] 24, verse 18 quoted above, suggests that even [[emptiness]], if taken to express a view, is to be ultimately abandoned.
  
  
===Nagarjuna's Madhyamika Successors in India===
+
===[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Madhyamika]] Successors in [[India]]===
  
  
Nagarjuna's oeuvre gave rise to numerous commentaries on his works, and original works from authors who saw themselves standing in the Madhyamika lineage. The earliest was Aryadeva (2nd-3rd centuries CE), who is traditionally understood to have been a direct disciple of Nagarjuna. His major text is an original work, The Four Hundred (Catuhsataka) This text traces the Bodhisattva's path from the cultivation of virtues up through the attainment of full awakening, thus situating Madhyamaka much more explicitly in Mahayana thought and practice than Nagarjuna's works. The complete text is extant only in Tibetan, and there is a full translation of Aryadeva's text into English by Karen Lang.29
+
[[Nagarjuna's]] oeuvre gave rise to numerous commentaries on his works, and original works from authors who saw themselves [[standing]] in the [[Madhyamika]] [[lineage]]. The earliest was [[Aryadeva]] (2nd-3rd centuries CE), who is [[traditionally]] understood to have been a direct [[disciple of Nagarjuna]]. His major text is an original work, The Four Hundred ([[Catuhsataka]]) This text traces the [[Bodhisattva's path]] from the [[cultivation]] of [[virtues]] up through the [[attainment]] of [[full awakening]], thus situating [[Madhyamaka]] much more explicitly in [[Mahayana]] [[thought]] and practice than [[Nagarjuna's]] works. The complete text is extant only in [[Tibetan]], and there is a full translation of [[Aryadeva's]] text into English by Karen Lang.29
Buddhapalita (early 6th century) wrote a commentary on Nagarjuna's MMK which is closely related to or identical with the commentary (Akutobhayd) sometimes attributed to Nagarjuna. In Buddhapalita's time, there were important new developments in Buddhist thought in the form of a highly developed epistemological system that would transform how Buddhist philosophy would be done. Buddhapalita resisted these innovations, employing only arguments that revealed the shortcomings of Nagarjuna's opponents' positions, consistent with Nagarjuna's own primary argumentative method.
+
[[Buddhapalita]] (early 6th century) wrote a commentary on [[Nagarjuna's]] MMK which is closely related to or [[identical]] with the commentary (Akutobhayd) sometimes attributed to [[Nagarjuna]]. In [[Buddhapalita's]] time, there were important new developments in [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] in the [[form]] of a highly developed [[epistemological]] system that would [[transform]] how [[Buddhist philosophy]] would be done. [[Buddhapalita]] resisted these innovations, employing only arguments that revealed the shortcomings of [[Nagarjuna's]] opponents' positions, consistent with [[Nagarjuna's]] [[own]] primary argumentative method.
Buddhapalita's conservatism on this point was criticized by the next major commentator, Bhaviveka (late 6th century). In his commentary on the MMK, the Lamp of Wisdom (Prajndpradrpa'), Bhaviveka took up a radically opposed position to that of Buddhapalita on the matter of what kind of argumentation was needed to establish the Madhyamika position. This shift is perhaps a result of the further integration of the epistemological advances of Dharmakirti (c. 650) into scholastic Mahayana discourse. Many thought that these new methods put Buddhists on a more solid footing in defending themselves against the critiques of non-Buddhist philosophers in India. Bhaviveka felt that the Madhyamika position needed more than the unwanted- consequence method of argumentation (prasanga) favored by Nagarjuna and Buddhapalita in order to give it logical establishment. Bhaviveka utilized logically elaborated syllogisms (svatantra anumana) in order to argue for the conclusions of Nagarjuna. For this reason, Bhaviveka would later be considered by the Tibetan traditions to be the founder of the Svatantrika school of interpretation. In addition to the Lamp of Wisdom, Bhaviveka wrote an independent verse treatise on Madhyamaka, the Verses on the Heart of the Middle Way (Madhyamakahrdayakarikd), with a prose commentary. In this work he surveys and critiques the perspective of non-Mahayana Buddhists, Yogacarins, and the six philosophical systems of Hinduism. Hence, this text presents us with a snapshot of the range of philosophical positions current in India in the 6th century.
+
[[Buddhapalita's]] conservatism on this point was criticized by the next major commentator, [[Bhaviveka]] (late 6th century). In his commentary on the MMK, the [[Lamp of Wisdom]] (Prajndpradrpa'), [[Bhaviveka]] took up a radically opposed position to that of [[Buddhapalita]] on the {{Wiki|matter}} of what kind of {{Wiki|argumentation}} was needed to establish the [[Madhyamika]] position. This shift is perhaps a result of the further {{Wiki|integration}} of the [[epistemological]] advances of [[Dharmakirti]] (c. 650) into {{Wiki|scholastic}} [[Mahayana]] [[discourse]]. Many [[thought]] that these new [[methods]] put [[Buddhists]] on a more solid footing in defending themselves against the critiques of [[non-Buddhist]] [[philosophers]] in [[India]]. [[Bhaviveka]] felt that the [[Madhyamika]] position needed more than the unwanted- consequence method of {{Wiki|argumentation}} ([[prasanga]]) favored by [[Nagarjuna]] and [[Buddhapalita]] in order to give it [[logical]] establishment. [[Bhaviveka]] utilized [[logically]] elaborated [[syllogisms]] ([[svatantra]] [[anumana]]) in order to argue for the conclusions of [[Nagarjuna]]. For this [[reason]], [[Bhaviveka]] would later be considered by the [[Tibetan traditions]] to be the founder of the [[Svatantrika school]] of [[interpretation]]. In addition to the [[Lamp of Wisdom]], [[Bhaviveka]] wrote an {{Wiki|independent}} verse treatise on [[Madhyamaka]], the Verses on the [[Heart of the Middle Way]] (Madhyamakahrdayakarikd), with a prose commentary. In this work he surveys and critiques the {{Wiki|perspective}} of non-Mahayana [[Buddhists]], [[Yogacarins]], and the six [[philosophical]] systems of [[Hinduism]]. Hence, this text presents us with a snapshot of the range of [[philosophical]] positions current in [[India]] in the 6th century.
  
  
In his extensive commentary on the MMK, Clear Words (Prasannapada), candrakirti (7th century) extensively critiqued Bhaviveka's introduction of the epistemological system of Dharmakirti into the exegesis of Madhyamaka and critiqued that system itself as well as doctrines of Yogacara. candrakirti, in defense of Buddhapalita, argued for exclusive reliance on prasanga arguments to establish the Madhyamika position. This emphasis on prasanga argumentation would cause later Tibetan doxographers to see Candrakirti to be the founder of the Prasangika school of Madhyamaka, which came to be seen as differing from the Svatantrikas not only in terms of methodology but also in terms of holding different philosophical positions.30 In
+
In his extensive commentary on the MMK, Clear Words ([[Prasannapada]]), [[candrakirti]] (7th century) extensively critiqued Bhaviveka's introduction of the [[epistemological]] system of [[Dharmakirti]] into the {{Wiki|exegesis}} of [[Madhyamaka]] and critiqued that system itself as well as [[doctrines]] of [[Yogacara]]. [[candrakirti]], in defense of [[Buddhapalita]], argued for exclusive reliance on [[prasanga]] arguments to establish the [[Madhyamika]] position. This {{Wiki|emphasis}} on [[prasanga]] {{Wiki|argumentation}} would [[cause]] later [[Tibetan]] [[Wikipedia:Doxography|doxographers]] to see [[Candrakirti]] to be the founder of the [[Prasangika school]] of [[Madhyamaka]], which came to be seen as differing from the [[Svatantrikas]] not only in terms of [[Wikipedia:scientific method|methodology]] but also in terms of holding different [[philosophical]] positions.30 In
  
addition to his commentary on the MMK, Candrakirti wrote commentaries on Nagarjuna's Sunyatasaptati and Yuktisastika as well as one on Aryadeva's Catuhsataka. His original work, Introduction to the Middle Way (Madhyamakavatara'), was intended to be a general introduction to Madhyamaka, but with an emphasis on Bodhisattva practice and realization. It is divided into ten sections on the production of the mind of awakening (bodhicitta), which are aligned with the ten Bodhisattva stages taught in the Sutra on the Ten Grounds (Dasabhumika Sutra) and the Ten Perfections. Because of this structuring, this text is far more focused on realization and soteriology than Nagarjuna's works of the analytic corpus. Despite the professed importance of the MMK among Tibetan scholars, Candrakirti's Introduction to the Middle Way has been the subject of far more commentary in Tibet.
+
addition to his commentary on the MMK, [[Candrakirti]] wrote commentaries on [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Sunyatasaptati]] and [[Yuktisastika]] as well as one on [[Aryadeva's]] [[Catuhsataka]]. His original work, [[Introduction to the Middle Way]] ([[Madhyamakavatara]]'), was intended to be a general introduction to [[Madhyamaka]], but with an {{Wiki|emphasis}} on [[Bodhisattva practice]] and [[realization]]. It is divided into ten [[sections]] on the production of [[the mind of awakening]] ([[bodhicitta]]), which are aligned with the ten [[Bodhisattva stages]] [[taught]] in the [[Sutra on the Ten Grounds]] ([[Dasabhumika Sutra]]) and the [[Ten Perfections]]. Because of this structuring, this text is far more focused on [[realization]] and {{Wiki|soteriology}} than [[Nagarjuna's]] works of the analytic corpus. Despite the professed importance of the MMK among [[Tibetan scholars]], [[Candrakirti's]] [[Introduction to the Middle Way]] has been the [[subject]] of far more commentary [[in Tibet]].
  
  
===Treatises of Late Indian Madhyamika Thinkers===
+
===Treatises of Late [[Indian]] [[Madhyamika]] Thinkers===
  
  
In India, Madhyamaka was followed by Yogacara, which, like Madhyamaka, can be seen as providing a reasoned explication of the doctrines of certain Mahayana sutras, especially in the Yogacara case, the Samdhmirmocana. From the Yogacara perspective, the Perfection of Wisdom Sutras and Madhyamaka are understood as clearing away the pernicious illusions projected by hypostatization (prapanca), but the final and definitive teachings of the Buddha were to be found in Yogacara sutras and treatises. In these texts, it is asserted that mind, once purified of hypostatization, was ultimate reality and awakening itself. Among the early commentators on Nagarjuna's texts are several by prominent masters of the Yogacara school. A portion of a commentary ascribed to Asanga (4th century) on the beginning of the MMK is found in the Chinese canon, and a commentary by Sthiramati (6th century) is also preserved there. Other commentaries by Yogacarins are also referred to in both Chinese and Tibetan sources, though they are not extant. This clearly demonstrates that Nagarjuna's works were not seen to be necessarily in conflict with the teachings of Yogacara.
+
In [[India]], [[Madhyamaka]] was followed by [[Yogacara]], which, like [[Madhyamaka]], can be seen as providing a reasoned explication of the [[doctrines]] of certain [[Mahayana sutras]], especially in the [[Yogacara]] case, the Samdhmirmocana. From the [[Yogacara]] {{Wiki|perspective}}, the [[Perfection of Wisdom Sutras]] and [[Madhyamaka]] are understood as clearing away the [[pernicious]] [[illusions]] {{Wiki|projected}} by {{Wiki|hypostatization}} ([[prapanca]]), but the final and [[definitive teachings]] of the [[Buddha]] were to be found in [[Yogacara]] [[sutras]] and treatises. In these texts, it is asserted that [[mind]], once [[purified]] of {{Wiki|hypostatization}}, was [[ultimate reality]] and [[awakening]] itself. Among the early commentators on [[Nagarjuna's]] texts are several by prominent [[masters]] of the [[Yogacara school]]. A portion of a commentary ascribed to [[Asanga]] (4th century) on the beginning of the MMK is found in the [[Chinese canon]], and a commentary by [[Sthiramati]] (6th century) is also preserved there. Other commentaries by [[Yogacarins]] are also referred to in both {{Wiki|Chinese}} and [[Tibetan]] sources, though they are not extant. This clearly demonstrates that [[Nagarjuna's]] works were not seen to be necessarily in conflict with the teachings of [[Yogacara]].
  
  
For the most part, Madhyamaka and Yogacara became synthesized into a complementary whole that addressed both the negation z
+
For the most part, [[Madhyamaka]] and [[Yogacara]] became synthesized into a complementary whole that addressed both the {{Wiki|negation}} z
of pernicious views and the establishment of ultimate truth as consciousness. The works of Jnanagarbha, Santaraksita and Kamalasila set the standard for Madhyamaka orthodoxy, and it was the latter two that took Madhyamaka to Tibet as part of the first establishment of Buddhism there. In India, the Svatantika-Prasangika distinction was not the important one; it was rather one between the views of those who accepted the (conventional) existence of external objects, which included both Bhaviveka and Candrakirti, and those who asserted a more Yogacarin understanding, in which external objects were ultimately mind- originated, though also empty in the last analysis.
+
of [[pernicious]] [[views]] and the establishment of [[ultimate truth]] as [[consciousness]]. The works of [[Jnanagarbha]], [[Santaraksita]] and [[Kamalasila]] set the standard for [[Madhyamaka]] {{Wiki|orthodoxy}}, and it was the [[latter]] two that took [[Madhyamaka]] to [[Tibet]] as part of the first establishment of [[Buddhism]] there. In [[India]], the Svatantika-Prasangika {{Wiki|distinction}} was not the important one; it was rather one between the [[views]] of those who accepted the ([[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]) [[existence]] of [[external objects]], which included both [[Bhaviveka]] and [[Candrakirti]], and those who asserted a more [[Yogacarin]] [[understanding]], in which [[external objects]] were ultimately [[mind]]- originated, though also [[empty]] in the last analysis.
  
  
This latter category included Jnanagarbha, Santaraksita and Kamalasila, and it was the dominant position in scholastic Buddhist India until at least the 11th century. Jnanagarbha wrote a treatise examining the Two Truths (Satyadvayavibhanga'), accompanied z
+
This [[latter]] category included [[Jnanagarbha]], [[Santaraksita]] and [[Kamalasila]], and it was the dominant position in {{Wiki|scholastic}} [[Buddhist]] [[India]] until at least the 11th century. [[Jnanagarbha]] wrote a treatise examining the [[Two Truths]] ([[Satyadvayavibhanga]]'), accompanied z
by an auto-commentary. Santaraksita wrote a treatise on Madhyamaka, the Ornament of the Middle Way (Madhyamakalamkara), which established the foundation of what would later be called the Yogacara-Madhyamaka school. He also composed the Tattvasamgraha, an extensive critical study of the doctrines of the different schools of Indian philosophy at the time. A commentary on Jnanagarbha's Satyadvayavibhanga is attributed to him as well. Kamalasila was the disciple of
+
by an auto-commentary. [[Santaraksita]] wrote a treatise on [[Madhyamaka]], the [[Ornament of the Middle Way]] ([[Madhyamakalamkara]]), which established the foundation of what would later be called the [[Yogacara-Madhyamaka]] school. He also composed the [[Tattvasamgraha]], an extensive critical study of the [[doctrines of the different schools]] of [[Indian philosophy]] at the time. A commentary on [[Jnanagarbha's]] [[Satyadvayavibhanga]] is attributed to him as well. [[Kamalasila]] was the [[disciple]] of
  
  
Santaraksita, on whose Tattvasamgraha he wrote a substantial commentary. Kamalasila also wrote an original work, the Illumination of the Middle Way (Madhyamakaloka), which expounds the Yogacara-Madhymaka system in great detail, building upon and elucidating the texts of his teacher.
+
[[Santaraksita]], on whose [[Tattvasamgraha]] he wrote a substantial commentary. [[Kamalasila]] also wrote an original work, the [[Illumination of the Middle]] Way ([[Madhyamakaloka]]), which expounds the Yogacara-Madhymaka system in great detail, building upon and elucidating the texts of his [[teacher]].
Madhyamaka in East Asia
+
[[Madhyamaka]] in {{Wiki|East Asia}}
Madhyamaka texts and teachings were brought to China by Kumarajiva (350-409), and these eventually became the foundation of an independent school, Sanlun or Three Treatise School. The three authoritative texts of Sanlun were the MMK (called the Madhyamakasastra in the Chinese canon),31 the Twelve Gate Treatise (Shih erh men lun) attributed to Nagarjuna, and the One Hundred Verse Treatise (Pai lun) attributed to Aryadeva. The latter two texts exist only here in Kumarajiva's translations. The text that has arguably had the greatest influence on East Asian Madhyamaka, however, was the massive Treatise Which is a Teaching on the Great Perfection of Wisdom (Ta-chih-tu lun), also translated by Kumarajiva. After Kumaraj iva, his disciple Sengzhao was the most important figure in the establishment and development of Chinese Madhyamaka.32 The Madhyamika commentaries that have figured so prominently in the Tibetan traditions' interpretation of Madhyamaka, and in modern scholarship, are not included in the Chinese canon, so the development of Madhyamika thought took a quite different path than in Tibet. In East Asia, there has tended to be a more ontologically positivist understanding of emptiness and a general harmonization of Madhyamaka and Yogacara, seeing them as complementary rather than opposing systems. Though Sanlun faded from importance as a distinct school of thought, Madhyamaka remained significant throughout the later development of Chinese Buddhism, influencing Tiantai, Huayan, and especially Chan.33
+
[[Madhyamaka]] texts and teachings were brought to [[China]] by [[Kumarajiva]] (350-409), and these eventually became the foundation of an {{Wiki|independent}} school, [[Sanlun]] or [[Three Treatise School]]. The three authoritative texts of [[Sanlun]] were the MMK (called the Madhyamakasastra in the {{Wiki|Chinese}} canon),31 the [[Twelve Gate Treatise]] (Shih erh men [[lun]]) attributed to [[Nagarjuna]], and the [[One Hundred Verse Treatise]] (Pai [[lun]]) attributed to [[Aryadeva]]. The [[latter]] two texts [[exist]] only here in [[Kumarajiva's]] translations. The text that has arguably had the greatest influence on {{Wiki|East Asian}} [[Madhyamaka]], however, was the massive Treatise Which is a [[Teaching]] on the [[Great Perfection of Wisdom]] ([[Ta-chih-tu lun]]), also translated by [[Kumarajiva]]. After Kumaraj iva, his [[disciple]] [[Sengzhao]] was the most important figure in the establishment and [[development]] of {{Wiki|Chinese}} Madhyamaka.32 The [[Madhyamika]] commentaries that have figured so prominently in the [[Tibetan traditions]]' [[interpretation]] of [[Madhyamaka]], and in {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}}, are not included in the [[Chinese canon]], so the [[development]] of [[Madhyamika]] [[thought]] took a quite different [[path]] than [[in Tibet]]. In {{Wiki|East Asia}}, there has tended to be a more [[ontologically]] positivist [[understanding]] of [[emptiness]] and a general {{Wiki|harmonization}} of [[Madhyamaka]] and [[Yogacara]], [[seeing]] them as complementary rather than opposing systems. Though [[Sanlun]] faded from importance as a {{Wiki|distinct}} school of [[thought]], [[Madhyamaka]] remained significant throughout the later [[development]] of [[Chinese Buddhism]], influencing [[Tiantai]], [[Huayan]], and especially Chan.33
  
  
===Madhyamaka in Tibet===
+
===[[Madhyamaka in Tibet]]===
  
  
The Tibetans received Madhyamika texts in both the first (7th-8th centuries) and second (11th-12th centuries) periods of the propagation of Buddhism there. Because scholastic monasticism was part of the institutional form that was imported, alongside Vajrayana, Madhaymaka was important from the very beginning, and has remained so. In Tibet, monk scholars sought to establish a hierarchy of Buddhist tenet systems (grub mtha') that encompassed all the Buddhist schools in an ascending order, beginning with the two Abhidarmika Schools (Vaibhasika and Sautrantika), which served as the elementary understandings of the Dharma, moving up to the Yogacara, and culminating in the Madhyamaka. It was assumed that the understanding of the philosophical positions of each of these schools enabled one to then understand the next higher level. Ascent up through this hierarchy represented a progressively more subtle understanding of the Two Truths. The two Abhidharma schools asserted that dharmas, understood in different ways, were ultimately real and anything that was the result of conceptual hypostatization was merely conventional. The Yogacara was understood to assert that external objects were ultimately unreal (i.e., projected by conceptual imposition) and only consciousness was ultimately real. Madhyamaka was understood to go one step further and assert that consciousness too was empty and thus only existent conventionally.
+
The [[Tibetans]] received [[Madhyamika]] texts in both the first (7th-8th centuries) and second (11th-12th centuries) periods of the [[propagation]] of [[Buddhism]] there. Because {{Wiki|scholastic}} [[monasticism]] was part of the institutional [[form]] that was imported, alongside [[Vajrayana]], [[Madhaymaka]] was important from the very beginning, and has remained so. In [[Tibet]], [[monk scholars]] sought to establish a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} of [[Buddhist]] [[tenet]] systems ([[grub mtha]]') that encompassed all the [[Buddhist schools]] in an ascending order, beginning with the two Abhidarmika Schools ([[Vaibhasika]] and [[Sautrantika]]), which served as the elementary understandings of the [[Dharma]], moving up to the [[Yogacara]], and culminating in the [[Madhyamaka]]. It was assumed that the [[understanding]] of the [[philosophical]] positions of each of these schools enabled one to then understand the next higher level. [[Ascent]] up through this {{Wiki|hierarchy}} represented a progressively more {{Wiki|subtle}} [[understanding]] of the [[Two Truths]]. The two [[Abhidharma]] schools asserted that [[dharmas]], understood in different ways, were [[ultimately real]] and anything that was the result of {{Wiki|conceptual}} {{Wiki|hypostatization}} was merely [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]. The [[Yogacara]] was understood to assert that [[external objects]] were ultimately unreal (i.e., {{Wiki|projected}} by {{Wiki|conceptual}} imposition) and [[only consciousness]] was [[ultimately real]]. [[Madhyamaka]] was understood to go one step further and assert that [[consciousness]] too was [[empty]] and thus only [[existent]] {{Wiki|conventionally}}.
  
  
Early in the doxographical project Tibetans followed the categorization of Madhyamaka inherited from India, in which Madhyamaka was divided into those who accepted the conventional existence of external objects (e.g., Bhaviveka and z
+
Early in the [[Wikipedia:Doxography|doxographical]] project [[Tibetans]] followed the categorization of [[Madhyamaka]] inherited from [[India]], in which [[Madhyamaka]] was divided into those who accepted the [[conventional existence]] of [[external objects]] (e.g., [[Bhaviveka]] and z
Candrakirti) and those who declared external objects to be projections of mind and ultimately empty (Jnanagarbha, Santaraksita and Kamalasila). In the late 11th century, the Madhyamaka works of Candrakirti were translated into Tibetan, and Tibetan doxographers began to factor them into their categorizing efforts. Shortly thereafter, the terms Svatantrika and Prasangika were coined (in Tibetan) and deployed in a new conceptualization of Madhyamaka schools. There were Tibetan scholars who accepted Candrakirti's interpretation of Madhyamaka and those who argued forcefully against it, but in the end it was the Prasangika approach that won the day, though it remained a matter of some dispute just what the differences between this school and the Svatantrika were.
+
[[Candrakirti]]) and those who declared [[external objects]] to be {{Wiki|projections}} of [[mind]] and ultimately [[empty]] ([[Jnanagarbha]], [[Santaraksita]] and [[Kamalasila]]). In the late 11th century, the [[Madhyamaka]] works of [[Candrakirti]] were translated into [[Tibetan]], and [[Tibetan]] [[Wikipedia:Doxography|doxographers]] began to factor them into their categorizing efforts. Shortly thereafter, the terms [[Svatantrika]] and [[Prasangika]] were coined (in [[Tibetan]]) and deployed in a new [[conceptualization]] of [[Madhyamaka]] schools. There were [[Tibetan scholars]] who accepted [[Candrakirti's]] [[interpretation]] of [[Madhyamaka]] and those who argued forcefully against it, but in the end it was the [[Prasangika]] approach that won the day, though it remained a {{Wiki|matter}} of some dispute just what the differences between this school and the [[Svatantrika]] were.
  
  
In the 14th century, it was the writings of Tsongkhapa that introduced a new distinction between Svatantrika and Prasangika, one which posited not just a methodological distinction between the two schools but also an ontological one. Prior to Tsongkhapa and continuing after him in the scholarship of the Sakya, Kagyu, and Nyingma sects, the principal difference was one of a whether the Madhyamika master used arguments that simply sought to demonstrate to the opponent the unwanted consequences of his position (prasanga) or rather utilized logically established arguments that positively proved the Madhyamika position (svatantra). Tsongkhapa argued instead that there is an actual difference in how the two schools understand conventional truth. In his understanding, Svatantrikas accept the conventional reality of the manifest world. In that world there are things that are real and things that are illusory. The sophisticated epistemological system of Dharmakirti was seen to provide tools to ascertain which are which, and to prove, in a real sense, the doctrinal position of Madhyamaka. According to Tsongkhapa, this entails a subtle realism that falls short of the definitive meaning of Nagarjuna's texts, which is that everything is empty of intrinsic nature. Only Candrakirti's interpretation of Madhyamaka is considered to go far enough and relegate everything in this world to the status of merely conventional.34 Though this understanding is accepted by only one of the four major sects of Tibetan Buddhism, it has had an inestimable impact on the modern scholarship on Madhyamaka.
+
In the 14th century, it was the writings of [[Tsongkhapa]] that introduced a new {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[Svatantrika]] and [[Prasangika]], one which posited not just a {{Wiki|methodological}} {{Wiki|distinction}} between the two schools but also an [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] one. Prior to [[Tsongkhapa]] and continuing after him in the {{Wiki|scholarship}} of the [[Sakya]], [[Kagyu]], and [[Nyingma]] sects, the [[principal]] difference was one of a whether the [[Madhyamika]] [[master]] used arguments that simply sought to demonstrate to the opponent the unwanted {{Wiki|consequences}} of his position ([[prasanga]]) or rather utilized [[logically]] established arguments that positively proved the [[Madhyamika]] position ([[svatantra]]). [[Tsongkhapa]] argued instead that there is an actual difference in how the two schools understand [[conventional truth]]. In his [[understanding]], [[Svatantrikas]] accept the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[reality]] of the [[manifest]] [[world]]. In that [[world]] there are things that are real and things that are [[illusory]]. The sophisticated [[epistemological]] system of [[Dharmakirti]] was seen to provide tools to ascertain which are which, and to prove, in a real [[sense]], the [[doctrinal]] position of [[Madhyamaka]]. According to [[Tsongkhapa]], this entails a {{Wiki|subtle}} [[realism]] that falls short of the [[definitive meaning]] of [[Nagarjuna's]] texts, which is that everything is [[empty]] of [[intrinsic nature]]. Only [[Candrakirti's]] [[interpretation]] of [[Madhyamaka]] is considered to go far enough and relegate everything in this [[world]] to the {{Wiki|status}} of merely conventional.34 Though this [[understanding]] is accepted by only one of the four major sects of [[Tibetan Buddhism]], it has had an inestimable impact on the {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} on [[Madhyamaka]].
  
  
Despite his proclaimed exclusive adherence to Candrakirti's understanding of Madhyamaka, Tsongkhapa in fact relies heavily on the logico-epistemological developments of Dharmakirti in his method of Madhyamaka argumentation and his understanding of ultimate truth. Tsongkhapa asserts that the object of Madhyamaka negation is inherent existence, but once that has been refuted, the basis of that negation, the phenomenon under analysis, can be said to exist conventionally. This move has the advantage of allowing a basis for the efficacy of logical argumentation, ethics, and religious practice. Tsongkhapa asserts that the ultimate truth, which is the emptiness of inherent existence, is itself an existent object of knowledge. This makes it possible for discursive thought to realize the ultimate truth—a claim that is unique to Tsongkhapa and the Geluk sect.
+
Despite his proclaimed exclusive adherence to [[Candrakirti's]] [[understanding]] of [[Madhyamaka]], [[Tsongkhapa]] in fact relies heavily on the {{Wiki|logico-epistemological}} developments of [[Dharmakirti]] in his method of [[Madhyamaka]] {{Wiki|argumentation}} and his [[understanding]] of [[ultimate truth]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] asserts that the [[object]] of [[Madhyamaka]] {{Wiki|negation}} is [[inherent existence]], but once that has been refuted, the basis of that {{Wiki|negation}}, the [[phenomenon]] under analysis, can be said to [[exist]] {{Wiki|conventionally}}. This move has the advantage of allowing a basis for the efficacy of [[logical]] {{Wiki|argumentation}}, [[ethics]], and [[religious practice]]. [[Tsongkhapa]] asserts that [[the ultimate truth]], which is the [[emptiness]] of [[inherent existence]], is itself an [[existent]] [[object of knowledge]]. This makes it possible for [[discursive thought]] to realize the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] truth—a claim that is unique to [[Tsongkhapa]] and the [[Geluk sect]].
The other three major sects of Tibetan Buddhism saw Tsongkhapa's understanding of Madhyamaka as straying from the original intent of Nagarjuna and his Indian commentators. For the Nyingma, Sakya, and Kagyu sects generally, the final purport of Madhyamaka is freedom from the extreme views of being and nonbeing. Ultimate truth is not regarded as an object of discursive knowledge, but rather the realization that things cannot be said to exist, not exist, both, or neither. Ontologically speaking, ultimate reality qua emptiness is reality free of hypostatization. The 19th-century Nyingma scholar Jamgon Mipham critiqued Tsongkhapa's position in his Beacon of Certainty and many other of his works.35 Mipham also wrote an extensive commentary on Santaraksita's Madhyamakalamkara?6 Though several prominent Sakya scholars wrote extensive refutations, Gorampa Sonam Senge's Distinguishing the Views is probably the most powerful critique of Tsongkhapa's Madhyamaka and elucidation of the Sakya Madhyamaka.37 Among Kagyu scholars, The Eighth and Ninth Karmapas composed commentaries on Candrakirti's Madhyamakavatara in which Tsongkhapa's views are frequently criticized.38
+
The other three major sects of [[Tibetan Buddhism]] saw [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[understanding]] of [[Madhyamaka]] as straying from the original intent of [[Nagarjuna]] and his [[Indian]] commentators. For the [[Nyingma]], [[Sakya]], and [[Kagyu]] sects generally, the final purport of [[Madhyamaka]] is freedom from the extreme [[views]] of being and nonbeing. [[Ultimate truth]] is not regarded as an [[object]] of discursive [[knowledge]], but rather the [[realization]] that things cannot be said to [[exist]], not [[exist]], both, or neither. [[Ontologically]] {{Wiki|speaking}}, [[ultimate reality]] qua [[emptiness]] is [[reality]] free of {{Wiki|hypostatization}}. The 19th-century [[Nyingma]] [[scholar]] [[Jamgon Mipham]] critiqued [[Tsongkhapa's]] position in his [[Beacon of Certainty]] and many other of his works.35 [[Mipham]] also wrote an extensive commentary on [[Santaraksita's]] Madhyamakalamkara?6 Though several prominent [[Sakya]] [[scholars]] wrote extensive refutations, [[Gorampa Sonam Senge's]] [[Distinguishing the Views]] is probably the most powerful critique of [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[Madhyamaka]] and elucidation of the [[Sakya]] Madhyamaka.37 Among [[Kagyu]] [[scholars]], The Eighth and Ninth [[Karmapas]] composed commentaries on [[Candrakirti's]] [[Madhyamakavatara]] in which [[Tsongkhapa's]] [[views]] are frequently criticized.38
  
  
Tibetan Buddhism is Vajrayana Buddhism, so tantric theory has always played an important role in Tibetan doctrinal formulations. Yogacara provides a more suitable foundation for tantric theory and practice, but Madhyamaka has nearly always been regarded as compatible with, or has served as the true doctrinal foundation of, Vajrayana. The Nyingma and Kagyu sects have typically been more inclined to an understanding of Yogacara and Madhyamaka as complementary teachings, and one in which both were seen through the lens of Vajrayana thought and practice.39 The Sakya and the Geluk sects have tended to privilege Candrakirti's understanding as definitive (though they disagree on what that understanding is) and have kept Madhyamika doctrine and Vajrayana more distinct.
+
[[Tibetan Buddhism]] is [[Vajrayana Buddhism]], so [[tantric]] {{Wiki|theory}} has always played an important role in [[Tibetan]] [[doctrinal]] formulations. [[Yogacara]] provides a more suitable foundation for [[tantric]] {{Wiki|theory}} and practice, but [[Madhyamaka]] has nearly always been regarded as compatible with, or has served as the true [[doctrinal]] foundation of, [[Vajrayana]]. The [[Nyingma]] and [[Kagyu]] sects have typically been more inclined to an [[understanding]] of [[Yogacara]] and [[Madhyamaka]] as complementary teachings, and one in which both were seen through the lens of [[Vajrayana]] [[thought]] and practice.39 The [[Sakya]] and the [[Geluk]] sects have tended to privilege [[Candrakirti's]] [[understanding]] as definitive (though they disagree on what that [[understanding]] is) and have kept [[Madhyamika]] [[doctrine]] and [[Vajrayana]] more {{Wiki|distinct}}.
  
  
One formulation of Tibetan Madhyamaka explicitly based itself on tantric thinking. The “Great Madhyamaka” tradition understands Madhyamaka to include not only Nagarjuna but also the great Yogacara figures Asanga and Vasubandhu as the exemplary Madhyamikas. Here Nagarjuna's works from the analytic corpus serve to eliminate the hypostatizing that leads to a belief in the ultimate reality of things in the world, but his hymns express the final meaning of Madhyamaka, which is the perfected state purified of ignorance, identified with mind. Great Madhyamaka thought is characterized by its emphasis on
+
One formulation of [[Tibetan Madhyamaka]] explicitly based itself on [[tantric]] [[thinking]]. The “[[Great Madhyamaka]]” [[tradition]] [[understands]] [[Madhyamaka]] to include not only [[Nagarjuna]] but also the great [[Yogacara]] figures [[Asanga]] and [[Vasubandhu]] as the exemplary [[Madhyamikas]]. Here [[Nagarjuna's]] works from the analytic corpus serve to eliminate the hypostatizing that leads to a [[belief]] in the [[ultimate reality]] of things in the [[world]], but his hymns express the final meaning of [[Madhyamaka]], which is the perfected [[state]] [[purified]] of [[ignorance]], identified with [[mind]]. [[Great Madhyamaka]] [[thought]] is characterized by its {{Wiki|emphasis}} on
“other-emptiness” (gzhan stong), which is the idea that the absolute is empty of conventional appearances but not of its own pure nature. This tradition is associated with Jonang Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen (1292-1361) and Taranatha (1575-1635), as well as the Sakya scholar Shakya Chokden (1428-1507).40 The tradition was highly influential in its time, but it was suppressed by the Fifth Dalai Lama and largely disappeared except for some regions along the Sino-Tibetan border. The 19th-century ecumenical movement (ris med) helped revive the knowledge of this once significant Madhyamaka vision, but it has received relatively little modern scholarly attention.
+
“[[other-emptiness]]” ([[gzhan stong]]), which is the [[idea]] that the [[absolute]] is [[empty]] of [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[appearances]] but not of its [[own]] [[pure]] [[nature]]. This [[tradition]] is associated with [[Jonang]] [[Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen]] (1292-1361) and [[Taranatha]] (1575-1635), as well as the [[Sakya]] [[scholar]] [[Shakya Chokden]] (1428-1507).40 The [[tradition]] was highly influential in its time, but it was suppressed by the [[Fifth Dalai Lama]] and largely disappeared except for some regions along the [[Sino-Tibetan]] border. The 19th-century {{Wiki|ecumenical}} {{Wiki|movement}} ([[ris med]]) helped revive the [[knowledge]] of this once significant [[Madhyamaka]] [[vision]], but it has received relatively little {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholarly]] [[attention]].
  
  
  
===Review of the Literature===
+
===Review of the {{Wiki|Literature}}===
  
  
  
Most of the modern academic interest in Nagarjuna and the Madhyamaka has been philosophical, and over time what has been of philosophical interest has evolved. As extensively discussed in his influential book Comparative Philosophy and the Philosophy of Scholarship,41 Andrew Tuck has pointed out that early works tended to examine similarities between Madhyamaka and one or another European philosopher.
+
Most of the {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|academic}} [[interest]] in [[Nagarjuna]] and the [[Madhyamaka]] has been [[philosophical]], and over time what has been of [[philosophical]] [[interest]] has evolved. As extensively discussed in his influential [[book]] Comparative [[Philosophy]] and the [[Philosophy]] of Scholarship,41 Andrew Tuck has pointed out that early works tended to examine similarities between [[Madhyamaka]] and one or another {{Wiki|European}} [[philosopher]].
  
  
By the end of the 19th century, European interest in Indian religions had emerged as a positive byproduct of empire. Early Orientalists, most famously Sir William Jones, discovered that India had an ancient religious and philosophical heritage equal to, or in some more enthusiastic estimates superior to, those of the West. The objects of this newfound research were primarily the “orthodox” six schools of Hindu philosophy that contemporary Indian authorities presented as the heart and pinnacle of Indian thinking. Advaita Vedanta, again in accord with Indian assumptions of the time, became particularly sought after by Orientalist scholars and became popular among Western literati. Buddhism, on the other hand, was much more slowly acknowledged as a part of this grand intellectual history of India. It was the publication of Eugene Burnouf's Introduction a l’histoire du Buddhisme indien42 (1844) and his annotated translation of the Lotus Sutra (Saddharmapundarlkam) (1852) that brought Indian Buddhism into the spotlight and firmly established the idea that it was a thoroughly nihilist religion. Burnouf's sources included Perfection of Wisdom (Prajnaparamita) texts and Nagarjuna's Mulamadhyamakakarika with Candrakirti's commentary. Burnouf was not alone in his estimation of Buddhism as nihilism, and this understanding held sway in Europe throughout the 19th century.
+
By the end of the 19th century, {{Wiki|European}} [[interest]] in [[Indian religions]] had emerged as a positive byproduct of [[empire]]. Early [[Orientalists]], most famously Sir William Jones, discovered that [[India]] had an [[ancient]] [[religious]] and [[philosophical]] heritage {{Wiki|equal}} to, or in some more {{Wiki|enthusiastic}} estimates {{Wiki|superior}} to, those of the [[West]]. The [[objects]] of this newfound research were primarily the “[[orthodox]]” six schools of {{Wiki|Hindu philosophy}} that contemporary [[Indian]] authorities presented as the [[heart]] and pinnacle of [[Indian]] [[thinking]]. [[Wikipedia:Advaita Vedanta|Advaita Vedanta]], again in accord with [[Indian]] {{Wiki|assumptions}} of the time, became particularly sought after by [[Orientalist]] [[scholars]] and became popular among [[Western]] literati. [[Buddhism]], on the other hand, was much more slowly [[acknowledged]] as a part of this grand [[intellectual]] history of [[India]]. It was the publication of Eugene [[Burnouf's]] Introduction a l’histoire du Buddhisme indien42 (1844) and his annotated translation of the [[Lotus Sutra]] (Saddharmapundarlkam) (1852) that brought [[Indian Buddhism]] into the spotlight and firmly established the [[idea]] that it was a thoroughly [[Wikipedia:Nihilist|nihilist]] [[religion]]. [[Burnouf's]] sources included [[Perfection of Wisdom]] ([[Prajnaparamita]]) texts and [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Mulamadhyamakakarika]] with [[Candrakirti's]] commentary. [[Burnouf]] was not alone in his estimation of [[Buddhism]] as [[nihilism]], and this [[understanding]] held sway in {{Wiki|Europe}} throughout the 19th century.
  
  
In the early 20th century, the Belgian scholar Louis de La Vallee Poussin published what would become the definitive edition of Nagarjuna's Mulamadhyamakakarika, along with Candrakirti's commentary. La Vallee Poussin too saw Madhyamaka as pure nihilism, but he was a champion of Mahayana thought more broadly. It was the Russian scholar Fyodor Ippolitovich Shtcherbatsky who first challenged this view, arguing that Madhyamaka was in fact the Buddhist parallel of Advaita Vedanta and could best be understood via Kant's dichotomous notions of noumena and phenomena. Madhyamaka could thus be read as an ancient precursor of European idealist philosophy. Shtcherbatsky's understanding, fully explicated in his Conception of Buddhist Nirvana (1927),43 became the new standard view about Madhyamaka, and was taken up by the Indian scholar T. R. V. Murti in his influential work The Central Philosophy of Buddhism (1955),44 in which the author pushed further the linkage of Madhyamaka, Vedanta, and Kant.
+
In the early 20th century, the Belgian [[scholar]] Louis de [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|La Vallee Poussin]] published what would become the definitive edition of [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Mulamadhyamakakarika]], along with [[Candrakirti's]] commentary. [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|La Vallee Poussin]] too saw [[Madhyamaka]] as [[pure]] [[nihilism]], but he was a champion of [[Mahayana]] [[thought]] more broadly. It was the {{Wiki|Russian}} [[scholar]] Fyodor Ippolitovich Shtcherbatsky who first challenged this view, arguing that [[Madhyamaka]] was in fact the [[Buddhist]] parallel of [[Wikipedia:Advaita Vedanta|Advaita Vedanta]] and could best be understood via [[Kant's]] {{Wiki|dichotomous}} notions of noumena and [[phenomena]]. [[Madhyamaka]] could thus be read as an [[ancient]] precursor of {{Wiki|European}} {{Wiki|idealist}} [[philosophy]]. Shtcherbatsky's [[understanding]], fully explicated in his [[Conception of Buddhist Nirvana]] (1927),43 became the new standard view about [[Madhyamaka]], and was taken up by the [[Indian scholar]] T. R. V. [[Murti]] in his influential work The Central [[Philosophy of Buddhism]] (1955),44 in which the author pushed further the linkage of [[Madhyamaka]], [[Vedanta]], and {{Wiki|Kant}}.
  
  
Reacting to the influence of the analytic philosophy of G. E. Moore, Bertrand Russell, and the Vienna Circle, a new generation of scholars began to see Nagarjuna as a dialectician, and the interest in his works was focused on the structure of his arguments. Only two years after Murti's book, the American Buddhist scholar Richard Robinson published the article “Some Logical Aspects of Nagarjuna's System,”45 in which he surveyed previous scholarship on Madhyamaka and dismissed it as philosophically unsophisticated. Unlike his predecessors, Robinson was not looking for transcendent truths, or confirmation of consistency with dominant trends in Western philosophy. He argued for taking Nagarjuna's arguments on their own terms, in their own forms, which he elucidated with the aid of logical notation. In the end, Robinson's conclusion was that Nagarjuna failed to successfully refute his opponents because his method of argumentation was logically or formally invalid.
+
Reacting to the influence of the {{Wiki|analytic philosophy}} of G. E. Moore, {{Wiki|Bertrand Russell}}, and the {{Wiki|Vienna}} Circle, a new generation of [[scholars]] began to see [[Nagarjuna]] as a {{Wiki|dialectician}}, and the [[interest]] in his works was focused on the {{Wiki|structure}} of his arguments. Only two years after Murti's [[book]], the [[American]] [[Buddhist scholar]] [[Richard Robinson]] published the article “Some [[Logical]] Aspects of [[Nagarjuna's]] System,”45 in which he surveyed previous {{Wiki|scholarship}} on [[Madhyamaka]] and dismissed it as [[philosophically]] unsophisticated. Unlike his predecessors, [[Robinson]] was not looking for [[transcendent]] [[truths]], or confirmation of consistency with dominant trends in {{Wiki|Western philosophy}}. He argued for taking [[Nagarjuna's]] arguments on their [[own]] terms, in their [[own]] [[forms]], which he elucidated with the aid of [[logical]] notation. In the end, Robinson's conclusion was that [[Nagarjuna]] failed to successfully refute his opponents because his method of {{Wiki|argumentation}} was [[logically]] or formally invalid.
  
  
The next phase of reading and explicating Madhyamaka similarly reflected the contemporaneous concerns of Western philosophy. Influenced by the works of Quine, Sellars, and especially the later Wittgenstein, several scholars began to assert that concepts such as “language game,” “forms of life,” and “ordinary language” provided helpful models for understanding not only what Nagarjuna's arguments meant, but also what they were for. Such scholars46 saw parallels between the way Wittgenstein and Nagarjuna used language, but they also saw commonality with the primarily soteriological intent of Madhyamaka in Wittgenstein's famous statement on the purpose of philosophy, “To show the fly the way out of the fly-bottle.” Further emphasizing this soteriological dimension of Madhyamaka, Frederick Streng published the first full translation of the Mulamadhyamakakarika,47 and though he too quoted from Wittgenstein in his analysis, his primary concern was for understanding Madhyamaka and, especially, the concept of emptiness from a religious rather than a philosophical perspective.
+
The next phase of reading and explicating [[Madhyamaka]] similarly reflected the contemporaneous concerns of {{Wiki|Western philosophy}}. Influenced by the works of Quine, Sellars, and especially the later {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}, several [[scholars]] began to assert that [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] such as “[[language]] game,” “[[forms]] of [[life]],” and “[[ordinary language]]” provided helpful models for [[understanding]] not only what [[Nagarjuna's]] arguments meant, but also what they were for. Such scholars46 saw parallels between the way {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} and [[Nagarjuna]] used [[language]], but they also saw commonality with the primarily [[soteriological]] intent of [[Madhyamaka]] in Wittgenstein's famous statement on the {{Wiki|purpose}} of [[philosophy]], “To show the fly the way out of the fly-bottle.” Further {{Wiki|emphasizing}} this [[soteriological]] [[dimension]] of [[Madhyamaka]], Frederick Streng published the first full translation of the Mulamadhyamakakarika,47 and though he too quoted from {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} in his analysis, his primary [[concern]] was for [[understanding]] [[Madhyamaka]] and, especially, the [[concept of emptiness]] from a [[religious]] rather than a [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|perspective}}.
  
  
In his seminal article “Nagarjuna's Appeal,”48 Richard Hayes nuances Tuck's thesis that interpretations of Madhyamaka are deeply informed by the ideological or methodological interest of the translators/interpreters by arguing that a number of Buddhist scholars have resisted this and produced translations or studies that place Nagarjuna's works solidly in their historical and cultural contexts. Hayes highlights the work of Stanislaw Schayer, David Seyfort Ruegg, Christian Lindtner, and Kamaleswar Bhattacharya as exemplars of the ideal of detached and scientific objectivity in Madhyamaka scholarship.
+
In his seminal article “[[Nagarjuna's]] Appeal,”48 Richard [[Hayes]] nuances Tuck's {{Wiki|thesis}} that interpretations of [[Madhyamaka]] are deeply informed by the {{Wiki|ideological}} or {{Wiki|methodological}} [[interest]] of the translators/interpreters by arguing that a number of [[Buddhist scholars]] have resisted this and produced translations or studies that place [[Nagarjuna's]] works solidly in their historical and {{Wiki|cultural}} contexts. [[Hayes]] highlights the work of Stanislaw Schayer, [[David Seyfort Ruegg]], [[Christian Lindtner]], and [[Kamaleswar Bhattacharya]] as exemplars of the {{Wiki|ideal}} of [[detached]] and [[scientific]] objectivity in [[Madhyamaka]] {{Wiki|scholarship}}.
  
  
In recent decades, scholars have tried to avoid the pitfalls described by Tuck and Hayes and have also argued for a deeper engagement of modern philosophy with Madhyamaka, or with Buddhist thought more broadly. These works make a plea for the inclusion of Buddhist thought, and particularly Madhyamaka, into a more globally construed notion of philosophy and engage in both exegesis and interpretation. Publications of Mark Siderits,49 Jay Garfield,50 Jan Westerhoff,51 Amber Carpenter52 and Tom Tillemans53 are among the most significant examples of this recent phase of the study of Madhyamaka. These works typically situate Madhyamaka within its Buddhist historical context as well as interrogating the texts for their potential value to modes of modern thought.
+
In recent decades, [[scholars]] have tried to avoid the pitfalls described by Tuck and [[Hayes]] and have also argued for a deeper engagement of {{Wiki|modern}} [[philosophy]] with [[Madhyamaka]], or with [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] more broadly. These works make a plea for the inclusion of [[Buddhist]] [[thought]], and particularly [[Madhyamaka]], into a more globally construed notion of [[philosophy]] and engage in both {{Wiki|exegesis}} and [[interpretation]]. Publications of Mark Siderits,49 Jay Garfield,50 Jan Westerhoff,51 {{Wiki|Amber}} Carpenter52 and Tom Tillemans53 are among the most significant examples of this recent phase of the study of [[Madhyamaka]]. These works typically situate [[Madhyamaka]] within its [[Buddhist]] historical context as well as interrogating the texts for their potential value to modes of {{Wiki|modern}} [[thought]].
  
  
In contemporary scholarship, the question of whether Madhyamaka thought is primarily about ultimate reality (the metaphysical interpretation) or what can be said about reality (the semantic interpretation) has become an important issue. In the past few decades the semantic interpretation has tended to predominate, but this approach is not unanimously accepted.
+
In contemporary {{Wiki|scholarship}}, the question of whether [[Madhyamaka]] [[thought]] is primarily about [[ultimate reality]] (the [[metaphysical]] [[interpretation]]) or what can be said about [[reality]] (the [[Wikipedia:Semantics|semantic]] [[interpretation]]) has become an important issue. In the {{Wiki|past}} few decades the [[Wikipedia:Semantics|semantic]] [[interpretation]] has tended to predominate, but this approach is not unanimously accepted.
  
  
A recent locus of controversy in interpreting Madhyamaka has centered on the question of contradiction in Madhyamaka argumentation and the ultimate purport of such arguments. Against some scholars who regard contradictions in the texts as intended to be understood metaphorically, or as expressions of skillful means (upaya), Jay Garfield, along with coauthors Yasuo Deguchi and Graham Priest, argues that at least some contradictions in Madhyamaka texts should be taken literally and be accepted as true (the dialetheist interpretation). This interpretation provoked a number of critical responses, resulting in an entire issue of the journal Philosophy East and West devoted to these critiques, along with responses by Deguchi, Garfield, and Priest.55 Tillemans's article in this issue is an excellent example of another current interpretation that sees Madhyamaka arguments, at least in early Madhyamaka texts, as having as their purpose the complete elimination of all views about reality (the quietist interpretation). Other recent studies have been published that question Tibetan Madhyamikas' doxographical categories, which have been accepted and employed by much of modern scholarship.56 A renewed interest in the question of Madhyamaka's relation to the other major Mahayana doctrinal system, Yogacara, has also recently come to the fore.57
+
A recent locus of [[controversy]] in interpreting [[Madhyamaka]] has centered on the question of {{Wiki|contradiction}} in [[Madhyamaka]] {{Wiki|argumentation}} and the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] purport of such arguments. Against some [[scholars]] who regard contradictions in the texts as intended to be understood {{Wiki|metaphorically}}, or as {{Wiki|expressions}} of [[skillful means]] ([[upaya]]), {{Wiki|Jay Garfield}}, along with coauthors Yasuo Deguchi and [[Graham Priest]], argues that at least some contradictions in [[Madhyamaka]] texts should be taken literally and be accepted as true (the dialetheist [[interpretation]]). This [[interpretation]] provoked a number of critical responses, resulting in an entire issue of the journal [[Philosophy East and West]] devoted to these critiques, along with responses by Deguchi, Garfield, and Priest.55 Tillemans's article in this issue is an {{Wiki|excellent}} example of another current [[interpretation]] that sees [[Madhyamaka]] arguments, at least in early [[Madhyamaka]] texts, as having as their {{Wiki|purpose}} the complete elimination of all [[views]] about [[reality]] (the quietist [[interpretation]]). Other recent studies have been published that question [[Tibetan]] [[Madhyamikas]]' [[Wikipedia:Doxography|doxographical]] categories, which have been accepted and employed by much of {{Wiki|modern}} scholarship.56 A renewed [[interest]] in the question of [[Madhyamaka's]] [[relation]] to the other major [[Mahayana]] [[doctrinal]] system, [[Yogacara]], has also recently come to the fore.57
  
  
Line 205: Line 205:
  
  
All Buddhist traditions and modern scholarship agree that the founding author of Madhyamaka is Nagarjuna. From among his many works, it is similarly unanimous that his magnum opus is The Root Verses of the Middle Way (Mulamadhyamakakarika). The Sanskrit text was translated into other Asian languages, most importantly Chinese and Tibetan. Modern translations from each of these languages have been made into English and other European languages. At the current stage of Madhyamaka scholarship, the definitive English translation is the one by Mark Siderits and ShoryU Katsura.58 This translation is based on the Sanskrit original and the Tibetan translation, and utilizes all four extant Indian  
+
All [[Buddhist traditions]] and {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} agree that the founding author of [[Madhyamaka]] is [[Nagarjuna]]. From among his many works, it is similarly unanimous that his [[Wikipedia:Masterpiece|magnum opus]] is The [[Root Verses of the Middle Way]] ([[Mulamadhyamakakarika]]). The [[Sanskrit]] text was translated into other {{Wiki|Asian}} [[languages]], most importantly {{Wiki|Chinese}} and [[Tibetan]]. {{Wiki|Modern}} translations from each of these [[languages]] have been made into English and other {{Wiki|European}} [[languages]]. At the current stage of [[Madhyamaka]] {{Wiki|scholarship}}, the definitive English translation is the one by [[Mark Siderits]] and ShoryU Katsura.58 This translation is based on the [[Sanskrit]] original and the [[Tibetan translation]], and utilizes all four extant [[Indian]]
  
commentaries in its insightful yet accessible commentary. The French translation from the Sanskrit by Guy Bugault59 is highly recommended, as is the pioneering translation from Sanskrit into Italian by Raniero Gnoli60 and the German translation from the Chinese by Lutz Geldsetzer.61
+
commentaries in its [[insightful]] yet accessible commentary. The {{Wiki|French}} translation from the [[Sanskrit]] by Guy Bugault59 is highly recommended, as is the pioneering translation from [[Sanskrit]] into {{Wiki|Italian}} by Raniero Gnoli60 and the [[German]] translation from the {{Wiki|Chinese}} by Lutz Geldsetzer.61
Nagarjuna's other works have often been traditionally divided into those with a methodological affinity to The Root Verses of the Middle Way (the analytic corpus), and his hymns and the collection of practical religious advice. Among the former, the most comprehensive and still classic collection by Lindtner62 is an excellent starting point for those wanting to explore these works. Though the hymns evince a very different picture of Madhyamaka, and they have received relatively little attention in modern scholarship, Tibetan traditions and many modern scholars accept them as authentic works of Nagarjuna. Lindtner's aforementioned collection includes two of the hymns, and Fernando Tola and Carmen Dragonetti's article63 contains translations and an exhaustive discussion of these works. Among the advice texts, the Ratnavali is widely regarded as an authentic composition of Nagarjuna and contains important similarities and complements to the Root Verses, though it is largely a text on ethics. The translation by Jeffrey Hopkins64 contains a commentary by Hopkins and an edition of the Tibetan text.
+
[[Nagarjuna's]] other works have often been [[traditionally]] divided into those with a {{Wiki|methodological}} [[affinity]] to The [[Root Verses of the Middle Way]] (the analytic corpus), and his hymns and the collection of {{Wiki|practical}} [[religious]] advice. Among the former, the most comprehensive and still classic collection by Lindtner62 is an {{Wiki|excellent}} starting point for those wanting to explore these works. Though the hymns evince a very different picture of [[Madhyamaka]], and they have received relatively little [[attention]] in {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}}, [[Tibetan traditions]] and many {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]] accept them as [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] works of [[Nagarjuna]]. Lindtner's aforementioned collection includes two of the hymns, and [[Fernando Tola]] and Carmen Dragonetti's article63 contains translations and an exhaustive [[discussion]] of these works. Among the advice texts, the [[Ratnavali]] is widely regarded as an [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] composition of [[Nagarjuna]] and contains important similarities and complements to the [[Root Verses]], though it is largely a text on [[ethics]]. The translation by Jeffrey Hopkins64 contains a commentary by Hopkins and an edition of the [[Tibetan text]].
  
  
The difficulty of the subject matter and the terse style of the karika form of Indian literature led to numerous commentaries on Nagarjuna's texts, especially the Root Verses of the Middle Way. The Tibetan traditions and most modern scholarship typically accept that there are four Indian commentaries on the text: the Akutobhaya attributed to Nagarjuna himself, the Mulamadhyamakavrtti by Buddhapalita, the Prajnapradlpa of Bhaviveka, and the Prasannapada of Candrakirti. The two most important of these, and the ones that have received the greatest amount of scholarly attention, are the Prajnapradlpa and the Prasannapada. Their authors, Bhaviveka and Candrakirti, came to be seen by the Tibetan traditions as embodying two distinct schools of interpretation: the Svatantrika and Prasangika, with the latter occupying the peak of the doxographical hierarchy for nearly all of the Tibetan scholastic schools. The first seven chapters of the Prajnapradipa have been translated into English in a series of articles by William Ames,65 and a complete translation of the Prasannapada into European languages has come together through the complementary efforts of a number of excellent scholars.66
+
The difficulty of the [[subject]] {{Wiki|matter}} and the terse style of the [[karika]] [[form]] of [[Indian literature]] led to numerous commentaries on [[Nagarjuna's]] texts, especially the [[Root Verses of the Middle Way]]. The [[Tibetan traditions]] and most {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} typically accept that there are four [[Indian]] commentaries on the text: the [[Akutobhaya]] attributed to [[Nagarjuna]] himself, the Mulamadhyamakavrtti by [[Buddhapalita]], the Prajnapradlpa of [[Bhaviveka]], and the [[Prasannapada]] of [[Candrakirti]]. The two most important of these, and the ones that have received the greatest amount of [[scholarly]] [[attention]], are the Prajnapradlpa and the [[Prasannapada]]. Their authors, [[Bhaviveka]] and [[Candrakirti]], came to be seen by the [[Tibetan traditions]] as [[embodying]] two {{Wiki|distinct}} schools of [[interpretation]]: the [[Svatantrika]] and [[Prasangika]], with the [[latter]] occupying the peak of the [[Wikipedia:Doxography|doxographical]] {{Wiki|hierarchy}} for nearly all of the [[Tibetan]] {{Wiki|scholastic}} schools. The first seven chapters of the Prajnapradipa have been translated into English in a series of articles by William Ames,65 and a complete translation of the [[Prasannapada]] into {{Wiki|European}} [[languages]] has come together through the complementary efforts of a number of {{Wiki|excellent}} scholars.66
  
  
The Madhyamika works of Jnanagarbha, Santaraksita, and Kamalasila have received less attention in modern scholarship. Jnanagarbha's Distinction Between the Two Truths has been translated by Malcolm David Eckel (Satyadvayavibhahga') and is accompanied by a useful introduction.67 Masamichi Ichigo has published a helpful overview and full translation of Santaraksita's Ornament of the Middle Way.68 Though there are no complete translations of Kamalasila's Madhyamika works, portions are translated and discussed by Ichigo,69 Ryusei Keira,70 and Sara McClintock.71
+
The [[Madhyamika]] works of [[Jnanagarbha]], [[Santaraksita]], and [[Kamalasila]] have received less [[attention]] in {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}}. [[Jnanagarbha's]] Distinction Between the [[Two Truths]] has been translated by [[Malcolm David Eckel]] (Satyadvayavibhahga') and is accompanied by a useful introduction.67 Masamichi Ichigo has published a helpful overview and full translation of [[Santaraksita's]] Ornament of the Middle Way.68 Though there are no complete translations of [[Kamalasila's]] [[Madhyamika]] works, portions are translated and discussed by Ichigo,69 Ryusei Keira,70 and Sara McClintock.71
  
  
Line 220: Line 220:
  
  
Bocking, Brian, trans. Nagarjuna in China: A Translation of the Middle Treatise. Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 1995.
+
Bocking, Brian, trans. [[Nagarjuna]] in [[China]]: A Translation of the [[Middle Treatise]]. Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 1995.
 
K Find this resource:
 
K Find this resource:
Brunnholzl, Karl. The Center of the Sunlit Sky: Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition. Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2004.
+
Brunnholzl, Karl. The [[Center]] of the Sunlit Sky: [[Madhyamaka]] in the [[Kagyu Tradition]]. [[Ithaca]], NY: [[Snow Lion]], 2004.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Cabezon, Jose Ignacio, and Geshe Lobsang Dargyay. Freedom from Extremes: Gorampa’s “Distinguishing the Views” and the Polemics of Emptiness. Boston: Wisdom, 2007.  
+
[[Cabezon]], Jose Ignacio, and [[Geshe Lobsang]] [[Dargyay]]. Freedom from Extremes: [[Gorampa’s]] “[[Distinguishing the Views]]” and the {{Wiki|Polemics}} of [[Emptiness]]. Boston: Wisdom, 2007.  
Chandrakirti and Ju Mipham. Introduction to the Middle Way: Chandrakirti’s Madhyamakavatara with Commentary by Ju Mipham. Translated by Padmakara Translation Group. Boston and London: Shambhala, 2004.
+
[[Chandrakirti]] and [[Ju Mipham]]. [[Introduction to the Middle Way]]: [[Chandrakirti’s]] [[Madhyamakavatara]] with Commentary by [[Ju Mipham]]. Translated by [[Padmakara Translation Group]]. [[Boston]] and [[London]]: [[Shambhala]], 2004.
  
  
Line 231: Line 231:
  
  
Eckel, Malcolm David. Jnanagarbha’s Commentary on the Distinction Between the Two Truths. SUNY Series in Buddhist Studies. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1987.
+
[[Eckel]], Malcolm David. [[Jnanagarbha’s]] Commentary on the Distinction Between the [[Two Truths]]. SUNY Series in [[Buddhist Studies]]. [[Albany]]: [[State University of New York Press]], 1987.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Garfield, Jay L., and Jan Westerhoff. Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies or Rivals? Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2015.
+
Garfield, Jay L., and [[Jan Westerhoff]]. [[Madhyamaka]] and [[Yogacara]]: Allies or Rivals? [[Oxford]] and [[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 2015.
 
|(+) Find this resource:
 
|(+) Find this resource:
Hamilton, Sue. Indian Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
+
Hamilton, Sue. [[Indian Philosophy]]: A Very Short Introduction. [[Oxford]] and [[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 2001.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Hayes, Richard P. “Nagarjuna's Appeal.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (1994): 299-378.
+
[[Hayes]], Richard P. “[[Nagarjuna's]] Appeal.” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 22 (1994): 299-378.
  
  
Ichigo, Masamichi. “Santaraksita's Madhyamakalamkara: Introduction, Edition and Translation.” In Studies in the Literature of the Great Vehicle: Three Mahayana Buddhist Texts. Edited by Luis Gomez and Jonathan Silk, 141-240. Ann Arbor: Collegiate Institute for the Study of Buddhist Literature and Center for South and Southeast Asian Studies, University of Michigan, 1989. |(+) Find this resource:
+
Ichigo, Masamichi. “[[Santaraksita's]] [[Madhyamakalamkara]]: Introduction, Edition and Translation.” In Studies in the {{Wiki|Literature}} of the [[Great Vehicle]]: Three [[Mahayana Buddhist Texts]]. Edited by Luis Gomez and [[Jonathan Silk]], 141-240. [[Ann Arbor]]: Collegiate Institute for the Study of [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Literature}} and [[Center]] for [[South]] and {{Wiki|Southeast Asian}} Studies, [[University of Michigan]], 1989. |(+) Find this resource:
Komarovski, Yaroslav. Visions of Unity: The Golden Pandita Shakya Chokden’s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2012.
+
[[Komarovski, Yaroslav]]. [[Visions]] of Unity: The Golden [[Pandita]] [[Shakya Chokden’s]] New Interpretation of [[Yogacara]] and [[Madhyamaka]]. [[Albany]]: [[State University of New York Press]], 2012.
 
[ I Find this resource:
 
[ I Find this resource:
 
Google Preview WorldCat
 
Google Preview WorldCat
Lang, Karen C. Aryadeva’s Catuhsataka: On the Bodhisattva’s Cultivation of Method and Knowledge. Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag, 1986.
+
Lang, Karen C. [[Aryadeva’s]] [[Catuhsataka]]: On the [[Bodhisattva’s]] [[Cultivation]] of Method and [[Knowledge]]. [[Copenhagen]]: Akademisk Forlag, 1986.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Lindtner, Christian. Nagarjuniana: Studies in the Writings and Philosophy of Nagarjuna. New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987. |(+) Find this resource:
+
[[Lindtner]], [[Christian]]. [[Nagarjuniana]]: Studies in the Writings and [[Philosophy]] of [[Nagarjuna]]. {{Wiki|New Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1987. |(+) Find this resource:
Liu, Ming-Wood. Madhyamaka Thought in China. Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill, 1994.
+
[[Liu]], Ming-Wood. [[Madhyamaka]] [[Thought]] in [[China]]. [[Leiden]], The {{Wiki|Netherlands}}: Brill, 1994.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Lopez, Donald S.The Madman’s Middle Way: Reflections of Reality of the Tibetan Monk Gendun Chopel (Buddhism and Modernity). Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007.
+
[[Lopez]], Donald S.The Madman’s [[Middle Way]]: Reflections of [[Reality]] of the [[Tibetan]] [[Monk]] [[Gendun Chopel]] ([[Buddhism]] and Modernity). {{Wiki|Chicago}}: [[University of Chicago Press]], 2007.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
MacDonald, Anne. In Clear Words: The Prasannapada, Chapter One, Vols. I & II. Vienna: Verlag der Osterreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 2015.
+
MacDonald, Anne. In Clear Words: The [[Prasannapada]], [[Chapter]] One, Vols. I & II. {{Wiki|Vienna}}: Verlag der Osterreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 2015.
McClintock, Sarah, and Georges Dreyfus. The Svatantrika-Prasangika Distintion: What Difference Does a Difference Make? Boston: Wisdom, 2002.
+
[[McClintock]], Sarah, and {{Wiki|Georges Dreyfus}}. The [[Svatantrika-Prasangika]] Distintion: What Difference Does a Difference Make? Boston: Wisdom, 2002.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Nagao, Gadjin M.Madhyamika and Yogdcara: A Study of Mahayana Philosophies. Translated by Leslie Kawamura. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1991.
+
[[Nagao]], Gadjin M.Madhyamika and Yogdcara: A Study of [[Mahayana]] [[Philosophies]]. Translated by [[Leslie Kawamura]]. [[Albany]]: [[State University of New York Press]], 1991.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Phuntsho, Karma. Mipham’s Dialectices and the Debates on Emptiness: To be, not to be, or neither. London and New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2005.
+
Phuntsho, [[Karma]]. [[Mipham’s]] Dialectices and the [[Debates]] on [[Emptiness]]: To be, not to be, or neither. [[London]] and [[New York]]: RoutledgeCurzon, 2005.
 
|(+) Find this resource:
 
|(+) Find this resource:
Seyfort Ruegg, David. “The Uses of the Four Positions of the Catuhskoti and the Problem of the Description of Reality in Mahayana Buddhism.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 5 (1977): 1-71.
+
[[Seyfort Ruegg]], David. “The Uses of the Four Positions of the Catuhskoti and the Problem of the Description of [[Reality]] in [[Mahayana Buddhism]].” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 5 (1977): 1-71.
 
K Find this resource:
 
K Find this resource:
Seyfort Ruegg, David. The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India. A History of Indian Literature 7. Wiesbaden, Germany: Otto Harrassowitz, 1981.
+
[[Seyfort Ruegg]], David. The {{Wiki|Literature}} of the [[Madhyamaka School]] of [[Philosophy]] in [[India]]. A History of [[Indian]] {{Wiki|Literature}} 7. [[Wiesbaden]], {{Wiki|Germany}}: Otto Harrassowitz, 1981.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Siderits, Mark, and Shoryu Katsura. Nagarjuna’s Middle Way: The Mulamadhyamakakarika. Boston: Wisdom, 2013.
+
[[Siderits, Mark]], and Shoryu [[Katsura]]. [[Nagarjuna’s]] [[Middle Way]]: The [[Mulamadhyamakakarika]]. Boston: Wisdom, 2013.
 
|(+) Find this resource:
 
|(+) Find this resource:
Thupten Jinpa. Self, Reason, and Reality in Tibetan Philosophy: Tsongkhapa’s Quest for the Middle Way. Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2008.
+
[[Thupten Jinpa]]. [[Self]], [[Reason]], and [[Reality]] in [[Tibetan Philosophy]]: [[Tsongkhapa’s]] Quest for the [[Middle Way]]. [[Ithaca]], NY: [[Snow Lion]], 2008.
 
K Find this resource:
 
K Find this resource:
Tillemans, Tom J. F.How Do Madhyamika’s Think: and Other Essays on the Buddhist Philosophy of the Middle. Boston: Wisdom, 2016.
+
[[Tillemans]], Tom J. F.How Do Madhyamika’s Think: and Other Essays on the [[Buddhist Philosophy]] of the Middle. Boston: Wisdom, 2016.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Tola, Fernando, and Carmen Dragonetti. “Nagarjuna's Catuhstava.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (1985): 1-54.
+
Tola, Fernando, and [[Carmen Dragonetti]]. “[[Nagarjuna's]] Catuhstava.” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 13 (1985): 1-54.
 
|(+) Find this resource:
 
|(+) Find this resource:
Vose, Kevin. Resurrecting Candrakirti: Disputes in the Tibetan Creation of Prasangika. Boston: Wisdom, 2009.
+
Vose, Kevin. Resurrecting [[Candrakirti]]: [[Disputes]] in the [[Tibetan]] Creation of [[Prasangika]]. Boston: Wisdom, 2009.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
Westerhoff, Jan. Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction. Oxford and London: Oxford University Press, 2009.
+
[[Wikipedia:Jan Westerhoff|Westerhoff]], Jan. [[Nagarjuna’s]] [[Madhyamaka]]: A [[Philosophical]] Introduction. [[Oxford]] and [[London]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 2009.
 
Find this resource:
 
Find this resource:
  
Line 280: Line 280:
  
  
(1.) The Sanskrit term madhyamaka literally means just “middle,” but throughout English scholarship this has been translated as “middle way.” For the sake of consistency and clarity, “middle way” will be used throughout.
+
(1.) The [[Sanskrit]] term [[madhyamaka]] literally means just “middle,” but throughout English {{Wiki|scholarship}} this has been translated as “[[middle way]].” For the [[sake]] of consistency and clarity, “[[middle way]]” will be used throughout.
(2.) Though many of the concepts discussed here are found in both Pali and Sanskrit sources, we will use the Sanskrit terms  
+
(2.) Though many of the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] discussed here are found in both [[Pali]] and [[Sanskrit]] sources, we will use the [[Sanskrit]] terms  
throughout, as Nagarjuna composed his texts in Sanskrit, and the Indian commentaries are in Sanskrit as well.
+
throughout, as [[Nagarjuna]] composed his texts in [[Sanskrit]], and the [[Indian]] commentaries are in [[Sanskrit]] as well.
(3.) Samyutta Nikaya, II.15 (5), in The Connected Discourses of the Buddha: A New Translation of the Samyutta Nikaya, trans. Bhikku Bodhi (Boston: Wisdom, 2000), 544.
+
(3.) [[Samyutta Nikaya]], II.15 (5), in The [[Connected Discourses]] of the [[Buddha]]: A [[New Translation]] of the [[Samyutta Nikaya]], trans. [[Bhikku]] [[Bodhi]] (Boston: Wisdom, 2000), 544.
 
(4.) Ibid.
 
(4.) Ibid.
  
(5.) The notion of Buddhist doctrinal schools has been a commonplace in Buddhist scholarship both traditional and modern, but this idea should be handled cautiously. The term “Madhyamaka School” really only refers to a lineage of writers (often separated by centuries) who wrote commentaries on one or another of Nagarjuna's works, and that much later were placed into a doxographical category, primarily by the Tibetan traditions. See, for example, Ian Charles Harris, The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogacara in Indian Mahayana Buddhism (Leiden and New York: Brill, 1991); and Richard King, “Early Yogacara and Its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School,” Philosophy East and West 40 (1994): 659-683.
+
(5.) The notion of [[Buddhist]] [[doctrinal]] schools has been a commonplace in [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|scholarship}} both [[traditional]] and {{Wiki|modern}}, but this [[idea]] should be handled cautiously. The term “[[Madhyamaka School]]” really only refers to a [[lineage]] of writers (often separated by centuries) who wrote commentaries on one or another of [[Nagarjuna's]] works, and that much later were placed into a [[Wikipedia:Doxography|doxographical]] category, primarily by the [[Tibetan traditions]]. See, for example, Ian [[Charles Harris]], The Continuity of [[Madhyamaka]] and [[Yogacara]] in [[Indian Mahayana Buddhism]] ([[Leiden]] and [[New York]]: Brill, 1991); and Richard [[King]], “Early [[Yogacara]] and Its Relationship with the [[Madhyamaka School]],” [[Philosophy East and West]] 40 (1994): 659-683.
(6.) For a helpful overview of Madhyamaka in China, see Dan Arnold, “Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy: Madhyamaka in East Asia,” in Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, eds. James Fieser and Bradley Dowden (2005).
+
(6.) For a helpful overview of [[Madhyamaka]] in [[China]], see Dan Arnold, “[[Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy]]: [[Madhyamaka]] in {{Wiki|East Asia}},” in [[Internet]] {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Philosophy]], eds. James Fieser and {{Wiki|Bradley}} Dowden (2005).
  
(7.) For a discussion of this categorization, see David Seyfort Ruegg, The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India (A History of Indian Literature 7; Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz, 1981), 7-9.
+
(7.) For a [[discussion]] of this categorization, see [[David Seyfort Ruegg]], The {{Wiki|Literature}} of the [[Madhyamaka School]] of [[Philosophy]] in [[India]] (A History of [[Indian]] {{Wiki|Literature}} 7; [[Wiesbaden]]: Otto Harrassowitz, 1981), 7-9.
(8.) The inclusion of the Vyavaharasiddhi was favored by most Tibetan scholars, but Tsongkhapa and his followers preferred the Ratnavali as the sixth text of this category. See Karma Phuntsho, Mipham's Dialectics and the Debates on Emptiness: To Be, Not to Be, or Neither (London and New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2005), 235.
+
(8.) The inclusion of the [[Vyavaharasiddhi]] was favored by most [[Tibetan scholars]], but [[Tsongkhapa]] and his followers preferred the [[Ratnavali]] as the sixth text of this category. See [[Karma Phuntsho]], [[Mipham's]] [[Dialectics]] and the [[Debates]] on [[Emptiness]]: To Be, Not to Be, or Neither ([[London]] and [[New York]]: RoutledgeCurzon, 2005), 235.
(9.) For a discussion of the full implications of these verses, see Eviatar Shulman, “Creative Ignorance: Nagarjuna on the Ontological Significance of Consciousness,” Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 30. 1-2 (2009): 139¬173.
+
(9.) For a [[discussion]] of the full implications of these verses, see Eviatar Shulman, “Creative [[Ignorance]]: [[Nagarjuna]] on the [[Ontological]] Significance of [[Consciousness]],” Journal of the [[International Association of Buddhist Studies]] 30. 1-2 (2009): 139¬173.
(10.) A significant exception to this is Shulman, “Creative Ignorance.”
+
(10.) A significant exception to this is Shulman, “Creative [[Ignorance]].”
(11.) Christian Lindtner, Nagarjuniana: Studies in the Writings and Philosophy of Nagarjuna (New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987), 31.
+
(11.) [[Christian Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]]: Studies in the Writings and [[Philosophy]] of [[Nagarjuna]] ({{Wiki|New Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1987), 31.
(12.) Aryadeva, Bhaviveka, Candrakirti, Prajnakaramati and other Indian commentators cite one or more of these hymns and attribute them to Nagarjuna. For an overview of this issue, see Fernando Tola and Carmen Dragonetti, “Nagarjuna's Catuhstava,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (1985): 1-6.
+
(12.) [[Aryadeva]], [[Bhaviveka]], [[Candrakirti]], [[Prajnakaramati]] and other [[Indian]] commentators cite one or more of these hymns and attribute them to [[Nagarjuna]]. For an overview of this issue, see [[Fernando Tola]] and [[Carmen Dragonetti]], “[[Nagarjuna's]] Catuhstava,” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 13 (1985): 1-6.
  
(13.) The hymns are not found in the Chinese Buddhist canon.
+
(13.) [[The hymns]] are not found in the [[Chinese Buddhist canon]].
(14.) Samyutta Nikaya, II.15 (5), in The Connected Discourses of the Buddha: A New Translation of the Samyutta Nikaya, trans. Bhikku Bodhi (Boston: Wisdom, 2000), 544.
+
(14.) [[Samyutta Nikaya]], II.15 (5), in The [[Connected Discourses]] of the [[Buddha]]: A [[New Translation]] of the [[Samyutta Nikaya]], trans. [[Bhikku]] [[Bodhi]] (Boston: Wisdom, 2000), 544.
(15.) Mark Siderits and Shoryu Katsura, Nagarjuna’s Middle Way: Mulamadhyamakakarika (Boston: Wisdom, 2013), 159.
+
(15.) [[Mark Siderits]] and Shoryu [[Katsura]], [[Nagarjuna’s]] [[Middle Way]]: [[Mulamadhyamakakarika]] (Boston: Wisdom, 2013), 159.
 
(16.) Ibid., 18.
 
(16.) Ibid., 18.
 
(17.) Ibid., 28.
 
(17.) Ibid., 28.
 
(18.) Ibid., 276-277.
 
(18.) Ibid., 276-277.
(19.) For a collection of essays on the status of conventional truth, see Cowherds, Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011).
+
(19.) For a collection of {{Wiki|essays}} on the {{Wiki|status}} of [[conventional truth]], see Cowherds, Moonshadows: [[Conventional Truth]] in [[Buddhist Philosophy]] ([[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 2011).
(20.) Siderits and Katsura, Nagarjuna's Middle Way, 277.
+
(20.) [[Siderits]] and [[Katsura]], [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Middle Way]], 277.
(21.) Mark Siderits, Buddhism as Philosophy: An Introduction (Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett, 2007), 182.
+
(21.) [[Mark Siderits]], [[Buddhism]] as [[Philosophy]]: An Introduction ({{Wiki|Indianapolis}} and [[Cambridge]]: Hackett, 2007), 182.
(22.) Siderits and Katsura, Nagarjuna's Middle Way, 13.
+
(22.) [[Siderits]] and [[Katsura]], [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Middle Way]], 13.
 
(23.) Ibid., 197.
 
(23.) Ibid., 197.
(24.) Lindtner, Nagarjuniana, 63-64.
+
(24.) [[Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]], 63-64.
(25.) Current scholarly consensus is that “Bhaviveka” is the proper spelling of this name, but earlier scholarship frequently used “Bhavaviveka,” or sometimes “Bhavya.”
+
(25.) Current [[scholarly]] consensus is that “[[Bhaviveka]]” is the proper spelling of this [[name]], but earlier {{Wiki|scholarship}} frequently used “[[Bhavaviveka]],” or sometimes “[[Bhavya]].”
(26.) Siderits and Katsura, Nagarjuna's Middle Way, 304.
+
(26.) [[Siderits]] and [[Katsura]], [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Middle Way]], 304.
 
(27.) Ibid., 315-316.
 
(27.) Ibid., 315-316.
 
(28.) Ibid., 334.
 
(28.) Ibid., 334.
(29.) Karen C. Lang, Aryadeva’s Catuhsataka: On the Bodhisattva’s Cultivation of Method and Knowledge (Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag, 1986).
+
(29.) Karen C. Lang, [[Aryadeva’s]] [[Catuhsataka]]: On the [[Bodhisattva’s]] [[Cultivation]] of Method and [[Knowledge]] ([[Copenhagen]]: Akademisk Forlag, 1986).
(30.) For a wide-ranging examination of the differences between these two schools, see Georges B. J. Dreyfus and Sara L. McClintock, eds., The Svatantika-Prasangika Distinction: What Difference Does a Difference Make? (Boston: Wisdom, 2003).
+
(30.) For a wide-ranging {{Wiki|examination}} of the differences between these two schools, see Georges B. J. [[Dreyfus]] and Sara L. [[McClintock]], eds., The Svatantika-Prasangika Distinction: What Difference Does a Difference Make? (Boston: Wisdom, 2003).
(31.) For an English translation of the Middle Treatise, see Brian Bocking, trans., Nagarjuna in China: A Translation of the Middle Treatise (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 1995).
+
(31.) For an English translation of the [[Middle Treatise]], see Brian Bocking, trans., [[Nagarjuna]] in [[China]]: A Translation of the [[Middle Treatise]] (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 1995).
  
(32.) For a translation of an important treatise of Sengzhao, see Walter Liebenthal, Chao Lun: The Treatises of Seng-chao: A Translation with Introduction, Notes and Appendices (2d rev. ed.; Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, 1968). For an article on Sengzhao's understanding of Madhyamaka, and the ways that his thought both remains true to the Indian sources, yet reflects Chinese religious and philosophical concerns, see Shohei Ichimura, “On the Paradoxical Method of the Chinese Madhyamika: Seng-chao and the Chao-lun Treatise,” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 19 (1992): 51-71.
+
(32.) For a translation of an important treatise of [[Sengzhao]], see [[Walter Liebenthal]], [[Chao Lun]]: The [[Treatises of Seng-chao]]: A Translation with Introduction, Notes and Appendices (2d rev. ed.; [[Hong Kong]]: [[Hong Kong]] {{Wiki|University}} Press, 1968). For an article on Sengzhao's [[understanding]] of [[Madhyamaka]], and the ways that his [[thought]] both remains true to the [[Indian]] sources, yet reflects {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[religious]] and [[philosophical]] concerns, see Shohei Ichimura, “On the {{Wiki|Paradoxical}} Method of the {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Madhyamika]]: [[Seng-chao]] and the [[Chao-lun]] Treatise,” [[Journal of Chinese Philosophy]] 19 (1992): 51-71.
(33.) For an overview of the Sanlun School as well as later developments on Chinese Madhyamaka and its influence on other schools of Buddhism, see Ming-Wood Liu, Madhyamaka Thought in China (Leiden: Brill, 1994).
+
(33.) For an overview of the [[Sanlun School]] as well as later developments on {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Madhyamaka]] and its influence on other [[schools of Buddhism]], see Ming-Wood [[Liu]], [[Madhyamaka]] [[Thought]] in [[China]] ([[Leiden]]: Brill, 1994).
(34.) There are many works in English on Tsongkhapa's formulation of Madhyamaka, but for a translation of his commentary on Nagarjuna's fundamental text, see Je Tsongkhapa, Jay L. Garfield, and Ngawang Samten, trans., Ocean of Reasoning: A Great Commentary on Nagarjuna’s Mulamadhyamakakarika (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006).
+
(34.) There are many works in English on [[Tsongkhapa's]] formulation of [[Madhyamaka]], but for a translation of his commentary on [[Nagarjuna's]] fundamental text, see [[Je Tsongkhapa]], [[Jay L. Garfield]], and [[Ngawang]] [[Samten]], trans., [[Ocean of Reasoning: A Great Commentary on Nagarjuna’s Mulamadhyamakakarika]] ([[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 2006).
(35.) For a translation of this work, see John Whitney Pettit, Mipham’s Beacon of Certainty: Illuminating the View of Dzogchen, the Great Perfection (Boston: Wisdom, 1999); for a comprehensive study of Mipham's Madhyamaka and his critiques of Tsongkhapa, see Phuntsho, Mipham’s Dialectics.
+
(35.) For a translation of this work, see John Whitney Pettit, [[Mipham’s]] [[Beacon of Certainty: Illuminating the View of Dzogchen, the Great Perfection]] (Boston: Wisdom, 1999); for a comprehensive study of [[Mipham's]] [[Madhyamaka]] and his critiques of [[Tsongkhapa]], see Phuntsho, [[Mipham’s]] [[Dialectics]].
  
(36.) Chandrakirti and Jamgon Mipham, Introduction to the Middle Way: Chandrakirti’s Madhyamakavatara with Commentary by Jamgon Mipham, trans. Padmakara Translation Group (Boston and London: Shambhala, 2002).
+
(36.) [[Chandrakirti]] and [[Jamgon Mipham]], [[Introduction to the Middle Way]]: [[Chandrakirti’s]] [[Madhyamakavatara]] with Commentary by [[Jamgon Mipham]], trans. [[Padmakara Translation Group]] ([[Boston]] and [[London]]: [[Shambhala]], 2002).
(37.) For a translation and study of this text, see Jose I. Cabezon and Geshe Lobsang Dargyay, trans., Freedom From Extremes: Gorampa's “Distinguishing the Views” and the Polemics of Emptiness (Boston: Wisdom, 2007).
+
(37.) For a translation and study of this text, see Jose I. [[Cabezon]] and [[Geshe Lobsang]] [[Dargyay]], trans., [[Freedom From Extremes]]: [[Gorampa's]] “[[Distinguishing the Views]]” and the {{Wiki|Polemics}} of [[Emptiness]] (Boston: Wisdom, 2007).
(38.) For English translations see Candrakirti and Mikyo Dorje, Ari Goldfield, Jules Levinson, Jim Scott, and Birgit Scott, trans., The Moon of Wisdom: Chapter Six of Chandrakirti's Entering the Middle Way with Commentary by the Eighth Karmapa Mikyo Dorje’s Chariot of the Dagpo Kagyu Siddhas (Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2005); and Dorje Wangchuk and Dewar Tyler, trans., The Karmapa's Middle Way: Feast for the Fortunate (Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2008).
+
(38.) For English translations see [[Candrakirti]] and [[Mikyo Dorje]], [[Ari Goldfield]], [[Jules Levinson]], [[Jim Scott]], and Birgit Scott, trans., The [[Moon of Wisdom]]: [[Chapter]] Six of [[Chandrakirti's]] [[Entering the Middle Way]] with Commentary by the [[Eighth Karmapa]] Mikyo Dorje’s [[Chariot of the Dagpo Kagyu Siddhas]] ([[Ithaca]], NY: [[Snow Lion]], 2005); and [[Dorje Wangchuk]] and Dewar Tyler, trans., The [[Karmapa's]] [[Middle Way]]: [[Feast for the Fortunate]] ([[Ithaca]], NY: [[Snow Lion]], 2008).
(39.) Among Nyingma scholars, Rongzom Chokyi Zangpo is an early and important figure in the establishment of the Nyingma Madhyamaka, and an example of the synthesis of Madhyamaka and Tantra. See Heidi I. Koppl, Establishing Appearances as Divine: Rongzom Chozang on Reasoning, Madhyamaka, and Purity (Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2008).
+
(39.) Among [[Nyingma scholars]], [[Rongzom Chokyi Zangpo]] is an early and important figure in the establishment of the [[Nyingma]] [[Madhyamaka]], and an example of the {{Wiki|synthesis}} of [[Madhyamaka]] and [[Tantra]]. See Heidi I. Koppl, [[Establishing Appearances as Divine]]: [[Rongzom]] Chozang on {{Wiki|Reasoning}}, [[Madhyamaka]], and [[Purity]] ([[Ithaca]], NY: [[Snow Lion]], 2008).
(40.) For translations and studies of these two Jonang figures, see Cyrus Stearns, The Buddha from Dolpo: A Study of the Life and Thought of the Tibetan Master Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen (Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2010); and Yaroslav Komarovski, Visions of Unity: The Golden Pandita Shakya Chokden’s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2012).
+
(40.) For translations and studies of these two [[Jonang]] figures, see [[Cyrus Stearns]], [[The Buddha from Dolpo]]: A Study of the [[Life]] and [[Thought]] of the [[Tibetan]] [[Master]] [[Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen]] ([[Ithaca]], NY: [[Snow Lion]], 2010); and Yaroslav Komarovski, [[Visions]] of Unity: The Golden [[Pandita]] [[Shakya Chokden’s]] New Interpretation of [[Yogacara]] and [[Madhyamaka]] ([[Albany]], NY: [[State University of New York Press]], 2012).
(41.) Andrew P. Tuck, Comparative Philosophy and the Philosophy of Scholarship: On the Western Interpretation of Nagarjuna (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990).
+
(41.) Andrew P. Tuck, Comparative [[Philosophy]] and the [[Philosophy]] of {{Wiki|Scholarship}}: On the [[Western]] Interpretation of [[Nagarjuna]] ([[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 1990).
  
(42.) Eugene Burnouf, Introduction to the History of Indian Buddhism (Buddhism and Modernity), trans. Katia Buffetrille and Donald S. Lopez, Jr. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2015).
+
(42.) Eugene [[Burnouf]], Introduction to the History of [[Indian Buddhism]] ([[Buddhism]] and Modernity), trans. Katia Buffetrille and [[Donald S. Lopez, Jr.]] ({{Wiki|Chicago}}: [[University of Chicago Press]], 2015).
(43.) Fyodor Shtcherbatsky, The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1968).
+
(43.) Fyodor Shtcherbatsky, The [[Conception of Buddhist Nirvana]] ([[Delhi]]: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1968).
(44.) T. R. V. Murti, The Central Philosophy of Buddhism (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1955).
+
(44.) T. R. V. [[Murti]], The Central [[Philosophy of Buddhism]] ([[London]]: George Allen & Unwin, 1955).
(45.) Richard H. Robinson, “Some Logical Aspects of Nagarjuna's System,” Philosophy East and West 6:4 (1957): 291-308.
+
(45.) Richard H. [[Robinson]], “Some [[Logical]] Aspects of [[Nagarjuna's]] System,” [[Philosophy East and West]] 6:4 (1957): 291-308.
(46.) A number of scholars, including B. K. Matilal, Ives Waldo, Nathan Katz, and Robert Thurman, utilize Wittgenstein's thought, especially in the Philosophical Investigations, to unpack Nagarjuna's arguments and ultimate intent. For an extensive comparison of Nagarjuna and Wittgenstein, see Chris Gudmunsen, Wittgenstein and Buddhism (London: Macmillan, 1977).
+
(46.) A number of [[scholars]], [[including]] B. K. [[Matilal]], Ives Waldo, [[Nathan Katz]], and [[Robert Thurman]], utilize Wittgenstein's [[thought]], especially in the [[Philosophical]] Investigations, to unpack [[Nagarjuna's]] arguments and [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] intent. For an extensive comparison of [[Nagarjuna]] and {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}, see Chris Gudmunsen, {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} and [[Buddhism]] ([[London]]: Macmillan, 1977).
(47.) Frederick Streng, Emptiness: A Study in Religious Meaning (Nashville: Abingdon, 1967).
+
(47.) Frederick Streng, [[Emptiness]]: A Study in [[Religious]] Meaning (Nashville: Abingdon, 1967).
(48.) Richard P. Hayes, “Nagarjuna's Appeal,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (1994): 299-378.
+
(48.) [[Richard P. Hayes]], “[[Nagarjuna's]] Appeal,” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 22 (1994): 299-378.
(49.) Siderits, Buddhism as Philosophy.
+
(49.) [[Siderits]], [[Buddhism]] as [[Philosophy]].
(50.) Jay L. Garfield, Engaging Buddhism: Why It Matters to Philosophy (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2015).
+
(50.) [[Jay L. Garfield]], Engaging [[Buddhism]]: Why It Matters to [[Philosophy]] ([[Oxford]] and [[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 2015).
(51.) Jan Westerhoff, Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2005).
+
(51.) [[Jan Westerhoff]], [[Nagarjuna’s]] [[Madhyamaka]]: A [[Philosophical]] Introduction ([[Oxford]] and [[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 2005).
(52.) Amber Carpenter, Indian Buddhist Philosophy (Ancient Philosophies; New York: Routledge, 2014).
+
(52.) {{Wiki|Amber}} Carpenter, [[Indian Buddhist]] [[Philosophy]] ([[Ancient]] [[Philosophies]]; [[New York]]: Routledge, 2014).
(53.) Tom J. F. Tillemans, How Do Madhyamika's Think: and Other Essays on the Buddhist Philosophy of the Middle (Boston: Wisdom, 2016).
+
(53.) Tom J. F. [[Tillemans]], How Do [[Madhyamika's]] Think: and Other Essays on the [[Buddhist Philosophy]] of the Middle (Boston: Wisdom, 2016).
(54.) See, for instance, Giuseppe Ferraro, “A Criticism of M. Siderits' and J. L. Garfields ‘Semantic Interpretation' of Nagarjuna's Theory of Two Truths,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (2013): 195-219. For a much broader critique of modern understanding of Madhyamaka, see Shulman, “Creative Ignorance.”
+
(54.) See, for instance, Giuseppe Ferraro, “A [[Criticism]] of M. [[Siderits]]' and J. L. Garfields ‘[[Semantic]] Interpretation' of [[Nagarjuna's]] {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Two Truths]],” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 41 (2013): 195-219. For a much broader critique of {{Wiki|modern}} [[understanding]] of [[Madhyamaka]], see Shulman, “Creative [[Ignorance]].”
  
(55.) Philosophy East and West 63.3 (2013) .
+
(55.) [[Philosophy East and West]] 63.3 (2013) .
(56.) See especially Kevin Vose, Resurrecting Candrakirti: Disputes in the Tibetan Creation of Prasangika (Boston: Wisdom, 2009).
+
(56.) See especially Kevin Vose, Resurrecting [[Candrakirti]]: [[Disputes]] in the [[Tibetan]] Creation of [[Prasangika]] (Boston: Wisdom, 2009).
(57.) Jay L. Garfield and Jan Westerhoff, eds., Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies or Rivals? (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press 2015).
+
(57.) [[Jay L. Garfield]] and [[Jan Westerhoff]], eds., [[Madhyamaka]] and [[Yogacara]]: Allies or Rivals? ([[Oxford]] and [[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]] 2015).
(58.) Siderits and Katsura, Nagarjuna's Middle Way.
+
(58.) [[Siderits]] and [[Katsura]], [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Middle Way]].
(59.) Guy Bugault, ed., Stances du milieu par excellence (Paris: Gallimard, 2002).
+
(59.) Guy Bugault, ed., Stances du {{Wiki|milieu}} par [[excellence]] ({{Wiki|Paris}}: Gallimard, 2002).
(60.) Raniero Gnoli, ed. and trans., Nagarjuna Madhyamaka Karika: Le stanze del cammino di mezzo (Enciclopedia di autori classici 61; Turin: P. Boringhieri, 1961).
+
(60.) [[Raniero Gnoli]], ed. and trans., [[Nagarjuna]] [[Madhyamaka]] [[Karika]]: Le stanze del cammino di mezzo (Enciclopedia di autori classici 61; Turin: P. Boringhieri, 1961).
  
(61.) Lutz Geldsetzer, ed. and trans., Die Lehre von der Mitte: Chinesisch-Deutsch (Philosophische Bibliotek 610; Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 2010).
+
(61.) Lutz Geldsetzer, ed. and trans., [[Die]] Lehre von der Mitte: Chinesisch-Deutsch (Philosophische Bibliotek 610; [[Hamburg]]: Felix Meiner, 2010).
(62.) Lindtner, Nagarjuniana.
+
(62.) [[Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]].
(63.) Tola and Dragonetti, “Nagarjuna's Catuhstava.”
+
(63.) Tola and Dragonetti, “[[Nagarjuna's]] Catuhstava.”
(64.) Jeffrey Hopkins, Nagarjuna's Precious Garland: Buddhist Advice for Living and Liberation (Albany, NY: Snow Lion, 2007).
+
(64.) [[Jeffrey Hopkins]], [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Precious Garland]]: [[Buddhist]] Advice for Living and [[Liberation]] ([[Albany]], NY: [[Snow Lion]], 2007).
(65.) William Ames, “Bhavaviveka's Prajnapradlpa: A Translation of Chapter One: ‘Examination of Causal Conditions' (Pratyaya), Part One,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 21 (1994): 209-259; “Bhavaviveka's Prajnapradlpa: A translation of Chapter Two: ‘Examination of the Traversed, the Untraversed, and That Which Is Being Traversed,'” Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (1995): 295-365; “Bhavaviveka's Prajnapradipa: A Translation of Chapter Three, Four, and Five: Examining the Ayatanas, Aggregates, and Elements,” Buddhist Literature 1 (1999): 1-119; “Bhavaviveka's Prajnapradlpa: A Translation of Chapters Six, Examination of Desire and the One Who Desires, and Seven, Examination of Origin, Duration and Cessation,” Buddhist Literature 2 (2000): 1-91.
+
(65.) William Ames, “[[Bhavaviveka's]] Prajnapradlpa: A Translation of [[Chapter]] One: ‘Examination of [[Causal Conditions]]' ([[Pratyaya]]), Part One,” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 21 (1994): 209-259; “[[Bhavaviveka's]] Prajnapradlpa: A translation of [[Chapter]] Two: ‘Examination of the Traversed, the Untraversed, and That Which Is Being Traversed,'” [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]] 23 (1995): 295-365; “[[Bhavaviveka's]] Prajnapradipa: A Translation of [[Chapter]] Three, Four, and Five: Examining the [[Ayatanas]], [[Aggregates]], and [[Elements]],” [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Literature}} 1 (1999): 1-119; “[[Bhavaviveka's]] Prajnapradlpa: A Translation of Chapters Six, Examination of [[Desire]] and the One Who [[Desires]], and Seven, Examination of Origin, Duration and [[Cessation]],” [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Literature}} 2 (2000): 1-91.
  
(66.) J. W. de Jong, Cinq chapitres de la Prasannapada (Paris: Geuthner, 1949); Etienne Lamotte, “Le Traite de l'acte de Vasubandhu, Karmasiddhiprakarana,” Melanges Chinois et Bouddhiques 4 (1936): 265-288; Anne MacDonald, In Clear Words: The Prasannapada, Chapter One. Vols. I & II (Vienna: Verlag der Osterreichischen Akadamie der Wissenschaften, 2015); Jacques May, Candrakirti: Prasannapada Madhyamakavrtti, douze chapitre traduit du sanscrit et du tibetain (Paris: Adrien- Maisonneuve, 1959); Stanislaw Schayer, “Feuer und Brennstoff,” Rocznik Orientalistyczny 7 (1929-1930): 26-52; Stanislaw Schayer, Ausgewahlte Kapitel aus der Prasannapada (Krakow: Naktadem Polskiej Akademji Umiejetnosci, 1931); and Theodore Stcherbatsky, The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1977).  
+
(66.) J. W. de Jong, Cinq chapitres de la [[Prasannapada]] ({{Wiki|Paris}}: Geuthner, 1949); {{Wiki|Etienne Lamotte}}, “Le Traite de l'acte de [[Vasubandhu]], [[Karmasiddhiprakarana]],” Melanges Chinois et Bouddhiques 4 (1936): 265-288; Anne MacDonald, In Clear Words: The [[Prasannapada]], [[Chapter]] One. Vols. I & II ({{Wiki|Vienna}}: Verlag der Osterreichischen Akadamie der Wissenschaften, 2015); Jacques May, [[Candrakirti]]: [[Prasannapada]] Madhyamakavrtti, douze chapitre traduit du sanscrit et du tibetain ({{Wiki|Paris}}: Adrien- Maisonneuve, 1959); Stanislaw Schayer, “Feuer und Brennstoff,” Rocznik Orientalistyczny 7 (1929-1930): 26-52; Stanislaw Schayer, Ausgewahlte Kapitel aus der [[Prasannapada]] (Krakow: Naktadem Polskiej Akademji Umiejetnosci, 1931); and [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Theodore Stcherbatsky]], The [[Conception of Buddhist Nirvana]] ([[Delhi]]: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1977).  
(67.) Malcolm David Eckel, Jnanagarbha’s Commentary on the Distinction Between the Two Truths (SUNY Series in Buddhist Studies; Albany: State University of New York Press, 1987).
+
(67.) [[Malcolm David Eckel]], [[Jnanagarbha’s]] Commentary on the Distinction Between the [[Two Truths]] (SUNY Series in [[Buddhist Studies]]; [[Albany]]: [[State University of New York Press]], 1987).
  
  
(68.) Masamichi Ichigo, “Santaraksita's Madhyamakalamkara: Introduction, Edition and Translation,” in Studies in the Literature of the Great Vehicle: Three Mahayana Buddhist Texts, eds. Luis Gomez and Jonathan Silk (Ann Arbor: Collegiate Institute for the Study of Buddhist Literature and Center for South and Southeast Asian Studies, University of Michigan, 1989), 141-240.
+
(68.) Masamichi Ichigo, “[[Santaraksita's]] [[Madhyamakalamkara]]: Introduction, Edition and Translation,” in Studies in the {{Wiki|Literature}} of the [[Great Vehicle]]: Three [[Mahayana Buddhist Texts]], eds. Luis Gomez and [[Jonathan Silk]] ([[Ann Arbor]]: Collegiate Institute for the Study of [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Literature}} and [[Center]] for [[South]] and {{Wiki|Southeast Asian}} Studies, [[University of Michigan]], 1989), 141-240.
  
  
  
(69.) Masamichi Ichigo, “Santaraksita and Bhavaviveka as Opponents of the Madhyamika in the Madhyamakaloka,” in Wisdom, Compassion, and the Search for Understanding: The Buddhist Studies Legacy of Gadjin M. Nagao, ed. Jonathan Silk (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press, 2000), 147-170.
+
(69.) Masamichi Ichigo, “[[Santaraksita]] and [[Bhavaviveka]] as Opponents of the [[Madhyamika]] in the [[Madhyamakaloka]],” in [[Wisdom]], [[Compassion]], and the Search for [[Understanding]]: The [[Buddhist Studies]] Legacy of Gadjin M. [[Nagao]], ed. [[Jonathan Silk]] ([[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University}} of Hawai‘i Press, 2000), 147-170.
  
(70.) Ryusei Keira, Madhyamika and Epistemology: A Study of Kamalaslla’s Method for Proving the Voidness of All Dharmas: Introduction, Annotated Translations and Tibetan Texts of Selected Sections of the Second Chapter of the Madhyamakaloka (Vienna: Arbeitskreis fur Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien, 2004).
+
(70.) Ryusei Keira, [[Madhyamika]] and {{Wiki|Epistemology}}: A Study of Kamalaslla’s Method for Proving the [[Voidness]] of All [[Dharmas]]: Introduction, Annotated Translations and [[Tibetan Texts]] of Selected [[Sections]] of the Second [[Chapter]] of the [[Madhyamakaloka]] ({{Wiki|Vienna}}: Arbeitskreis fur Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien, 2004).
  
  
(71.) Sara L. McClintock, Omniscience and Rhetoric of Reason: Santaraksita and Kamalasila on Rationality, Argumentation and Religious Authority (Boston: Wisdom, 2010).
+
(71.) Sara L. [[McClintock]], [[Omniscience]] and [[Rhetoric]] of [[Reason]]: [[Santaraksita]] and [[Kamalasila]] on {{Wiki|Rationality}}, Argumentation and [[Religious]] Authority (Boston: Wisdom, 2010).
  
  
 
Paul B. Donnelly
 
Paul B. Donnelly
  
Northern Arizona University
+
[[Northern]] Arizona {{Wiki|University}}
  
  

Revision as of 22:29, 2 February 2020




Paul B. Donnelly


Subject: Buddhism, Schools, Lineages, and Movements Online Publication Date: Jan 2017


Summary and Keywords


Along with Yogacara, Madhyamaka (Middle Way) is one of the two foundational doctrinal systems of Indian Mahayana Buddhism, which flourished from the 3rd century CE to the final disappearance of Buddhism from the subcontinent in the 12th- 13th centuries. Beginning in the 4th century, it spread to East Asia, where it became the foundation of an independent school of thought and influenced the other major Chinese Buddhist schools. It took root in Tibet beginning in the 7th century, where it served as the cornerstone of all the scholastically inclined Buddhist sects. Throughout the Mahayana Buddhist world, Madhyamaka has occupied a foundational position in doctrinal formulations and practices. Madhyamaka has tended to be regarded as either the supreme formulation of Mahayana thought, as was often the case in Tibet, or as complementary to Yogacara, which was more commonly held in China and Japan.


The nameMiddle Way” references a fundamental assumption in Buddhism that stakes a middle position between the idea that the self is an irreducible, enduring entity and one in which it is wholly reducible to the physical body and perishes after death. Though central Madhyamaka ideas, such as the doctrine of the Two Truths, Dependent Origination, and Emptiness, can be found in Nikaya Buddhism and in Mahayana sutras, it is in the treatises of Nagarjuna (2nd-3rd centuries CE) that we have a fully formed and distinct system of thought that can be called Madhyamaka. In earlier canonical works, and more explicitly in the Abhidharma, this notion of middle way applied exclusively to the self (Skt atmanlPaM atta) and conceptually constructed phenomena. In Mahayana sutras and in Nagarjuna works, the assertion is extended to the fundamental component parts of all existents, which are declared to be empty of intrinsic nature. In Abhidharma works, the self and other composite phenomena are said to be reducible to their fundamental parts, the dharmas (Pali dhamma), which, being irreducible, must have their own identifiable intrinsic mode of existence even if they exist dependently. According to Madhyamaka, a dharma cannot possess an intrinsic nature precisely because it exists dependently. Denying any intrinsic nature, Madhyamaka asserts that things exist only dependently, and this only in terms of conventional truth, and that ultimately, emptiness of intrinsic nature is the truth and reality of all things. Not surprisingly, such a position was contentious, and numerous interpreters attempted to elucidate this rather radical position. The question of which commentator or commentators are definitive has occupied many generations of Indian, East Asian, and Tibetan Buddhists, and the issue remains very much alive in modern scholarship on Madhyamaka. Though much of this scholarship has come from a philosophical perspective, the intent of Madhyamaka, like all Buddhist thought, is primarily soteriological in nature.


Keywords: Madhyamaka, Nagarjuna, emptiness (sunyata), dependent origination (pratityasamutpada), Mahayana, Abhidharma, intrinsic nature (svabhava), Two Truths


Historical Background and Context of Madhyamaka

In numerous discourses, the Buddha refers to his teaching as a middle way1 between extreme and erroneous views about the putative self (Skt. atman2). An example of this is the frequently referenced Kaccayanagotta Sutta, in which the Buddha tells Kaccana that right view occupies a middle position between the two extreme conceptions of existence and nonexistence: This world, Kaccana, for the most part depends upon a duality—upon the notion of existence and the notion of nonexistence. But for one who sees the origin of the world as it really is with correct wisdom, there is no notion of nonexistence in regard to the world. And for one who sees the cessation of the world as it really is with correct wisdom, there is no notion of existence in regard to the world... “All exists”: Kaccana, this is one extreme. ‘All does not exist': this is the second extreme. Without veering towards either of these extremes, the Tathagata teaches a Dhamma by the middle.3


This passage is followed by an iteration of the teaching on the twelve links of dependent origination (pratityasamutpada), which describes the process of the origination of suffering from ignorance (avidya), and explains that the cessation of the first link leads to the cessation of “this whole mass of suffering.”4 Right view is the antidote to ignorance, and thus to suffering. The Sutta explicitly states that this middle view pertains to views about the self and to the cessation of suffering as its goal.


With the Abhidharma literature, we see the beginnings of categorization and standardization of concepts understood to be presented in the Suttas. Some early Buddhist traditions made this literature canonical, raising it to the status of “word of the Buddha” (buddhavacana), but others did not, and in some cases the latter integrated such material into the Sutta Pitaka. Interpretations of the Abhidharma texts led to a proliferation of systems of exposition, and the depth and complexity of the material provided fertile ground for the further explication of Buddhist doctrine. It is against this background that Madhyamaka as a distinct doctrinal system arose. Nagarjuna's arguments are predominantly directed against other Buddhists, presumably Abhidharmikas. As Siderits and Katsura in their translation of the Nagarjuna's Root Verses of the Middle Way (Mulamadhyamakakarika) point out, Nagarjuna's adversaries would have shared a core set of presuppositions, which establish the parameters of what Nagarjuna seeks to refute. These presuppositions can be summarized as follows.


What really exists, in the last analysis, and in yogic realization, is in fact a dynamic flow of fundamental, irreducible entities called dharmas. All facts about things of the conventional world, and especially the self, can be explained entirely and ultimately in terms of dharmas and their relations with one another. What one can say about composite phenomena, such as the self, is only true conventionally. Only statements grounded at the level of dharmas can be ultimately true, because only dharmas have ultimate existence. An element of the assumptions about this ultimate existence is that dharmas possess their own intrinsic natures (svabhava), a unique property that is inherent to them and depends on nothing else. Nothing that lacks an intrinsic nature can be ultimate. The Buddhist goal of nirvana, the complete and final cessation of suffering, was held to be achieved through the realization of what is ultimately true about ourselves and the world. The erroneous belief that keeps us bound in samsara is the mistaken assumption that the self is ultimately real, when in fact it is a conceptual fiction that we superimpose upon an impersonal stream of mental and physical phenomena.


Nagarjuna and Mahayana

Nagarjuna (2nd-3rd centuries CE) is generally regarded by later Buddhist traditions and modern scholarship as the founder of the Madhyamaka “school.”5 Traditional accounts also associate Nagarjuna with the rise of the Mahayana. In Tibetan traditions, Nagarjuna (along with Asanga) is called one of the two “Re-openers” of the Mahayana and is credited with the return of the Perfection of Wisdom texts to the world of humans by retrieving them from the realm of the Nagas, where they had been kept safe for centuries. He is revered as a patriarch in numerous Buddhist traditions in East Asia and Tibet, including Ch'an/Zen, Pure Land, Shingon, and the Tibetan Vajrayana.


The emergence of the Mahayana is characterized by the appearance of new texts, most notably the Perfection of Wisdom (Prajnaparamita) sutras, attributed to the Buddha. This genre of sutra focuses on the six, or ten, perfections of the Bodhisattva culminating in the perfection of wisdom itself called, among other things, the “mother of all the Buddhas.” These texts, which depict themselves as discourses of the Buddha, flatly reject the position that, while self was utterly illusory, the skandhas, the dynamic processes upon which a self was wrongly imputed, actually had an ontological status. In these sutras we read that the five skandhas do not exist, or are empty (sunya) Madhyamaka thought is traditionally understood as elucidating the meaning of such assertions in the Perfection of Wisdom sutras. In Nagarjuna's texts, arguments are made to demonstrate how and why this way of expressing the dharma is not only justified, but is in fact the actual and final intent of the Buddha's teachings.


The Textual Foundations of Madhyamaka

In the Chinese Buddhist canon there are eight texts attributed to Nagarjuna, and in the Tibetan canon, there are 116. Studies of Chinese Madhyamaka have tended to focus on the Sanlun School and the influence of Madhyamaka on later syncretic schools such as Tiantai, Huayan, and Chan.6 The bulk of most modern scholarly interest in Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka has been on just a few of the Indian texts, in some cases in their Tibetan translations. Some disagreement remains about which of them can be reliably attributed to Nagarjuna, but there is a general consensus that the texts that the later Tibetan traditions group into the “analytic corpus” are genuine works of Nagarjuna. In addition to the analytic corpus (rigs tshogs), the Tibetan categorization includes the hymnic corpus (bstod tshogs) and the advice corpus (gtam tshogs).7 The analytic corpus includes the Root Verses of the Middle Way (Mulamadhyamakakorikd), the Sixty Stanzas on Analysis (Yuktisastika), the Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness


(Sunyatasaptati), the Dispeller of Objections (Vigrahavyavatanl), the Treatise on Pulverization (Vaidalyaprakarano), and the non-extant Proof of Conventions (Vyavaharasiddhi)? The Precious Garland (Ratnavall) is sometimes substituted in the place of the latter, but it is in fact a very different sort of text from the other five, much more in accord with the advice corpus, and is often placed in that category. The Root Verses of the Middle Way (MMK) was regarded by all the major commentators in India, China, and Tibet as Nagarjuna's magnum opus. Modern scholarship has accepted this and has used this text as the touchstone for determining the authenticity of the other works attributed to Nagarjuna. The Mulamadhyamakakarika consists of 447 verses in twenty-seven chapters, though some modern scholars argue that the text originally ended with chapter 25. Typical of the karika genre, the subject matter is presented in a terse style, leading to the composition of numerous commentaries in India, China, and Tibet to elucidate the meaning of the Mulamadhyamakakarika.


The Sixty Stanzas on Analysis (Yuktisastika) is a text consisting of sixty-one verses that explain Madhyamika analysis as the elimination of thinking in terms of existence and nonexistence of what is dependently originated (pratityasamutpada). The Sixty Stanzas on Analysis makes the striking assertion that the world is a construction of ignorance, and nirvana is precisely the realization of this fact/ It is extant in both Chinese and Tibetan translations. The Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness (Sunyatasaptati) is a text of seventy-three verses that deals with the central Madhyamaka concept of emptiness (sunyata), accompanied by a commentary said to be authored by Nagarjuna himself. It exists only in Tibetan translation. The Dispeller of Objections (Vigrahavyavartint) is a seventy-verse text that answers objections to Nagarjuna's views expressed in his other works, especially the MMK. It is available in the original Sanskrit and also in Chinese and Tibetan translations. The Treatise on Pulverization (Vaidalyaprakarana') is a work that critiques the sixteen logical categories of Nyaya philosophy. It exists only in Tibetan translation. The Precious Garland (Ratnavalt) is a 500-verse work that is said to be advice given to a king. Among the minor analytic corpus texts, the Dispeller of Objections is often invoked to help clarify points in the MMK, especially on the issue of Nagarjuna's assertion that Madhyamikas have no philosophical thesis of their own. In the major English translations and the broader attempts to establish Nagarjuna's system, neither the Sixty Stanzas on Analysis nor the Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness has been much taken into account,10 despite the fact that the 7th-century Indian commentator Candrakirti held the Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness, along with the Dispeller of Objections, to form an appendix to the MMK.11


The hymns have received relatively little attention in Western scholarship despite their importance in the Tibetan traditions and many scholars' acceptance that at least some of these texts were likely written by the same author as the Mulamadhyakakarika.12 In Tibet, for the proponents of the more cataphaticother-emptiness” (gzhan stong) doctrine, the hymns were revered as expressing Nagarjuna's final philosophical position and the definitive meaning of the Middle Way. For the most part, however, these texts and their message have not played a significant part in the understanding of Madhyamaka for Indian or Tibetan13 authors or for modern scholars. What Did Nagarjuna Mean by “Middle Way?”


As mentioned above, the early Buddhist meaning of the idea that the Buddha's teaching is a middle way was that it staked out a position between the extreme views of “all exists” and “all does not exist.” These two views are often referred to as “eternalism” (sasvatadarsanam) and “annihilationism” (ucchedadarsanam), and they specifically refer to views about the self. An eternalist view of the self holds that the self abides through time and across lives, and an annihilationist view holds that personal existence is annihilated at death, thus rendering null questions of karmic reward or retribution. The meaning of right view, in the Kaccayanagotta Sutta, is defined: “Without veering towards either of these extremes, the Tathagata teaches the Dhamma by the middle.”14 That Dhamma is the teaching of the twelve links of dependent origination.


Nagarjuna cites the Sanskrit parallel of this sutta but takes its implications further. In chapter fifteen of the MMK, he says, “In ‘The Instructing of Katyayana,' both ‘it exists' and ‘it does not exist' are denied by the Blessed One, who clearly perceives the existent and nonexistent.”15 Here, and throughout the MMK, Nagarjuna takes this sense of right view to apply not just to the self but to everything, including the skandhas, which are the basis for the mistaken assumption of an existent self that Abhidarmikas held to ultimately exist. Echoing numerous statements in the Perfection of Wisdom sutras, where it says that the five skandhas are as empty as the putative self, Nagarjuna argues in the MMK and other texts of the analytic corpus that any conceivable entity can be demonstrated to be empty, that is, not existent, nonexistent, both existent and nonexistent, neither existent or nonexistent.


In chapter after chapter, Nagarjuna subjects to analysis numerous things, from conditionality up through the Buddha, the Four Noble Truths, and nirvana. In every case, the object is revealed not to exist in any ultimate sense. Though he uses a number of common patterns of argumentation, underlying them all is a method that sets up all possible ways that the object could exist, and then refutes each possibility. For example, in chapter 1 Nagarjuna takes on the concept that things exist in the sense that they


arise from causal conditions. He begins, “Not from itself, not from another, not from both, nor without a cause: never in any way is there any existing thing that has arisen.”16 The four possibilities for the arising of a thing are considered to exhaust the possibilities for a meaningful explanation of causation, and Nagarjuna rejects each one as incoherent. To come to this conclusion, Nagarjuna points out that dichotomous concepts like “self/other” are mutually dependent for their meaning, or existence. According to Abhidharmikas, for a thing to be real, it must have an intrinsic nature (svabhava), which makes it what it is. Nagarjuna denies the possibility of intrinsic nature, as well as the possibility of the nature of a thing arising from something else (parabhava), because “other” depends on “self.” Nagarjuna seeks to demonstrate that the Abhidharmikas' own positions are incoherent. The conclusion here is that conditions, regarded as real things by Abhidharmikas, are empty. “Therefore neither a product consisting of conditions nor one consisting of nonconditions exists; if the product does not exist, how can there be a condition or noncondition.”17 This discursive “emptying” of concepts that were widely accepted by scholastically inclined Buddhists of Nagarjuna's time is the main work of the MMK, and the conclusion that Nagarjuna reaches again and again is that when analyzed deeply, everything is revealed to lack any unique nature or essential nature of its own. Abhidarmikas insisted that the possession of such an intrinsic nature was necessary for something to exist in an ultimate sense; thus, from their perspective Nagarjuna seemed to be arguing that nothing really existed, and this was thought to be thoroughly incompatible with the teachings of the Buddha.


It takes until chapter 24 of the MMK, “An Analysis of the Four Noble Truths,” before Nagarjuna responds to this not unreasonable concern. His response is to invoke the structure of the Two Truths, which Abhidarmikas accept, though in a completely different way, as discussed above. Nagarjuna's analyses have revealed that the arising and passing away of things in the phenomenal world, about which the Buddha taught, is possible only because those things lack intrinsic nature—they are neither existent, nonexistent, both, or neither. Exactly what that entails for the level of conventional truth/existence has been disputed by Nagarjuna's Indian and Chinese commentators, as well as modern interpreters. If nothing can be said to exist (or not, or both, or neither) in any ultimate sense, numerous questions obviously arise about ethics, the path, nirvana, and more. Nagarjuna's response to those who say that emptiness undermines all these things is to state that it is in fact the assumptions of existence/nonexistence, or existence by intrinsic nature, that would make the phenomenal world, knowledge of it, and the attainment of nirvana impossible. “All is possible when emptiness is possible. Nothing is possible when emptiness is impossible... If you look upon existents as real intrinsically, in that case you regard existents as being without cause and conditions.. Effect and cause, as well as agent, instrument and act, arising and ceasing, and fruit—all these you thereby deny.”18 Later commentators, both ancient and modern, however, have struggled with the full implications of the status of the phenomenal world after it has been emptied by Madhyamika analysis.19 Emptiness, however, is not some ultimate nature of the sort imagined by the Abhidarmikas. It is just a useful way of talking, a convention, that steers a middle course between absolutism and nihilism. In probably the most famous verse of the MMK, Nagarjuna says, “Dependent Origination we declare to be emptiness. It [[[emptiness]]] is a dependent concept; just that is the middle path.”20 If everything is dependently originated, as the Buddha taught and Nagarjuna has argued, it follows that things cannot be accurately described as existing, not existing, both, or neither. Those concepts, and all others, are only conventional. As Mark Siderits has pithily put this, “The ultimate truth is that there is no ultimate truth.”21


What is the Purpose of Madhyamaka?

A great deal of the modern scholarship on Madhyamaka approaches and engages with it as philosophy, but Buddhism has always been more than what we usually mean by this term. The Buddhist path is concerned with the eradication of existential suffering. Knowledge is for the sake of liberation from suffering and the cycle of birth and death (samsara). What then does Madhyamaka have to do with this? It is worthwhile to look at what the MMK states as its purpose. It is often the case that Indian treatises such as the MMK lay out the intended purpose of the text in the opening dedicatory verse:


I salute the Fully Enlightened One, the best of orators, who taught the doctrine of dependent origination, according to which there is neither cessation nor origination, neither annihilation nor the eternal, neither singularity nor plurality, neither the coming nor the going [of any dharma, for the purpose of nirvana characterized by] the auspicious cessation of hypostatization.22 Nagarjuna identifies the Buddha's fundamental teaching to be dependent origination, characterized by the negation of four pairs of concepts. The purpose of this teaching, or the fruit of its realization, is said to be cessation of “hypostatization” (prapanca}, or the mental process of conceptualization or “thing-ification.”


In chapter 18, “An Analysis of the Self,” Nagarjuna says, “Liberation is attained through the destruction of actions and defilements; actions and defilements arise because of falsifying conceptualizations; those arise from hypostatization; but hypostatization is extinguished in emptiness. In the Sunyatasaptati, considered by Candrakirti to be a supplement for understanding the MMK, Nagarjuna says, “To imagine that things born by causes and conditions are real is called ignorance by the Teacher. From that the twelve members arise. But when one, by seeing correctly, has understood that things are empty one is not infatuated. That is the cessation of ignorance. Thereupon the twelve members stop.”


The final verse of an Indian treatise of this sort can also conclude or restate the purport of all that came before it. Though the two 25 major Indian commentators, Bhaviveka and Candrakirti, take the current twenty-seven-chapter version of the MMK to be entirely composed by Nagarjuna, some modern scholars have asserted that the final two chapters were later additions by another author. If this were so, the final verse of chapter 25, “An Analysis of Nirvana,” should be expected to tell us about the intent of the work. “This halting of cognizing everything, the halting of hypostatizing, is blissful. No Dharma whatsoever was ever taught by the Buddha to anyone.” This verse clearly echoes the dedicatory verse, though the translation here obscures this slightly in that the same phrase (prapancopasamah sivah) found in both verses is translated differently here. In the translation of the dedicatory verse this is rendered “the auspicious cessation of hypostatization.” The second part of the dedicatory verse is the salutation to the Buddha, who taught dependent origination characterized by the eight negations. In the final line of the verse at the end of chapter 25, having been through twenty-five chapters of negations, we hear that the Buddha did not teach any dharma at all, to anyone. Without taking a stand on whether or not this was the final verse of the original text, this statement does indeed sum up the text's work, though concluding on a far more radical point than the one on which it started, but for which Nagarjuna has argued thus far.


Chapter 26 is an orthodox teaching on the twelve links of dependent origination, perhaps, as the commentator Bhaviveka suggests, in response to those who would take issue with the concluding verse of the nirvana chapter. It is also worth noting that Nagarjuna has used the doctrine of dependent origination as an argument for how things are in fact empty throughout the text up to this point, so perhaps this uncontroversial teaching of the twelve links helps us to see what he has meant by “dependent origination,” and links it back to the intrinsically soteriological purpose of Madhyamaka. “Upon the cessation of ignorance there is the nonarising of volitions. But the cessation of ignorance is due to meditation on just the knowledge of this. By reason of the cessation of one factor in the twelvefold chain, another successor factor fails to arise. Thus does the entire mass of suffering completely cease.”


The twenty-seventh chapter is “An Analysis of Views,” in which Nagarjuna tackles the so-called indeterminate questions posed to the Buddha in some sutras. These are questions that the Buddha refused to answer, such as past and future existence of the person, the world, and so on. These questions were answered with silence, because they involved false presuppositions and thus could not be answered in a fashion that would be helpful to the questioner. Up until the final verse, most of what Nagarjuna has said would be acceptable to his Abhidharmika contemporaries, but the final verse says, “I salute Gautama, who, based on compassion, taught the true Dharma for the abandonment of all views.”28 In the dedicatory verse, the Buddha is praised as the teacher of dependent origination, which is described in terms of four pairs of dichotomous concepts, or views, all of which are negated. Here the purpose is stated as the abandonment of all views, the aforementioned, and presumably any and every possible view at all about the self and the world. Chapter 24, verse 18 quoted above, suggests that even emptiness, if taken to express a view, is to be ultimately abandoned.


Nagarjuna's Madhyamika Successors in India

Nagarjuna's oeuvre gave rise to numerous commentaries on his works, and original works from authors who saw themselves standing in the Madhyamika lineage. The earliest was Aryadeva (2nd-3rd centuries CE), who is traditionally understood to have been a direct disciple of Nagarjuna. His major text is an original work, The Four Hundred (Catuhsataka) This text traces the Bodhisattva's path from the cultivation of virtues up through the attainment of full awakening, thus situating Madhyamaka much more explicitly in Mahayana thought and practice than Nagarjuna's works. The complete text is extant only in Tibetan, and there is a full translation of Aryadeva's text into English by Karen Lang.29 Buddhapalita (early 6th century) wrote a commentary on Nagarjuna's MMK which is closely related to or identical with the commentary (Akutobhayd) sometimes attributed to Nagarjuna. In Buddhapalita's time, there were important new developments in Buddhist thought in the form of a highly developed epistemological system that would transform how Buddhist philosophy would be done. Buddhapalita resisted these innovations, employing only arguments that revealed the shortcomings of Nagarjuna's opponents' positions, consistent with Nagarjuna's own primary argumentative method. Buddhapalita's conservatism on this point was criticized by the next major commentator, Bhaviveka (late 6th century). In his commentary on the MMK, the Lamp of Wisdom (Prajndpradrpa'), Bhaviveka took up a radically opposed position to that of Buddhapalita on the matter of what kind of argumentation was needed to establish the Madhyamika position. This shift is perhaps a result of the further integration of the epistemological advances of Dharmakirti (c. 650) into scholastic Mahayana discourse. Many thought that these new methods put Buddhists on a more solid footing in defending themselves against the critiques of non-Buddhist philosophers in India. Bhaviveka felt that the Madhyamika position needed more than the unwanted- consequence method of argumentation (prasanga) favored by Nagarjuna and Buddhapalita in order to give it logical establishment. Bhaviveka utilized logically elaborated syllogisms (svatantra anumana) in order to argue for the conclusions of Nagarjuna. For this reason, Bhaviveka would later be considered by the Tibetan traditions to be the founder of the Svatantrika school of interpretation. In addition to the Lamp of Wisdom, Bhaviveka wrote an independent verse treatise on Madhyamaka, the Verses on the Heart of the Middle Way (Madhyamakahrdayakarikd), with a prose commentary. In this work he surveys and critiques the perspective of non-Mahayana Buddhists, Yogacarins, and the six philosophical systems of Hinduism. Hence, this text presents us with a snapshot of the range of philosophical positions current in India in the 6th century.


In his extensive commentary on the MMK, Clear Words (Prasannapada), candrakirti (7th century) extensively critiqued Bhaviveka's introduction of the epistemological system of Dharmakirti into the exegesis of Madhyamaka and critiqued that system itself as well as doctrines of Yogacara. candrakirti, in defense of Buddhapalita, argued for exclusive reliance on prasanga arguments to establish the Madhyamika position. This emphasis on prasanga argumentation would cause later Tibetan doxographers to see Candrakirti to be the founder of the Prasangika school of Madhyamaka, which came to be seen as differing from the Svatantrikas not only in terms of methodology but also in terms of holding different philosophical positions.30 In

addition to his commentary on the MMK, Candrakirti wrote commentaries on Nagarjuna's Sunyatasaptati and Yuktisastika as well as one on Aryadeva's Catuhsataka. His original work, Introduction to the Middle Way (Madhyamakavatara'), was intended to be a general introduction to Madhyamaka, but with an emphasis on Bodhisattva practice and realization. It is divided into ten sections on the production of the mind of awakening (bodhicitta), which are aligned with the ten Bodhisattva stages taught in the Sutra on the Ten Grounds (Dasabhumika Sutra) and the Ten Perfections. Because of this structuring, this text is far more focused on realization and soteriology than Nagarjuna's works of the analytic corpus. Despite the professed importance of the MMK among Tibetan scholars, Candrakirti's Introduction to the Middle Way has been the subject of far more commentary in Tibet.


Treatises of Late Indian Madhyamika Thinkers

In India, Madhyamaka was followed by Yogacara, which, like Madhyamaka, can be seen as providing a reasoned explication of the doctrines of certain Mahayana sutras, especially in the Yogacara case, the Samdhmirmocana. From the Yogacara perspective, the Perfection of Wisdom Sutras and Madhyamaka are understood as clearing away the pernicious illusions projected by hypostatization (prapanca), but the final and definitive teachings of the Buddha were to be found in Yogacara sutras and treatises. In these texts, it is asserted that mind, once purified of hypostatization, was ultimate reality and awakening itself. Among the early commentators on Nagarjuna's texts are several by prominent masters of the Yogacara school. A portion of a commentary ascribed to Asanga (4th century) on the beginning of the MMK is found in the Chinese canon, and a commentary by Sthiramati (6th century) is also preserved there. Other commentaries by Yogacarins are also referred to in both Chinese and Tibetan sources, though they are not extant. This clearly demonstrates that Nagarjuna's works were not seen to be necessarily in conflict with the teachings of Yogacara.


For the most part, Madhyamaka and Yogacara became synthesized into a complementary whole that addressed both the negation z of pernicious views and the establishment of ultimate truth as consciousness. The works of Jnanagarbha, Santaraksita and Kamalasila set the standard for Madhyamaka orthodoxy, and it was the latter two that took Madhyamaka to Tibet as part of the first establishment of Buddhism there. In India, the Svatantika-Prasangika distinction was not the important one; it was rather one between the views of those who accepted the (conventional) existence of external objects, which included both Bhaviveka and Candrakirti, and those who asserted a more Yogacarin understanding, in which external objects were ultimately mind- originated, though also empty in the last analysis.


This latter category included Jnanagarbha, Santaraksita and Kamalasila, and it was the dominant position in scholastic Buddhist India until at least the 11th century. Jnanagarbha wrote a treatise examining the Two Truths (Satyadvayavibhanga'), accompanied z by an auto-commentary. Santaraksita wrote a treatise on Madhyamaka, the Ornament of the Middle Way (Madhyamakalamkara), which established the foundation of what would later be called the Yogacara-Madhyamaka school. He also composed the Tattvasamgraha, an extensive critical study of the doctrines of the different schools of Indian philosophy at the time. A commentary on Jnanagarbha's Satyadvayavibhanga is attributed to him as well. Kamalasila was the disciple of


Santaraksita, on whose Tattvasamgraha he wrote a substantial commentary. Kamalasila also wrote an original work, the Illumination of the Middle Way (Madhyamakaloka), which expounds the Yogacara-Madhymaka system in great detail, building upon and elucidating the texts of his teacher. Madhyamaka in East Asia Madhyamaka texts and teachings were brought to China by Kumarajiva (350-409), and these eventually became the foundation of an independent school, Sanlun or Three Treatise School. The three authoritative texts of Sanlun were the MMK (called the Madhyamakasastra in the Chinese canon),31 the Twelve Gate Treatise (Shih erh men lun) attributed to Nagarjuna, and the One Hundred Verse Treatise (Pai lun) attributed to Aryadeva. The latter two texts exist only here in Kumarajiva's translations. The text that has arguably had the greatest influence on East Asian Madhyamaka, however, was the massive Treatise Which is a Teaching on the Great Perfection of Wisdom (Ta-chih-tu lun), also translated by Kumarajiva. After Kumaraj iva, his disciple Sengzhao was the most important figure in the establishment and development of Chinese Madhyamaka.32 The Madhyamika commentaries that have figured so prominently in the Tibetan traditions' interpretation of Madhyamaka, and in modern scholarship, are not included in the Chinese canon, so the development of Madhyamika thought took a quite different path than in Tibet. In East Asia, there has tended to be a more ontologically positivist understanding of emptiness and a general harmonization of Madhyamaka and Yogacara, seeing them as complementary rather than opposing systems. Though Sanlun faded from importance as a distinct school of thought, Madhyamaka remained significant throughout the later development of Chinese Buddhism, influencing Tiantai, Huayan, and especially Chan.33


Madhyamaka in Tibet

The Tibetans received Madhyamika texts in both the first (7th-8th centuries) and second (11th-12th centuries) periods of the propagation of Buddhism there. Because scholastic monasticism was part of the institutional form that was imported, alongside Vajrayana, Madhaymaka was important from the very beginning, and has remained so. In Tibet, monk scholars sought to establish a hierarchy of Buddhist tenet systems (grub mtha') that encompassed all the Buddhist schools in an ascending order, beginning with the two Abhidarmika Schools (Vaibhasika and Sautrantika), which served as the elementary understandings of the Dharma, moving up to the Yogacara, and culminating in the Madhyamaka. It was assumed that the understanding of the philosophical positions of each of these schools enabled one to then understand the next higher level. Ascent up through this hierarchy represented a progressively more subtle understanding of the Two Truths. The two Abhidharma schools asserted that dharmas, understood in different ways, were ultimately real and anything that was the result of conceptual hypostatization was merely conventional. The Yogacara was understood to assert that external objects were ultimately unreal (i.e., projected by conceptual imposition) and only consciousness was ultimately real. Madhyamaka was understood to go one step further and assert that consciousness too was empty and thus only existent conventionally.


Early in the doxographical project Tibetans followed the categorization of Madhyamaka inherited from India, in which Madhyamaka was divided into those who accepted the conventional existence of external objects (e.g., Bhaviveka and z Candrakirti) and those who declared external objects to be projections of mind and ultimately empty (Jnanagarbha, Santaraksita and Kamalasila). In the late 11th century, the Madhyamaka works of Candrakirti were translated into Tibetan, and Tibetan doxographers began to factor them into their categorizing efforts. Shortly thereafter, the terms Svatantrika and Prasangika were coined (in Tibetan) and deployed in a new conceptualization of Madhyamaka schools. There were Tibetan scholars who accepted Candrakirti's interpretation of Madhyamaka and those who argued forcefully against it, but in the end it was the Prasangika approach that won the day, though it remained a matter of some dispute just what the differences between this school and the Svatantrika were.


In the 14th century, it was the writings of Tsongkhapa that introduced a new distinction between Svatantrika and Prasangika, one which posited not just a methodological distinction between the two schools but also an ontological one. Prior to Tsongkhapa and continuing after him in the scholarship of the Sakya, Kagyu, and Nyingma sects, the principal difference was one of a whether the Madhyamika master used arguments that simply sought to demonstrate to the opponent the unwanted consequences of his position (prasanga) or rather utilized logically established arguments that positively proved the Madhyamika position (svatantra). Tsongkhapa argued instead that there is an actual difference in how the two schools understand conventional truth. In his understanding, Svatantrikas accept the conventional reality of the manifest world. In that world there are things that are real and things that are illusory. The sophisticated epistemological system of Dharmakirti was seen to provide tools to ascertain which are which, and to prove, in a real sense, the doctrinal position of Madhyamaka. According to Tsongkhapa, this entails a subtle realism that falls short of the definitive meaning of Nagarjuna's texts, which is that everything is empty of intrinsic nature. Only Candrakirti's interpretation of Madhyamaka is considered to go far enough and relegate everything in this world to the status of merely conventional.34 Though this understanding is accepted by only one of the four major sects of Tibetan Buddhism, it has had an inestimable impact on the modern scholarship on Madhyamaka.


Despite his proclaimed exclusive adherence to Candrakirti's understanding of Madhyamaka, Tsongkhapa in fact relies heavily on the logico-epistemological developments of Dharmakirti in his method of Madhyamaka argumentation and his understanding of ultimate truth. Tsongkhapa asserts that the object of Madhyamaka negation is inherent existence, but once that has been refuted, the basis of that negation, the phenomenon under analysis, can be said to exist conventionally. This move has the advantage of allowing a basis for the efficacy of logical argumentation, ethics, and religious practice. Tsongkhapa asserts that the ultimate truth, which is the emptiness of inherent existence, is itself an existent object of knowledge. This makes it possible for discursive thought to realize the ultimate truth—a claim that is unique to Tsongkhapa and the Geluk sect. The other three major sects of Tibetan Buddhism saw Tsongkhapa's understanding of Madhyamaka as straying from the original intent of Nagarjuna and his Indian commentators. For the Nyingma, Sakya, and Kagyu sects generally, the final purport of Madhyamaka is freedom from the extreme views of being and nonbeing. Ultimate truth is not regarded as an object of discursive knowledge, but rather the realization that things cannot be said to exist, not exist, both, or neither. Ontologically speaking, ultimate reality qua emptiness is reality free of hypostatization. The 19th-century Nyingma scholar Jamgon Mipham critiqued Tsongkhapa's position in his Beacon of Certainty and many other of his works.35 Mipham also wrote an extensive commentary on Santaraksita's Madhyamakalamkara?6 Though several prominent Sakya scholars wrote extensive refutations, Gorampa Sonam Senge's Distinguishing the Views is probably the most powerful critique of Tsongkhapa's Madhyamaka and elucidation of the Sakya Madhyamaka.37 Among Kagyu scholars, The Eighth and Ninth Karmapas composed commentaries on Candrakirti's Madhyamakavatara in which Tsongkhapa's views are frequently criticized.38


Tibetan Buddhism is Vajrayana Buddhism, so tantric theory has always played an important role in Tibetan doctrinal formulations. Yogacara provides a more suitable foundation for tantric theory and practice, but Madhyamaka has nearly always been regarded as compatible with, or has served as the true doctrinal foundation of, Vajrayana. The Nyingma and Kagyu sects have typically been more inclined to an understanding of Yogacara and Madhyamaka as complementary teachings, and one in which both were seen through the lens of Vajrayana thought and practice.39 The Sakya and the Geluk sects have tended to privilege Candrakirti's understanding as definitive (though they disagree on what that understanding is) and have kept Madhyamika doctrine and Vajrayana more distinct.


One formulation of Tibetan Madhyamaka explicitly based itself on tantric thinking. The “Great Madhyamakatradition understands Madhyamaka to include not only Nagarjuna but also the great Yogacara figures Asanga and Vasubandhu as the exemplary Madhyamikas. Here Nagarjuna's works from the analytic corpus serve to eliminate the hypostatizing that leads to a belief in the ultimate reality of things in the world, but his hymns express the final meaning of Madhyamaka, which is the perfected state purified of ignorance, identified with mind. Great Madhyamaka thought is characterized by its emphasis on “other-emptiness” (gzhan stong), which is the idea that the absolute is empty of conventional appearances but not of its own pure nature. This tradition is associated with Jonang Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen (1292-1361) and Taranatha (1575-1635), as well as the Sakya scholar Shakya Chokden (1428-1507).40 The tradition was highly influential in its time, but it was suppressed by the Fifth Dalai Lama and largely disappeared except for some regions along the Sino-Tibetan border. The 19th-century ecumenical movement (ris med) helped revive the knowledge of this once significant Madhyamaka vision, but it has received relatively little modern scholarly attention.


Review of the Literature

Most of the modern academic interest in Nagarjuna and the Madhyamaka has been philosophical, and over time what has been of philosophical interest has evolved. As extensively discussed in his influential book Comparative Philosophy and the Philosophy of Scholarship,41 Andrew Tuck has pointed out that early works tended to examine similarities between Madhyamaka and one or another European philosopher.


By the end of the 19th century, European interest in Indian religions had emerged as a positive byproduct of empire. Early Orientalists, most famously Sir William Jones, discovered that India had an ancient religious and philosophical heritage equal to, or in some more enthusiastic estimates superior to, those of the West. The objects of this newfound research were primarily the “orthodox” six schools of Hindu philosophy that contemporary Indian authorities presented as the heart and pinnacle of Indian thinking. Advaita Vedanta, again in accord with Indian assumptions of the time, became particularly sought after by Orientalist scholars and became popular among Western literati. Buddhism, on the other hand, was much more slowly acknowledged as a part of this grand intellectual history of India. It was the publication of Eugene Burnouf's Introduction a l’histoire du Buddhisme indien42 (1844) and his annotated translation of the Lotus Sutra (Saddharmapundarlkam) (1852) that brought Indian Buddhism into the spotlight and firmly established the idea that it was a thoroughly nihilist religion. Burnouf's sources included Perfection of Wisdom (Prajnaparamita) texts and Nagarjuna's Mulamadhyamakakarika with Candrakirti's commentary. Burnouf was not alone in his estimation of Buddhism as nihilism, and this understanding held sway in Europe throughout the 19th century.


In the early 20th century, the Belgian scholar Louis de La Vallee Poussin published what would become the definitive edition of Nagarjuna's Mulamadhyamakakarika, along with Candrakirti's commentary. La Vallee Poussin too saw Madhyamaka as pure nihilism, but he was a champion of Mahayana thought more broadly. It was the Russian scholar Fyodor Ippolitovich Shtcherbatsky who first challenged this view, arguing that Madhyamaka was in fact the Buddhist parallel of Advaita Vedanta and could best be understood via Kant's dichotomous notions of noumena and phenomena. Madhyamaka could thus be read as an ancient precursor of European idealist philosophy. Shtcherbatsky's understanding, fully explicated in his Conception of Buddhist Nirvana (1927),43 became the new standard view about Madhyamaka, and was taken up by the Indian scholar T. R. V. Murti in his influential work The Central Philosophy of Buddhism (1955),44 in which the author pushed further the linkage of Madhyamaka, Vedanta, and Kant.


Reacting to the influence of the analytic philosophy of G. E. Moore, Bertrand Russell, and the Vienna Circle, a new generation of scholars began to see Nagarjuna as a dialectician, and the interest in his works was focused on the structure of his arguments. Only two years after Murti's book, the American Buddhist scholar Richard Robinson published the article “Some Logical Aspects of Nagarjuna's System,”45 in which he surveyed previous scholarship on Madhyamaka and dismissed it as philosophically unsophisticated. Unlike his predecessors, Robinson was not looking for transcendent truths, or confirmation of consistency with dominant trends in Western philosophy. He argued for taking Nagarjuna's arguments on their own terms, in their own forms, which he elucidated with the aid of logical notation. In the end, Robinson's conclusion was that Nagarjuna failed to successfully refute his opponents because his method of argumentation was logically or formally invalid.


The next phase of reading and explicating Madhyamaka similarly reflected the contemporaneous concerns of Western philosophy. Influenced by the works of Quine, Sellars, and especially the later Wittgenstein, several scholars began to assert that concepts such as “language game,” “forms of life,” and “ordinary language” provided helpful models for understanding not only what Nagarjuna's arguments meant, but also what they were for. Such scholars46 saw parallels between the way Wittgenstein and Nagarjuna used language, but they also saw commonality with the primarily soteriological intent of Madhyamaka in Wittgenstein's famous statement on the purpose of philosophy, “To show the fly the way out of the fly-bottle.” Further emphasizing this soteriological dimension of Madhyamaka, Frederick Streng published the first full translation of the Mulamadhyamakakarika,47 and though he too quoted from Wittgenstein in his analysis, his primary concern was for understanding Madhyamaka and, especially, the concept of emptiness from a religious rather than a philosophical perspective.


In his seminal article “Nagarjuna's Appeal,”48 Richard Hayes nuances Tuck's thesis that interpretations of Madhyamaka are deeply informed by the ideological or methodological interest of the translators/interpreters by arguing that a number of Buddhist scholars have resisted this and produced translations or studies that place Nagarjuna's works solidly in their historical and cultural contexts. Hayes highlights the work of Stanislaw Schayer, David Seyfort Ruegg, Christian Lindtner, and Kamaleswar Bhattacharya as exemplars of the ideal of detached and scientific objectivity in Madhyamaka scholarship.


In recent decades, scholars have tried to avoid the pitfalls described by Tuck and Hayes and have also argued for a deeper engagement of modern philosophy with Madhyamaka, or with Buddhist thought more broadly. These works make a plea for the inclusion of Buddhist thought, and particularly Madhyamaka, into a more globally construed notion of philosophy and engage in both exegesis and interpretation. Publications of Mark Siderits,49 Jay Garfield,50 Jan Westerhoff,51 Amber Carpenter52 and Tom Tillemans53 are among the most significant examples of this recent phase of the study of Madhyamaka. These works typically situate Madhyamaka within its Buddhist historical context as well as interrogating the texts for their potential value to modes of modern thought.


In contemporary scholarship, the question of whether Madhyamaka thought is primarily about ultimate reality (the metaphysical interpretation) or what can be said about reality (the semantic interpretation) has become an important issue. In the past few decades the semantic interpretation has tended to predominate, but this approach is not unanimously accepted.


A recent locus of controversy in interpreting Madhyamaka has centered on the question of contradiction in Madhyamaka argumentation and the ultimate purport of such arguments. Against some scholars who regard contradictions in the texts as intended to be understood metaphorically, or as expressions of skillful means (upaya), Jay Garfield, along with coauthors Yasuo Deguchi and Graham Priest, argues that at least some contradictions in Madhyamaka texts should be taken literally and be accepted as true (the dialetheist interpretation). This interpretation provoked a number of critical responses, resulting in an entire issue of the journal Philosophy East and West devoted to these critiques, along with responses by Deguchi, Garfield, and Priest.55 Tillemans's article in this issue is an excellent example of another current interpretation that sees Madhyamaka arguments, at least in early Madhyamaka texts, as having as their purpose the complete elimination of all views about reality (the quietist interpretation). Other recent studies have been published that question Tibetan Madhyamikas' doxographical categories, which have been accepted and employed by much of modern scholarship.56 A renewed interest in the question of Madhyamaka's relation to the other major Mahayana doctrinal system, Yogacara, has also recently come to the fore.57


Primary Sources


All Buddhist traditions and modern scholarship agree that the founding author of Madhyamaka is Nagarjuna. From among his many works, it is similarly unanimous that his magnum opus is The Root Verses of the Middle Way (Mulamadhyamakakarika). The Sanskrit text was translated into other Asian languages, most importantly Chinese and Tibetan. Modern translations from each of these languages have been made into English and other European languages. At the current stage of Madhyamaka scholarship, the definitive English translation is the one by Mark Siderits and ShoryU Katsura.58 This translation is based on the Sanskrit original and the Tibetan translation, and utilizes all four extant Indian

commentaries in its insightful yet accessible commentary. The French translation from the Sanskrit by Guy Bugault59 is highly recommended, as is the pioneering translation from Sanskrit into Italian by Raniero Gnoli60 and the German translation from the Chinese by Lutz Geldsetzer.61 Nagarjuna's other works have often been traditionally divided into those with a methodological affinity to The Root Verses of the Middle Way (the analytic corpus), and his hymns and the collection of practical religious advice. Among the former, the most comprehensive and still classic collection by Lindtner62 is an excellent starting point for those wanting to explore these works. Though the hymns evince a very different picture of Madhyamaka, and they have received relatively little attention in modern scholarship, Tibetan traditions and many modern scholars accept them as authentic works of Nagarjuna. Lindtner's aforementioned collection includes two of the hymns, and Fernando Tola and Carmen Dragonetti's article63 contains translations and an exhaustive discussion of these works. Among the advice texts, the Ratnavali is widely regarded as an authentic composition of Nagarjuna and contains important similarities and complements to the Root Verses, though it is largely a text on ethics. The translation by Jeffrey Hopkins64 contains a commentary by Hopkins and an edition of the Tibetan text.


The difficulty of the subject matter and the terse style of the karika form of Indian literature led to numerous commentaries on Nagarjuna's texts, especially the Root Verses of the Middle Way. The Tibetan traditions and most modern scholarship typically accept that there are four Indian commentaries on the text: the Akutobhaya attributed to Nagarjuna himself, the Mulamadhyamakavrtti by Buddhapalita, the Prajnapradlpa of Bhaviveka, and the Prasannapada of Candrakirti. The two most important of these, and the ones that have received the greatest amount of scholarly attention, are the Prajnapradlpa and the Prasannapada. Their authors, Bhaviveka and Candrakirti, came to be seen by the Tibetan traditions as embodying two distinct schools of interpretation: the Svatantrika and Prasangika, with the latter occupying the peak of the doxographical hierarchy for nearly all of the Tibetan scholastic schools. The first seven chapters of the Prajnapradipa have been translated into English in a series of articles by William Ames,65 and a complete translation of the Prasannapada into European languages has come together through the complementary efforts of a number of excellent scholars.66


The Madhyamika works of Jnanagarbha, Santaraksita, and Kamalasila have received less attention in modern scholarship. Jnanagarbha's Distinction Between the Two Truths has been translated by Malcolm David Eckel (Satyadvayavibhahga') and is accompanied by a useful introduction.67 Masamichi Ichigo has published a helpful overview and full translation of Santaraksita's Ornament of the Middle Way.68 Though there are no complete translations of Kamalasila's Madhyamika works, portions are translated and discussed by Ichigo,69 Ryusei Keira,70 and Sara McClintock.71


Further Reading


Bocking, Brian, trans. Nagarjuna in China: A Translation of the Middle Treatise. Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 1995. K Find this resource: Brunnholzl, Karl. The Center of the Sunlit Sky: Madhyamaka in the Kagyu Tradition. Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2004. Find this resource: Cabezon, Jose Ignacio, and Geshe Lobsang Dargyay. Freedom from Extremes: Gorampa’sDistinguishing the Views” and the Polemics of Emptiness. Boston: Wisdom, 2007. Chandrakirti and Ju Mipham. Introduction to the Middle Way: Chandrakirti’s Madhyamakavatara with Commentary by Ju Mipham. Translated by Padmakara Translation Group. Boston and London: Shambhala, 2004.


Find this resource:


Eckel, Malcolm David. Jnanagarbha’s Commentary on the Distinction Between the Two Truths. SUNY Series in Buddhist Studies. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1987. Find this resource: Garfield, Jay L., and Jan Westerhoff. Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies or Rivals? Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2015. |(+) Find this resource: Hamilton, Sue. Indian Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2001. Find this resource: Hayes, Richard P. “Nagarjuna's Appeal.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (1994): 299-378.


Ichigo, Masamichi. “Santaraksita's Madhyamakalamkara: Introduction, Edition and Translation.” In Studies in the Literature of the Great Vehicle: Three Mahayana Buddhist Texts. Edited by Luis Gomez and Jonathan Silk, 141-240. Ann Arbor: Collegiate Institute for the Study of Buddhist Literature and Center for South and Southeast Asian Studies, University of Michigan, 1989. |(+) Find this resource: Komarovski, Yaroslav. Visions of Unity: The Golden Pandita Shakya Chokden’s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2012. [ I Find this resource: Google Preview WorldCat Lang, Karen C. Aryadeva’s Catuhsataka: On the Bodhisattva’s Cultivation of Method and Knowledge. Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag, 1986. Find this resource: Lindtner, Christian. Nagarjuniana: Studies in the Writings and Philosophy of Nagarjuna. New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987. |(+) Find this resource: Liu, Ming-Wood. Madhyamaka Thought in China. Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill, 1994. Find this resource: Lopez, Donald S.The Madman’s Middle Way: Reflections of Reality of the Tibetan Monk Gendun Chopel (Buddhism and Modernity). Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007. Find this resource: MacDonald, Anne. In Clear Words: The Prasannapada, Chapter One, Vols. I & II. Vienna: Verlag der Osterreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 2015. McClintock, Sarah, and Georges Dreyfus. The Svatantrika-Prasangika Distintion: What Difference Does a Difference Make? Boston: Wisdom, 2002. Find this resource: Nagao, Gadjin M.Madhyamika and Yogdcara: A Study of Mahayana Philosophies. Translated by Leslie Kawamura. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1991. Find this resource: Phuntsho, Karma. Mipham’s Dialectices and the Debates on Emptiness: To be, not to be, or neither. London and New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2005. |(+) Find this resource: Seyfort Ruegg, David. “The Uses of the Four Positions of the Catuhskoti and the Problem of the Description of Reality in Mahayana Buddhism.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 5 (1977): 1-71. K Find this resource: Seyfort Ruegg, David. The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India. A History of Indian Literature 7. Wiesbaden, Germany: Otto Harrassowitz, 1981. Find this resource: Siderits, Mark, and Shoryu Katsura. Nagarjuna’s Middle Way: The Mulamadhyamakakarika. Boston: Wisdom, 2013. |(+) Find this resource: Thupten Jinpa. Self, Reason, and Reality in Tibetan Philosophy: Tsongkhapa’s Quest for the Middle Way. Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2008. K Find this resource: Tillemans, Tom J. F.How Do Madhyamika’s Think: and Other Essays on the Buddhist Philosophy of the Middle. Boston: Wisdom, 2016. Find this resource: Tola, Fernando, and Carmen Dragonetti. “Nagarjuna's Catuhstava.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (1985): 1-54. |(+) Find this resource: Vose, Kevin. Resurrecting Candrakirti: Disputes in the Tibetan Creation of Prasangika. Boston: Wisdom, 2009. Find this resource: Westerhoff, Jan. Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction. Oxford and London: Oxford University Press, 2009. Find this resource:


Notes:


(1.) The Sanskrit term madhyamaka literally means just “middle,” but throughout English scholarship this has been translated as “middle way.” For the sake of consistency and clarity, “middle way” will be used throughout. (2.) Though many of the concepts discussed here are found in both Pali and Sanskrit sources, we will use the Sanskrit terms throughout, as Nagarjuna composed his texts in Sanskrit, and the Indian commentaries are in Sanskrit as well. (3.) Samyutta Nikaya, II.15 (5), in The Connected Discourses of the Buddha: A New Translation of the Samyutta Nikaya, trans. Bhikku Bodhi (Boston: Wisdom, 2000), 544. (4.) Ibid.

(5.) The notion of Buddhist doctrinal schools has been a commonplace in Buddhist scholarship both traditional and modern, but this idea should be handled cautiously. The term “Madhyamaka School” really only refers to a lineage of writers (often separated by centuries) who wrote commentaries on one or another of Nagarjuna's works, and that much later were placed into a doxographical category, primarily by the Tibetan traditions. See, for example, Ian Charles Harris, The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogacara in Indian Mahayana Buddhism (Leiden and New York: Brill, 1991); and Richard King, “Early Yogacara and Its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School,” Philosophy East and West 40 (1994): 659-683. (6.) For a helpful overview of Madhyamaka in China, see Dan Arnold, “Madhyamaka Buddhist Philosophy: Madhyamaka in East Asia,” in Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, eds. James Fieser and Bradley Dowden (2005).

(7.) For a discussion of this categorization, see David Seyfort Ruegg, The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India (A History of Indian Literature 7; Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz, 1981), 7-9. (8.) The inclusion of the Vyavaharasiddhi was favored by most Tibetan scholars, but Tsongkhapa and his followers preferred the Ratnavali as the sixth text of this category. See Karma Phuntsho, Mipham's Dialectics and the Debates on Emptiness: To Be, Not to Be, or Neither (London and New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2005), 235. (9.) For a discussion of the full implications of these verses, see Eviatar Shulman, “Creative Ignorance: Nagarjuna on the Ontological Significance of Consciousness,” Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 30. 1-2 (2009): 139¬173. (10.) A significant exception to this is Shulman, “Creative Ignorance.” (11.) Christian Lindtner, Nagarjuniana: Studies in the Writings and Philosophy of Nagarjuna (New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987), 31. (12.) Aryadeva, Bhaviveka, Candrakirti, Prajnakaramati and other Indian commentators cite one or more of these hymns and attribute them to Nagarjuna. For an overview of this issue, see Fernando Tola and Carmen Dragonetti, “Nagarjuna's Catuhstava,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (1985): 1-6.

(13.) The hymns are not found in the Chinese Buddhist canon. (14.) Samyutta Nikaya, II.15 (5), in The Connected Discourses of the Buddha: A New Translation of the Samyutta Nikaya, trans. Bhikku Bodhi (Boston: Wisdom, 2000), 544. (15.) Mark Siderits and Shoryu Katsura, Nagarjuna’s Middle Way: Mulamadhyamakakarika (Boston: Wisdom, 2013), 159. (16.) Ibid., 18. (17.) Ibid., 28. (18.) Ibid., 276-277. (19.) For a collection of essays on the status of conventional truth, see Cowherds, Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011). (20.) Siderits and Katsura, Nagarjuna's Middle Way, 277. (21.) Mark Siderits, Buddhism as Philosophy: An Introduction (Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett, 2007), 182. (22.) Siderits and Katsura, Nagarjuna's Middle Way, 13. (23.) Ibid., 197. (24.) Lindtner, Nagarjuniana, 63-64. (25.) Current scholarly consensus is that “Bhaviveka” is the proper spelling of this name, but earlier scholarship frequently used “Bhavaviveka,” or sometimes “Bhavya.” (26.) Siderits and Katsura, Nagarjuna's Middle Way, 304. (27.) Ibid., 315-316. (28.) Ibid., 334. (29.) Karen C. Lang, Aryadeva’s Catuhsataka: On the Bodhisattva’s Cultivation of Method and Knowledge (Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag, 1986). (30.) For a wide-ranging examination of the differences between these two schools, see Georges B. J. Dreyfus and Sara L. McClintock, eds., The Svatantika-Prasangika Distinction: What Difference Does a Difference Make? (Boston: Wisdom, 2003). (31.) For an English translation of the Middle Treatise, see Brian Bocking, trans., Nagarjuna in China: A Translation of the Middle Treatise (Lewiston, NY: Edwin Mellen, 1995).

(32.) For a translation of an important treatise of Sengzhao, see Walter Liebenthal, Chao Lun: The Treatises of Seng-chao: A Translation with Introduction, Notes and Appendices (2d rev. ed.; Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, 1968). For an article on Sengzhao's understanding of Madhyamaka, and the ways that his thought both remains true to the Indian sources, yet reflects Chinese religious and philosophical concerns, see Shohei Ichimura, “On the Paradoxical Method of the Chinese Madhyamika: Seng-chao and the Chao-lun Treatise,” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 19 (1992): 51-71. (33.) For an overview of the Sanlun School as well as later developments on Chinese Madhyamaka and its influence on other schools of Buddhism, see Ming-Wood Liu, Madhyamaka Thought in China (Leiden: Brill, 1994). (34.) There are many works in English on Tsongkhapa's formulation of Madhyamaka, but for a translation of his commentary on Nagarjuna's fundamental text, see Je Tsongkhapa, Jay L. Garfield, and Ngawang Samten, trans., Ocean of Reasoning: A Great Commentary on Nagarjuna’s Mulamadhyamakakarika (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006). (35.) For a translation of this work, see John Whitney Pettit, Mipham’s Beacon of Certainty: Illuminating the View of Dzogchen, the Great Perfection (Boston: Wisdom, 1999); for a comprehensive study of Mipham's Madhyamaka and his critiques of Tsongkhapa, see Phuntsho, Mipham’s Dialectics.

(36.) Chandrakirti and Jamgon Mipham, Introduction to the Middle Way: Chandrakirti’s Madhyamakavatara with Commentary by Jamgon Mipham, trans. Padmakara Translation Group (Boston and London: Shambhala, 2002). (37.) For a translation and study of this text, see Jose I. Cabezon and Geshe Lobsang Dargyay, trans., Freedom From Extremes: Gorampa'sDistinguishing the Views” and the Polemics of Emptiness (Boston: Wisdom, 2007). (38.) For English translations see Candrakirti and Mikyo Dorje, Ari Goldfield, Jules Levinson, Jim Scott, and Birgit Scott, trans., The Moon of Wisdom: Chapter Six of Chandrakirti's Entering the Middle Way with Commentary by the Eighth Karmapa Mikyo Dorje’s Chariot of the Dagpo Kagyu Siddhas (Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2005); and Dorje Wangchuk and Dewar Tyler, trans., The Karmapa's Middle Way: Feast for the Fortunate (Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2008). (39.) Among Nyingma scholars, Rongzom Chokyi Zangpo is an early and important figure in the establishment of the Nyingma Madhyamaka, and an example of the synthesis of Madhyamaka and Tantra. See Heidi I. Koppl, Establishing Appearances as Divine: Rongzom Chozang on Reasoning, Madhyamaka, and Purity (Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2008). (40.) For translations and studies of these two Jonang figures, see Cyrus Stearns, The Buddha from Dolpo: A Study of the Life and Thought of the Tibetan Master Dolpopa Sherab Gyaltsen (Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion, 2010); and Yaroslav Komarovski, Visions of Unity: The Golden Pandita Shakya Chokden’s New Interpretation of Yogacara and Madhyamaka (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2012). (41.) Andrew P. Tuck, Comparative Philosophy and the Philosophy of Scholarship: On the Western Interpretation of Nagarjuna (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990).

(42.) Eugene Burnouf, Introduction to the History of Indian Buddhism (Buddhism and Modernity), trans. Katia Buffetrille and Donald S. Lopez, Jr. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2015). (43.) Fyodor Shtcherbatsky, The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1968). (44.) T. R. V. Murti, The Central Philosophy of Buddhism (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1955). (45.) Richard H. Robinson, “Some Logical Aspects of Nagarjuna's System,” Philosophy East and West 6:4 (1957): 291-308. (46.) A number of scholars, including B. K. Matilal, Ives Waldo, Nathan Katz, and Robert Thurman, utilize Wittgenstein's thought, especially in the Philosophical Investigations, to unpack Nagarjuna's arguments and ultimate intent. For an extensive comparison of Nagarjuna and Wittgenstein, see Chris Gudmunsen, Wittgenstein and Buddhism (London: Macmillan, 1977). (47.) Frederick Streng, Emptiness: A Study in Religious Meaning (Nashville: Abingdon, 1967). (48.) Richard P. Hayes, “Nagarjuna's Appeal,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 22 (1994): 299-378. (49.) Siderits, Buddhism as Philosophy. (50.) Jay L. Garfield, Engaging Buddhism: Why It Matters to Philosophy (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2015). (51.) Jan Westerhoff, Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2005). (52.) Amber Carpenter, Indian Buddhist Philosophy (Ancient Philosophies; New York: Routledge, 2014). (53.) Tom J. F. Tillemans, How Do Madhyamika's Think: and Other Essays on the Buddhist Philosophy of the Middle (Boston: Wisdom, 2016). (54.) See, for instance, Giuseppe Ferraro, “A Criticism of M. Siderits' and J. L. Garfields ‘Semantic Interpretation' of Nagarjuna's Theory of Two Truths,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (2013): 195-219. For a much broader critique of modern understanding of Madhyamaka, see Shulman, “Creative Ignorance.”

(55.) Philosophy East and West 63.3 (2013) . (56.) See especially Kevin Vose, Resurrecting Candrakirti: Disputes in the Tibetan Creation of Prasangika (Boston: Wisdom, 2009). (57.) Jay L. Garfield and Jan Westerhoff, eds., Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies or Rivals? (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press 2015). (58.) Siderits and Katsura, Nagarjuna's Middle Way. (59.) Guy Bugault, ed., Stances du milieu par excellence (Paris: Gallimard, 2002). (60.) Raniero Gnoli, ed. and trans., Nagarjuna Madhyamaka Karika: Le stanze del cammino di mezzo (Enciclopedia di autori classici 61; Turin: P. Boringhieri, 1961).

(61.) Lutz Geldsetzer, ed. and trans., Die Lehre von der Mitte: Chinesisch-Deutsch (Philosophische Bibliotek 610; Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 2010). (62.) Lindtner, Nagarjuniana. (63.) Tola and Dragonetti, “Nagarjuna's Catuhstava.” (64.) Jeffrey Hopkins, Nagarjuna's Precious Garland: Buddhist Advice for Living and Liberation (Albany, NY: Snow Lion, 2007). (65.) William Ames, “Bhavaviveka's Prajnapradlpa: A Translation of Chapter One: ‘Examination of Causal Conditions' (Pratyaya), Part One,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 21 (1994): 209-259; “Bhavaviveka's Prajnapradlpa: A translation of Chapter Two: ‘Examination of the Traversed, the Untraversed, and That Which Is Being Traversed,'” Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (1995): 295-365; “Bhavaviveka's Prajnapradipa: A Translation of Chapter Three, Four, and Five: Examining the Ayatanas, Aggregates, and Elements,” Buddhist Literature 1 (1999): 1-119; “Bhavaviveka's Prajnapradlpa: A Translation of Chapters Six, Examination of Desire and the One Who Desires, and Seven, Examination of Origin, Duration and Cessation,” Buddhist Literature 2 (2000): 1-91.

(66.) J. W. de Jong, Cinq chapitres de la Prasannapada (Paris: Geuthner, 1949); Etienne Lamotte, “Le Traite de l'acte de Vasubandhu, Karmasiddhiprakarana,” Melanges Chinois et Bouddhiques 4 (1936): 265-288; Anne MacDonald, In Clear Words: The Prasannapada, Chapter One. Vols. I & II (Vienna: Verlag der Osterreichischen Akadamie der Wissenschaften, 2015); Jacques May, Candrakirti: Prasannapada Madhyamakavrtti, douze chapitre traduit du sanscrit et du tibetain (Paris: Adrien- Maisonneuve, 1959); Stanislaw Schayer, “Feuer und Brennstoff,” Rocznik Orientalistyczny 7 (1929-1930): 26-52; Stanislaw Schayer, Ausgewahlte Kapitel aus der Prasannapada (Krakow: Naktadem Polskiej Akademji Umiejetnosci, 1931); and Theodore Stcherbatsky, The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1977). (67.) Malcolm David Eckel, Jnanagarbha’s Commentary on the Distinction Between the Two Truths (SUNY Series in Buddhist Studies; Albany: State University of New York Press, 1987).


(68.) Masamichi Ichigo, “Santaraksita's Madhyamakalamkara: Introduction, Edition and Translation,” in Studies in the Literature of the Great Vehicle: Three Mahayana Buddhist Texts, eds. Luis Gomez and Jonathan Silk (Ann Arbor: Collegiate Institute for the Study of Buddhist Literature and Center for South and Southeast Asian Studies, University of Michigan, 1989), 141-240.


(69.) Masamichi Ichigo, “Santaraksita and Bhavaviveka as Opponents of the Madhyamika in the Madhyamakaloka,” in Wisdom, Compassion, and the Search for Understanding: The Buddhist Studies Legacy of Gadjin M. Nagao, ed. Jonathan Silk (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press, 2000), 147-170.

(70.) Ryusei Keira, Madhyamika and Epistemology: A Study of Kamalaslla’s Method for Proving the Voidness of All Dharmas: Introduction, Annotated Translations and Tibetan Texts of Selected Sections of the Second Chapter of the Madhyamakaloka (Vienna: Arbeitskreis fur Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien, 2004).


(71.) Sara L. McClintock, Omniscience and Rhetoric of Reason: Santaraksita and Kamalasila on Rationality, Argumentation and Religious Authority (Boston: Wisdom, 2010).


Paul B. Donnelly

Northern Arizona University




Source