Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Uhuuuuuu"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
Line 2: Line 2:
  
  
 +
puted for the [[sake]] of analysis. This problem is described in the next [[stanza]]. STANZA 70 /'[[jig rten]] [[pa yi]] [[chos]] bstan mi 'jig [[cing]]/ /[[yang dag]] [[nyid]] du nam [[yang]] [[chos]] l)bstan med/ /de bzhin gshegs 2)pas gsungs pa ma rig pas/ /de las [[dri med]] brjod pa 'di las skrag/ l)D:bsten 2)P:psa What is shown {{Wiki|conventionally}} to the [[world]] appears to be without {{Wiki|disintegration}}, but the [[Buddha]] has never actually shown anything with [[true existence]]. Those who do not understand what is explained by the Tathii­ [[gata]] to be {{Wiki|conventionally}} [[existent]] and [[empty]] of the sign of [[true existence]] are frightened by this [[teaching]]. Here we see that when making comparisons the [[Buddha]] and [[Nagarjuna]] seem to speak as if things were [[permanent]], that is, do not disintegrate, but this is only because conven­ tional {{Wiki|expressions}} make things seem [[permanent]]. Such [[permanence]] would imply [[true existence]] for things, which they never assert. [[People]] who make such interpretations merely demonstrate their lack of [[understanding]] of the Bud­ dha's {{Wiki|intentions}}. Furthermore, many of these [[people]] have a [[dangerous]] {{Wiki|misunderstanding}} of the [[middle way]], believing that [[non-existence]] is being [[taught]], when actually non­ [[inherent existence]] is being [[taught]]. They have fallen into the extreme of the [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] view, misinterpreting [[emptiness]] as indicating actual [[non-existence]], and this [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] [[attitude]] [[causes]] them to be {{Wiki|fearful}} when they hear the [[Buddha]] teach about [[non-inherent]] [[existence]]. Another misinterpretation would be to take the [[Buddha's teaching]] about [[causality]] at face value, {{Wiki|forgetting}} his chief underlying [[thought]]. This is discussed in the next [[stanza]]. STANZA 7 1
  
same, then we cannot differentiate between them. Yet, if our {{Wiki|examination}} shows them to have [[inherent existence]] and to be different, then they will be completely unrelated, like a [[tree]] and a [[vase]]. But this is [[contradictory]] because compos­ ite and non-composite [[phenomena]] are known through their [[relation]] to each other and we cannot find a composite [[phenomenon]] with a self-sufficient [[existence]] which doesn't depend on non-composite [[phenomena]]. If the opponent accepts our argument up to this point, he may still assert that composite [[phenomena]], at any rate, have [[inherent existence]]. Therefore we ask: within the context of your [[belief]] in [[inherent existence]], does a composite phe­ nomenon arise which is already [[existent]], or does a compos­ ite [[phenomenon]] arise which lacks [[existence]], or does a composite [[phenomenon]] arise which is both [[existent]] and [[non-existent]]? If a composite [[phenomenon]] [[exists]] inherently, it would [[exist]] from the beginning, so it would have no need to arise. But if it doesn't [[exist]] inherently, then it couldn't come into [[existence]] because it would be [[non-existent]] for­ ever. Nor is it possible for a [[phenomenon]] to be both [[existent]] and [[non-existent]] as these are [[contradictory]] assertions in [[relation]] to a single [[object]]. Thus we have shown that all composite and non­ composite [[phenomena]] lack [[inherent existence]], and since composite [[phenomena]] are [[compounded]] of parts and parti­ cles, all these must also lack [[inherent existence]]. STANZA 33 The opponent now offers [[reasons]] to prove that [[phenomena]] [[exist]] inherently. /bcom ldan [[bla mas]] las [[gnas]] dang/ /las [[bdag]] las kyi [['bras bu]] dang/ /[[sems can]] rang gi las dang nil /las [[rnams]] chud mi l )za bar gsungs/ l)D:bra Opponent: The Peerless Subduer has [[taught]] that
+
I' di la brten nas 'di 'byung zhes/
  
146
+
1 80
  
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]] there is continuity in the flow of [[actions]]. Likewise, he has [[taught]] about the [[nature]] of [[actions]] and their results. He has also [[taught]] that the results of [[actions]] performed by an {{Wiki|individual}} [[sentient being]] must be [[experienced]] by him and that whatever [[actions]] are performed 2)are certain to bear fruit. For these four [[reasons]] [[actions]] have [[inherent existence]]. 2)Lit: chud mi za bar, will not be wasted.
+
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]] /'[[jig rten]] tshul 'di mi 'gog [[cing]]/ / l)gang brten [[rang bzhin med]] 2)pas de/ /ji ltar [[yod]] 'gyur [[de nyid]] nges/ l)P:kang 2)P:bas It is known in the way of the [[world]] that "this arises in [[dependence]] on that." Such statements are not refuted. But whatsoever arises dependently does not [[exist]] in­ herently, and how can that [[non-inherent]] [[existence]] itself have [[inherent existence]]? In fact, that non­ [[inherent existence]] must definitely not [[exist]] in­ herently!
  
The opponent believes that because the [[Buddha]] spoke of a continuity in the flow of [[actions]], this means that these [[actions]] endure and have [[inherent existence]]. Continuity in the flow of [[actions]] is understood to mean, for example, that whatever [[actions]] we perform to [[accumulate]] [[wealth]] will bear some fruit in the {{Wiki|future}}, even though at [[death]] the [[wealth]] we have [[accumulated]] will have to be left behind. The opponent believes that this [[teaching of the Buddha]] shows that such [[actions]] must have the [[nature]] of [[inherent existence]] or else they could not endure into the {{Wiki|future}}. Furthermore, the [[Buddha]] [[taught]] that there is {{Wiki|certainty}} that the result of [[actions]] will have to be [[experienced]] by the one who per­ formed them. For example, if a [[person]] performs nonvir­ tuous [[actions]] and does not apply the four powerful anti­ dotes but continues to perform [[nonvirtuous actions]], then it is certain that that [[person]] will [[experience]] bad {{Wiki|consequences}}. Since the [[Buddha]] has [[taught]] about [[actions]] in these ways, the opponent takes this as a [[proof]] that [[actions]] must have [[inherent existence]]. STANZA 34 We agree with the opponent that [[Buddha]] [[taught]] about the law of [[action]] and result, but we disagree with him in that we believe that [[Buddha]] [[taught]] these things {{Wiki|conventionally}}, but not ultimately. So where the opponent [[understands]] the [[Buddha's]] use of the term "[[existence]]" to mean [[inherent existence]], we understand the [[Buddha]] to mean [[conventional existence]]. We point out that the [[Buddha]] [[taught]] that all
+
Here [[Nagarjuna]] reminds his auditors that [[causality]], which in [[reality]] is [[dependent arising]], is itself without inher­ ent [[existence]]. It would also be a mistake to believe that the [[non-inherent]] [[existence]] of [[dependent arising]] itself had [[true existence]], when in [[actuality]] it too must be without [[inherent existence]]. In another context this is known as the [[emptiness]] of [[emptiness]]. Both are refutations of a {{Wiki|subtle}} {{Wiki|eternalist}} [[interpretation]] of a [[teaching]] meant to refute {{Wiki|eternalism}}. In the last two [[stanzas]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] on Empti­ ness, [[Nagarjuna]] moves on from this point and summarizes the way in which his [[middle view]] leads to a nirviiQ.a which is {{Wiki|superior}} to the nirviiQ.a of the [[lesser vehicle]] because it does not postulate the extreme view which asserts an actual non-cyclic [[existence]]. STANZA 72 /dad ldan [[de nyid]] l )[[chos]] 2)la brtson/ /3)tshul 'di [[rigs]] pas rjes 4)dpogs gang/ /S)rten med [[chos]] 6)'ga' 7)bstan [[pa yi]]/ /srid dang srid min spangs nas zhi/ l)P:tshol 2)D:lar rtson 3)P:chu la 4)P:dbogs S)D:brten 6)P,D:'gal 7)D:brtan
 +
 
 +
Those who have [[faith]] in the [[teaching]] of [[emptiness]] will strive for it through a number of different kinds of {{Wiki|reasoning}}. Whatever they have understood about it in
  
 
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
 
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
  
147
+
181
 +
 
 +
terms of [[non-inherent]] [[existence]], they clarify this for others, which helps others to attain 8)nirvii1J.ll by [[abandoning]] [[grasping]] at the apparently [[true existence]] of [[cyclic existence]] and non-cyclic [[existence]]. 8)Lit: zhi; [[tranquility]]. STANZA 73 I'di dag [[rkyen]] 'di las 1 )rig nas/ /lta [[ngan]] [[dra ba]] kun ldog des/ /[[chags]] rmongs [[khong khro]] spangs pa'i [[phyir]]/ /ma gos mya [[ngan]] [['das]] pa thob/ 1)D:rigs
 +
 
 +
By [[seeing]] these internal and external [[phenomena]] [[arising]] from [[causes and conditions]] they will eliminate the whole network of [[wrong views]]. With the elimina­ tion of [[wrong views]] they will have abandoned attach­ ment, closed-mindedness and [[hatred]] and thereby attain nirvii1Jil unstained by [[wrong views]]. The clarification for others which is referred to in [[stanza]] 72 is not considered by [[Tibetans]] to be an act of [[compassion]], or of [[bodhicitta]], but a simple [[offering]] of the [[teaching]] which is an offshoot of the practitioner's [[own]] striving for under­ [[standing]] through {{Wiki|reasoning}}. [[Tibetans]] hold two [[views]] on [[Nagarjuna's]] [[teaching]] about [[great compassion]]. One group asserts that [[compassion]] is implied in texts such as the Mulamadhyamakakiirikii and the [[Seventy Stanzas]] on Empti­ ness, while another group asserts that such texts are strictly [[philosophical]] and that [[Nagarjuna's]] teachings about com­ [[passion]] are to be found in other texts, such as Ratniivali, or [[Sutrasamuccaya]]. In any case, whatever our opinion on this [[subject]] may be, it is clear that here, in the concluding fifteen [[stanzas]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]], Nagar­ juna has demonstrated the {{Wiki|practical}} implications of adopt­ ing the [[correct view]] of the [[middle way]]. For this view, implemented by [[meditative practice]], will free the [[yogi]] from [[grasping]] after [[cyclic existence]] and set him on the [[path]] to nirvai].a.
 +
 
 +
1 82
 +
 
 +
Niigiirjuna' s [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
composite or produced [[phenomena]] are [[impermanent]]. He also said that [[impermanent]] [[phenomena]] lack [[inherent]] exist­ ence. Because all [[actions]] are [[impermanent]] [[phenomena]], so they must be devoid of [[inherent existence]]. If they did [[exist]] inherently then they couldn't be [[impermanent]] [[phenomena]] because [[phenomena]] which [[exist]] inherently should not undergo change. /las [[rnams]] [[rang bzhin med]] gsungs te/ /[[ma skyes]] gang de chud mi zal /de las [[kyang]] ni [[bdag 'dzin]] skye/ /de bskyed '[[dzin]] de'ng [[rnam rtog]] las/ Reply: [[Buddha]] [[taught]] that [[actions]] do not [[exist]] in­ herently and so they cannot arise inherently . Although [[actions]] do not [[exist]] inherently, they will not be wasted but it is certain that they will bear fruit. From these [[actions]] arise [[consciousness]], [[name and form]], and the rest of the limbs of [[dependent origination]]. {{Wiki|Conception}} of [[self]] l )is generated through focusing on the [[person]] who is merely [[imputed]] upon these dependent limbs. Also, it arisesfrom the precon­ ception which takes improper [[objects]] and overesti­ mates them. l)Lit: skye, arises. STANZA 35 /gal te las la [[rang bzhin]] yodl /de l)bskyed lus ni rtag par 'gyur/ /las [[kyang]] [[sdug bsngal]] [[rnam]] [[smin]] can/ /mi 'gyur de [[phyir]] [[bdag]] tu 'gyur/ l)D:bskyes
+
THE COLOPHON /[[stong nyid]] [[bdun]] cu 1)pa'i tshig le'ur [[byas pa]] [[zhes bya]] ha/slob dpon [['phags pa]] [[klu sgrub]] [[kyis]] [[mdzad pa]] [[rdzogs]] so/lo tsa' ba [[gzhon nu mchog]] dang/ 2)gnyan [[dharma]] grags dang khu'i 'gyur dag las don dang tshig bzang du bris pa'o 1 )P omits 2)D:snyan dar ma These [[Seventy Stanzas]] Explaining How [[Phenomena]] Are [[Empty]] Of [[Inherent]] [[Existence]] have been written by the [[Teacher]] A rya Niigiirjuna and compiled by an unknown editor who referred to the better wordings and meanings of the translations by the [[translators]] [[Gzhon nu]] mchog, [[Gnyan]] [[dharma]] grags and Khu. [[Nagarjuna's]] seventy three [[stanzas]] were translated into English in the years 1 982 and 1983 by the [[Venerable]] [[Geshe Sonam Rinchen]], the [[Venerable]] Tenzin Dorjee and David Ross Komito at the {{Wiki|Library of Tibetan Works and Archives}} in {{Wiki|Dharamsala}}, [[India]]. The commentary on the seventy three [[stanzas]] is based on the oral explanations given by [[Geshe Sonam Rinchen]] while the translation was in prog­ ress and later edited by David Komito. The [[root]] [[stanzas]] and commentary were then orally retranslated into [[Tibetan]] and corrected by [[Geshe Sonam Rinchen]]. Our translation and [[interpretation]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] pri­ marily follows the [[traditions]] of [[Sera Monastery]], [[Lhasa]], [[Tibet]], and that given by [[Candrakirti]] in his ShUnyatiisaptati­ [[vrtti]] ([[sTong pa nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i 'grel pa) and secondarily follows that given by [[Parahita]] in his ShUnyatiisaptativivrtti ([[sTong pa nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i [[rnam]] par [[bshad pa]]). Italicized words in the English translation of the [[root]] [[stanzas]] corres­ pond to those [[Tibetan]] words which actually appear in the [[Tibetan]] [[root]] [[stanzas]]; words which are not italicized in the English translation of the [[root]] [[stanzas]] are interpolations placed in the [[stanzas]] in order to clarify their meaning and are based on the commentaries and on [[oral tradition]].
  
If [[actions]] were to have [[inherent existence]] then they would not be [[impermanent]] but would have the [[nature]] of [[permanence]], and then the [[body]] which results from those [[actions]] would also be [[permanent]]. If [[actions]] were to be 2)permanent then they could not
+
[[Chapter]] Three The [[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
  
148
+
1 83
  
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]] give rise to [[suffering]], which is the ripening of [[actions]]. If [[actions]] were non-changing then they would have the [[nature]] of [[permanence]] and then they would have self-existence. But then [[Buddha]] would not have [[taught]] about the lack of [[self-nature]]. 2)Lit: mi 'gyur, unchangeable.
+
Section 3-1 Treatises by [[Nagarjuna]] [[Nagarjuna]], who seems to have lived in the second century, may be regarded as the father of philo­ sophical [[Mahayana]]. We know little or nothing a­ bout the circumstances of his [[life]], and the legendary reports to be found in the works of [[Taranatha]] and other [[Tibetan]] {{Wiki|historians}} obviously refer chiefly to a later [[Nagarjuna]], a [[Tantric]] and sorcerer, whose fig­ ure has become merged into that of the earlier [[philosophical]] [[Nagarjuna]] in the [[consciousness]] of lat­ ter times. 1 Lamentably, this situation of minimal clarity concerning the details of the [[life]] of [[Nagarjuna]] has not-altered since 1956 when these words were written. Perhaps we shall never have much in the way of facts about [[Nagarjuna's]] [[life]] due to the general disinterest of {{Wiki|Indians}} in historical or "biographi­ cal" records. K. Inada's work NO,garjuna (1970) contains a [[bibliography]] which lists all the significant articles and [[books]] which deal with such biographical concerns up to the date of its publication. If we survey these citations, we find a veritable quagmire of conflicting opinions. [[Robinson]] has quoted a number of these alternative [[views]] on pages 2 1 to 26 of his work Early [[Madhyamika]] in [[India]] and [[China]]. From
  
There must be a correspondence between [[cause]] and re­ sult, which is why, for example, [[nonvirtuous actions]] give rise to [[suffering]]. Following this [[principle]], if the opponent asserts that [[actions]] have [[inherent existence]], then so must their results. This means that the [[body]], which is the result of previous [[actions]], would have to [[exist]] inherently. Moreover, if [[actions]] existed inherently, then they would be [[permanent]], and so would their results, which means that the [[body]] would be [[permanent]]. This is clearly false. Also, if [[actions]] were [[permanent]] they could not give rise to [[suffering]] because [[permanent]] [[phenomena]] cannot give rise to results. This is because [[permanent]] [[phenomena]] do not change, but for there to be some [[arising]] there must be some change. Thus, [[actions]] cannot be [[permanent]], because ac­ tions do produce [[suffering]]. The [[Buddha]] [[taught]] that all composite [[phenomena]] are [[impermanent]], and whatever is [[impermanent]] has a [[suffering]] [[nature]]. Because whatever has a [[suffering]] [[nature]] lacks self­ [[existence]], so [[actions]] must lack a [[self-nature]]. STANZA 36 In the previous [[stanza]] we proved that [[actions]] lack [[inherent existence]] by demonstrating the fallacies which result from such a view. Now, taking another [[reason]], we will again prove that [[actions]] lack [[inherent existence]]. /las ni [[rkyen]] skyes [[yod]] min [[zhing]]/ /[[rkyen]] min las skyes cung [[zad]] 1 )min/ I'du [[byed]] [[rnams]] ni [[sgyu ma]] dang/ /dri za'i [[grong]] [[khyer]] smig rgyu mtshungsi 1)P,D:med
+
185
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
186
  
149
+
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
If [[actions]] were to [[exist]] at the time of [[conditions]], those [[actions]] could not arise from those [[conditions]]. And if [[conditions]] do not have the potential to give rise to [[actions]], then [[actions]] cannot arise from condi­ tions because those [[conditions]] are similar to non­ [[conditions]]. Because [[actions]] cannot arise even slightly from non-conditions, so therefore all composite phe­ nomena are [[like an illusion]], and a [[gandharva]] town and a [[mirage]], and therefore they lack [[inherent]] ex­ istence. If [[actions]] [[exist]] inherently, do they arise from [[causes and conditions]] or not? If we answer that [[actions]] arise from [[conditions]], then we must ask whether [[actions]] arise at the time of [[conditions]] or not. If an [[action]] does arise at the time of its [[conditions]], then there is no need for the [[conditions]], because the [[action]] is already [[existent]] at that time. If it doesn't, then the [[conditions]] have ceased when the [[action]] arises, so the [[conditions]] cannot serve their function in giv­ ing rise to the [[action]]. In this case, it is like a non-condition. It is impossible for [[actions]] to arise from non-conditions. Hence they lack [[inherent existence]]. All composite phe­ nomena are [[empty of inherent existence]] like [[illusions]] and mirages, etc. Here we are showing that [[actions]] lack [[inherent existence]], but this does not mean that they are completely non­ [[existent]]. Rather, they are non-inherently [[existent]], like illu­ sions and mirages. STANZA 37 /las ni [[nyon mongs]] [[rgyu mtshan]] can/ /[[nyon mongs]] [['du byed]] las [[bdag]] nyidl /lus ni lus kyi [[rgyu mtshan]] can/ /[[gsum]] ka'ng [[ngo bo nyid]] [[kyis]] stong/
+
his summary it can be seen that [[scholars]] are unlikely to ever establish anything like a {{Wiki|factual}} {{Wiki|biography}} of [[Nagarjuna]]. I will simply follow the opinion of the majority of [[scholars]] and place his [[activities]] between 1 50 and 250 A.D. in [[India]]. As to the details of his [[life]], I shall simply refer the reader to the above-mentioned references, as such details are second­ ary to our concerns in this [[book]]. The difficulty of identifying the [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] works of the second century [[Nagarjuna]] is clearly a more relevant issue, and is connected with the problem of establishing the best redaction of the text of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] for translation purposes. Some of the works in the [[Tibetan canon]] which are attributed to [[Nagarjuna]] have a clearly [[tantric]] [[character]], and obviously belong to a later [[Nagarjuna]]. For other works, such a method of {{Wiki|discrimination}} is not applicable, for their content is not so clearly [[tantric]]. The method typically adopted by the most discriminating [[Tibetan]] authorities, as well as by many {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]], is to only accept as [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] those works whose style and content closely agree with the [[Mulamadhyamakakarika]] ([[Mula]]). Thus, in [[essence]], [[Nagarjuna]] is defined as being the author of the [[Mula]], and any work which appears to accept or propose [[views]] other than those in the M ula is by [[definition]] authored by someone other than the [[Nagarjuna]] of the second century, and is not considered "[[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]]. " Such a method has its [[own]] strengths and weaknesses. Its strength lies in its exclusion of such clearly inappropriate works as those of the [[tantra class]], for the [[tantric]] {{Wiki|literature}} is, by common agreement of all {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]], a develop­ ment which postdates the second century [[Nagarjuna]], no {{Wiki|matter}} in what {{Wiki|era}} its [[roots]] may lie. The weakness of this method lies in the tendency of some [[scholars]] to exclude works which seem to have minimal {{Wiki|emphasis}} on the pras­ aJiga style of [[exposition]]. Thus, if a work seems to make some positive assertions or to have some [[Cittamatra]] tenden­ cies, for example, these [[scholars]] would have to consider it to be inauthentic. The problem here is that [[Nagarjuna]]
  
[[Actions]] are [[caused]] by [[delusions]]. Our [[body]] arises from the [[nature]] of [[delusions]] and [[actions]]. Because the [[cause]] of the [[body]] is [[actions]], and [[actions]] arise from delu-
+
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
  
1 50
+
1 87
  
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]] sions, so therefore these three are devoid of [[inherent existence]].
+
preceded such {{Wiki|sectarian}} splits in the Mahiiyana {{Wiki|stream}} which he so influenced. As the general approach I follow in this [[book]] is to express the [[views]] of [[Tibetan scholars]], I will also do so in regards to the question of determining what are the [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] works of [[Nagarjuna]]. {{Wiki|Modern}} [[scholarly]] opinion may disagree with the [[views]] of [[Tibetan scholars]], and, indeed, often such {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholarly]] opinion is not unanimous on a variety of issues. [[Lindtner]] has a very useful summary of the opinions of {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]] concerning the authenticity of various works attributed to [[Nagarjuna]]. 2 But since our general pur­ pose is to {{Wiki|present}} the [[Tibetan]] [[scholarly]] view, such disagree­ ments only become relevant in regards to questions about the authenticity of the so-called "autocommentary" (Shiinya­ ttisaptativrtti) to the [[Seventy Stanzas]] and its appropriate­ ness for establishing the text of the [[Seventy Stanzas]], so I will simply refer the [[interested]] reader to Lindtner's summary. As to the authenticity of the "autocommentary" to the [[Seventy Stanzas]], I will return to this problem shortly. If we turn to the writings of [[Tibetan]] authorities on [[Nagarjuna]], we will find that there is a group of works which they all attribute to him and there is a second group of works which is considered [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] by some and is rejected by others. [[Bu ston]], in his [[History of Buddhism]] ([[Chos 'byung]]) indi­ cates that there are " . . . six main treatises of the Madhyami­ ka [[Doctrine]] (by [[Nagarjuna]]) demonstrating that, which is expressed by the sii.tras directly, or otherwise, the [[essential meaning]] (of the [[Doctrine]]). " [sic] 3 They are, in the order which he gives them: [[Shunyatasaptati]], Prajiiamula, Yuk­ tishash#ka, [[Vigrahavyavartani]], Vaidalyasu.tra and Vyavahara­ [[siddhi]]. He further states that [[Shunyatasaptati]] expounds " . . . the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[Relativity]] [shii.nyata] of all [[elements of existence]], devoid of the extremities of [[causality]] ([[rten 'brel]]) and [[pluralism]] ([[spros pa]]) . . . "4 "Tson[g] kha pa in his [[Gser]] phren says that the sixth work is considered by some to be the Vyavahara-siddhi, by
  
In the previous [[stanza]] we have seen that [[actions]] have [[non-inherent]] [[existence]], a type of [[existence]] which is like a [[mirage]]. Now Niigarjuna shows us that these non-inherently [[existing]] [[actions]] are [[caused]] by [[delusions]], and that these two are, in their turn, the [[cause]] of the [[body]]. Because [[body]] [[exists]] in [[dependence]] on [[actions]] and [[actions]] [[exist]] in depend­ ence o>J. [[delusion]] and because we have already seen that [[actions]] lack [[inherent existence]], so all these three lack inher­ ent [[existence]]. This is because whatever [[exists]] in depend­ ence on something must lack {{Wiki|independent}}, [[inherent]] exist­ ence. Applying this [[principle]] to the [[relation]] of [[delusion]] and [[action]], it can be seen that since [[action]] lacks [[inherent]] exist­ ence, so too must its [[cause]], [[delusion]]. STANZA 38 Our opponent says that [[actions]] are [[inherently existent]] be­ [[cause]] a [[person]] who is dominated by [[ignorance]] is the perform­ er of unmeritorious [[actions]] and accumulates them. As he [[exists]], [[actions]] [[exist]] to produce results which would be [[experienced]] by him. /las med na ni [[byed]] po med/ /de [[gnyis med]] pas [['bras bu]] med/ /de med nye bar [[spyod]] l)po med/ /de bas [[dngos po]] [[dben pa]] [[yin]]/ l)D:pa, P:bo When [[actions]] do not have [[inherent existence]] there will be no [[person]] to perform [[actions]]. Because both of them do not [[exist]], results do not [[exist]]. When there are no results there will be no [[person]] to [[experience]] those results {{Wiki|physically}} and [[mentally]]. Because of that [[reason]] that [[actions]] do not [[exist]] inherently, so all [[phenomena]] are devoid of [[inherent existence]]. Since [[actions]] are devoid of [[inherent existence]] there can
+
188
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
15 1
+
others - the Akutobhayii or the Ratniivali, but that it is not correct to insist upon the number of treatises as being six. "5 And he adds, in his [[rTsa]] she ti ka [[chen]] [[rigs pa'i rgya mtsho]], that the [[Seventy Stanzas]] was written in response to an objection raised concerning [[chapter]] seven of the [[Mula]]. 6 [[Taranatha]] mentions "five fundamental works" which according to Walleser does not include Vyavahiirasiddhi. 7 According to Obermiller, this work was never translated into [[Tibetan]]. 8 [[Atisha]] also lists the important treatises of [[Nagarjuna]]. In his [[Lamp]] of the [[Enlightenment]] [[Path]] ([[Byang chub lam gyi sgron ma]]), which is a signally important work for [[Tibetan Buddhism]], he mentions only two works by [[Nagarjuna]]: [[Seventy Stanzas]] and [[Mula]]. 9 In his autocommentary to that work ([[Byang chub]] lam gyi [[sgron]] ma'i dka' 'grel) he expands upon this grouping, stating that similar to these two are Akutobhayii, Vigrahavyiivartani, Yuktishash#kii, Ratniivali, Mahiiyiinavi'f!lshikii, Ak�arashqtaka and Shiilistambakati­ kii. 10 Taking the {{Wiki|Chinese}} point of view, [[Robinson]] notes that " . . . the basic [[stanzas]] in the [[Three Treatises]] [i.e. , the [[Madhyamika school]]] are the work of [[Nagarjuna]] and [[Aryadeva]] and correspond fairly closely with counterparts in [[Sanskrit]] and [[Tibetan ]]. . . " 11 One of these treatises is called the Twelve Topics ([[Shih-erh-men-lun]], [[Taisho]] # 1568). As it quotes the eighth and nineteenth [[stanzas]] from the [[Seventy Stanzas]] and was itself translated by [[Kumarajiva]], we have an established later limit for the composition of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] and a further attestation of its authenticity. Thus, if we define [[Nagarjuna]] as being the indiviaual who authored the M ula, then he certainly is also the same [[Nagarjuna]] who authored the [[Seventy Stanzas]], and accord­ ing to the consensus of the indigenous experts, this same [[person]] also authored Yuktishash#kii, Vigrahavyiivartani and Vaidalyasutra. These are the agreed upon five fundamental treatises which comprise a class with certain authorship. The second class of works, accepted as [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] by some experts but not considered [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] by others would in.
  
be no [[truly existent]] [[person]] to perform [[actions]], but only an [[illusory]], {{Wiki|conventionally}} [[existent]] [[person]] (which is described in [[stanzas]] 40-42). The results of the [[actions]] of such an [[illusory]] [[person]] are also, still in a {{Wiki|metaphoric}} [[sense]], [[illusory]]; that is, they are devoid of [[inherent existence]]. As we have already seen, the [[body]] and the [[mind]], which are interdepend­ ent, lack [[inherent existence]], so there is no truely [[existent]] [[person]] having [[body]] or [[mind]] to [[experience]] the results of previous [[actions]]. But there is a {{Wiki|conventionally}} [[existent]] per­ son having [[body]] and [[mind]] which does [[experience]] the con­ ventionally [[existent]] results of {{Wiki|conventionally}} [[existent]] ac­ tions. STANZA 39 /las ni stong par [[yang dag]] 1)par/ /shes na [[de nyid]] [[mthong]] ba'i [[phyir]]/ /las 2)mi 'byung [[ste]] de med nal /las las 'byung gang mi 'byung ngo/ 1)D:pa'i 2)D:ni
+
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
  
[[understands]] how [[actions]] are 3)devoid of inher­ ent [[existence]], then he sees the [[suchness]] of [[actions]]. When he has seen [[suchness]] he will have eliminated If one
+
189
  
[[ignorance]] and when there is no [[ignorance]] then the [[actions]] which are [[caused]] by [[ignorance]] cannot arise in him, and so 4)the results of [[actions]] such as conscious­ ness and so forth up to [[aging and death]] will not be [[experienced]] by him. When [[consciousness]] ceases to [[exist]] the dependent limb of [[aging and death]] cannot occur; thus he will attain the [[state of liberation]] free from [[aging and death]]. 3)Lit: yan dag; real or {{Wiki|perfect}}. The real [[nature]] of [[actions]] is their being devoid of [[inherent]] exist­ ence. 4)Lit: las las 'byung gang; that which ori­ ginates from [[actions]]. [[Actions]] cannot arise without a [[cause]], so when one has understood how [[actions]] are devoid of [[inherent existence]]
+
elude : Vyavah arasiddhi, A k u to b haya, R a tnavali, Mahayanavi�shika, Ak�arashataka and Shalistambakatika. Note that the "autocommentary" to the [[Seventy Stanzas]] is not included in either of these classes and that the Aku­ tobhaya, which is an "autocommentary" to the [[Mula]], is not considered by all authorities to have been authored by [[Nagarjuna]]. Besides the karika(s) of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] itself ({{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5227), the [[bsTan 'gyur]] contains three commentaries on the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. The so called "autocommentary" is titled Shunyatasaptativrtti ([[sTong pa nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i 'grel pa; {{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5231); it is attributed to [[Nagarjuna]]. There is another and longer work of the same title which is au­ thored by [[Candrakirti]] ({{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5268). The third com­ mentary is called Shunyatasaptativivrtti ([[sTong pa nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i [[rnam]] par [[bshad pa]]; {{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5269), and is authored by Parahita(bhadra). All three commentaries on the [[Seventy Stanzas]], as well as the isolated karika(s) themselves, are extant only in [[Tibetan]]. 12 Just one [[karika]] has survived in [[Sanskrit]], which is quoted in the [[Prasannapada]]. 13 Although the [[Seventy Stanzas]] was translated into {{Wiki|Chinese}}, it has since been lost, 14 except for the two karika(s) found in the Twelve Topic Treatise. 15 In addition to the redaction of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] kari­ ka(s) in an isolated [[form]], each of the three commentaries also contains a version of the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. As Ruegg says, " . . . the variations between these versions pose a num­ ber of philological and historical problems . . . . The version accompanying the [[Tibetan translation]] of [[Candrakirti's]] com­ mentary, and hence this commentary itself, differs from the version accompanying the commentary ascribed to Nagar­ juna; and the question arises as to whether [[Candrakirti]] knew this commentary or [[recognized]] it to be by [[Nagarjuna]]. " 16 I will investigate some ofthese historical and philological problems in the [[balance]] of this [[chapter]]. A parallel to the problem of the authenticity of the "auto­ commentary" to the [[Seventy Stanzas]] is the problem of the
  
152
+
1 90
  
 
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
 
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
and seen the [[suchness]] of [[actions]], then [[meditating]] on it one can eliminate the [[ignorance]] of [[grasping]] at the [[inherent existence]] of [[actions]] and since this [[ignorance]] is the [[cause]] of contaminated [[actions]], so then such [[actions]] cannot arise. When contaminated [[actions]] cannot arise then their results, such as [[consciousness]] and so forth up to [[aging and death]], also cannot arise and in that case one has achieved libera­ tion. However, a [[person]] who achieves [[liberation]] does not be­ come absolutely [[non-existent]]. In fact, such a [[person]] will take [[rebirths]] in [[dependence]] upon his uncontaminated ac­ tions and thereby work for others. As he has abandoned delusive [[obscurations]] he won't be influenced by them in his [[activities]]. Therefore, his [[actions]] become [[virtuous]]. Any other view would be [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] because if one could not perform [[actions]] after [[attaining]] the [[liberation]] which comes from destroying [[ignorance]], then one couldn't work for the [[benefit]] of others. Within the context of the twelve dependent limbs, the dependent limb of [[consciousness]] does not refer to con­ sciousness in general but rather refers specifically to the sixth, [[mental consciousness]] (yid kyi [[rnams]] par [[shes pa]]), which is associated with the [[mind]] [[sense organ]]. This con­ sciousness receives the imprints of [[virtuous]] and nonvir­ tuous [[actions]] and entering the [[womb]] of the mother is the source of the [[person]] who ages and eventually [[dies]]. STANZAS 40-41 /ji ltar bcom ldan de bzhin gshegs/ /[[rdzu 'phrul]] gyis ni [[sprul pa]] sprull /[[sprul pa]] de yis slar [[yang]] nil /[[sprul pa]] [[gzhan]] [[zhig]] [[sprul]] gyur pa /de la de bzhin gshegs [[sprul]] stong/ /[[sprul]] pas [[sprul pa]] smos ci dgos/ /[[gnyis]] po [[ming tsam]] [[yod pa]] [[yang]]/ / 1 )ci [[yang]] rung [[ste]] [[rtog pa tsam]]/ 1)D:gang ci 'ng
+
authenticity of the "autocommentary" to the [[Mula]], called the Aukutobhaya ({{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5231). This treatise was translated into [[German]] by Max Walleser in 191 1 Y As the karika(s) of the [[Mula]] are embedded in this treatise, this translation was the first [[appearance]] of the complete text of the [[Mula]] in a [[western]] [[language]]. Walleser accepted the attribution of [[Nagarjuna's]] authorship, though later [[western]] [[scholars]] have taken exception to this view. De Jong does not consider this work to have been written by [[Nagarjuna]], 18 nor does Lindtner/9 nor does Murti.20 The most convinc­ ing argument is given by Obermiller: As concerns the [[Akutobhaya]], we have the following [[interesting]] statement in the Stoii thun Bskal bzaii mig hbyeq of Khai dub . . . It is said that many [[Tibetan]] authors consider the [[Akutobhaya]] to be an autocommentary (ran Q.grel) of [[Arya Nagarjuna]], but such an opinion shows that they have not correctly analyzed the text. Indeed, the [[Akutobhaya]], in com­ menting on the 2 7th [[chapter]] of the Miila­ [[Madhyamika]], quotes from the Catul}.satika of [[Aryadeva]] with the indication: 'It has thus been said by the [[venerable]] [[Aryadeva]].' It is quite impossible that [[Nagarjuna]] could have quoted the work of his pupil in such a manner . . . . Similar indications are to be found likewise in Tsoii kha pa's {{Wiki|Legs}} bsad sftin po . . . where it is moreover said that Buddhapa­ lita, [[Candrakirti]], and [[Bhavaviveka]] have not made a single quotation from the [[Akutobhaya]] and have not even mentioned it in their works. This is like­ [[wise]] an argument for denying the authorship of [[Nagarjuna]]. 2 1 Thus this commentary to the [[Mula]] loses some of its author­ itative [[character]], though its usefulness for interpreting [[Madhyamika]] is not necessarily thereby diminished.22 It may be that we face a similar situation with the "auto­ commentary" to the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. As demonstrated by
 +
 
 +
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
 +
 
 +
191
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
the case of the "autocommentary" to the M ula, just because a text is attributed to [[Nagarjuna]] does not mean that it was authored by [[Nagarjuna]]. Following this line of {{Wiki|reasoning}}, there is thus no basis for asserting that the "autocommen­ tary" to the [[Seventy Stanzas]] was authored by [[Nagarjuna]] just because the colophon makes this indication. Now this does not mean that the treatise is of no value, but it does suggest that there is no [[reason]] to believe that the "autocommen­ tary" is [[Nagarjuna's]] explanation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] or that its version of the karika(s) is either older or more accurate than that in either the [[Candrakirti]] or [[Parahita]] commentaries. As Ruegg has pointed out, it is not clear that [[Candrakirti]] either knew of this "autocommentary" to the [[Seventy Stanzas]] or [[recognized]] it to be by [[Nagarjuna]]. He may have known of it, but not accepted its authenticity, or he may not have known of it, perhaps because it was au­ thored after [[Candrakirti]] composed his [[own]] commentary to the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. Should either be the case, then the "autocommentary" loses any special significance and should simply be considered a commentary with uncertain authorship and whose date of composition is uncertain, but possibly postdates [[Candrakirti]] (approx. 600-650 A. D . ).23 The [[balance]] of this [[chapter]] should shed some {{Wiki|light}} on this problem, which is important when it comes to selecting the most appropriate redaction of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] for trans­ lating purposes.
 +
 
 +
Section 3-2 Translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] During the First Introduction ofBuddhism to [[Tibet]] Thanks to the efforts of [[Lalou]], we can ascertain that the [[Seventy Stanzas]] was first translated into [[Tibetan]] during the {{Wiki|Imperial}} period. In Journal Asiatique1 she has translated a work from the {{Wiki|Peking}} [[bsTan 'gyur]], [[mDo]] 'grel Vol. CXXVII, which she has shown to be, in [[actuality]], a cata­ logue of the [[Tibetan]] [[Wikipedia:canonical|canonical]] collection as it existed either at the time of the [[Emperor]] [[Khri srong lde brtsan]] (775-797 A . D . ), which is Lalou's position, or at the time of the [[Emperor]] [[Khri lde srong brtsan]] (799-8 1 5 A.D.), which is [[Tucci's]] position. He reviews the {{Wiki|evidence}} in his Minor [[Buddhist]] Texts2 and concludes that the catalogue in the [[bsTan 'gyur]] can be dated to 8 12 A . D . This catalogue was assembled at the "Palace of lDan kar in [[sTod]] than" by dPal brcegs and Nam mkha'i snyin po, and contains over seven hundred works. In section XXII, titled "[[dbu ma'i bstan bcos]] la," i.e. , [[shastras]] on [[Madhyamika]], we find listed a translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] and one of its commentaries. They are: Lalou's # 593 titled 1/sTong pa [[nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i chig le'ur byas pal in 74 [[slokas]]; and Lalou's #594 titled 1/sTong pa 192
  
153
+
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
  
Through his [[miraculous powers]], Tathiigata the Sub­ duer emitted an [[emanation]] and that [[emanation]] emitted another [[emanation]]. As the [[emanation]] emitted by the Tathiigata is devoid of [[inherent existence]], it is hardly necessary to say that the [[emanation]] emitted by the [[emanation]] is also devoid of [[inherent existence]]. When we say that these two [[emanations]] do not [[exist]] inherently, that does not mean that they are com­ pletely [[non-existent]] but rather that both of them, just like [[actions]] and the one who performs [[actions]], merely [[exist]] through terms because they are separated from the [[nature]] of [[inherent existence]]. 2)They do [[exist]], but merely through [[imputation]] by [[thought]] in a deceptive way. 2)Lit: ci [[yang]] rung; all that are [[existent]]. [[Stanzas]] 40 and 41 give examples whose meaning is given in [[stanza]] 42 . Though they constitute two separate [[stanzas]], the [[Tibetan tradition]] is to explain them both at the same time. Though the [[stanzas]] end with the [[assertion]] "They do [[exist]] . . . ," this does not simply mean that only [[actions]] and the actor or the various [[emanations]] merely [[exist]] through im­ putation by [[thought]], but that all [[phenomena]] merely [[exist]] through [[imputation]] by [[thought]]. This means that all phe­ nomena which {{Wiki|conventionally}} [[exist]] have a deceptive [[appearance]]. It is possible to know the [[basis of imputation]] of phe­ nomena. For example, the [[five aggregates]] are the basis for imputing the [[existence]] of a [[person]], and these [[aggregates]] are knowable. A [[person]] doesn't [[exist]] inherently from the side of his [[aggregates]] because he becomes unfindable under [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] analysis, but he does [[exist]] {{Wiki|conventionally}} by way of mere [[imputation]] by terms and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. Likewise, what you are now [[looking at]] is the basis for imputing the term "[[book]]," and when you see that the [[book]] is not [[inherently existent]] from the side of its [[basis of imputation]], you have
+
193
  
1 54
+
[[nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i 'grel pal [[rigs pa]] {{Wiki|drug}} cu pa'i 'grel pal in 280 [[slokas]]. # 593 is of course our very [[own]] [[Seventy Stanzas]], as is evident from the title and from the number of [[stanzas]]. Though our {{Wiki|Peking}} edition of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] has 73 [[stanzas]] instead of the 74 mentioned in this catalogue, this should not be considered as counterindicative of our con­ clusion. We know that portions of a text can be omitted by a copyist and it would be no surprise if a [[stanza]] were lost between the edition of the eighth or ninth centuries and that of the seventeenth or eighteenth centuries, or, for that {{Wiki|matter}}, if one crept in. Indeed, [[stanza]] 67 in the {{Wiki|Peking}} edition of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] is omitted in the [[sDe dge]] edition. In this case its authenticity might be confirmed by its [[existence]] in the "autocommentary" to the Seventy Stan­ zas in both the {{Wiki|Peking}} edition and the [[sDe dge]] edition (folio 120b2). On the other hand, there is no {{Wiki|certainty}} that the "autocommentary" itself was authored by [[Nagarjuna]]. That [[stanza]] 67 is missing in the {{Wiki|Peking}} and [[sDe dge]] editions of the [[Candrakirti]] and [[Parahita]] commentaries suggests not only that [[stanza]] 67 is an interpolation but also that if either of these commentators knew of the "autocommentary" they rejected its authority. Furthermore, [[Lalou]] states that in regards to this cata­ logue of lDan kar a [[sloka]] is meant to indicate a meter of {{Wiki|recitation}}, and not a [[stanza]] or [[phrase]] [[per se]]. 3 Thus the salutation and colophon could have been counted as two [[slokas]] along with 72 [[stanzas]] in the [[body]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. Or there may have been 73 [[stanzas]] plus either the salutation or the colophon. Unfortunately, we cannot deter­ mine what is actually included in the number 74. Lalou's #594 presents another difficulty. As no author's [[name]] is indicated in the catalogue, we cannot know if this commentary is the "autocommentary," or if it is the com­ mentary of [[Candrakirti]], which has the same title. As follows from Lalou's statement about the significance of the term "[[sloka]]" within this context, we cannot simply count up the number of phrases in any of the currently [[existing]] commen-
  
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
+
1 94
  
understood its [[emptiness]] of [[inherent existence]]. Because the [[book]] [[exists]] merely through the [[imputation]] of words and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] that is indicative of its [[conventional existence]]. Thus it is said that the [[world]] which we see merely [[exists]] through words and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] and that there is no other [[world]] which [[exists]] except that [[world]] which [[exists]] through words and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. However, the imputations can be re­ moved and the [[six sense organs]] can know the [[basis of imputation]] as it actually is. STANZA 42 /de bzhin [[byed]] po [[sprul]] dang mtshungs/ /las ni [[sprul]] pas [[sprul]] dang mtshungs/ /[[rang bzhin]] gyis stong gang cung [[zad]]/ /[[yod pa]] de dag 1 )[[rtog pa tsam]]/ 1)P:ni
+
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
The [[person]] who performs [[actions]] is said to be similar to the [[emanation]] emitted by the Tathiigata because he is led by [[ignorance]]. And so his [[actions]] are said to be similar to the [[emanation]] emitted by the [[emanation]]. All of these are devoid of [[inherent existence]], though they do have a slight [[existence]] as mere imputations supported by terms and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. Without the [[Tathagata]] there could be [[no existence]] of the [[Tathagata's]] [[emanation]]. Similarly, both the [[person]] who per­ [[forms]] [[actions]] and his [[actions]] cannot come into [[existence]] without there being the [[ignorance]] which leads that [[person]]. As both of the [[emanations]], being dependent on the Tatha­ [[gata]], lack [[inherent existence]], so also do the [[person]] who performs [[actions]] and the [[actions]] which are performed lack [[inherent existence]], for they depend on [[ignorance]]. Though the [[person]] who performs [[actions]] and the [[actions]] which are performed lack [[inherent existence]], they are said to "have a slight [[existence]]. " The meaning here is that they have an [[existence]] through mere terms and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], that is, they [[exist]] {{Wiki|conventionally}}. If this were not the case, then
+
taries and compare that number with the number of [[slokas]] given in the catalogue. However, as the commentary of [[Candrakirti]] is rather extensive, we can assume with reason­ able {{Wiki|certainty}} that it was not indicated by this entry in the catalogue, which would have been a considerably shorter work. However, the possibility that the commentary is actually by some currently unknown author cannot be ruled out. We can, nevertheless, adduce some other {{Wiki|evidence}} which will demonstrate that, indeed, it is very likely that this commentary from the {{Wiki|Imperial}} period is the same as the one which we have termed the "autocommentary. " To begin with, although the colophon to the "autocommentary" in the {{Wiki|Peking}} edition (#523 1) mentions [[Nagarjuna]], it does not list any [[translators]]. However, the colophon to the [[sDe dge]] edition of this work ({{Wiki|Tohoku}} #3831) states that it was translated by [[Jinamitra]] and [[Ye shes]] sde.4 Hoffmann has identified these men as two of the compilers of [[Mahavyutpatti]]. 5 This work is known to be contemporary with the reign of [[Khri lde srong brtsan]] (following [[Tucci]], above, who dates the [[Mahavyutpatti]] at 8 1 2 A. D.), and thus also the catalogue of Ldan kar. Therefore, the redaction of the autocommentary in the [[sDe dge]] edition would appear to be a copy of a work which was first translated during the {{Wiki|Imperial}} period. This would seem to have survived the general destruction of texts during the [[Tibetan]] persecution of [[Buddhists]] during the ninth century. Indeed, the [[Blue Annals]] implies that such works had been preserved, as do {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]], such as Wayman.6 Additionally, Stein's explorations into Inner {{Wiki|Asia}} and subsequent retrieval of [[manuscripts]] from [[Tun-huang]] has given us some further {{Wiki|evidence}} in this {{Wiki|matter}}. The [[India Office Library]] possesses a single folio in [[Tibetan]] of a work which [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|La Vallee Poussin]] has identified as Shunyatasapta­ tivrtti. 7 The karika(s) commented upon are 19 through 23 inclusive. As the [[manuscripts]] in this collection are believed to be the production of [[translators]] and copyists from the
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
  
155
+
195
  
[[Nagarjuna]] would b e arguing from a [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] extreme, asserting the actual [[non-existence]] of [[phenomena]]. (On this point, cf. [[stanza]] 44. ) STANZA 43 /gal te las kyi [[rang bzhin]] [[yod]]/ /myang [['das]] [[byed]] po la$ [[kyang]] med/ /gal te med na las bskyed pal /'[[bras bu]] sdug dang mi sdug med/
+
{{Wiki|Imperial}} period, a comparison of these five karika(s) from the [[Tun-huang]] collection with the similar karika(s) from later editions of the [[bsTan 'gyur]] should be most informa­ tive. Therefore we include this fragment of the text below, accompanied by the [[corresponding]] karika(s) from Lind­ tner's edition of the "autocommentary. " 8 As can be seen, the [[Tun-huang]] karika(s) are much more similar to those in the "autocommentary" then they are to those in our edition of the [[Seventy Stanzas]], which are based upon the isolated karika(s) in the [[bsTan 'gyur]] and the embedded karika(s) in the [[Candrakirti]] commentary. This further supports the view that the "autocommentary" in the [[bsTan 'gyur]] was, as indicated by its colophon, translated during the {{Wiki|Imperial}} period, that it survived the destruction of texts during the ninth century, and is, most likely, the text indicated in the lDan dkar catalogue (#549). [[Tun-huang]]: 19 /dngos dang dngos myed cig car myed/ /dngos myed myed par [[dngos po]] myed/ /rtag du dngos po'i dngos myed de/ /dngos myed myed na dngos myed myed/ autocommentary: 19 Idngos dang [[dngos med]] cig car med/
  
If [[actions]] were to have the [[nature]] of [[inherent existence]], then they would be [[permanent]]. But if [[actions]] were [[permanent]] then they would not depend on a per­ son, and if there were no [[person]] to perform [[actions]], then [[actions]] would not [[exist]]. In that case, nirvii'f)(l, which is the [[state]] of [[cessation]] of [[delusions]] and [[actions]], could not be [[attained]]. If [[actions]] did not [[exist]] through mere terms and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] then their ripening results such as [[happiness]] and [[suffering]] could not arise. If [[actions]] are [[inherently existent]] they should be perma­ nent and [[unchanging]] [[phenomena]]. In that case, nirvaq.a, which refers to the [[state]] of [[extinguished]] contaminated ac­ tions and [[delusions]], could not be achieved. Moreover, such [[actions]] would be [[causeless]] as they could not depend on a [[person]] led by [[ignorance]] as their [[cause]]. But this is not appropriate. Also, if [[actions]] [[exist]] inherently they cannot have [[imputed]] [[existence]], which means that [[happy]] and suf­ fering results will not arise from them. But this is not true, as we can see how [[happy]] and [[suffering]] results occur from [[virtuous]] and [[nonvirtuous actions]]. This clearly speaks to the fact that they [[exist]] merely through the [[imputation]] of terms and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. In other words, they [[exist]] {{Wiki|conventionally}}. STANZA 44 In this [[stanza]] [[Nagarjuna]] clarifies the [[language]] he uses when discussing extreme [[views]] about [[existence]] which may be held by various opponents.
+
/[[dngos med]] med par [[dngos po]] med/ /rtag tu dngos dang [[dngos med]] 'gyur/ /dngos dang [[dngos po]] med mi 'gyur/ [[Tun-huang]]: 20 /[[dngos po]] myed par dngos myed myed/ /[[bdag]] las ma [[yin]] [[gzhan]] las myin/ /de lta has na [[dngos po]] myed/ /de myed na ni dngos myed myed/ autocommentary:20 /[[dngos po]] med par [[dngos med]] med/
  
156
+
1 96
  
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]] /[[yod]] ces pa 1 )dang [[yod med]] ces/ /[[yod]] dang med ces de [[yang]] [[yod]]/ /[[sangs rgyas]] [[rnams]] kyi [[dgongs pa]] yis/ /gsungs pa 2)rtogs par 3)bla ma [[yin]]/ 1)D:yod med ces [[yod]] 2)P:rtog 3)P:sla Whatever is said by the [[Buddha]] has the [[two truths]] as its chief underlying [[thought]]; it is 4)hard to understand and must be interpreted in this {{Wiki|light}}. When the [[Buddha]] says "[[existence]]" his chief underlying [[thought]] is [[conventional existence]]; when he says "[[non-existence]]" his chief underlying [[thought]] is non­ [[inherent existence]]; when he says "existence-and-non­ [[existence]]" his chief underlying [[thought]] is conven­ tional-existence-and-non-inherent-existence as a mere [[object]] of {{Wiki|examination}}. 4)Lit: rtogs par [[bla ma]]; not easily understood.
+
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]] /[[bdag]] las ma [[yin]] [[gzhan]] las min/ Ide lta bas na [[dngos po]] med/ Ide med na ni [[dngos med]] med/ [[Tun-huang]]: 2 1 /[[dngos po]] [[yod pa]] [[nyid]] na rtag/ /myed na nges par [[chad pa]] [[yin]]/ /[ [[dngos po]] yo ]d na de [[gnyis]] [[yin]]/ /de [[phyir]] [[dngos po]] khas blangs myin/ autocommentary: 2 1 /[[dngos po]] [[yod pa]] [[nyid]] na rtag/ /med na nges par [[chad pa]] [[yin]]/ /[[dngos po]] [[yod]] na de [[gnyis]] [[yin]]/ /de'i [[phyir]] [[dngos po]] khas blangs min/ Tun-huang:22 /[[rgyun]] gyi [[phyir]] na de myed de/ /rgyu [[byin]] nas ni [[dngos po]] '[[gag]]/ /snga ma bzhin du 'di [[ma grub]]/ /rgyu chad pa'i [[nyes pa]] 'ng [[yod]]/ autocommentary:22 /[[rgyun]] gyi [[phyir]] na de med de/ /rgyu [[byin]] nas ni [[dngos po]] '[[gag]]/ /snga ma bzhin du 'di [[ma grub]]/ /[[rgyun]] [[chad pa]] yi nyes pa'ng [[yod]]/ Tun-huang:23 /skye 'jig gzigs pas mya [[ngan]] [['das]]/ /lam bstan [[stong nyid]] [[phyir]] ma [[yin]]/ /'di dag phan tsun bzlog [[phyir]] dang/ /log pa'i [[phyir]] na [[mthong]] ba [[yin]]/ autocommentary:23 /skye 'jig gzigs pas mya [[ngan]] [['das]]/ /lam bstan [[stong nyid]] [[phyir]] ma [[yin]]/
  
[[Nagarjuna]] himself must use predicates such as "[[exists]]" in his [[discourse]], but, like the [[Buddha]], he does so only for the {{Wiki|purpose}} of instructing the [[ignorant]] who need to develop a [[mental]] (generic) image of [[emptiness]]. He himself main­ tains the [[correct view]] as his chief underlying [[thought]]. In order to argue against the extreme of [[nihilism]] he uses the term "[[exists]]," thereby establishing [[conventional existence]]. Then, at the next level, he says "does not [[exist]]" in order to argue against the extreme of [[permanence]], thereby estab­ lishing [[non-inherent]] [[existence]]. Finally, he says "exists-and­ does-not-exist" to show the [[middle view]] which is free from both of these extremes. This is his real goal, the demonstra­ tion that things are actually mere [[objects]] of {{Wiki|examination}} upon which we impute extreme [[views]]. With this [[realization]] we cease [[grasping]] at the supposed [[true existence]] of [[objects]]. In regards to the topic under [[discussion]], the [[nature]] of [[actions]], the [[Buddha]] has made what appear to be contradic­ tory statements, even though his chief underlying [[thought]] has remained the same. This is because although his audi­ ence consistently held the view that [[actions]] [[exist]] inherently,
+
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
197
  
157
+
/'di dag [[phan tshun]] bzlog [[phyir]] dang/ /log pa'i [[phyir]] na [[mthong]] ba [[yin]]/ Returning to the catalogue of lDan kar, we find another title which follows Lalou's #593, and # 594 in consecutive order. Lalou's #595 is a work which is missing from the [[Tibetan canon]] as it is currently known to us. The title of the work in the lDan kar catalogue is 1/sTong pa [[nyid]] kyi sgo bcu [[gnyis]] pal [[rtsa ba]] dan 'grel par bcas pal in 600 [[slokas]]. This may be translated as Twelve Entrances of [[Shunyata]] Com­ mented (Upon) With [[Root]] (Verses). Unfortunately, no author is given and beyond the title we know nothing more ahout this work except that it does not appear in any current editions of the [[bsTan 'gyur]]. Apparently this is the same treatise as the work in the [[Chinese canon]] called Twelve Topic Treatise ([[Shih-erh-men-lun]]; [[Taisho]] # 1568) which we discussed earlier, an opinion shared by [[Lindtner]] and others. 9 [[Robinson]], for example, has reconstructed the San­ skrit title of this {{Wiki|Chinese}} translation as Dvadashamukhashas­ tra. Thus Twelve Topic Treatise is the same as Twelve En­ [[Wikipedia:trance|trances]] of [[Shunyata]] Commented Upon With [[Root Verses]]. The {{Wiki|Chinese}} version is attributed to Niigiirjuna and was, as stated earlier, translated by Kumiirajiva. 10 The text is divided into twelve chapters, each dealing with one topic: the first [[chapter]] deals with [[causes and conditions]]; the seventh [[chapter]] deals with the [[existent]] and the [[non-existent]]. [[Chapter]] one contains a [[stanza]] which turns out to be [[stanza]] 8 in the [[Seventy Stanzas]], and [[chapter]] seven contains only one [[stanza]], which turns out to be [[stanza]] 1 9 in the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. 1 1 Seventeen of the other [[stanzas]] in the Twelve Topic Treatise are [[identical]] to [[stanzas]] in the [[Mula]]. [[Robinson]] states that the content of this treatise "is mostly a duplication" of the M ula; 12 its authorship is disputed. 1 3 The occurrence of [[Seventy Stanzas]] [[stanzas]] 8 and 19 in the Twelve Topic Treatise establishes an historical "later-limit" for the [[Seventy Stanzas]] which stands {{Wiki|independently}} of any questions about the dates of Niigiirjuna's [[life]]. [[Robinson]]
  
at different times the [[Buddha]] wished to refute different errors connected with this view. When the [[Buddha]] said that "[[actions]] [[exist]]" he meant that they [[exist]] {{Wiki|conventionally}}, but not inherently. He knew that if he said that [[actions]] did not [[exist]] inherently his auditors would misunderstand him and take [[non-inherent]] [[existence]] to mean actual [[non-existence]]. To preserve them from this extreme [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] view which leads to the [[three lower realms]] he therefore said "[[actions]] [[exist]]. " At other times the [[Buddha]] told the same audience that "[[actions]] do not [[exist]]," by which he meant that they do not [[exist]] inherently. Here his {{Wiki|purpose}} was to counter the eter­ nalist extreme that [[actions]] [[exist]] inherently and thus per­ manently, for unless his auditors discarded this extreme view they could not become free of [[cyclic existence]]. At yet other times the [[Buddha]] said that [[actions]] "[[exist]] and do not [[exist]]," by which he meant that [[actions]] [[exist]] conven­ tionally and non-inherently. In this third case his [[intention]] was to eliminate both extremes of [[nihilism]] and {{Wiki|eternalism}} at the same time. STANZA 45 1)/gal te 'byung ba'i [[rang bzhin]] [[gzugs]]/ /'byung las [[gzugs]] ni 'byung ba min/ /rang las 'byung min [[gzhan]] las [[kyang]]/ /'byung min di phyin med min narnl 1)The wording of [[stanza]] 45 in the [[root text]] differs quite markedly from the wording of [[stanza]] 45 in the [[Candrakirti]] commentary, though there is no difference in meaning. We prefer the wording in the [[Candrakirti]] version, which is given above. The version in the [[root text]] is given below. /gal te [[gzugs]] ni rang 'byung bzhin/ /[[gzugs]] de 'byung las 'byung ma [[yin]]/ /rang las 'byung min ma [[yin]] narnl /[[gzhan]] las [[kyang]] min de med [[phyir]]/
+
198
  
158
+
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]] Neither does [[inherently existent]] [[form]], [[having the nature of]] [[elements]], arise from [[elements]] nor from itself and not even from others. Therefore, it does not [[exist]], does it?
+
believes that [[Kumarajiva]] obtained a copy of the Twelve Topic Treatise while still in [[wikipedia:Kashgar|Kashgar]], perhaps about 360 A.D . , though he can produce no hard facts to support this [[assertion]]. 1 4 Inada gives the date of its translation by [[Kumarajiva]] as 409 A.D. 1 5 At any rate, it was certainly translated before his [[death]] in 413 A . D .
  
When we say that [[form]] lacks [[inherent existence]] the oppo­ nent argues that this is wrong because the [[Buddha]] has said that [[form]] arises from the [[four elements]]. This statement of the [[Buddha]] expresses clearly how [[form]] lacks [[inherent]] exist­ ence because of its [[arising]] in [[dependence]] upon the ele­ ments. Also, we argue that if [[inherently existing]] [[form]] has arisen from the [[four elements]], then we must consider whether or not [[form]] has the same [[nature]] as the four ele­ ments. If it is said that [[form]] has the same [[nature]] as the [[four elements]] then it would have arisen by itself. But here [[form]] refers to the [[material body]] (whereas in other cases [[form]] refers to shape and {{Wiki|color}}), which can be seen, while the [[four elements]] can be [[experienced]] by the [[body]] [[sense]] but not seen, so these must be different. Because they are different they cannot have the same [[inherent nature]], so then in­ herently [[existing]] [[form]] cannot have arisen by itself. Also, if the [[four elements]] have a different [[nature]] then the inherent­ ly [[existing]] [[form]], in that case, after eliminating them, [[form]] should still be [[existent]], but this is not the case, so [[form]] does not [[exist]] inherently other than the [[elements]]. As [[form]] is dependent on the [[four elements]], then it [[exists]] conventional­ ly but not inherently. STANZA 46 /gcig la bzhi [[nyid]] [[yod]] min [[cing]]/ /bzhi la'ng gcig [[nyid]] [[yod]] min pas/ /[[gzugs]] ni [['byung ba chen po]] bzhil /rgyur byas nas grub ji ltar yodl
+
Section 3-3 Translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] During the Second Introduction ofBuddhism to [[Tibet]] During the "second introduction" of [[Buddhism]] to [[Tibet]], the [[Seventy Stanzas]] again became a point of [[interest]] for [[translators]] rendering [[Madhyamika philosophy]] into Tibet­ an. It appears that much of the initial impetus for the work on [[Madhyamika]] came from [[Atisha]], whose [[name]] is intimate­ ly connected with the reintroduction. In his influential work [[Lamp]] for the [[Bodhi]] [[Path]] he writes: The {{Wiki|reasoning}} of the ShUnyatiisaptati, And of works like the M ulamadhyamaka also, Explain the [[proof]] for the [[emptiness]] Of [[inherent existence]] in entities. 1 He thus recommends these works to his [[disciples]] and all later generations of [[Tibetan Buddhists]]. If we look at the various works relating to the [[Seventy Stanzas]] in the [[bsTan 'gyur]], we find that with the exception of the "autocommentary," the remaining two show the influence of [[Atisha]] to some [[degree]]. Let us therefore now examine these texts and the [[translators]] who worked with 199
  
A [[form]] cannot have the fourfold [[nature]] of the ele­ ments because if the [[form]] has [[four elements]] then it will be fourfold and the [[four elements]] cannot have a singular [[form]] or else they will become one like [[form]],
+
200
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
1 59
+
them. They are: [1] [[Seventy Stanzas]] itself, Shunyatiisaptati­ kiirikaniima; ({{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5227); author: [[Nagarjuna]]; [[translators]]: [[gZhon nu mchog]], [[gNyan]] [[dharma]] grags and Khu. [2] ShUnyatiisaptativrtti; ({{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5268); author: [[Candrakirti]]; [[translators]]; [[Abhayakara]] and [[Dharma]] grags. [3] ShUnyatiisaptativivrtti; ({{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5269); author: Pa­ [[rahita]]; [[translators]]: [[Parahita]] and [[gZhon nu mchog]]. The first point to note is that of the three [[translators]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas]], except for Khu, each of the remaining two is also a eo-translator of a commentary upon the [[Seventy Stanzas]] [[root verses]], and in the colophons to each of these commentaries the [[name]] of an [[Indian]] [[pandita]] is also men­ tioned. However, no [[Indian]] [[pandita's]] [[name]] is associated with the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. As each of the commentaries contain the [[Seventy Stanzas]] [[root verses]] they comment upon, it is my {{Wiki|hypothesis}} that the [[root verses]] which are now extant under the title ShUnyatiisaptatikarikiiniima are an edition which was compiled out of previous translations of the commentaries to the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. To explore this {{Wiki|hypothesis}}, and also to develop some of the historical con­ text of the translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] from [[Sanskrit]] into [[Tibetan]] during the second introduction of [[Buddhism]] to [[Tibet]], we will turn our [[attention]] to these [[translators]]. The colophon to Shunyatiisaptativivrtti indicates that the treatise was translated at mTho gling [[monastery]] by [[Parahita]] (who is also its author) and [[gZhon nu mchog]]. mTho gling was the center of [[Atisha's]] initial [[activities]] in [[western Tibet]] during the years 1042 to 1045 , and we know from the {{Wiki|biography}} of [[Atisha]] that [[Parahita]] accompanied him from [[Nalanda]] to mTho gling.2 Moreover, we also know from the colophon to {{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5633 that [[Atisha]] and [[gZhon nu mchog]] worked together. Since we may assume that if Para­ [[hita]] accompanied [[Atisha]] to mTho gling, he in all likelihood also accompanied him to [[central Tibet]], and since we have ample {{Wiki|evidence}} of [[gZhon nu]] mchog's translating [[activities]] at mTho gling with other of [[Atisha's]] traveling companions, we may reasonably assume that ShUnyatiisaptativivrtti was
  
so how can [[form]] arise from the [[four great elements]] as its [[cause]]? Here again, [[form]] refers to the [[body]]. The question is, how can the [[four great elements]] be the [[cause]] of the [[body]]? There are two [[reasons]] why this is not possible. If [[form]] depends upon the [[nature]] of the four [[inherently existing]] [[elements]] then it should be like the [[four elements]], that is, it should have a fourfold [[nature]]. Alternatively, the four [[inherently existing]] [[elements]] would have to have a singular [[nature]], like [[form]]. But because [[form]] doesn't have a fourfold [[nature]] like the [[elements]], and because the [[elements]] do not have a singular [[nature]] like [[form]], therefore, how could [[form]] arise from the four [[inherently existing]] [[elements]] as its [[cause]]? In fact, [[form]] [[exists]] {{Wiki|conventionally}} through a dependent relationship with the [[four elements]]. STANZA 47 In the previous [[stanzas]] we have refuted the [[inherent]] exist­ ence of [[form]], but now the opponent asserts that [[form]] must have [[inherent existence]] because it can be apprehended by a [[mind]]. [[Nagarjuna]] answers: /[[shin]] tu mi '[[dzin]] [[phyir]] de med/ /[[rtags]] las she na l )[[rtags]] de'ng med/ /rgyu dang [[rkyen]] las skyes pa'i [[phyir]]/ /2)rtags med par [[yang]] [[mi rigs]] so/ l )P:rtag 2)P:rtag [[Form]] is not apprehended as [[inherently existing]], so therefore the [[form]] does not [[exist]] inherently. If it is said that the [[inherent existence]] of [[form]] is under­ stood 3)by the [[mind]] which apprehends it, then such a [[mind]] does not [[exist]] inherently because it has arisen from [[causes and conditions]] so it cannot be used as a [[reason]] for proving the [[inherent existence]] of a [[form]]. 3)Lit: [[rtags]] las; from a mark. If, says [[Nagarjuna]], a [[form]] were to be [[perceived]] or
+
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
  
160
+
201
  
Niigiiriuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
+
translated between 1042 and 1045 A. D . Since the text itself primarily explains the meaning of terms in the [[Seventy Stanzas]], we may also presume that it was composed at mTho gling in the course of preparing the translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] which is embedded in it. 3 The colophon to the {{Wiki|Peking}} edition of [[Candrakirti's]] Shunyatasaptativrtti indicates that it was translated in [[India]] at [[Nalanda monastery]] by [[Abhayakara]] and [[Dharma]] grags. [[Abhayakara]] was, according to Ruegg, "one of the last of the great [[Indian Buddhist masters]] whose works we possess," and "a prolific polymath" who was "a [[scholar]] of the Vikra­ mashila seminary" and "flourished at the time of [[King]] [[Ramapala]] (rg. ea. 1077- 1 1 30). "4 According to the Cam­ bridge History of [[India]], Ramapala's reign dates are about 1077 to 1 120. 5 [[Taranatha]] states that [[Abhayakara]] was upa­ dhyaya ("[[gatekeeper]]," actually a title of [[respect]]) at both Vikramashlla and [[Nalanda]] during the reign of [[King]] Ramapala.6 He may have [[died]] in 1 125 A . D . 7 However, such statements do not mean that [[Abhayakara]] lived during the entire period of Ramapala's reign; indeed there is evi­ dence to suggest that he lived at the beginning of Ramapa­ la's reign, but not the end and that either he did not [[die]] in 1 125, or else lived an exceedingly long [[life]]. For example, the [[Blue Annals]] states that [[Abhayakara]] was a [[disciple of Naropa]] in the [[Kalachakra lineage]]. 8 The date of [[Naropa's]] [[death]] is not certain. [[Guenther]] suggests 1 100 A.D.,9 while Ferrari suggests 1040 A.D. 10 In the {{Wiki|biography}} of [[Atisha]] we read that [[Naropa]] visited [[Vikramashila]] for about twenty days while [[Tshul khrims]] of Nag tsho was there, conversed with [[Atisha]], and [[died]] several days later. We also read that "Some [[relics]] of his remains were brought to [[Tibet]] by [[Atisha]]. " 1 1 In the {{Wiki|biography}} of [[Marpa]] we read of [[Atisha]] meeting [[Marpa]] after he had left [[Vikramashila]] and telling [[Marpa]] of [[Naropa's]] [[death]]. 1 2 This {{Wiki|evidence}} would suggest that [[Naropa]] [[died]] around 1040 A . D . If [[Abhayakara]] [[died]] in 1 125, then he must have received his [[initiation]] into the [[Kalachakra]] at a very young age and lived to a very ripe [[old age]].
  
apprehended, then, as you assert, that [[form]] should have [[inherent existence]]. But it is not apprehended at all, so [[form]] lacks [[inherent existence]]. What [[reason]] could you put forth to prove that the [[inherent existence]] of [[form]] can be apprehended by [[mind]]? The opponent answers that we know something is a [[form]] because we first {{Wiki|perceive}} it as a [[form]] and then we can get an image of a [[form]] in our [[mind]] and we can think "that is a [[form]]." So, says the opponent, unless we can {{Wiki|perceive}} a [[form]] we cannot think "it is a [[form]]" and with this [[reason]] we can understand how [[form]] is per­ ceived, and since it is [[perceived]], it has [[inherent existence]]. But, says Niigiirjuna, what lacks [[inherent existence]] can­ not be used as a [[proof]] of something else having [[inherent existence]]. Since the [[mind]] which is doing the apprehending lacks [[inherent existence]] because it is dependent on [[causes and conditions]] so too must the [[form]] which is apprehended by that [[mind]] lack [[inherent existence]]. Moreover, the [[reasons]] put forth by that non-inherently [[existing]] [[mind]] must also lack [[inherent existence]], so they too are not suitable for proving an argument about the [[inherent existence]] of some­ thing. Therefore, because the [[mind]] does not apprehend the [[form]] as [[inherently existing]], so it does not [[exist]] inherently. STANZA 48 Again, refuting the [[assertion]] of the opponent that if a [[mind]] apprehends a [[form]] then the [[form]] must [[exist]], Niigarjuna says: /gal te blo des [[gzugs]] '[[dzin]] na/ /rang l )gi [[rang bzhin]] la '[[dzin]] 'gyur/ /[[rkyen]] las skyes pas [[yod]] min pas/ /[[yang dag]] [[gzugs]] med ji ltar '[[dzin]]/ l)P:gis
+
202
  
If a [[mind]] apprehends a [[form]] with [[inherent existence]] then the [[mind]] will apprehend its [[own]] [[nature]]. Such a [[mind]] has arisen from [[causes and conditions]], so it is a [[dependent arising]] which lacks [[inherent existence]]. In
+
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
Further {{Wiki|evidence}} comes from several colophons which show [[Abhayakara]] and [[Tshul khrims]] [[rgyal ba]] of Nag tsho as eo-translators: {{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #3965 , #3969, #3975 , #4012, and #40 1 8 . As [[Tshul khrims]] [[rgyal ba]] spent a few years at [[Nalanda]], invited [[Atisha]] to [[Tibet]] and accompanied him to mTho gling, it is clearly the case that [[Abhayakara]] was active at [[Nalanda]] prior to 1040 A . D . , when [[Atisha]] and [[Tshul khrims]] departed for [[Tibet]]. I can find little further {{Wiki|evidence}} which will help us to pin down [[Abhayakara's]] dates, and thus the dates of the translation of the Candrakir­ ti commentary. 13 Unfortunately, if we look for [[information]] about [[Dharma]] grags to help us in this {{Wiki|matter}}, we find the yield very scanty. 14 Thus it is impossible to ascertain whether the [[Candrakirti]] commentary to the [[Seventy Stanzas]] was translated prior to [[Atisha's]] departure for [[Tibet]] or pos­ terior to his departure, and thus we also cannot know whether or not such a translation was in the possession of [[Parahita]] and [[gZhon nu mchog]] at mTho gling [[monastery]], and thus whether the [[Tibetan translation]] of the [[Candrakirti]] commentary influenced the translation of Parahita's com­ mentary. This also implies that although the colophon to the [[Seventy Stanzas]] lists the names of [[gZhon nu mchog]] and [[Dharma]] grags, we do not know if one utilized the transla­ tion of the other to produce the isolated karika(s) of the [[Seventy Stanzas]], or if yet a third [[person]] utilized their two commentary translations to produce the isolated karika(s) of the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. The third [[person]] listed in the Seven­ ty [[Stanzas]] colophon might seem to be a likely candidate; unfortunately, this third [[translator]], whose [[name]] is Khu, is also hard to pin down, as Khu is the [[name]] of a {{Wiki|clan}} which produced a number of able [[translators]]. Two likely candi­ dates do emerge, however. Khu ston [[brtson 'grus]] byung [[drung]] (101 1 - 1075)15 was born in [[eastern Tibet]], and "conducted extensive studies under Jo bo se [[btsun]]" in [[Khams]]. 16 He later became a [[disciple]] of Atisha17 and did some translation work with
  
161
+
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
  
the same way, [[form]] does not [[exist]] truly, so how can that [[mind]] apprehend a [[form]] with [[true existence]]? If a [[mind]] which apprehends [[form]] were to [[exist]] inherently such a [[mind]] and its [[object]] - [[form]] - will have the same [[inherent nature]] and the [[mind]] would apprehend its [[own]] [[nature]]. If [[mind]] apprehends its [[own]] [[nature]] it would follow that the [[subjective mind]] and its [[object]] become inseparably one and we cannot find the {{Wiki|distinction}} between the two: one as {{Wiki|perceiver}} and the other as that which is [[perceived]]. But if such a [[mind]] does not apprehend itself then how can it apprehend another? It will be like a stone or [[vase]] which does not apprehend an other as it cannot apprehend itself. Because [[mind]] is a [[dependent arising]], how can it apprehend an [[inherently existing]] [[form]]; in fact, it cannot. STANZA 49 Although we have explained how the [[mind]] which apprehends and the [[form]] apprehended do not [[exist]] in­ herently, still the opponent maintains that a [[person]] can apprehend a [[form]] with [[true existence]] because in the Siitra PiJaka it is explained how in the three times [[forms]] can be apprehended. Thus, says the opponent, [[form]] must [[exist]]. We agree that [[form]] may be apprehended, but not inherent­ ly [[existing]] [[form]], while the opponent asserts that [[inherently existing]] [[form]] can be apprehended. [[Nagarjuna]] then argues as follows: /ji skad bshad [[gzugs]] skyes 1 )pa'i blo'i/ /[[skad cig]] [[skad cig]] gis mi '[[dzin]]/ /'das dang ma 'ongs 2)pa [[gzugs]] [[kyang]]/ /de 3)yis ji ltar rtogs 4)bar 'gyur/ 1 )P:pa 2)D:gzugs kyi ni 3)P:yi 4)D:ngar
+
203
  
The kind ofform, which has arisen but not ceased to [[exist]], that I have explained is not apprehended by each [[moment]] of the [[mind]] in the {{Wiki|present}}. Therefore, how can such a [[mind]] apprehend [[forms]] of the {{Wiki|past}} and also the {{Wiki|future}}?
+
him. 1 8 He is also known to have [[taught]] the Prajfiiiparamita at [[Thang]] po che. It is possible that he is the Khu mentioned in the [[Seventy Stanzas]] colophon. If so, this is particularly [[interesting]] as we have already established that the "auto­ commentary" survived the persecution and text destruction of the ninth century, and was thus probably current in [[eastern Tibet]] where the [[practice of Buddhism]] was maintained. 19 Perhaps Khu ston brought this "autocom­ mentary" with him to [[central Tibet]] and utilized it, along with the other commentaries, in establishing the edition of the [[Seventy Stanzas]]? We simply do not have adequate evi­ dence to know. Moreover, there is a second Khu who is perhaps even a more likely candidate to be the Khu of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] colophon. The [[Blue Annals]] indicates that [[Pa tshab nyi ma grags]], who was born in lOSS A.D. ,20 spent twenty three years in [[India]], was active in the early twelfth century as a great [[expositor]] of the Miidhyamika system according to Candra­ klrti, and also states that his [[disciples]] were responsible for the spread of [[Madhyamika]] in [[central Tibet]]. 21 "The [[great commentary]] composed by the [[Acarya]] [[Candrakirti]] on the [[sTong pa nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa (ShUnyatiisaptati) has been trans­ lated by [[Abhaya]] and sNur [[dharma]] grags. sPa tshab [sic] with the [[pandita]] [[Mudita]] revised more than 300 [[slokas]] of the first part of this commentary. "22 We know from the col­ ophon to [[Sutrasamuccaya]] ({{Wiki|Tohoku}} #3934), that a Khu [[mdo sde]] [['bar]] worked with [[Pa tshab]]. We also find Khu mdo's [[name]] in other colophons to works by Niigiirjuna (for exam­ ple, {{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #S230 and #2666). We also know that [[Pa tshab]] prepared translations of Niigiirjuna's Yuktishashfikii and its commentaries, as well as [[Candrakirti's]] Prasannapa­ dii and Madhyamakiivatiira. Perhaps it was Pa tshab's col­ league or [[disciple]] Khu mdo who, working in Pa tshab's circle of [[translators]], prepared an edition of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] based on the three available commentaries? We do know that among Pa tshab's "[[four sons]]" (i.e., his chief [[disciples]]), [[Zhang thang sag pa]] founded [[Thang]] sag monas-
  
162
+
204
  
 
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
 
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
Both [[mind]] and [[form]] are momentary [[phenomena]]. Every [[moment]] of the [[mind]] (e.g. , [[eye consciousness]]) in the {{Wiki|present}} is unable to apprehend a [[form]] which has arisen but not ceased because of its extremely short duration. If the oppo­ nent asserts that the passage of moments between the occurrence of the [[form]] and its apprehension by the [[eye consciousness]] is not a problem because the [[eye]] conscious­ ness can apprehend a [[form]] in the {{Wiki|past}} or the {{Wiki|future}}, we say that this is impossible because the [[form]] of the {{Wiki|past}} has disintegrated and the [[form]] of the {{Wiki|future}} is yet to arise. Thus both are [[non-existent]] at the time of the [[eye consciousness]] of the {{Wiki|present}}, so how can they be apprehended? STANZA SO In the preceeding [[stanzas]] we explained how [[form]] doesn't [[exist]] inherently. Now the opponent argues that since the [[form]] entrance (i.e. , [[form]] as an [[object]] of [[perception]]) [[exists]], so [[form]] should [[exist]]. Moreover, he says, [[form]] [[exists]] in­ herently because {{Wiki|color}} and shape [[exist]] inherently. Niigiir­ juna refutes this [[assertion]] beginning from the position that the [[form]] entrance is coordinated to {{Wiki|color}} and shape and cannot be identified individually if the {{Wiki|color}} and shape of [[forms]] are excluded. If {{Wiki|color}} and shape lack [[inherent]] exist­ ence, so must [[form]] and then so must the [[form]] entrance. /gang [[tshe]] nam [[yang]] [[kha dog]] dang/ /[[dbyibs]] dag [[tha dad]] [[nyid]] med pas/ /de dag [[tha dad]] '[[dzin]] [[yod]] mini /[[gzugs]] de gcig tu'ng [[grags pa]] mini
+
tery, where he [[taught]] [[Madhyamika]] in accordance with Can­ drakirti's [[interpretation]]. The [[Blue Annals]] [[state]] that "due to him the [[teaching]] of the [[Madhyamika]] system continued up to the {{Wiki|present}} time [i.e., 1476 A.D. when composition of the [[Blue Annals]] began] in [[Thang]] sag. "23 The inhabitants of this [[monastery]] "which was of great [[benefit]] for the [[Madhyamika]] system" include both [[Candrakirti]] and Para­ [[hita]] through [[Pa tshab]] in their lineage,24 which clearly sug­ gests that they had access to both commentaries on the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. In the end, there seems inadequate {{Wiki|evidence}} to determine who this Khu mentioned in the [[Seventy Stanzas]] actually was, nor is the {{Wiki|evidence}} adequate to arrive at a final conclu­ sion about the origin of the edition of the isolated karika(s) of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] in the [[bsTan 'gyur]]. Finally, one must even suppose that [[Bu ston]] ( 1290- 1 364 A. D.), who actually determint>d which treatises and redactions were to be in­ cluded in the [[bsTan 'gyur]], might have had a hand in the final editing of the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. For one thing, the actual original {{Wiki|manuscript}} of the [[Candrakirti]] commentary of [[Dharma]] grags (either the [[Tibetan]] or the [[Sanskrit]], which one is unclear) was preserved at [[Bu ston's]] [[monastery]] of Zha lu up until the 1 940's. 25 Perhaps, in the end, he compared the versions of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] in the three commentar­ ies, produced an edited version based on those three, linked the names of the original [[translators]] of the differing com­ mentaries in a new colophon, and it is his edition which has come down to us as the [[Seventy Stanzas]] in the [[bsTan 'gyur]]! The karika(s) of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] do, at any rate, read differently at places than do the karika(s) in the commentar­ ies on it, although their meanings generally agree. For the most part the [[Candrakirti]] and [[Parahita]] commentaries have quite similar versions of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] [[root verses]] and these are in closer agreement with the isolated [[root verses]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] than are the [[root verses]] in the "auto­ commentary. " [[Lindtner]], who also notes this, suggests that the [[latter]] commentary may have been unknown to those
 +
 
 +
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
 +
 
 +
205
 +
 
 +
who prepared the former two commentaries, as does Ruegg.26 The {{Wiki|evidence}} which we have thus far adduced in this [[chapter]] would tend to support this conclusion. We are thus left with what appear to be two separate [[transmissions]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. One is represented by the isolated [[Seventy Stanzas]] karika(s) in the [[bsTan 'gyur]], the Candra­ kirti commentary and the [[Parahita]] commentary, and the other is represented by the "autocommentary. " Although the [[Tibetan]] version of the "autocommentary" is certainly older than the [[Tibetan]] versions of the [[Candrakirti]] and [[Parahita]] commentaries, this says nothing about the age of the [[Sanskrit]] originals. Finally, we have no clear [[information]] which would allow us to date the redaction of the isolated karika(s) of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] in the [[bsTan 'gyur]], although it seems probable that they are based on the Can­ drakirti and [[Parahita]] commentaries. There is thus no basis for determining which transmis­ sion is derived from the oldest [[Sanskrit]] redaction of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] nor which [[transmission]] is the more accurate translation of the lost [[Sanskrit]] original. Thus a [[decision]] about the most accurate reading for establishing a text edition or translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] is left in the hands of {{Wiki|individual}} contemporary [[translators]] who must make such [[judgements]] in accordance with other criteria.
  
In all times {{Wiki|color}} and shape do not [[exist]] as two different things. If they were to [[exist]] as two different things then a [[mind]] could apprehend shape without con­ sidering {{Wiki|color}} or {{Wiki|color}} without considering shape. Because these two do not [[exist]] as two different things, so therefore there is not a [[mind]] which apprehends l)shape without taking {{Wiki|color}} into consid­ eration nor {{Wiki|color}} without taking shape into consid-
+
Section 3-4 Contemporary Translation [[Activities]] Among [[Nagarjuna's]] treatises, the [[Seventy Stanzas]] seems not to have aroused too much [[interest]] on the part of [[translators]] until about the last ten years. No [[doubt]] this is due, in part, to the difficulties of the text and its discrepencies in the commentaries, the loss of the [[Sanskrit]] original and the assumption that for the most part it merely duplicates argu­ ments made in the [[Mula]]. As to this assumption, readers who compare the two texts will find that this is not entirely the case, although in both style and content the two trea­ tises are similar enough to assure that they were composed by the same author. In recent years the [[Seventy Stanzas]] has been translated into {{Wiki|Danish}} 1 and Japanese.2 A number of [[stanzas]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] have been translated into English in various [[scholarly]] articles and popular [[books]]. 3 The first complete translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] into English was my [[own]] in 1 979.4 In 198 1 Luvsantseren published an English trans­ lation of the Seventy Stanzas5 which was followed by Lindt­ ner's in 1982 .6 Unfortunately, as Luvsantseren's transla­ tion was published in [[Mongolia]] I have been unable to obtain a copy. 206
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
 +
 
 +
207
 +
 
 +
[[Lindtner]], in commenting on his translation of the Seven­ ty [[Stanzas]] states "Though I have consulted C[andrakirti] and P[arahita] my translation of the [[karikas]] strictly follows the svavrtti [autocommentary] which must, of course, re­ main the final authority in questions of [[interpretation]]. "7 I see no [[reason]] why the "autocommentary" should remain "the final authority. " As I have shown, the "autocommen­ tary" was translated several centuries prior to the Candra­ kirti and [[Parahita]] commentaries and {{Wiki|independently}} of them. But this does not mean that it was authored prior to these commentaries, and there is some {{Wiki|evidence}} to suggest that indeed it was not authored prior to them (cf. section 3-1). There also is no {{Wiki|certainty}} that the "autocommentary" was actually authored by [[Nagarjuna]]. It may have been, but it may not have been; in the case of the "autocommentary" on the Mu/a (Akutobhayii) [[scholarly]] opinion leans in the [[direction]] of refuting the attribution of authorship to Nagar­ juna, as I also have suggested (cf. section 3-1) and as Lind­ tner suggests. 8 Though the original translation of the "auto­ commentary" certainly predates the translation of the Can­ drakirti and [[Parahita]] commentaries as well as the isolated karika(s) of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] in the [[bsTan 'gyur]], there is no [[reason]] to assume that any one of the [[Sanskrit]] redactions of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] which were translated and worked into the [[Tibetan]] translations of the commentaries was a more [[faithful]] copy of the second or third century A.D. original. Nor is there any [[reason]] to presume that an earlier translation is more accurate than a later translation. There is thus no [[reason]] to presume the {{Wiki|superiority}} of the "auto­ commentary" as a basis for establishing the text of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] or for making translations or interpreta­ tions. On the other hand, there is also no fundamental [[reason]] for not using the "autocommentary" for establishing the text of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] or for guidance in translating it or interpreting it. As I suggested in section 3-3, the "autocommentary" represents one [[transmission]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] while the [[Candrakirti]] and [[Parahita]] com­ mentaries represent another. The isolated karika(s) of the
 +
 
 +
208
 +
 
 +
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
 +
 
 +
[[Seventy Stanzas]] in the [[bsTan 'gyur]] are probably connected to the [[Candrakirti]] and [[Parahita]] [[transmissions]], and were certainly edited after these two commentaries were trans­ lated, but the "autocommentary" may also have been con­ sulted by the editor who prepared this redaction of the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. My aim in translating and presenting the [[Seventy Stanzas]] has been to document what the contemporary [[Tibetan tradition]] believes [[Nagarjuna]] to be saying, and to place this explication in the framework of the [[monastic]] educational {{Wiki|curriculum}} because the texts studied in this {{Wiki|curriculum}} determine the interpretations given to Na"garjuna. Since this [[tradition]] selfconsciously places itself in the [[lineage]] which follows [[Candrakirti's]] [[interpretation]] of [[Nagarjuna]], it makes [[sense]] to use the [[Candrakirti]] commentary as the basis for making interpretations of the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. We have used all the available commentaries and versions of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] when clarifying obscurities and scrib­ al errors in the [[Tibetan text]] of the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. When discrepencies in the texts have gone beyond this and there has been no other way to establish the best reading of the text we have followed [[Candrakirti]], both to establish the text and to translate it. In [[truth]] I can make no claim that the translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] in this volume is a com­ pletely accurate version of what [[Nagarjuna]] was saying when he wrote the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. There have been too many centuries of copying, editing and interpreting the karika(s) for any [[translator]] to make such a claim. Moreover, every [[translator]] brings certain [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|assumptions}} into the [[activity]] of translating, and the resultant text bears the stamp of these {{Wiki|assumptions}}. Different {{Wiki|assumptions}} also effect the choice of redactions used as the bases for the translation. As we have followed the [[Candrakirti]] commen­ tary to clarify difficulties in the [[Seventy Stanzas]] text, our translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] differs in places from Lindtner's, who has followed the "autocommentary. " This does not make either translation {{Wiki|superior}} to the other: each
 +
 
 +
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] and its [[Transmission]]
 +
 
 +
209
 +
 
 +
is correct in what it translates. One claim that I can make, however, is that our translation is an accurate rendering of what contemporary [[Tibetans]] of the [[dGe lugs pa]] [[sect]] say [[Nagarjuna]] means, and this is all we had in [[mind]]. In a larger {{Wiki|cultural}} [[sense]], however, there is a problem with assuming that English speakers will be able to under­ stand what [[Tibetans]] say [[Nagarjuna]] means simply because they say it in English or because I have translated it into English. Concepts like "[[inherent existence]]" ([[svabhava]]; [[rang bzhin]]) or "[[emptiness]]" (shiinyata, [[stong pa nyid]]) or even "[[permanence]]" (nityatva, [[rtag pa]] [[nyid]]) all have special technical meanings in a treatise such as the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. These are familiar to a [[Tibetan monk]] who has engaged in many years of formal study of the various treatises which explain these terms and their significance in the larger [[Buddhist]] [[scriptural]] context. Most English speakers do not have the [[benefit]] of such an [[education]], and so lacking the proper context for [[understanding]] the terms in the [[Seventy Stanzas]], may misinterpret their meanings. We have sought to minimize this problem by interpolating many words into our translation of the [[Seventy Stanzas]] which do not appear in the [[Tibetan text]] and by providing a [[stanza]] by [[stanza]] commentary on it. To maintain a {{Wiki|distinction}} between those words which do and do not appear in the [[Tibetan text]], in section 2-2 we have italicized those English words which literally translate words in the [[Tibetan text]], and left our interpolated words without italicization. For the [[scholar]], the [[Tibetan text]] is also provided. I have already indicated how we established the text. To provide a more systematic [[insight]] into the [[scriptural]] context in which [[Tibetan monks]] function when reading [[Nagarjuna]] and to aid the reader in [[understanding]] the thrust of the arguments in the [[Seventy Stanzas]] I have written a [[chapter]] which outlines some fundamentals of [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] ( 1 -2), epistemology ( 1-3) and {{Wiki|psychology}} ( 1 -4 and 1-5). I have also written a section which summarizes the basic [[elements]] of [[Nagarjuna's]] [[discourse]] ( 1 -6).
 +
 
 +
Footnotes FOOTNOTES, Preface 1 . I have discussed this issue and the value of Bud­ dhadharma for the practice of {{Wiki|psychotherapy}} in the [[west]] in: Komito, "[[Tibetan Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Psychotherapy}}: A Con­ versation with the [[Dalai Lama]]," and "[[Tibetan Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Psychotherapy}}: Further Conversations with the [[Dalai Lama]]."
 +
 
 +
FOOTNOTES, Section 1 -2 1 . [[Majjhima]] Nikiiya, 1 .262; [[Samyutta]] Nikiiya, 2 . 28 . 2 . {{Wiki|Conze}}, [[Buddhist]] [[Thought]] in [[India]], p. 1 5 . 3 . [[Dhammasangani]] 1309. 4. Segal, "[[Sleep]] and The Inner Landscape: An interview with the [[Tibetan]] [[physician]] Dr. Yeshe Dhonden," p. 3 1 . FOOTNOTES, Section 1 -3 1 . Elaborated in [[Dharmakirti's]] Commentary to {{Wiki|Ideal}} [[Mind]], Pramiir}llviirttikiikiirikii, [[Tshad ma rnam 'grel]] gyi tshig le'ur [[byas pa]]. A complete outline of [[Dharmakirti's]] episte­ mology can be found in [[Rabten]], The [[Mind]] and its Functions. In this section I only discuss those aspects of this episternal210
 +
 
 +
Footnotes
 +
 
 +
211
  
163
+
ogy that are directly relevant to [[understanding]] the [[Seventy Stanzas]]. This epistemology is also presented, in a somewhat different arrangement, in Akya Yong [[dzin]], A Compendium of Ways of [[Knowing]] and Rinbochay and Napper, [[Mind]] in [[Tibetan Buddhism]]. 2. Cf. also [[stanza]] 62 .
  
eration. 2)/n the [[world]], a [[form]] is known to be singular; if its shape and {{Wiki|color}} were to [[exist]] as two different things then the [[form]] would appear to the [[world]] as two instead of one. l)Lit: [[tha dad]]; {{Wiki|distinction}}, difference, separated­ ness. 2)Lit: [[grags pa]] min; isn't known. [[Form]] refers to shape and {{Wiki|color}}. If it [[exists]] inherently, does it [[exist]] as one with shape and {{Wiki|color}} or different from them? If they [[exist]] as one, in that case both shape and {{Wiki|color}} would mean the same thing, which means shape and {{Wiki|color}} become undifferentiable. But if they [[exist]] differently, in that case also, [[form]] should [[exist]] individually after [[excluding]] its shape and {{Wiki|color}}. An [[eye consciousness]] should be able to {{Wiki|perceive}} a [[form]] without considering its shape just as we see a [[vase]] without depending on a pillar or woolen cloth for [[seeing]] it. But that is not the case. Therefore, [[form]] cannot [[exist]] inherently, so also its shape and {{Wiki|color}}. Doesn't the [[world]] know that a [[form]] is singular? If it [[exists]] inherently, either its shape and {{Wiki|color}} must be one, as it is, or it should be two, as are its shape and {{Wiki|color}}. In [[reality]], they are mutually dependent on each other and thus lack [[inherent existence]]. STANZA S ! The opponent now asserts that [[form]] [[exists]] inherently be­ [[cause]] an [[eye]] can {{Wiki|perceive}} it. [[Nagarjuna]] refutes this by asking, does the [[subject]] have [[eye consciousness]] or does the [[object]] have [[eye consciousness]]? /mig blo mig la [[yod]] min te/ /[[gzugs]] la [[yod]] min bar na med/ /[[gzugs]] dang mig la brten nas de/ /yongs su [[rtog pa]] log pa [[yin]]/ The [[eye]] has no [[consciousness]] because the [[eye]] is a [[form]] but [[eye consciousness]] is [[formless]] and that which is [[formless]] cannot adhere to [[form]]. In the same way
+
FOOTNOTES, Section 1-4 1 . Especially Asarlga's [[Compendium of Abhidharma]], [[Abhidharmasamuccaya]], mNgon pa kun btus. Asarlga's system is summarized in [[Rabten]], The [[Mind]] and its Functions. 2. [[Rabten]], ibid. , p . 5 2 . 3 . Ibid. 4. Ibid. , p. 59. 5. Ibid. , p. 58. FOOTNOTES, Section 1 -5 1 . Taken from the [[Visuddhimagga]] as translated by {{Wiki|Conze}} in [[Buddhist Meditation]], p. 1 1 3-1 1 8 . I have substituted the term "[[dhyana]]" for "[[jhana]]" throughout. 2 . The description of the [[meditative]] [[path]] is extremely complex, and what follows is a mere thumbnail sketch which, for the [[sake]] of brevity, leaves out many important details. A full detailed description of these [[techniques]] of [[meditation]] can be found in Rinbochay et al. , [[Meditative]] States in [[Tibetan Buddhism]]. A detailed description of the [[path]] in regards to taking [[emptiness]] as the [[object]] of medita­ tion can be found in Hopkins, [[Meditation on Emptiness]]. 3 . The [[Tibetan]] view is that to obtain this final [[path]] one must take up the practice of [[tantra]]; cf. Hopkins, ibid. , p. 109- 123. FOOTNOTES, Section 1 -6 1 . Cf. section 1-2 and Hopkins' various discussions of [[ignorance]] listed on p. 996 of [[Meditation on Emptiness]]. Hop­ kins' [[book]] is the most complete [[exposition]] of the [[Tibetan]] [[interpretation]] of [[Candrakirti]] now available in English; it
  
164
+
212
  
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]] the [[form]] which is observed has no [[eye consciousness]], nor is it between [[eye]] and [[form]]. Because [[eye]] con­ sciousness is generated in [[dependence]] on [[eye]] and [[form]], if it is apprehended as having [[inherent]] exist­ ence, that is a mistaken {{Wiki|conception}}.
+
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
If [[form]] is [[inherently existent]], does the [[eye]] [[sense]] or the [[form]] have [[eye consciousness]]? Also, does [[eye consciousness]] [[exist]] in between the [[eye]] [[sense]] and [[form]]? If [[form]] as an [[object]] has [[eye consciousness]] it means [[eye consciousness]] cannot be [[formless]] because of its being inseparably one with the in­ herently [[existing]] [[form]]. This is incorrect. But now if it is different from [[form]] that means there is no relationship at all between the two. Obviously it cannot [[exist]] between the [[eye]] [[sense]] and the [[form]]. Because of their mutual [[dependence]], [[eye]] [[sense]], [[form]] and [[eye consciousness]] are [[empty]] of inher­ ent [[existence]] and apprehending them to [[exist]] inherently is a mistaken {{Wiki|conception}}. STANZA 52 /gal te mig [[bdag]] l )mi [[mthong]] na/ /2)des [[gzugs]] [[mthong]] bar ji ltar 'gyur/ /de [[phyir]] mig dang [[gzugs]] [[bdag med]]/ /[[skye mched]] [[lhag]] ma'ng de bzhin no/ l)P,D:mig 2)D:de
+
expounds in detail many of the points I have summarized in this section. 2 . [[Prasannapada]], folio 456-7; Sprung, Lucid [[Exposition]] of the [[Middle Way]], p. 2 1 1 . Sprung's [[book]] is the most complete translation of [[Candrakirti's]] [[Prasannapada]] now available in English. 3 . [[Seventy Stanzas]], [[stanza]] 2. Here nirvai].a refers to "in­ trinsic" or "natural" nirvai].a; cf. [[stanza]] 63.
  
When the [[eye]] does not see itself, how can it see [[forms]]? Therefore the [[eye]] and the [[forms]] do not have self­ [[existence]] and the remaining entrances should be understood in the same way. If an [[eye]] could {{Wiki|perceive}} a [[form]] with [[inherent existence]] then, as we have previously shown, it would be able to {{Wiki|perceive}} itself. This does not mean that the [[eye]] [[sense organ]] should be able to {{Wiki|perceive}} itself as an [[object]] which is an [[eye]] [[sense organ]]. Rather, this means that if the [[eye]] could per­ ceive a [[form]] with [[inherent existence]] then it too would have [[inherent existence]] and could therefore {{Wiki|perceive}} its [[own]]
+
FOOTNOTES, Section 3-1 1 . Hoffmann, [[Religions]] of [[Tibet]], p. 32. 2. [[Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]], p. 9- 1 7 . 3 . Obermiller, [[History of Buddhism]], Vol. I, p. 50. 4. Ibid . , p. 5 1 . 5 . Obermiller, "The [[Doctrine]] of Prajiiaparamita as Ex­ posed in the [[Abhisamayalamkara]] of [[Maitreya]]," Acta Orient­ alia, XI, p. 4 . 6 . [[Tsong kha]] p a , [[rTsa]] she ti k a [[chen]] [[rigs pa'i rgya mtsho]], p. 26-27. 7 . [[Chattopadhyaya]], [[Taranatha's]] [[History of Buddhism in India]], [[chapter]] on [[Nagarjuna]]. Walleser, [[Life]] of [[Nagarjuna]], p. 434, as quoted in [[Robinson]], Early [[Madhyamika]] in [[India]] and [[China]], p . 26. 8 . Obermiller, "The [[Doctrine]] of Prajiiaparamita as Ex­ posed in the [[Abhisamayalamkara]] of [[Maitreya]]," in [[Acta Orientalia]] XI, p. 4 . 9 . {{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5344, folio 276b. 10. {{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5345 , folio 324a. 1 1 . [[Robinson]], Early [[Madhyamika]] in [[India]] and [[China]], p. 28. 1 2 . [[Murti]], The Central [[Philosophy of Buddhism]], p. 89; [[Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]], p. 3 1-33 . 1 3 . la Vallee [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Poussin]], [[Prasannapada]], p. 89. 14. Ramanan, [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Philosophy]], p. 36. 1 5 . [[Robinson]], Early [[Madhyamika]] in [[India]] and [[China]], p. 32; Hsueh-li [[Cheng]], [[Nagarjuna's]] '[[Twelve Gate Treatise]],' translates [[Seventy Stanzas]] [[stanza]] 8 on p. 56 and [[stanza]] 19 on p. 85, but does not provide the text.
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
Footnotes
 +
 
 +
213
  
165
+
16. Ruegg, The {{Wiki|Literature}} of The [[Madhyamaka School]] of [[Philosophy]] in [[India]], p. 2 1 . 17. Walleser, [[Die]] M ittlere des Niigiirjuna nach der tibetischen version ubertragen. 1 8 . De Jong, Cing Chapitres de la Prasannapadii, p. IX . 19. [[Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]], p. 15-16. 20. [[Murti]], The Central [[Philosophy of Buddhism]], p . 89. 2 1 . Obermiller, "The [[Doctrine]] of Prajiiaparamita as Ex­ posed in the [[Abhisamayalamkara]] of [[Maitreya]]," Acta Orient­ alia XI, p . 4-5 . 22. Streng, [[Emptiness]], p. 239. 23. Ruegg, The {{Wiki|Literature}} of the [[Madhyamaka School]] of [[Philosophy]] in [[India]], p. 7 1 .
  
[[inherent existence]]. By this we mean that if the [[eye]] existed inherently it would not need to depend on any other factor or thing in order to {{Wiki|perceive}} its [[object]]. Since it wouldn't need to depend on any other factor or thing it would be able to {{Wiki|perceive}} itself. However, it can't {{Wiki|perceive}} itself, so it is non-inherently [[existent]], and by this [[logic]] it also can't per­ ceive the [[inherent existence]] of any other [[object]]. Because [[perception]], [[eye]] and [[object]] are mutually [[interdependent]] it means they lack [[inherent existence]], and whatever depends on something non-inherently [[existent]] must also be non­ [[inherently existent]]. For our opponent, lack of [[inherent existence]] means [[non-existence]]. So from the {{Wiki|perspective}} of his assertions, the [[eye]] would not be able to {{Wiki|perceive}} [[form]] at all. However the [[eye]] does, as we know, {{Wiki|perceive}} [[form]]. If it is not perceiving [[inherently existing]] [[form]] then it must be perceiving non-inherently [[existing]] [[form]], and since the one depends on the other, so both [[eye]] and [[form]] lack [[inherent existence]] or self-existence. The same [[logic]] can be applied to the remaining five entrances and prove their [[non-inherent]] [[existence]]. STANZA 53 /mig ni rang [[bdag nyid]] [[kyis]] stong/ /de ni [[gzhan]] l)bdag gis [[kyang]] stong/ /[[gzugs]] [[kyang]] de bzhin [[stong pa]] [[ste]]/ /skye 2)mched [[lhag]] ma'ng de bzhin no/ l)P:dag 2)P:de ched The [[eye]] is devoid of its [[own]] [[self-existent]] [[nature]]. It is also devoid of the [[self-existent]] [[nature]] of an other. In the same way, [[form]] is devoid of its [[own]] [[self-existent]] [[nature]] as well as that of another. And it is the same with the rest of the entrances. When it is said that [[eye]] and [[form]] are devoid of the [[self-existent]] [[nature]] of another, this refers to the fact that [[consciousness]], [[eye]] and [[form]] arise together and the "other"
+
FOOTNOTES, Section 3-2 1 . 1953, p. 3 1 3 . 2 . [[Tucci]], Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], Part 11, p . 52-54. 3. [[Journal Asiatique]], 1953, p. 3 1 5 . 4. Folio 27a, and also Inada, Niigiirjuna, p. 188. 5. Hoffmann, [[Tibet]]: A Handbook, p. 133. 6. [[Roerich]], The [[Blue Annals]], p. 45 , and also [[Wayman]], [[Calming]] the [[Mind]] and Discerning the Real, p. 5 . See also section 3-3 note 19. 7. la Vallt!e [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Poussin]], Catalogue of the [[Tibetan]] Manuscripts from the [[India Office Library]], p. 204. 8. [[Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]], p. 42-44. 9. Ibid. , p. 1 1 . 10. [[Robinson]], Early Miidhyamika in [[India]] and [[China]], p. 26-27. 1 1 . Hsueh-li [[Cheng]], Niigiirjuna's '[[Twelve Gate Treatise]],' p. 56 and 85 . 12. [[Robinson]], Early Miidhyamika in [[India]] and [[China]], p. 32-33. 13. [[Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]], p. 1 1 ; [[Cheng]], Niigiirjuna's '[[Twelve Gate Treatise]],' p. 27. 14. [[Robinson]], Early Miidhyamika in [[India]] and [[China]], p. 72 . 1 5 . Inada, Niigiirjuna, p. 19 1 .
  
1 66
+
2 14
  
 
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
 
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
referred to are [[consciousness]] and [[eye]] in the case of [[form]], and [[consciousness]] and [[form]] in the case of the [[eye]]. STANZA 54 In the previous [[stanza]] we showed how [[eye consciousness]] and [[form]] do not have [[inherent existence]]. The opponent, however, still asserts that they [[exist]] inherently because [[eye consciousness]] does arise in [[dependence]] on the [[contact]] of [[eye]] and [[form]]. /gang [[tshe]] gcig reg lhan cig 'gyur/ /de [[tshe]] [[gzhan]] [[rnams]] [[stong pa nyid]]/ /stong pa'm mi stong mi l)bsten la/ /mi [[stong pa]] [[yang]] 2)stong mi brten/ l)D:stong 2)P:brten, D:rten
+
FOOTNOTES, Section 3-3 1 . {{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5344, folio 276b. 2 . Das, Journal of the [[Buddhist Text]] [[Society]], p. 29. 3. See Komito, A Study of Niigiirjuna's 'Sunyatii-saptati­ kiirikii-niima,' p. 33-36 for further details concerning Para­ [[hita]] and [[gZhon nu mchog]]. 4. Ruegg, "The [[gotra]], [[ekayana]] and [[tathagatagarbha]] theories of the Prajiiaparamita according to [[Dharmamitra]] and [[Abhayakaragupta]]," in Prajiiiipiiramitii and Related Sys­ tems, p. 284. 5. Vol. Ill , p. 5 1 1 . 6. [[Chattopadhyaya]], Tiiriinatha's [[History of Buddhism in India]], p. 329. 7 . "According to Sum pa [[Ye shes]] dpal 'byor('s) Re'u mig [[Abhayakaragupta]] [[died]] in [[shin]] [[sbrul]] 1 125." Ruegg, The {{Wiki|Literature}} of the [[Madhyamaka School]] of [[Philosophy]] in [[India]], p . 1 14. 8. [[Roerich]], The [[Blue Annals]], p. 760. 9. The [[Life]] and [[Teaching]] of Niiropa, Introduction. 1 0 . Ibid . , note 2 . 1 1 . Das, "[[Indian]] [[Pandits]] [[in Tibet]]," in Journal of the [[Buddhist Text]] and Research [[Society]], Vol. I, part 1 , p. 2 1 . 1 2 . Bacot, La Vie de [[Marpa]], p . 34. 1 3 . See Komito, A Study of Niigiirjuna's 'Sunyatii-saptati­ kiirikii-niima , ' p . 3 6 - 4 3 for more [[information]] on [[Abhayakara]]. 14. Ibid . , p. 43-44. 1 5 . [[Roerich]], The [[Blue Annals]], p. 93-94 and p. 404. 16. Ibid. , p. 93 . 1 7 . [[Chattopadhyaya]], [[Atisha]] and [[Tibet]], p. 363. 1 8 . Cf. colophon to {{Wiki|Peking}} Ed. #5028. 1 9 . "In his [rNgog [[lo tsa ba]] [[blo ldan]] [[shes rab]], born 1059 A.D.] [[teaching]] he followed the [[traditions]] of the Prajiiapara­ [[mita]] as [[taught]] during the period of the early spread of the [[Doctrine]] and which had been preserved in [[Khams]]. " [[Roerich]], The .[[Blue Annals]], p . 328 and p. 330. 20. Ruegg, The {{Wiki|Literature}} of the [[Madhyamaka School]] of =
  
When any of the six internal entrances arises simul­ taneously with [[contact]], at that time the rest of the entrances will be devoid of the [[nature]] of [[contact]]. The rest of the entrances which are devoid of the [[nature]] of [[contact]] do not depend on the [[nature]] of [[contact]]. That which is not devoid of the [[nature]] of [[contact]] will not depend on that which is devoid of the [[nature]] of [[contact]]. Only one of the entrances at a time can arise simul­ taneously with [[contact]]; at that [[moment]] the rest of the entrances are not in [[contact]] with their [[objects]]. Now, if it is asserted that [[contact]] has [[inherent existence]], then that which depends on it, the [[eye]] entrance, must also have [[inherent existence]]. In this case the [[eye]] entrance and [[contact]] have the same [[nature]], which is their [[inherent existence]], and these two would be [[inseparable]]. The other five entrances have not, at this [[moment]], arisen and each of them is different than the [[eye]] entrance. For example, the [[eye]] entrance and the {{Wiki|ear}} entrance are differ­ ent. Now if the [[eye]] entrance arises with [[contact]] and has [[inherent existence]], then the other five entrances which are
+
Footnotes
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
215
  
167
+
[[Philosophy]] in [[India]], p. 1 14. 2 1 . [[Roerich]], The [[Blue Annals]], p. 34 1-343 . 22. Ibid. , p. 342 . 23. Ibid . , p. 344-45. 24. Ibid. , p. 344. 2 5 . Ibid. , p. 342 . 26. [[Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]], p. 32; Ruegg, The Litera­ ture of the [[Madhyamaka School]] of [[Philosophy]] in [[India]], p. 20. FOOTNOTES, Section 3-4 1 . [[Lindtner]], Niigiirjuna's Filosofiske Voerker, 1982 . 2 . Uryuzu, [[Daijo]] Butten XIV. 3. [[Dalai Lama XIV]] and Hopkins, The [[Buddhism of Tibet]] and the Key to the [[Middle Way]], 1 975 , translates [[Seventy Stanzas]] 5ab on p . 69 and [[stanza]] 64 on p. 75 . [[Wayman]], [[Calming]] the [[Mind]] and Discerning the Real, 1978, translates [[stanza]] 1 on p. 276 and [[stanza]] 68 on p. 1 95 . Ruegg, The {{Wiki|Literature}} of the [[Madhyamaka School]] of [[Philosophy]] in [[India]], 198 1 , translates [[stanzas]] 58, 69, 70, 7 1 and 72 on p . 2 1 . [[Cheng]], Niigiirjuna's '[[Twelve Gates Treatise]],' 1982, translates [[stanza]] 19 from the {{Wiki|Chinese}} on p. 85 and apparently, though there is no formal attribution to this effect, [[stanza]] 8 on p. 56. 4. Komito, A Study of N_iigiirjuna's 'Sunyatii-saptati­ kiirikii-niima,' 1979. 5 . Luvsantseren, [[Philosophical]] [[Views]] of Niigiirjuna, 198 1 . Reviewed in [[Buddhists]] for [[Peace]], Journal of the {{Wiki|Asian}} [[Buddhist]] Conference for [[Peace]], Vol. 3 ( 198 1), p. 63. 6. [[Lindtner]], [[Nagarjuniana]], 1982 . 7. Ibid. , p. 32-33. 8 . Ibid. , p. 15-16.
  
different than the [[eye]] entrance and have not arisen at that [[moment]] (and so are devoid of the [[nature]] of [[contact]]) must lack [[inherent existence]], for what does not have the [[nature]] of [[contact]] does not depend on what has the [[nature]] of [[contact]]. But what has [[inherent existence]] must [[exist]] inherently at all times, so these five entrances can never [[exist]] inherently. But since this example could have been used for the {{Wiki|ear}} entrance, then in that case the [[eye]] entrance would lack [[inherent existence]]! So this shows that the argument is falla­ cious and neither the entrances nor [[contact]] [[exists]] in­ herently. STANZA [[SS]] /[[ngo bo]] mi nas [[yod]] min pas/ /[[gsum]] [['dus pa]] [[yod]] ma [[yin]] no/ /de l )[[bdag nyid]] 2)kyi reg med 3)pas/ /de 4)tshe [[tshor ba]] [[yod]] ma [[yin]]/ l )P:dag 2)D:gyis 3)D:nga 4)P:che, D:cha The [[eye]], [[eye consciousness]] and its [[object]] arise and immediately disintegrate, so they cannot [[exist]] as abiding in their natures and so those three cannot assemble. S)When these three cannot assemble, con­ tact cannot [[exist]] and if [[contact]] cannot [[exist]], so there cannot be [[feeling]]. S)Lit: de [[bdag nyid]] kyi, by those (having no) [[self-nature]]. If an [[eye consciousness]] were to [[exist]] inherently, in that case, it might be possible for the three - [[eye]], [[eye]] con­ sciousness and its [[object]] - to have an assembled [[nature]] from which [[contact]] could arise. But [[eye]], [[eye consciousness]] and [[object]] are all momentary [[phenomena]] without self­ [[nature]]. Since they disintegrate immediately after they arise there is not time for the three of them to assemble and for [[contact]] to occur between them. Also, since they do not have their [[own]] natures a� [[existing]] by themselves, how could they come together and have an assembled [[inherent nature]]?
+
[[Bibliography]]
  
168
+
Entries under "{{Wiki|Peking}} Edition" refer to The [[Tibetan]] Tripi­ taka, D . T . Suzuki, ed. [[Tokyo]]: [[Otani University]], 1962. Akya Yong [[dzin]]. [[Blo rigs]] kyi [[sdom]] tshig [[blang dor]] [[gsal]] ba'i [[me long]]. Translated by [[Geshe Ngawang Dhargyey]] et al. as A Compendium of Ways of [[Knowing]]. {{Wiki|Dharamsala}}: {{Wiki|Library of Tibetan Works and Archives}}, 1976. Asaiiga. [[Compendium of Abhidharma]]. Abhidharmasamuc­ caya, mNgon pa kun btus. {{Wiki|Peking}} Edition #550. [[Atisha]]. [[Bodhipathapradipa]], [[Byang chub lam gyi sgron ma]] and Bodhimargapradipapafljika, [[Byang chub]] lam gyi [[sgron]] ma'i dka' 'grel. Text in Sherburne, Richard F. A Study of AtiSa's 'Commentary' on His '[[Lamp]] of the [[Enlightenment]] [[Path]].' [[Ann Arbor]]: {{Wiki|University}} Microfilms International, 1 976. Bacot, Jacques. La Vie de [[Marpa]] le "Traducteur. " {{Wiki|Paris}}: Buddhica 1 , 7, 1937. [[Buddhaghosa]], [[Bhadantacariya]]. [[Visuddhimagga]]. Selections translated by {{Wiki|Conze}}, Edward in [[Buddhist Meditation]]. [[New York]]: Harper and Row, 1969. 216
  
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
+
[[Bibliography]]
  
If these three cannot assemble in this way, then how can there be any [[contact]] with a [[nature]] of [[inherent existence]]? Since [[feeling]] depends on [[contact]], so [[feeling]] must also lack [[inherent existence]]. STANZA 56 /[[nang]] dang phyi yi [[skye mched]] la/ /brten nas [[rnam par shes pa]] 1 )'byung/ /de 2)lta has na [[rnam shes]] nil /smig rgyu [[sgyu ma]] bzhin du stong/ 1 )P: 'gyung, D:'gyur 2)P:ltang, D:ltar
+
217
  
[[Consciousness]] arises in [[dependence]] on internal and ex­ ternal entrances. Because [[consciousness]] arises in de­ pendence on the entrances, so it is like a [[mirage]] and an [[illusion]] which are devoid of [[inherent existence]]. Still, the opponent asserts that the entrances do [[exist]] inherently because [[consciousness]] arises in [[dependence]] on those entrances. We argue, however, that if [[consciousness]] were to [[exist]] inherently then it could not arise in depend­ ence on internal and external entrances, because what is [[inherently existent]] must be {{Wiki|independent}}. As [[consciousness only]] arises in [[dependence]] upon external entrances such as [[form]] and internal entrances such as an [[eye]], it is clear that it is [[empty of inherent existence]]. It is like a [[mirage]] which appears as [[water]] or a magician's [[illusion]] which appears as [[horses]] and [[elephants]]. Because [[consciousness]] lacks [[inherent existence]] it is like a [[mirage]], which is something which [[exists]], but not in the way it appears to [[exist]]. It is this very mode of the [[appearance]] of an [[object]] to our [[eye consciousness]] which is the thing which Niigarjuna wishes to refute. STANZA 57 /[[rnam shes]] [[shes bya]] la brten 1)na/ /'byung la [[shes bya]] [[yod]] ma [[yin]]/
+
[[Candrakirti]]. M ulamadhyamakavrttiprasannapadii, db U ma rtsa ba'i 'grel pa [[tshig gsal]] ba. {{Wiki|Peking}} Edition #5260. [[Candrakirti]]. Shunyatiisaptativrtti, [[sTong pa nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i 'grel pa. {{Wiki|Peking}} Edition #5268 [[Chattopadhyaya]], [[Alaka]]. [[Atisa]] and [[Tibet]]. [[Calcutta]]: {{Wiki|Indian Studies}}, 1967. [[Chattopadhyaya]], D. Tiiriinatha's [[History of Buddhism in India]]. {{Wiki|Simla}}: {{Wiki|Indian Institute of Advanced Study}}, 1970. [[Cheng]], Hsueh-li. Niigiirjuna's '[[Twelve Gates Treatise]]. ' Dor­ drecht: Reidel, 1982 . {{Wiki|Conze}}, Edward. [[Buddhist]] [[Thought]] in [[India]]. [[Ann Arbor]]: [[University of Michigan]] Press, 1973 . Das, Sarat C. "[[Indian]] [[Pandits]] [[in Tibet]]," Journal of the [[Buddhist Text]] and Research [[Society]], [[Calcutta]]. Vol. I, part 1 , 1 893 . De Jong, J . W. Cing Chapitres de la Prasannapadii. {{Wiki|Paris}}: Librarie Orientaliste Paul Geuthner, 1949. [[Dhammasangani]]. Translated by Caroline [[Wikipedia:Thomas William Rhys Davids|Rhys Davids]] as A [[Buddhist]] Manual of [[Psychological]] [[Ethics]]. {{Wiki|New Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Oriental}} [[Books]] Reprint Corporation, 1975 . [[Dharmakirti]]. Commentary to {{Wiki|Ideal}} M ind, PramiirJ.a­ viirttikakiirikii, [[Tshad ma rnam 'grel]] gyi tshig le'ur [[byas pa]]. {{Wiki|Peking}} Edition #5709. [[Guenther]], Herbert. The [[Life]] and [[Teaching]] of [[Naropa]]. Lon­ don: [[Oxford University Press]], 1974. Gyatso, Tenzin: The [[Fourteenth Dalai Lama]]. The Buddh­ ism of [[Tibet]] and the Key to the [[Middle Way]]. [[New York]]: Harper and Row, 1975 . Hoffmann, Helmut. [[Religions]] of [[Tibet]]. [[London]]: Alien and Unwin, 196 1 . Hoffmann, Helmut. [[Tibet]]: A Handbook. [[Bloomington]]: Re­ search [[Center]] for the [[Language]] [[Sciences]], 1975 . Hopkins, Jeffrey. [[Meditation on Emptiness]]. [[London]]: Wis­ dom Publications, 1983. Inada, Kenneth . Nagiirjuna: Mulamadhyamakakiirikii. [[Tokyo]]: Hokuseido Press, 1970. Komito, David. A Study of Niigiirjuna's 'Sunyatii-saptati-
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
218
  
169
+
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
/[[shes bya]] [[shes pa]] med pa'i [[phyir]]/ /de [[phyir]] [[shes pa]] po [[nyid]] med/ l)D:nas
+
kiirikii-niima.' [[Ann Arbor]]: {{Wiki|University}} Microfilms Inter­ national, 1979. Komito, David. "[[Tibetan Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Psychotherapy}}: A [[Conversation]] with the [[Dalai Lama]]," The Journal of {{Wiki|Transpersonal Psychology}}, Vol. XV, # 1 , 1983 . Komito, David. "[[Tibetan Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Psychotherapy}}: Further Conversations with the [[Dalai Lama]]," The Jour­ nal of {{Wiki|Transpersonal Psychology}}, Vol. XVI, # 1 , 1984. la Vallee [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Poussin]], Louis de. Mulamadhyamakakiirikiis de Niigiirjuna avec la Prasannapadii. St. Petersberg, 19031914. la Vallee [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Poussin]], Louis de. Catalogue of the [[Tibetan]] Manu­ scripts from the [[India Office Library]]. [[London]]: [[Oxford University Press]], 1962 . [[Lalou]], Marcelle. "Les Textes Bouddhiques au Temps du Roi [[Khri-srong]] lde-bcan," [[Journal Asiatique]], 1953. L i n d t n e r , C h r . N iigiirjuna's Filosofiske Voerk er. [[Copenhagen]]: (publisher unknown), 1982 . [[Lindtner]], Chr. [[Nagarjuniana]] . [[Copenhagen]]: Akademisk Forlag, 1982 . Luvsantseren, S . [[Philosophical]] [[Views]] of Niigiirjuna . (pub­ lisher unknown), 198 1 . [[Majjhima]] Nikiiya. Selections translated in David Kalupaha­ na. [[Buddhist Philosophy]]: A Historical Analysis. [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University Press of Hawaii}}, 1976. May, Jacques. [[Candrakirti]] Prasannapadii Madhyamakavrtti. {{Wiki|Paris}}: Adrien Maisonneuve, 1959. [[Murti]], Tirupattur. The Central [[Philosophy of Buddhism]]. [[London]]: Allen and Unwin, 1970. [[Nagarjuna]]. Shunyatiisaptatikiirikiiniima, [[sTong pa nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i tshig le'ur [[byas pa]] [[zhes bya ba]]. {{Wiki|Peking}} Edition #5227. [[Nagarjuna]]. ShUnyatiisaptativrtti, [[sTong pa nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i 'grel pa. {{Wiki|Peking}} Edition #523 1 . Obermiller, Eugene. "The [[Doctrine]] of Prajiiaparamita as Exposed in the Abhisamayalaf\lkiira of [[Maitreya]]," [[Acta Orientalia]], XI, 1932 .
  
[[Consciousness]] cannot arise without taking its [[object]], so it depends on the [[object of knowledge]]. The [[object of knowledge]] cannot arise without depending on the [[consciousness]] which apprehends it, and therefore because they [[exist]] in a mutually dependent · way both of them lack [[inherent existence]]. The [[object of knowledge]] and the apprehension of the [[object]] do not [[exist]] inherently, therefore the [[person]] who [[knows]] the [[object]] does not [[exist]] inherently. Now, the opponent still believes that even though the [[object of knowledge]] and the apprehension of the [[object]] don't [[exist]] inherently, since there are persons who know the [[object]], therefore these persons do have [[inherent existence]]. We argue that if the obj ect of [[knowledge]] and the apprehension of the [[object of knowledge]] don't [[exist]] in­ herently, how can the [[person]] who [[knows]] the [[object]] [[exist]] inherently? STANZA 58 /thams cad mi rtag [[yang]] na ni/ /[[mi rtag pa]] [[yang]] [[rtag pa]] med/ /dngos l )po rtag dang mi rtag [[nyid]]/ I' gyur na de lta ga la [[yod]]/ l)D:bo [[Buddha]] has seen no [[essence]] in composite phe­ nomena with [[inherent existence]] so he said that all composite [[phenomena]] are [[impermanent]], so therefore they are devoid of [[inherent existence]], or because he said that all composite [[phenomena]] are [[impermanent]], so how could they 2)exist inherently in the [[nature]] of [[permanent]] [[phenomena]]? If [[phenomena]] were to have [[inherent existence]] they should either be [[permanent]]
+
[[Bibliography]]
  
170
+
2 19
  
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]] or [[impermanent]]: how can there be [[phenomena]] which are both [[permanent]] and [[impermanent]] at the same time? 2)Lit: [[rtag pa]] med; do not [[exist]] permanently.
+
Obermiller, Eugene. [[History of Buddhism]] by [[Bu-ston]]. Suzu­ ki Research Foundation (no date given) . Parahita(bhadra). Shunyatasaptativivrtti, [[sTong pa nyid]] [[bdun]] cu pa'i [[rnam]] par [[bshad pa]]. {{Wiki|Peking}} Edition #5269. [[Rabten]], [[Geshe]]. The [[Mind]] and its Functions. Mt. Pelerin: [[Tharpa]] Choeling, 198 1 . Ramanan, K . Venkata. [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Philosophy]] as Presented in the Maha-Prajiiaparamita-Sastra. Rutland : Tuttle, 1 960. Rinbochay, Lati and Napper, [[Elizabeth]]. [[Mind]] in [[Tibetan Buddhism]]. Valois: Gabriel Press, 1980. Rinbochay, Lati, et al. [[Meditative]] States in [[Tibetan]] Buddh­ ism. [[London]]: [[Wisdom Publications]], 1983. [[Robinson]], Richard. Early [[Madhyamika]] in [[India]] and [[China]]. [[Madison]]: [[University of Wisconsin]] Press, 1967 . [[Wikipedia:George Nicolas de Roerich|Roerich, George]] N. The [[Blue Annals]]. [[Delhi]]: Banarsidass, 1976. Ruegg, David S. "The [[gotra]], [[ekayana]] and [[tathagatagarbha]] theories of the Prajftaparamita according to [[Dharmamitra]] and [[Abhayakaragupta]]," in Prajiiaparamita· and Related Systems, Louis [[Lancaster]], ed. [[Korea]]: .[[Berkeley]] [[Buddhist Studies]] Series, 1977 . Ruegg, David S . The {{Wiki|Literature}} of the [[Madhyamaka School]] of [[Philosophy]] in [[India]]. [[Wiesbaden]]: Harrassowitz, 198 1 . [[Samyutta]] Niktiya . Selections translated in David Kalupaha­ na. [[Buddhist Philosophy]]: A Historical Analysis. [[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University Press of Hawaii}}, 1976. Segal, William and Segal, Marielle. "[[Sleep]] and The Inner Landscape: An interview with the [[Tibetan]] [[physician]] Dr. Yeshe Dhonden," Parabola, Vol. VII, # 1 , 1982 . Sprung, Mervyn. Lucid [[Exposition]] of the [[Middle Way]]. Lon­ don: Routledge, 1979. Streng, Frederick. [[Emptiness]] - A Study in [[Religious]] Mean­ ing. [[New York]]: Abingdon, 1967. [[Tsong kha pa]]. [[rTsa]] she ti ka [[chen]] [[rigs pa'i rgya mtsho]]. [[Varanasi]]: [[Pleasure of Elegant Sayings]] Press, 1973. [[Tucci]], Giuseppe. Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], Part 11. {{Wiki|Rome}}:
  
Because [[Buddha]] has seen [[reality]] he has said that all composite things are [[impermanent]]. The opponent mis­ takenly believes that this means that [[impermanence]] has [[inherent existence]]. We refute this. Because all composite things are [[impermanent]], they lack [[inherent existence]]. When [[Buddha]] says that all composite things are [[impermanent]] he also implies that [[permanent]] [[phenomena]] lack [[inherent existence]]. STANZA 59 /sdug dang mi sdug phyi ci log/ /[[rkyen]] las [[chags sdang]] [[gti mug]] dngos/ /'byung [[phyir]] [[chags sdang]] [[gti mug]] dang/ /[[rang bzhin]] gyis ni [[yod]] ma [[yin]]/ Through superimposition one develops the three distorted preconceptions toward [[pleasing]], repulsive and [[neutral]] [[objects]], which respectively [[cause]] attach­ ment, [[hatred]] and closed-mindedness. Because they arise in [[dependence]] on these [[conditions]], the ! )[[essential nature]] of [[attachment]], [[hatred]] and closed­ mindedness is without [[inherent existence]]. 1 )[[rang bzhin]]. Superimposition (sgro '[[dogs]]) is an imposition or imputa­ tion of an extreme {{Wiki|conception}} upon a [[basis of imputation]], which is a supposed [[object]]. It is actually a process of over­ estimating the [[nature]] of such a basis in either of two ex­ treme [[directions]]. An example would be the [[seeing]] of [[permanence]] in what is actually a transitory [[phenomenon]]. Out of this superimposing process we develop [[attachment]] for what appears to be [[pleasing]], [[hatred]] for what appears repulsive, and closed-mindedness or [[confusion]] for what
+
220
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
171
+
Serie Orientale Roma, 1958. Uryuzu, [[Ryushin]]. [[Daijo]] Butten XIV. (publisher unknown). Walleser, Max. [[Die]] Mitt/ere des Niigiirjuna nach der tibetis­ [[chen]] version ubertragen. [[Heidelberg]], 191 1 . Walleser, Max. "The [[Life]] of [[Nagarjuna]] from [[Tibetan]] and {{Wiki|Chinese}} Sources," Hirth Anniversary Volume, Bruno Schindler, ed. [[London]]: Probsthain, (no date given). [[Wayman, Alex]]. [[Calming]] the [[Mind]] and Discerning the Real. [[New York]]: [[Columbia University Press]], 1978.
  
appears to be [[neutral]]. Such preconceptions ([[pleasing]], re­ pulsive, and [[neutral]] [[thoughts]] and [[feelings]]) are mere im­ putations without [[inherent existence]], because they arise in [[dependence]] on the [[condition]] of superimposition. STANZA 60 /gang [[phyir]] [[de nyid]] la [[chags]] [[shing]]/ /de la she sdang de la rmongs/ /de [[phyir]] [[rnam]] par [[rtog]] pas bskyed/ /[[rtog]] de'ng [[yang dag]] [[nyid]] du med/ A [[pleasing]] [[object]] does not [[exist]] inherently because some persons develop [[attachment]] towards it, others develop [[hatred]] towards it, and still others develop closed-mindedness towards it. Therefore such qualities of the [[object]] are merely created by preconceptions, and these preconceptions also l)do not [[exist]] inherently because they develop from superimposition. l)Lit: [[yang dag]] [[nyid]] du med; do not truely [[exist]]. Here [[Nagarjuna]] carries the argument in the previous [[stanza]] a step further. At a given [[moment]] three different observers may demonstrate the three distorted preconcep­ tions towards the same [[object]]. This shows that the qualities associated with an [[object]] do not inhere in it, but are im­ puted to it through the power of the preconceptions. For instance, an attractive thing does not [[exist]] inherently be­ [[cause]] its [[quality]] - attractiveness - is [[fabricated]] by a {{Wiki|concept}}. Whatever is [[imputed]] upon it lacks [[inherent]] exist­ ence as it is created by a [[thought]] (a preconception). Such a preconception has to be [[empty of inherent existence]] be­ [[cause]] of its [[dependent arising]]. From that it also follows that the three {{Wiki|poisonous}} [[delusions]] ([[attachment]], [[hatred]] and [[ignorance]]) which are produced by such distorted precon­ ceptions lack [[inherent existence]] and so do the [[actions]] moti­ vated by them. Also, if a [[pleasant]] thing [[exists]] inherently it should be seen as [[pleasant]] by all [[people]], which does not stand true as some see it as repulsive and generate [[hatred]]
+
Index [[Abhayakara]] 201 [[Abhidharma]] 53, 97 [[action]] 56, 145-157 agent 15{}..- 1 5 1 , 154-155 [[aggregates]] 27, 33 aggregation 102 analytic [[meditation]] 62 - see also [[meditation]] {{Wiki|annihilationist}} view 129 - see also extreme view [[appearances]] 66, 69, 7 1 , 120, 132 [[appearing object]] 40, 57, 66 - see also [[object]] [[appreciation]] S S [[Arhat]] 1 0 1 [[arising]] 9 8 , 105-107, 125, 127 - see also [[dependent arising]] [[arising]], enduring, ceasing 1 25-143 [[Arya]] 56, 58, 64, 174 Asatiga 52, 66 [[aspiration]] S S [[Atisha]] 1 8 8 , 199 [[attention]] 52, [[SS]], 56 [[attraction]] 3 1 [[auditory consciousness]] 37 - see also [[consciousness]] [[basis of imputation]] 98, 1 19, 154 - see also functional basis see also [[imputation]] -
  
1 72
+
becoming 26, 29 [[birth]] 26 [[birth]] and [[death]] 30 [[body]] 37, 148-151 [[Bu ston]] 187 [[Buddha]] 23-24, 97, 156 [[buddhahood]] 65 [[calm abiding]] 63 [[Candrakirti]] 157, 177, 189, 202 [[cause]] 102, 107, 138 - see also [[dependent arising]] - see also result cause-effect relationships 25, 107, 129-1 3 1 , 138-139 [[cessation]] 125, 127, 135 [[cognition]] 37 - see also {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[cognition]] - see also deceived [[cognition]] - see also direct valid [[cognition]] - see also erroneous [[cognition]] - see also erroneous {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[cognition]] - see also {{Wiki|ideal}} [[cognition]] - see also mistaken {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[cognition]] - see also mistaken sensory [[cognition]] see also {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[cognition]] - see also {{Wiki|perfect}} [[cognition]] -
  
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
+
221
  
towards it, whereas some others see it neither as [[pleasant]] nor as [[unpleasant]] and maintain a [[neutral]] [[feeling]]. If this [[object]] lacks [[inherent existence]], so must the thought­ [[consciousness]] which imputes qualities to it, for they both arise in [[dependence]], as [[Nagarjuna]] states in the next [[stanza]]. STANZA 6 1 /brtag bya gang de [[yod]] ma [[yin]]/ /brtag [[bya med]] [[rtog]] ga la yodl /de [[phyir]] brtag bya [[rtog pa]] dag /[[rkyen]] las skyes [[phyir]] [[stong pa nyid]]/
+
222
  
Whatever may be an [[object]] of {{Wiki|examination}} does not [[exist]] inherently. As that [[object]] of {{Wiki|examination}} does not [[exist]] inherently, how can the thought-consciousness of that non-inherently [[existing]] [[object]] [[exist]] inherently? Therefore, because the [[object]] of {{Wiki|examination}} and the thought-consciousness arise from [[causes and conditions]], they are [[empty of inherent existence]]. STANZA 62 Having demonstrated in the previous [[stanza]] that thought­ [[consciousness]] itself is without [[inherent existence]], Nagar­ juna now turns to the [[heart]] of his [[discourse]], which is its implications for [[liberation]]. 1de [[nyid]] rtogs l )pas phyin ci log /bzhi las byung ba'i ma rig medl /de med na ni [['du byed]] [[rnams]]/ /mi 'byung [[lhag]] ma'ng de bzhin no/ l)P:ba'i The [[mind]] which directly [[understands]] [[emptiness]] is an unmistaken [[mind]] which eliminates the [[ignorance]] that arises from the four [[evil]] preconceptions. Without that [[ignorance]] the [[karmic formations]] will not arise, and so neither will the remaining limbs.
+
Niigiirjuna's Sevenly [[Stanzas]]
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
- see also valid [[cognition]] - see also valid {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[cognition]] - see also valid {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[cognition]] [[compassion]] 1 8 1 composite [[phenomenon]] 142-144, 149 - see also [[phenomenon]] composite thing 105 - see also thing [[compounded]] [[phenomenon]] 104 - see also [[phenomenon]] [[concentration]] 5 5 , 56 - see also eight stages of con­ centration - see also [[meditation]] {{Wiki|conception}} 36, 42, 50, 154 - see also extreme {{Wiki|conception}} {{Wiki|conception}} of [[self]] 14 7 - see also [[self]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] 37, 66 {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[cognition]] 4 1 , 43 - see also [[cognition]] [[condition]] 102 - see also [[dominant condition]] - see also [[immediate condition]] - see also [[object]] [[condition]] [[consciousness]] 26, 30, 37-38, 52, 152, 164, 168-169, 1 72 - see also [[auditory]] conscious­ ness - see also {{Wiki|gustatory}} conscious­ ness - see also [[mental consciousness]] - see also [[olfactory consciousness]] - see also primary conscious­ ness - see also [[tactile consciousness]] - see also [[visual consciousness]] [[consciousness]] limb 26, 52 [[consciousness]] [[skandha]] 38 [[contact]] 2&-28, 37, 5 5 , 16&-168 continuity 130 - see also [[moment]] [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] 146, 1 5 3 , 1 78 - see also [[truth]]
  
173
+
[[conventional existence]] 99, 1 56 - see also [[existence]] [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] "I " 100 - see also "I" - see also [[self]] [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] terms 178 - see also [[worldy]] convention [[conventional truth]] 65 , 7 1 , 178-179 - see also [[truth]] correct [[belief]] 47-48, 62, 67 [[craving]] 26, 28 [[cyclic existence]] 3 1 [[death]], [[grief]], [[suffering]] 26 - see also [[suffering]] deceived [[cognition]] 43 - see also [[cognition]] defined 137 [[definition]] 1 37 [[delusion]] 3 1 , 150 [[dependence]] 28, 120 [[dependent arising]] - see [[dependence]] - see also [[dependent origination]] [[dependent origination]] 2 5 , 1 101 2 1 , 172-178 devoid of [[inherent existence]] 69, 102 - see also [[empty of inherent existence]] [[Dharma]] 1 80 [[Dharma]] grags 1 8 1 , 20 1 Dharmaltirti 36, 50, 67 direct valid [[cognition]] 48 - see also [[cognition]] [[discernment]] 55-56 [[discernment]] [[without signs]] 5&-57 {{Wiki|disintegration}} 127 - see also momentary {{Wiki|disintegration}} {{Wiki|distinctions}} 140 distorted traces 3 1 [[distortions]] 1 12 , 124, 170, 172 "does not [[exist]]" 69, 1 56 - see also [[existence]] "does not [[exist]] inherently" 70 - see also [[existence]]
  
When the [[mind]] directly sees the lack of [[inherent]] exist­ ence both of things and of itself (that is, their [[emptiness]]), then it is unmistaken. Such an unmistaken [[mind]] eliminates [[ignorance]] [[arising]] from the preconceptions by [[seeing]] the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[nature]] of things, thereby preventing the [[arising]] of new [[karmic formations]], and so freeing one from the [[cyclic existence]] whose [[arising]] is described by the twelve limbs of [[dependent origination]]. {{Wiki|Reasoning}}, such as that employed in the [[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]], is a necessary step in developing an unmis­ taken [[mind]]. This is because although one can directly per­ ceive the gross [[nature]] of an [[object]], one must first [[reason]] about the {{Wiki|subtle}} [[nature]] of the [[object]], which is its lack of [[inherent existence]], before one can develop the direct per­ ceiver which directly [[perceives]] this {{Wiki|subtle}} [[nature]] of an [[object]]. A thought-consciousness which correctly analyzes the {{Wiki|subtle}} [[nature]] of an [[object]] is converted through medita­ tion into an unmistaken direct {{Wiki|perceiver}} which [[knows]] the {{Wiki|subtle}} [[nature]] of an [[object]], which is a mere [[vacuity]]: The [[conversion]] of thought-consciousness into an unmis­ taken direct {{Wiki|perceiver}} can only be accomplished through [[meditation]]. This [[meditation]] must follow the earlier reason­ ing about the {{Wiki|subtle}} [[nature]] of an [[object]], for this has shown the [[practitioner]] what is to be [[meditated]] upon. A two-step process is being described here which a {{Wiki|metaphor}} will help to clarify. Suppose a [[Wikipedia:Magician(paranormal)|magician]] were to come to a crossroads and, setting up some sticks which were found there, magi­ cally convert them into [[horses]] and [[elephants]]. Attracting an audience, he bids the [[animals]] to do tricks for the entertain­ ment of the onlookers. When the crowd disperses, the [[Wikipedia:Magician(paranormal)|magician]] goes on his way, leaving the sticks behind. If some [[person]] were now to pass by the crossroads he would know nothing of the earlier performance, and would simply see some sticks at the crossroads. In this {{Wiki|metaphor}}, the [[Wikipedia:Magician(paranormal)|magician]] sees a mere [[appearance]] of [[horses]] and [[elephants]] but does not [[cling]] to them as [[horses]] and [[elephants]] for he [[knows]] that he created them. Similarly,
+
Index [[dominant condition]] 38 - see also [[condition]] {{Wiki|ear}} 37 eight stages of [[concentration]] 59 - see also [[concentration]] [[emanation]] 1 54 [[empty]] ([[emptiness]]) 62-65, 68-70, 102, 133, 176--178 - see also [[inherent existence]] - see also [[truth]] [[empty of inherent existence]] 69 - see also devoid of [[inherent existence]] - see also [[empty]] - see also [[existence]] enduring 127 entrances - see [[sense fields]] epistemology 37 erroneous [[cognition]] 44 - see also [[cognition]] erroneous {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[cognition]] 41 - see also [[cognition]] {{Wiki|eternalism}} 134, 1 7 5 , 1 77, 180 {{Wiki|eternalist}} extreme 1 5 7 {{Wiki|eternalist}} view 129 - see also extreme view [[existence]] 69, 99, 156 - see also [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] exist­ ence - see also devoid of [[inherent existence]] - see also "does not [[exist]]" - see also "does not [[exist]] inherently" - see also [[empty]] - see also [[empty of inherent existence]] - see also [[exists]] non-inherently - see also [[inherent existence]] - see also [[non-inherent]] [[existence]] - see also [[true existence]] [[existence]] and [[non-existence]] 103104, 125-129, 14�145 "exists-and-does-not-exist" 1 56 [[exists]] non-inherently 70
  
17 4
+
223
  
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
+
[[experience]] 1 5 1 [[extinction]] 134 extreme {{Wiki|conception}} 170 - see also {{Wiki|conception}} extreme view 73, 157 - see also {{Wiki|annihilationist}} view - see also {{Wiki|eternalist}} view - see also [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] view - see also overestimation - see also underestimation [[eye]] 37 [[feeling]] 26--27, S S , 1 38-139, 167 [[five aggregates]] 1 5 3 - see also [[aggregates]] [[form]] 1 5 7-167 four [[evil]] preconceptions - see [[distortions]] [[four great elements]] 32, 1 5 8-159 [[four noble truths]] 3 1 functional basis 1 4 1 - see also basis o f [[imputation]] functional [[phenomenon]] 68, 123, 126 - see also [[phenomenon]] functional thing 68, 99, 1 75 - see also thing gateways - see [[sense fields]] general {{Wiki|examination}} S S , 57 [[generic image]] - see [[mental]] image [[grasping]] 26, 28 [[grasping]] at [[self]] 100 - see also [[self]] [[gustatory consciousness]] 37 - see also [[consciousness]] [[gZhon nu mchog]] 1 82 , 200 "I" 29, 33, 99-100 - see also [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] "I" {{Wiki|ideal}} [[cognition]] 44 - see also [[cognition]] [[ignorance]] 26, 30, 1 1� 1 1 7 , 1 72 , 1 75-176 [[immediate condition]] 38 - see also [[condition]] [[impermanence]] 170
  
the [[practitioner]] who has understood [[emptiness]] through modes of profound {{Wiki|reasoning}} does not [[cling]] to [[phenomena]] as having [[true existence]] although they appear to [[exist]] tru­ ly. [[Ordinary people]] hold things to [[exist]] truely and phe­ nomena appear to them in such a manner. This is similar to the type of [[appearance]] and the [[perception]] of [[people]] who watch the [[magic]] [[illusion]]. Now as to the one who has elimin­ ated [[ignorance]] and sees [[emptiness]] directly, things neither appear to him as [[truly existent]] nor does he [[cling]] to them as having [[true existence]]. His position is similar to that of the [[person]] who has not watched the [[magic]] [[illusion]], he won't see either the [[appearance]] of [[illusory]] [[horses]] and [[elephants]] or have any [[clinging]] to them as [[horses]] and [[elephants]]. The [[Wikipedia:Magician(paranormal)|magician]] is also analogous to the [[practitioner]] who has entered the [[Path of Accumulation]] ([[tshogs lam]]). He gains his [[understanding]] through hearing and contempla­ tion, using a [[mental]] image of [[emptiness]]. Then, entering the [[Path of Preparation]], he utilizes [[meditation]] in order to prog­ ress through four levels, [[successively]] removing the [[mental]] image at each level. When it is completely gone and the [[practitioner]] [[perceives]] [[emptiness]] directly, he has entered the [[Path of Seeing]] ([[mthong lam]]) and is called an "[[Arya]]. " What he sees and the [[state]] he has [[attained]] is indicated in the next [[stanza]]. STANZA 63 /gang gang la brten skye ba'i dngos/ /de de med pas de mi skye/ /dngos dang [[dngos med]] [['dus byas]] dang/ /'dus [[ma byas]] 'di mya [[ngan]] [['das]]/
+
224
  
Anything which arises in [[dependence]] on any [[causes]] will not arise without those [[causes]]. Hence, functional things in the [[form]] of produced [[phenomena]] and non­ functional things as unproduced [[phenomena]] would be [[empty of inherent existence]] which is the natural [[state]] of nirviit)ll .
+
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
- see also [[permanence]] [[imputation]] 50, 66, 7�7 1 , 98 - see also [[basis of imputation]] - see also superimposition [[imputation]] by [[thought]] 1 5 3
  
175
+
inattentive [[perception]] 46 - see also [[perception]] [[individuality]] 102-103 infallible 45 {{Wiki|inference}} 45 [[inherent existence]] 68-69, 99, 102 - see also devoid of [[inherent existence]] - see also [[empty]] - see also [[empty of inherent existence]] - see also [[existence]] [[inherently existing]] [[characteristics]] so, 1 1 3 initial [[moment]] 40 - see also [[moment]] innate {{Wiki|conception}} of [[inherent]] ex­ istence 64 - see also [[existence]] intelligence/wisdom 55-56 [[intention]] 55-56, 1 5 7 [[karmic formations]] 2 6 , 30 Khu 182, 202-204 lDan kar catalog 192 [[liberation]] 1 32-133, 1 3 5 , 1 52 , 172 - see also [[peace]] [[main mind]] 1 16 - see also [[mind]] [[Manjushri]] 97 mark 1 10 - see also sign [[meditation]] 59, 1 73 - see also analytic [[meditation]] - see also [[concentration]] [[mental consciousness]] 37, 39, 1 5 2 - see also [[consciousness]] - see also [[mind]] [[mental factors]] 1 16 - see also secondary [[mental]] fac­ tors
  
[[Ignorance]] as a [[cause]] produces [[karmic formations]] and so forth, which are functional things, but these cannot arise without that [[ignorance]]. When such functional things do not [[exist]], their opposite [[nature]], non-functional things, cannot [[exist]]. Therefore functional things in the [[form]] of composite [[phenomena]] and non-functional things as non-composite [[phenomena]] are devoid of an [[inherently existent]] [[nature]]; this is known as natural nirvaQ.a. If a [[person]] develops the [[wisdom]] which [[understands]] this and acquaints himself more and more with this [[wisdom]], assisted by the method of repeated [[meditation]], he or she can attain the [[state]] of non­ abiding nirvaQ.a which is free from the extremes of [[cyclic existence]] and [[solitary peace]]. The [[two extremes]] of [[eternalism and nihilism]] do not [[exist]] but there are [[people]] who fall on these extremes. However, the [[two extremes]] of [[cyclic existence]] and [[solitary peace]] which are posited from the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] point of view are [[existent]] and also there are [[people]] who fall on these ex­ tremes. The nonabiding nirvaQ.a of the [[Mahayana]] Vehi· :e is free from these extremes. STANZA 64 /rgyu [[rkyen]] las skyes [[dngos po]] [[rnams]]/ /[[yang dag]] [[nyid]] du [[rtog pa]] gang/ /de ni ston pas ma rig gsungs/ /de las yan l)lag bcu [[gnyis]] 'byung/ l )P:yag
+
[[mental]] (generic) image 40, 42, 50, 63, 156 [[mental]] image of [[emptiness]] 63, 178 [[middle way]] 1 79 [[mind]] 37-38, 16�162 - see also [[main mind]] - see also [[mental consciousness]] - see also moments of [[mind]] - see also unmistaken [[mind]] mistaken {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[cognition]] 47, 62 - see also [[cognition]] - see also {{Wiki|conception}} mistaken [[sensory perception]] 46 - see also [[perception]] [[moment]] 37 - see also initial [[moment]] momentary {{Wiki|disintegration}} 132, 143 - see also {{Wiki|disintegration}} moments of [[mind]] 1 1 1 , 162 - see also [[mind]]
  
The [[Teacher]], [[Buddha]], said that the {{Wiki|conception}} of [[true existence]] of functional things which arise from [[causes and conditions]] is [[ignorance]]. From this [[ignorance]] arise the twelve dependent limbs. Things which are produced by [[causes and conditions]] do not [[exist]] truly or inherently. The {{Wiki|conception}} of the [[self]] of [[phenomena]] refers to the [[ignorance]] of [[grasping]] at the [[true existence]] of [[aggregates]] contaminated by [[actions]] and delu­ sion. The twelve dependent limbs arise from this [[ignorance]].
+
[[Mula]] - see M ulamadhyamakaktirikti Mulamadhyamakaktirika 1 8 1 , 1 86 mutually dependent 137, 1 39
  
1 76
+
Nagiirjuna 17, 67-74, 156, 185187 [[name and form]] 26-27, 2 9 , 3 2 [[name]] 3 2 [[nihilism]] 1 7 5 , 1 7 7 [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] view 1 3 4 , 1 5 7, 1 79 - see also extreme view nirv8I].a - see [[peace]] non-composite [[phenomenon]] 142, 144 - see also [[phenomenon]] [[non-existing]] 99 - see also [[existence]] non-functional [[phenomenon]] 123, 126 - see also [[phenomenon]] non-functional thing 99, 175 - see also thing [[non-inherent]] [[existence]] 70, 74, 176 - see also [[existence]] {{Wiki|nose}} 37
  
Niigiirjuna's [[Seventy Stanzas]]
+
Index [[object]] 66, 120 - see also [[appearing object]] [[object]] [[condition]] 38, 68 - see also [[condition]] [[olfactory consciousness]] 37 - see also [[consciousness]] [[omniscience]] 65 - see also [[truth]] origination - see [[dependent origination]] overestimation 73, 129, 147, 170 - see also extreme view [[Parahita]] 177, 189, 200 [[path of accumulation]] 174 [[path of meditation]] 64 [[path]] of no more {{Wiki|learning}} 65 [[path]] of preparation 64, 17 4 [[path of seeing]] 49, 64, 133, 174 [[peace]] 3 1 , 35, 1 0 1 , 1 32-136, 1 5 5 , 1 7 5 , 180-181 - see also [[liberation]] [[perception]] 36 - see also inattentive percep­ tion - see also mistaken [[sensory perception]] - see also valid direct percep­ tion - see also valid {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[cognition]] {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[cognition]] 41 - see also [[cognition]] {{Wiki|perfect}} [[cognition]] 44 - see also [[cognition]] {{Wiki|perfect}} [[reason]] - see {{Wiki|inference}} [[permanence]] 129 - see also [[impermanence]] [[person]] 32-36, 74, 99, 104, 1 5 1 - see also [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] "I" - see also [[self]] [[phenomenon]] 68, 72, 124 - see also composite phe­ nomenon - see also functional phe­ nomenon - see also non-functional phe-
  
STANZA 65 /[[dngos po]] stong par de rtogs l )na/ /[[yang dag]] [[mthong]] [[phyir]] rmongs mi 'gyur/ /de ni ma rig [['gog pa]] [[yin]]/ /de las [[yan lag]] bcu [[gnyis]] '[[gag]]/ l)D:nas
+
225
  
[[Understanding]] the [[non-inherent]] [[existence]] of things means [[seeing]] the [[reality]] [i.e., [[emptiness]]] which elim­ inates [[ignorance]] about the [[reality]] of things. This brings about the [[cessation]] of ignorantly [[grasping]] at an apparently [[true existence]]. From that the twelve limbs of [[dependent origination]] cease. In this and the previous [[stanza]] we have [[Nagarjuna's]] restatement of the [[four noble truths]]. The twelve limbs are [[suffering]] [[existence]]. Their source is [[ignorant]] [[grasping]]. Suf­ fering ceases when [[ignorant]] [[grasping]] ceases. [[Seeing]] [[reality]] is the [[path]]. The [[reality]] of things is then described in the next [[stanza]] in terms familiar to us from the MUlamadhyama­ kakiirikii and the [[Perfection of Wisdom]] sfltras.
+
nomenon - see also produced and com­ pounded [[phenomena]] - see also thing
  
STANZA 66 /'[[du byed]] dri za'i [[grong]] l)khyer dang/ /[[sgyu ma]] 2)smig rgyu skra shad dang/ /dbu 3)ba chu bur [[sprul]] 4)pa dang/ /[[rmi lam]] mgal me'i [['khor lo]] mtshungs/ l)D:khyeng 2)P:mig 3)D:pa 4)P:ma
+
Prasannapadii 157, 189
  
Produced [[phenomena]] are similar to a village of gan­ dharvas, an [[illusion]], a [[hair]] net in the [[eyes]], foam, a bubble, an [[emanation]], a [[dream]], and a circle of {{Wiki|light}} produced by a whirling firebrand. A less {{Wiki|metaphoric}} description of the [[reality]] of things is found in the next two [[stanzas]].
+
precise analysis S S , 57 preconceptions 1 7 1 - see also [[distortions]] [[primary consciousness]] 38, 5 3 - see also [[consciousness]] produced and [[compounded]] phe­ nomena 1 04 - see also [[phenomenon]]
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
Ratniivali 1 8 1
  
177
+
[[reason]] 160 - see also {{Wiki|inference}} [[rebirth]] 29, 35 - see also [[liberation]] [[recollection]] S S [[regret]] S S result 103, 107 , 1 38 - see also [[cause]] - see also cause-effect relationships revulsion 3 1 secondary [[mental factors]] 3 8 , 5 3 - see also [[mental factors]] [[seeing]] 1 39 - see also [[sense fields]] [[self]] 69, 175 - see also {{Wiki|conception}} of [[self]] - see also [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] "I" - see also [[grasping]] at [[self]] - see also [[person]] - see also [[selflessness]] [[self-existent]] 165 [[selflessness]] 32-35, 49 - see also [[person]] self-sufficient 74 sense-fields 2fr.27, 165-166
  
STANZA 67 /[[rang bzhin]] gyis ni 'ga' [[yang]] med/ /'di la [[dngos po]] med pa'ng med/ /rgyu dang [[rkyen]] las skyes ba yi! /dngos dang [[dngos med]] stong ba [[yin]]/ There is nothing which [[exists]] inherently. In that fashion even non-functional things do not [[exist]]. There­ fore, functional things which arise from [[causes and conditions]] as well as non-functional things are [[empty of inherent existence]]. STANZA 68 /dngos kun [[rang bzhin]] stong l )pas na/ /[[de bzhin gshegs pa]] mtshungs med pas/ /rten [[cing]] 'brel par 'byung ba 'dil /[[dngos po]] [[rnams]] su nye bar bstan/ l)D: has
+
[[Seventy Stanzas]] - see S hunyatiisaptatikiirikii­ niima
  
Because all things are [[empty of inherent existence]] the Peerless Tathiigata has shown the [[emptiness]] of inher­ ent [[existence]] of [[dependent arising]] as the [[reality of all things]]. [[Stanza]] 67 lays the [[logical]] groundwork for [[stanza]] 68, but it does seem rather superfluous, as [[stanza]] 63 has already made the same argument. Indeed, although this [[stanza]] appears in the [[root verses]] and in the "autocommentary, it is missing from both the [[Candrakirti]] and [[Parahita]] commen­ taries, suggesting that it may be an interpolation. At any rate, [[stanza]] 68 is very [[interesting]] because it is such a clear statement of the actual [[nature]] of the [[reality]] whose conven­ tional aspect was {{Wiki|metaphorically}} described in [[stanza]] 66. As we see, it is quite free from extremes. By asserting depend­ ent [[arising]], [[nihilism]] is avoided, and by asserting the [[emptiness]] of [[inherent existence]], {{Wiki|eternalism}} is avoided. The [[reality]] revealed by the [[Buddha]] in the [[middle view]] is the [[empty nature]] of [[dependent arising]]. Its reverse face is the "
+
[[Seventy Stanzas]] Explaining How [[Phenomena]] Are [[Empty]] of Inhe-
  
178
+
226
  
 
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
 
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[Seventy Stanzas]]
  
[[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[appearance]] of things. In a certain [[sense]] the two complement each other, like concave and convex, be­ [[cause]] they are two aspects of one [[reality]]. In the next [[stanza]] this complementarity is implied by the postulating of a single limit for all [[reality]]. This naturally leads to a further [[discussion]] of the [[Buddha's]] use of [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] {{Wiki|expressions}} when [[teaching]] about this [[reality]]. STANZA 69 /[[dam]] pa'i don ni der [[zad]] de/ /'[[jig rten]] [[ngor]] byas [[tha snyad]] dag/ /[[sna tshogs]] thams cad [[rdzogs]] [[sangs rgyas]]/ /[[bcom ldan 'das]] [[kyis]] l )[[bden]] [[brtags]] [[mdzad]]/ l)D:brten brtag
+
rent [[Existence]] S hunyatasaptatikarika­ ndma [[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]] - see S hUnyatdsaptatikarika­ ndma S hunyatasaptatikarikanama 12-14, - see
  
[[Ultimate reality]] is contained within the limit of the [[non-inherent]] [[existence]] of a thing. For that [[reason]], the Accomplished [[Buddha]], the Subduer, has [[imputed]] various terms in the manner of the [[world]] through comparison. [[Reality]] is not beyond the limit of what is known by a valid direct {{Wiki|perceiver}}. This limit must also subsume con­ ventional [[reality]]. Within this limit the [[Buddha]] makes two kinds of comparisons. One is to examine the various things of [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[reality]], to determine whether the names used to designate these [[objects]] are actually suitable for this {{Wiki|purpose}}. In the second case, he compares the different aspects of an [[object]] to each other and to their names. These comparisons require that the [[Buddha]] utilize the different [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] terms used by the [[people]] of the [[world]] in order to examine the [[objects]] which they believe to [[exist]]. This process will eventually lead to the creation of a [[mental]] image of [[emptiness]] whose actual limit corresponds to that of [[reality]]. But in this process some [[people]] may become confused and, not [[understanding]] that the [[Buddha]] only uses these conventionalities for the [[sake]] of comparison, may take them to be [[realities]], though actually they are merely im-
+
79, 96, 200, 208--2 10
  
[[Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness]]
+
Shunyatasaptativivrtti 1 89, 200 Shunyatdsaptativrtti 1 89, 200-20 1 sign 56, 109
 +
 
 +
- see also mark simultaneously 1 1 8 [[six sense]] fields - see [[sense fields]] [[skandha]] - see [[aggregates]] [[sleep]] 5 5 {{Wiki|smells}} 3 7 {{Wiki|sounds}} 3 7 [[special insight]] 6 3 subsequent moments 40 - see also [[moment]] [[suchness]] 152 [[suffering]] 148 - see also [[death]], [[grief]], suf­ fering - see also [[liberation]] superimposition 49, 170 - see also [[imputation]] [[Sutra Pitaka]] 1 6 1 sutrasaniuccaya 1 8 1 [[tactile consciousness]] 3 7 - see also [[consciousness]] tangibles 37 {{Wiki|tastes}} 37 Tathiigina 152, 1 79 thing 68 - see also composite thing - see also functional thing - see also non-functional thing - see also phenomemon thought-consciousness 172 - see also [[consciousness]] [[three poisons]] 3 1 three times 107, 140 time
  
179
+
- see three times {{Wiki|tongue}} 37 [[true existence]] 99, 1 2 5 , 175 - see also [[existence]] [[truth]] - see [[conventional truth]] - see [[two truths]] - see [[ultimate truth]] [[Tsong kha pa]] 187 [[Tun-huang]] [[manuscripts]] 194-197 twelve limbs of [[dependent origination]] 26-32 - see also dependent origina­ tion Twelve Topic Treatise 189, 197-198 [[two truths]] 65 - see also [[truth]] [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] 146, 173 - see also [[truth]] [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] analysis 1 5 3 [[ultimate reality]] 1 78 - see also [[ultimate truth]] [[ultimate truth]] 65, 7 1 - see also [[truth]] underestimation 129 - see also extreme view unmistaken [[mind]] 1 73 - see also [[cognition]] - see also [[mind]] valid [[cognition]] 4 1 , 44-45, 67, 1 1 6 - see also [[cognition]] valid {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[cognition]] 44, 48, 50, 62 - see also [[cognition]] valid direct [[perception]] 178 - see also [[perception]] valid {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[cognition]] 44 - see also [[cognition]] - see also [[perception]] [[visual consciousness]] 37 - see also [[consciousness]] ways of [[knowing]] 52 [[wisdom]] - see intelligence/wisdom [[worldly]] convention 97-99 - see also [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] terms

Latest revision as of 15:06, 7 May 2020


puted for the sake of analysis. This problem is described in the next stanza. STANZA 70 /'jig rten pa yi chos bstan mi 'jig cing/ /yang dag nyid du nam yang chos l)bstan med/ /de bzhin gshegs 2)pas gsungs pa ma rig pas/ /de las dri med brjod pa 'di las skrag/ l)D:bsten 2)P:psa What is shown conventionally to the world appears to be without disintegration, but the Buddha has never actually shown anything with true existence. Those who do not understand what is explained by the Tathii­ gata to be conventionally existent and empty of the sign of true existence are frightened by this teaching. Here we see that when making comparisons the Buddha and Nagarjuna seem to speak as if things were permanent, that is, do not disintegrate, but this is only because conven­ tional expressions make things seem permanent. Such permanence would imply true existence for things, which they never assert. People who make such interpretations merely demonstrate their lack of understanding of the Bud­ dha's intentions. Furthermore, many of these people have a dangerous misunderstanding of the middle way, believing that non-existence is being taught, when actually non­ inherent existence is being taught. They have fallen into the extreme of the nihilistic view, misinterpreting emptiness as indicating actual non-existence, and this nihilistic attitude causes them to be fearful when they hear the Buddha teach about non-inherent existence. Another misinterpretation would be to take the Buddha's teaching about causality at face value, forgetting his chief underlying thought. This is discussed in the next stanza. STANZA 7 1

I' di la brten nas 'di 'byung zhes/

1 80

Niigiirjuna's Seventy Stanzas /'jig rten tshul 'di mi 'gog cing/ / l)gang brten rang bzhin med 2)pas de/ /ji ltar yod 'gyur de nyid nges/ l)P:kang 2)P:bas It is known in the way of the world that "this arises in dependence on that." Such statements are not refuted. But whatsoever arises dependently does not exist in­ herently, and how can that non-inherent existence itself have inherent existence? In fact, that non­ inherent existence must definitely not exist in­ herently!

Here Nagarjuna reminds his auditors that causality, which in reality is dependent arising, is itself without inher­ ent existence. It would also be a mistake to believe that the non-inherent existence of dependent arising itself had true existence, when in actuality it too must be without inherent existence. In another context this is known as the emptiness of emptiness. Both are refutations of a subtle eternalist interpretation of a teaching meant to refute eternalism. In the last two stanzas of the Seventy Stanzas on Empti­ ness, Nagarjuna moves on from this point and summarizes the way in which his middle view leads to a nirviiQ.a which is superior to the nirviiQ.a of the lesser vehicle because it does not postulate the extreme view which asserts an actual non-cyclic existence. STANZA 72 /dad ldan de nyid l )chos 2)la brtson/ /3)tshul 'di rigs pas rjes 4)dpogs gang/ /S)rten med chos 6)'ga' 7)bstan pa yi/ /srid dang srid min spangs nas zhi/ l)P:tshol 2)D:lar rtson 3)P:chu la 4)P:dbogs S)D:brten 6)P,D:'gal 7)D:brtan

Those who have faith in the teaching of emptiness will strive for it through a number of different kinds of reasoning. Whatever they have understood about it in

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness

181

terms of non-inherent existence, they clarify this for others, which helps others to attain 8)nirvii1J.ll by abandoning grasping at the apparently true existence of cyclic existence and non-cyclic existence. 8)Lit: zhi; tranquility. STANZA 73 I'di dag rkyen 'di las 1 )rig nas/ /lta ngan dra ba kun ldog des/ /chags rmongs khong khro spangs pa'i phyir/ /ma gos mya ngan 'das pa thob/ 1)D:rigs

By seeing these internal and external phenomena arising from causes and conditions they will eliminate the whole network of wrong views. With the elimina­ tion of wrong views they will have abandoned attach­ ment, closed-mindedness and hatred and thereby attain nirvii1Jil unstained by wrong views. The clarification for others which is referred to in stanza 72 is not considered by Tibetans to be an act of compassion, or of bodhicitta, but a simple offering of the teaching which is an offshoot of the practitioner's own striving for under­ standing through reasoning. Tibetans hold two views on Nagarjuna's teaching about great compassion. One group asserts that compassion is implied in texts such as the Mulamadhyamakakiirikii and the Seventy Stanzas on Empti­ ness, while another group asserts that such texts are strictly philosophical and that Nagarjuna's teachings about com­ passion are to be found in other texts, such as Ratniivali, or Sutrasamuccaya. In any case, whatever our opinion on this subject may be, it is clear that here, in the concluding fifteen stanzas of the Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness, Nagar­ juna has demonstrated the practical implications of adopt­ ing the correct view of the middle way. For this view, implemented by meditative practice, will free the yogi from grasping after cyclic existence and set him on the path to nirvai].a.

1 82

Niigiirjuna' s Seventy Stanzas

THE COLOPHON /stong nyid bdun cu 1)pa'i tshig le'ur byas pa zhes bya ha/slob dpon 'phags pa klu sgrub kyis mdzad pa rdzogs so/lo tsa' ba gzhon nu mchog dang/ 2)gnyan dharma grags dang khu'i 'gyur dag las don dang tshig bzang du bris pa'o 1 )P omits 2)D:snyan dar ma These Seventy Stanzas Explaining How Phenomena Are Empty Of Inherent Existence have been written by the Teacher A rya Niigiirjuna and compiled by an unknown editor who referred to the better wordings and meanings of the translations by the translators Gzhon nu mchog, Gnyan dharma grags and Khu. Nagarjuna's seventy three stanzas were translated into English in the years 1 982 and 1983 by the Venerable Geshe Sonam Rinchen, the Venerable Tenzin Dorjee and David Ross Komito at the Library of Tibetan Works and Archives in Dharamsala, India. The commentary on the seventy three stanzas is based on the oral explanations given by Geshe Sonam Rinchen while the translation was in prog­ ress and later edited by David Komito. The root stanzas and commentary were then orally retranslated into Tibetan and corrected by Geshe Sonam Rinchen. Our translation and interpretation of the Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness pri­ marily follows the traditions of Sera Monastery, Lhasa, Tibet, and that given by Candrakirti in his ShUnyatiisaptati­ vrtti (sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa'i 'grel pa) and secondarily follows that given by Parahita in his ShUnyatiisaptativivrtti (sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa'i rnam par bshad pa). Italicized words in the English translation of the root stanzas corres­ pond to those Tibetan words which actually appear in the Tibetan root stanzas; words which are not italicized in the English translation of the root stanzas are interpolations placed in the stanzas in order to clarify their meaning and are based on the commentaries and on oral tradition.

Chapter Three The Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

1 83

Section 3-1 Treatises by Nagarjuna Nagarjuna, who seems to have lived in the second century, may be regarded as the father of philo­ sophical Mahayana. We know little or nothing a­ bout the circumstances of his life, and the legendary reports to be found in the works of Taranatha and other Tibetan historians obviously refer chiefly to a later Nagarjuna, a Tantric and sorcerer, whose fig­ ure has become merged into that of the earlier philosophical Nagarjuna in the consciousness of lat­ ter times. 1 Lamentably, this situation of minimal clarity concerning the details of the life of Nagarjuna has not-altered since 1956 when these words were written. Perhaps we shall never have much in the way of facts about Nagarjuna's life due to the general disinterest of Indians in historical or "biographi­ cal" records. K. Inada's work NO,garjuna (1970) contains a bibliography which lists all the significant articles and books which deal with such biographical concerns up to the date of its publication. If we survey these citations, we find a veritable quagmire of conflicting opinions. Robinson has quoted a number of these alternative views on pages 2 1 to 26 of his work Early Madhyamika in India and China. From

185

186

Nagarjuna's Seventy Stanzas

his summary it can be seen that scholars are unlikely to ever establish anything like a factual biography of Nagarjuna. I will simply follow the opinion of the majority of scholars and place his activities between 1 50 and 250 A.D. in India. As to the details of his life, I shall simply refer the reader to the above-mentioned references, as such details are second­ ary to our concerns in this book. The difficulty of identifying the authentic works of the second century Nagarjuna is clearly a more relevant issue, and is connected with the problem of establishing the best redaction of the text of the Seventy Stanzas for translation purposes. Some of the works in the Tibetan canon which are attributed to Nagarjuna have a clearly tantric character, and obviously belong to a later Nagarjuna. For other works, such a method of discrimination is not applicable, for their content is not so clearly tantric. The method typically adopted by the most discriminating Tibetan authorities, as well as by many modern scholars, is to only accept as authentic those works whose style and content closely agree with the Mulamadhyamakakarika (Mula). Thus, in essence, Nagarjuna is defined as being the author of the Mula, and any work which appears to accept or propose views other than those in the M ula is by definition authored by someone other than the Nagarjuna of the second century, and is not considered "authentic. " Such a method has its own strengths and weaknesses. Its strength lies in its exclusion of such clearly inappropriate works as those of the tantra class, for the tantric literature is, by common agreement of all modern scholars, a develop­ ment which postdates the second century Nagarjuna, no matter in what era its roots may lie. The weakness of this method lies in the tendency of some scholars to exclude works which seem to have minimal emphasis on the pras­ aJiga style of exposition. Thus, if a work seems to make some positive assertions or to have some Cittamatra tenden­ cies, for example, these scholars would have to consider it to be inauthentic. The problem here is that Nagarjuna

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

1 87

preceded such sectarian splits in the Mahiiyana stream which he so influenced. As the general approach I follow in this book is to express the views of Tibetan scholars, I will also do so in regards to the question of determining what are the authentic works of Nagarjuna. Modern scholarly opinion may disagree with the views of Tibetan scholars, and, indeed, often such modern scholarly opinion is not unanimous on a variety of issues. Lindtner has a very useful summary of the opinions of modern scholars concerning the authenticity of various works attributed to Nagarjuna. 2 But since our general pur­ pose is to present the Tibetan scholarly view, such disagree­ ments only become relevant in regards to questions about the authenticity of the so-called "autocommentary" (Shiinya­ ttisaptativrtti) to the Seventy Stanzas and its appropriate­ ness for establishing the text of the Seventy Stanzas, so I will simply refer the interested reader to Lindtner's summary. As to the authenticity of the "autocommentary" to the Seventy Stanzas, I will return to this problem shortly. If we turn to the writings of Tibetan authorities on Nagarjuna, we will find that there is a group of works which they all attribute to him and there is a second group of works which is considered authentic by some and is rejected by others. Bu ston, in his History of Buddhism (Chos 'byung) indi­ cates that there are " . . . six main treatises of the Madhyami­ ka Doctrine (by Nagarjuna) demonstrating that, which is expressed by the sii.tras directly, or otherwise, the essential meaning (of the Doctrine). " [sic] 3 They are, in the order which he gives them: Shunyatasaptati, Prajiiamula, Yuk­ tishash#ka, Vigrahavyavartani, Vaidalyasu.tra and Vyavahara­ siddhi. He further states that Shunyatasaptati expounds " . . . the theory of Relativity [shii.nyata] of all elements of existence, devoid of the extremities of causality (rten 'brel) and pluralism (spros pa) . . . "4 "Tson[g] kha pa in his Gser phren says that the sixth work is considered by some to be the Vyavahara-siddhi, by

188

Niigiirjuna's Seventy Stanzas

others - the Akutobhayii or the Ratniivali, but that it is not correct to insist upon the number of treatises as being six. "5 And he adds, in his rTsa she ti ka chen rigs pa'i rgya mtsho, that the Seventy Stanzas was written in response to an objection raised concerning chapter seven of the Mula. 6 Taranatha mentions "five fundamental works" which according to Walleser does not include Vyavahiirasiddhi. 7 According to Obermiller, this work was never translated into Tibetan. 8 Atisha also lists the important treatises of Nagarjuna. In his Lamp of the Enlightenment Path (Byang chub lam gyi sgron ma), which is a signally important work for Tibetan Buddhism, he mentions only two works by Nagarjuna: Seventy Stanzas and Mula. 9 In his autocommentary to that work (Byang chub lam gyi sgron ma'i dka' 'grel) he expands upon this grouping, stating that similar to these two are Akutobhayii, Vigrahavyiivartani, Yuktishash#kii, Ratniivali, Mahiiyiinavi'f!lshikii, Ak�arashqtaka and Shiilistambakati­ kii. 10 Taking the Chinese point of view, Robinson notes that " . . . the basic stanzas in the Three Treatises [i.e. , the Madhyamika school] are the work of Nagarjuna and Aryadeva and correspond fairly closely with counterparts in Sanskrit and Tibetan . . . " 11 One of these treatises is called the Twelve Topics (Shih-erh-men-lun, Taisho # 1568). As it quotes the eighth and nineteenth stanzas from the Seventy Stanzas and was itself translated by Kumarajiva, we have an established later limit for the composition of the Seventy Stanzas and a further attestation of its authenticity. Thus, if we define Nagarjuna as being the indiviaual who authored the M ula, then he certainly is also the same Nagarjuna who authored the Seventy Stanzas, and accord­ ing to the consensus of the indigenous experts, this same person also authored Yuktishash#kii, Vigrahavyiivartani and Vaidalyasutra. These are the agreed upon five fundamental treatises which comprise a class with certain authorship. The second class of works, accepted as authentic by some experts but not considered authentic by others would in.

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

189

elude : Vyavah arasiddhi, A k u to b haya, R a tnavali, Mahayanavi�shika, Ak�arashataka and Shalistambakatika. Note that the "autocommentary" to the Seventy Stanzas is not included in either of these classes and that the Aku­ tobhaya, which is an "autocommentary" to the Mula, is not considered by all authorities to have been authored by Nagarjuna. Besides the karika(s) of the Seventy Stanzas itself (Peking Ed. #5227), the bsTan 'gyur contains three commentaries on the Seventy Stanzas. The so called "autocommentary" is titled Shunyatasaptativrtti (sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa'i 'grel pa; Peking Ed. #5231); it is attributed to Nagarjuna. There is another and longer work of the same title which is au­ thored by Candrakirti (Peking Ed. #5268). The third com­ mentary is called Shunyatasaptativivrtti (sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa'i rnam par bshad pa; Peking Ed. #5269), and is authored by Parahita(bhadra). All three commentaries on the Seventy Stanzas, as well as the isolated karika(s) themselves, are extant only in Tibetan. 12 Just one karika has survived in Sanskrit, which is quoted in the Prasannapada. 13 Although the Seventy Stanzas was translated into Chinese, it has since been lost, 14 except for the two karika(s) found in the Twelve Topic Treatise. 15 In addition to the redaction of the Seventy Stanzas kari­ ka(s) in an isolated form, each of the three commentaries also contains a version of the Seventy Stanzas. As Ruegg says, " . . . the variations between these versions pose a num­ ber of philological and historical problems . . . . The version accompanying the Tibetan translation of Candrakirti's com­ mentary, and hence this commentary itself, differs from the version accompanying the commentary ascribed to Nagar­ juna; and the question arises as to whether Candrakirti knew this commentary or recognized it to be by Nagarjuna. " 16 I will investigate some ofthese historical and philological problems in the balance of this chapter. A parallel to the problem of the authenticity of the "auto­ commentary" to the Seventy Stanzas is the problem of the

1 90

Nagarjuna's Seventy Stanzas

authenticity of the "autocommentary" to the Mula, called the Aukutobhaya (Peking Ed. #5231). This treatise was translated into German by Max Walleser in 191 1 Y As the karika(s) of the Mula are embedded in this treatise, this translation was the first appearance of the complete text of the Mula in a western language. Walleser accepted the attribution of Nagarjuna's authorship, though later western scholars have taken exception to this view. De Jong does not consider this work to have been written by Nagarjuna, 18 nor does Lindtner/9 nor does Murti.20 The most convinc­ ing argument is given by Obermiller: As concerns the Akutobhaya, we have the following interesting statement in the Stoii thun Bskal bzaii mig hbyeq of Khai dub . . . It is said that many Tibetan authors consider the Akutobhaya to be an autocommentary (ran Q.grel) of Arya Nagarjuna, but such an opinion shows that they have not correctly analyzed the text. Indeed, the Akutobhaya, in com­ menting on the 2 7th chapter of the Miila­ Madhyamika, quotes from the Catul}.satika of Aryadeva with the indication: 'It has thus been said by the venerable Aryadeva.' It is quite impossible that Nagarjuna could have quoted the work of his pupil in such a manner . . . . Similar indications are to be found likewise in Tsoii kha pa's Legs bsad sftin po . . . where it is moreover said that Buddhapa­ lita, Candrakirti, and Bhavaviveka have not made a single quotation from the Akutobhaya and have not even mentioned it in their works. This is like­ wise an argument for denying the authorship of Nagarjuna. 2 1 Thus this commentary to the Mula loses some of its author­ itative character, though its usefulness for interpreting Madhyamika is not necessarily thereby diminished.22 It may be that we face a similar situation with the "auto­ commentary" to the Seventy Stanzas. As demonstrated by

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

191

the case of the "autocommentary" to the M ula, just because a text is attributed to Nagarjuna does not mean that it was authored by Nagarjuna. Following this line of reasoning, there is thus no basis for asserting that the "autocommen­ tary" to the Seventy Stanzas was authored by Nagarjuna just because the colophon makes this indication. Now this does not mean that the treatise is of no value, but it does suggest that there is no reason to believe that the "autocommen­ tary" is Nagarjuna's explanation of the Seventy Stanzas or that its version of the karika(s) is either older or more accurate than that in either the Candrakirti or Parahita commentaries. As Ruegg has pointed out, it is not clear that Candrakirti either knew of this "autocommentary" to the Seventy Stanzas or recognized it to be by Nagarjuna. He may have known of it, but not accepted its authenticity, or he may not have known of it, perhaps because it was au­ thored after Candrakirti composed his own commentary to the Seventy Stanzas. Should either be the case, then the "autocommentary" loses any special significance and should simply be considered a commentary with uncertain authorship and whose date of composition is uncertain, but possibly postdates Candrakirti (approx. 600-650 A. D . ).23 The balance of this chapter should shed some light on this problem, which is important when it comes to selecting the most appropriate redaction of the Seventy Stanzas for trans­ lating purposes.

Section 3-2 Translation of the Seventy Stanzas During the First Introduction ofBuddhism to Tibet Thanks to the efforts of Lalou, we can ascertain that the Seventy Stanzas was first translated into Tibetan during the Imperial period. In Journal Asiatique1 she has translated a work from the Peking bsTan 'gyur, mDo 'grel Vol. CXXVII, which she has shown to be, in actuality, a cata­ logue of the Tibetan canonical collection as it existed either at the time of the Emperor Khri srong lde brtsan (775-797 A . D . ), which is Lalou's position, or at the time of the Emperor Khri lde srong brtsan (799-8 1 5 A.D.), which is Tucci's position. He reviews the evidence in his Minor Buddhist Texts2 and concludes that the catalogue in the bsTan 'gyur can be dated to 8 12 A . D . This catalogue was assembled at the "Palace of lDan kar in sTod than" by dPal brcegs and Nam mkha'i snyin po, and contains over seven hundred works. In section XXII, titled "dbu ma'i bstan bcos la," i.e. , shastras on Madhyamika, we find listed a translation of the Seventy Stanzas and one of its commentaries. They are: Lalou's # 593 titled 1/sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa'i chig le'ur byas pal in 74 slokas; and Lalou's #594 titled 1/sTong pa 192

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

193

nyid bdun cu pa'i 'grel pal rigs pa drug cu pa'i 'grel pal in 280 slokas. # 593 is of course our very own Seventy Stanzas, as is evident from the title and from the number of stanzas. Though our Peking edition of the Seventy Stanzas has 73 stanzas instead of the 74 mentioned in this catalogue, this should not be considered as counterindicative of our con­ clusion. We know that portions of a text can be omitted by a copyist and it would be no surprise if a stanza were lost between the edition of the eighth or ninth centuries and that of the seventeenth or eighteenth centuries, or, for that matter, if one crept in. Indeed, stanza 67 in the Peking edition of the Seventy Stanzas is omitted in the sDe dge edition. In this case its authenticity might be confirmed by its existence in the "autocommentary" to the Seventy Stan­ zas in both the Peking edition and the sDe dge edition (folio 120b2). On the other hand, there is no certainty that the "autocommentary" itself was authored by Nagarjuna. That stanza 67 is missing in the Peking and sDe dge editions of the Candrakirti and Parahita commentaries suggests not only that stanza 67 is an interpolation but also that if either of these commentators knew of the "autocommentary" they rejected its authority. Furthermore, Lalou states that in regards to this cata­ logue of lDan kar a sloka is meant to indicate a meter of recitation, and not a stanza or phrase per se. 3 Thus the salutation and colophon could have been counted as two slokas along with 72 stanzas in the body of the Seventy Stanzas. Or there may have been 73 stanzas plus either the salutation or the colophon. Unfortunately, we cannot deter­ mine what is actually included in the number 74. Lalou's #594 presents another difficulty. As no author's name is indicated in the catalogue, we cannot know if this commentary is the "autocommentary," or if it is the com­ mentary of Candrakirti, which has the same title. As follows from Lalou's statement about the significance of the term "sloka" within this context, we cannot simply count up the number of phrases in any of the currently existing commen-

1 94

Nagarjuna's Seventy Stanzas

taries and compare that number with the number of slokas given in the catalogue. However, as the commentary of Candrakirti is rather extensive, we can assume with reason­ able certainty that it was not indicated by this entry in the catalogue, which would have been a considerably shorter work. However, the possibility that the commentary is actually by some currently unknown author cannot be ruled out. We can, nevertheless, adduce some other evidence which will demonstrate that, indeed, it is very likely that this commentary from the Imperial period is the same as the one which we have termed the "autocommentary. " To begin with, although the colophon to the "autocommentary" in the Peking edition (#523 1) mentions Nagarjuna, it does not list any translators. However, the colophon to the sDe dge edition of this work (Tohoku #3831) states that it was translated by Jinamitra and Ye shes sde.4 Hoffmann has identified these men as two of the compilers of Mahavyutpatti. 5 This work is known to be contemporary with the reign of Khri lde srong brtsan (following Tucci, above, who dates the Mahavyutpatti at 8 1 2 A. D.), and thus also the catalogue of Ldan kar. Therefore, the redaction of the autocommentary in the sDe dge edition would appear to be a copy of a work which was first translated during the Imperial period. This would seem to have survived the general destruction of texts during the Tibetan persecution of Buddhists during the ninth century. Indeed, the Blue Annals implies that such works had been preserved, as do modern scholars, such as Wayman.6 Additionally, Stein's explorations into Inner Asia and subsequent retrieval of manuscripts from Tun-huang has given us some further evidence in this matter. The India Office Library possesses a single folio in Tibetan of a work which La Vallee Poussin has identified as Shunyatasapta­ tivrtti. 7 The karika(s) commented upon are 19 through 23 inclusive. As the manuscripts in this collection are believed to be the production of translators and copyists from the

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

195

Imperial period, a comparison of these five karika(s) from the Tun-huang collection with the similar karika(s) from later editions of the bsTan 'gyur should be most informa­ tive. Therefore we include this fragment of the text below, accompanied by the corresponding karika(s) from Lind­ tner's edition of the "autocommentary. " 8 As can be seen, the Tun-huang karika(s) are much more similar to those in the "autocommentary" then they are to those in our edition of the Seventy Stanzas, which are based upon the isolated karika(s) in the bsTan 'gyur and the embedded karika(s) in the Candrakirti commentary. This further supports the view that the "autocommentary" in the bsTan 'gyur was, as indicated by its colophon, translated during the Imperial period, that it survived the destruction of texts during the ninth century, and is, most likely, the text indicated in the lDan dkar catalogue (#549). Tun-huang: 19 /dngos dang dngos myed cig car myed/ /dngos myed myed par dngos po myed/ /rtag du dngos po'i dngos myed de/ /dngos myed myed na dngos myed myed/ autocommentary: 19 Idngos dang dngos med cig car med/

/dngos med med par dngos po med/ /rtag tu dngos dang dngos med 'gyur/ /dngos dang dngos po med mi 'gyur/ Tun-huang: 20 /dngos po myed par dngos myed myed/ /bdag las ma yin gzhan las myin/ /de lta has na dngos po myed/ /de myed na ni dngos myed myed/ autocommentary:20 /dngos po med par dngos med med/

1 96

Niigiirjuna's Seventy Stanzas /bdag las ma yin gzhan las min/ Ide lta bas na dngos po med/ Ide med na ni dngos med med/ Tun-huang: 2 1 /dngos po yod pa nyid na rtag/ /myed na nges par chad pa yin/ /[ dngos po yo ]d na de gnyis yin/ /de phyir dngos po khas blangs myin/ autocommentary: 2 1 /dngos po yod pa nyid na rtag/ /med na nges par chad pa yin/ /dngos po yod na de gnyis yin/ /de'i phyir dngos po khas blangs min/ Tun-huang:22 /rgyun gyi phyir na de myed de/ /rgyu byin nas ni dngos po 'gag/ /snga ma bzhin du 'di ma grub/ /rgyu chad pa'i nyes pa 'ng yod/ autocommentary:22 /rgyun gyi phyir na de med de/ /rgyu byin nas ni dngos po 'gag/ /snga ma bzhin du 'di ma grub/ /rgyun chad pa yi nyes pa'ng yod/ Tun-huang:23 /skye 'jig gzigs pas mya ngan 'das/ /lam bstan stong nyid phyir ma yin/ /'di dag phan tsun bzlog phyir dang/ /log pa'i phyir na mthong ba yin/ autocommentary:23 /skye 'jig gzigs pas mya ngan 'das/ /lam bstan stong nyid phyir ma yin/

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

197

/'di dag phan tshun bzlog phyir dang/ /log pa'i phyir na mthong ba yin/ Returning to the catalogue of lDan kar, we find another title which follows Lalou's #593, and # 594 in consecutive order. Lalou's #595 is a work which is missing from the Tibetan canon as it is currently known to us. The title of the work in the lDan kar catalogue is 1/sTong pa nyid kyi sgo bcu gnyis pal rtsa ba dan 'grel par bcas pal in 600 slokas. This may be translated as Twelve Entrances of Shunyata Com­ mented (Upon) With Root (Verses). Unfortunately, no author is given and beyond the title we know nothing more ahout this work except that it does not appear in any current editions of the bsTan 'gyur. Apparently this is the same treatise as the work in the Chinese canon called Twelve Topic Treatise (Shih-erh-men-lun; Taisho # 1568) which we discussed earlier, an opinion shared by Lindtner and others. 9 Robinson, for example, has reconstructed the San­ skrit title of this Chinese translation as Dvadashamukhashas­ tra. Thus Twelve Topic Treatise is the same as Twelve En­ trances of Shunyata Commented Upon With Root Verses. The Chinese version is attributed to Niigiirjuna and was, as stated earlier, translated by Kumiirajiva. 10 The text is divided into twelve chapters, each dealing with one topic: the first chapter deals with causes and conditions; the seventh chapter deals with the existent and the non-existent. Chapter one contains a stanza which turns out to be stanza 8 in the Seventy Stanzas, and chapter seven contains only one stanza, which turns out to be stanza 1 9 in the Seventy Stanzas. 1 1 Seventeen of the other stanzas in the Twelve Topic Treatise are identical to stanzas in the Mula. Robinson states that the content of this treatise "is mostly a duplication" of the M ula; 12 its authorship is disputed. 1 3 The occurrence of Seventy Stanzas stanzas 8 and 19 in the Twelve Topic Treatise establishes an historical "later-limit" for the Seventy Stanzas which stands independently of any questions about the dates of Niigiirjuna's life. Robinson

198

Nagarjuna's Seventy Stanzas

believes that Kumarajiva obtained a copy of the Twelve Topic Treatise while still in Kashgar, perhaps about 360 A.D . , though he can produce no hard facts to support this assertion. 1 4 Inada gives the date of its translation by Kumarajiva as 409 A.D. 1 5 At any rate, it was certainly translated before his death in 413 A . D .

Section 3-3 Translation of the Seventy Stanzas During the Second Introduction ofBuddhism to Tibet During the "second introduction" of Buddhism to Tibet, the Seventy Stanzas again became a point of interest for translators rendering Madhyamika philosophy into Tibet­ an. It appears that much of the initial impetus for the work on Madhyamika came from Atisha, whose name is intimate­ ly connected with the reintroduction. In his influential work Lamp for the Bodhi Path he writes: The reasoning of the ShUnyatiisaptati, And of works like the M ulamadhyamaka also, Explain the proof for the emptiness Of inherent existence in entities. 1 He thus recommends these works to his disciples and all later generations of Tibetan Buddhists. If we look at the various works relating to the Seventy Stanzas in the bsTan 'gyur, we find that with the exception of the "autocommentary," the remaining two show the influence of Atisha to some degree. Let us therefore now examine these texts and the translators who worked with 199

200

Niigiirjuna's Seventy Stanzas

them. They are: [1] Seventy Stanzas itself, Shunyatiisaptati­ kiirikaniima; (Peking Ed. #5227); author: Nagarjuna; translators: gZhon nu mchog, gNyan dharma grags and Khu. [2] ShUnyatiisaptativrtti; (Peking Ed. #5268); author: Candrakirti; translators; Abhayakara and Dharma grags. [3] ShUnyatiisaptativivrtti; (Peking Ed. #5269); author: Pa­ rahita; translators: Parahita and gZhon nu mchog. The first point to note is that of the three translators of the Seventy Stanzas, except for Khu, each of the remaining two is also a eo-translator of a commentary upon the Seventy Stanzas root verses, and in the colophons to each of these commentaries the name of an Indian pandita is also men­ tioned. However, no Indian pandita's name is associated with the Seventy Stanzas. As each of the commentaries contain the Seventy Stanzas root verses they comment upon, it is my hypothesis that the root verses which are now extant under the title ShUnyatiisaptatikarikiiniima are an edition which was compiled out of previous translations of the commentaries to the Seventy Stanzas. To explore this hypothesis, and also to develop some of the historical con­ text of the translation of the Seventy Stanzas from Sanskrit into Tibetan during the second introduction of Buddhism to Tibet, we will turn our attention to these translators. The colophon to Shunyatiisaptativivrtti indicates that the treatise was translated at mTho gling monastery by Parahita (who is also its author) and gZhon nu mchog. mTho gling was the center of Atisha's initial activities in western Tibet during the years 1042 to 1045 , and we know from the biography of Atisha that Parahita accompanied him from Nalanda to mTho gling.2 Moreover, we also know from the colophon to Peking Ed. #5633 that Atisha and gZhon nu mchog worked together. Since we may assume that if Para­ hita accompanied Atisha to mTho gling, he in all likelihood also accompanied him to central Tibet, and since we have ample evidence of gZhon nu mchog's translating activities at mTho gling with other of Atisha's traveling companions, we may reasonably assume that ShUnyatiisaptativivrtti was

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

201

translated between 1042 and 1045 A. D . Since the text itself primarily explains the meaning of terms in the Seventy Stanzas, we may also presume that it was composed at mTho gling in the course of preparing the translation of the Seventy Stanzas which is embedded in it. 3 The colophon to the Peking edition of Candrakirti's Shunyatasaptativrtti indicates that it was translated in India at Nalanda monastery by Abhayakara and Dharma grags. Abhayakara was, according to Ruegg, "one of the last of the great Indian Buddhist masters whose works we possess," and "a prolific polymath" who was "a scholar of the Vikra­ mashila seminary" and "flourished at the time of King Ramapala (rg. ea. 1077- 1 1 30). "4 According to the Cam­ bridge History of India, Ramapala's reign dates are about 1077 to 1 120. 5 Taranatha states that Abhayakara was upa­ dhyaya ("gatekeeper," actually a title of respect) at both Vikramashlla and Nalanda during the reign of King Ramapala.6 He may have died in 1 125 A . D . 7 However, such statements do not mean that Abhayakara lived during the entire period of Ramapala's reign; indeed there is evi­ dence to suggest that he lived at the beginning of Ramapa­ la's reign, but not the end and that either he did not die in 1 125, or else lived an exceedingly long life. For example, the Blue Annals states that Abhayakara was a disciple of Naropa in the Kalachakra lineage. 8 The date of Naropa's death is not certain. Guenther suggests 1 100 A.D.,9 while Ferrari suggests 1040 A.D. 10 In the biography of Atisha we read that Naropa visited Vikramashila for about twenty days while Tshul khrims of Nag tsho was there, conversed with Atisha, and died several days later. We also read that "Some relics of his remains were brought to Tibet by Atisha. " 1 1 In the biography of Marpa we read of Atisha meeting Marpa after he had left Vikramashila and telling Marpa of Naropa's death. 1 2 This evidence would suggest that Naropa died around 1040 A . D . If Abhayakara died in 1 125, then he must have received his initiation into the Kalachakra at a very young age and lived to a very ripe old age.

202

Niigiirjuna's Seventy Stanzas

Further evidence comes from several colophons which show Abhayakara and Tshul khrims rgyal ba of Nag tsho as eo-translators: Peking Ed. #3965 , #3969, #3975 , #4012, and #40 1 8 . As Tshul khrims rgyal ba spent a few years at Nalanda, invited Atisha to Tibet and accompanied him to mTho gling, it is clearly the case that Abhayakara was active at Nalanda prior to 1040 A . D . , when Atisha and Tshul khrims departed for Tibet. I can find little further evidence which will help us to pin down Abhayakara's dates, and thus the dates of the translation of the Candrakir­ ti commentary. 13 Unfortunately, if we look for information about Dharma grags to help us in this matter, we find the yield very scanty. 14 Thus it is impossible to ascertain whether the Candrakirti commentary to the Seventy Stanzas was translated prior to Atisha's departure for Tibet or pos­ terior to his departure, and thus we also cannot know whether or not such a translation was in the possession of Parahita and gZhon nu mchog at mTho gling monastery, and thus whether the Tibetan translation of the Candrakirti commentary influenced the translation of Parahita's com­ mentary. This also implies that although the colophon to the Seventy Stanzas lists the names of gZhon nu mchog and Dharma grags, we do not know if one utilized the transla­ tion of the other to produce the isolated karika(s) of the Seventy Stanzas, or if yet a third person utilized their two commentary translations to produce the isolated karika(s) of the Seventy Stanzas. The third person listed in the Seven­ ty Stanzas colophon might seem to be a likely candidate; unfortunately, this third translator, whose name is Khu, is also hard to pin down, as Khu is the name of a clan which produced a number of able translators. Two likely candi­ dates do emerge, however. Khu ston brtson 'grus byung drung (101 1 - 1075)15 was born in eastern Tibet, and "conducted extensive studies under Jo bo se btsun" in Khams. 16 He later became a disciple of Atisha17 and did some translation work with

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

203

him. 1 8 He is also known to have taught the Prajfiiiparamita at Thang po che. It is possible that he is the Khu mentioned in the Seventy Stanzas colophon. If so, this is particularly interesting as we have already established that the "auto­ commentary" survived the persecution and text destruction of the ninth century, and was thus probably current in eastern Tibet where the practice of Buddhism was maintained. 19 Perhaps Khu ston brought this "autocom­ mentary" with him to central Tibet and utilized it, along with the other commentaries, in establishing the edition of the Seventy Stanzas? We simply do not have adequate evi­ dence to know. Moreover, there is a second Khu who is perhaps even a more likely candidate to be the Khu of the Seventy Stanzas colophon. The Blue Annals indicates that Pa tshab nyi ma grags, who was born in lOSS A.D. ,20 spent twenty three years in India, was active in the early twelfth century as a great expositor of the Miidhyamika system according to Candra­ klrti, and also states that his disciples were responsible for the spread of Madhyamika in central Tibet. 21 "The great commentary composed by the Acarya Candrakirti on the sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa (ShUnyatiisaptati) has been trans­ lated by Abhaya and sNur dharma grags. sPa tshab [sic] with the pandita Mudita revised more than 300 slokas of the first part of this commentary. "22 We know from the col­ ophon to Sutrasamuccaya (Tohoku #3934), that a Khu mdo sde 'bar worked with Pa tshab. We also find Khu mdo's name in other colophons to works by Niigiirjuna (for exam­ ple, Peking Ed. #S230 and #2666). We also know that Pa tshab prepared translations of Niigiirjuna's Yuktishashfikii and its commentaries, as well as Candrakirti's Prasannapa­ dii and Madhyamakiivatiira. Perhaps it was Pa tshab's col­ league or disciple Khu mdo who, working in Pa tshab's circle of translators, prepared an edition of the Seventy Stanzas based on the three available commentaries? We do know that among Pa tshab's "four sons" (i.e., his chief disciples), Zhang thang sag pa founded Thang sag monas-

204

Nagarjuna's Seventy Stanzas

tery, where he taught Madhyamika in accordance with Can­ drakirti's interpretation. The Blue Annals state that "due to him the teaching of the Madhyamika system continued up to the present time [i.e., 1476 A.D. when composition of the Blue Annals began] in Thang sag. "23 The inhabitants of this monastery "which was of great benefit for the Madhyamika system" include both Candrakirti and Para­ hita through Pa tshab in their lineage,24 which clearly sug­ gests that they had access to both commentaries on the Seventy Stanzas. In the end, there seems inadequate evidence to determine who this Khu mentioned in the Seventy Stanzas actually was, nor is the evidence adequate to arrive at a final conclu­ sion about the origin of the edition of the isolated karika(s) of the Seventy Stanzas in the bsTan 'gyur. Finally, one must even suppose that Bu ston ( 1290- 1 364 A. D.), who actually determint>d which treatises and redactions were to be in­ cluded in the bsTan 'gyur, might have had a hand in the final editing of the Seventy Stanzas. For one thing, the actual original manuscript of the Candrakirti commentary of Dharma grags (either the Tibetan or the Sanskrit, which one is unclear) was preserved at Bu ston's monastery of Zha lu up until the 1 940's. 25 Perhaps, in the end, he compared the versions of the Seventy Stanzas in the three commentar­ ies, produced an edited version based on those three, linked the names of the original translators of the differing com­ mentaries in a new colophon, and it is his edition which has come down to us as the Seventy Stanzas in the bsTan 'gyur! The karika(s) of the Seventy Stanzas do, at any rate, read differently at places than do the karika(s) in the commentar­ ies on it, although their meanings generally agree. For the most part the Candrakirti and Parahita commentaries have quite similar versions of the Seventy Stanzas root verses and these are in closer agreement with the isolated root verses of the Seventy Stanzas than are the root verses in the "auto­ commentary. " Lindtner, who also notes this, suggests that the latter commentary may have been unknown to those

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

205

who prepared the former two commentaries, as does Ruegg.26 The evidence which we have thus far adduced in this chapter would tend to support this conclusion. We are thus left with what appear to be two separate transmissions of the Seventy Stanzas. One is represented by the isolated Seventy Stanzas karika(s) in the bsTan 'gyur, the Candra­ kirti commentary and the Parahita commentary, and the other is represented by the "autocommentary. " Although the Tibetan version of the "autocommentary" is certainly older than the Tibetan versions of the Candrakirti and Parahita commentaries, this says nothing about the age of the Sanskrit originals. Finally, we have no clear information which would allow us to date the redaction of the isolated karika(s) of the Seventy Stanzas in the bsTan 'gyur, although it seems probable that they are based on the Can­ drakirti and Parahita commentaries. There is thus no basis for determining which transmis­ sion is derived from the oldest Sanskrit redaction of the Seventy Stanzas nor which transmission is the more accurate translation of the lost Sanskrit original. Thus a decision about the most accurate reading for establishing a text edition or translation of the Seventy Stanzas is left in the hands of individual contemporary translators who must make such judgements in accordance with other criteria.

Section 3-4 Contemporary Translation Activities Among Nagarjuna's treatises, the Seventy Stanzas seems not to have aroused too much interest on the part of translators until about the last ten years. No doubt this is due, in part, to the difficulties of the text and its discrepencies in the commentaries, the loss of the Sanskrit original and the assumption that for the most part it merely duplicates argu­ ments made in the Mula. As to this assumption, readers who compare the two texts will find that this is not entirely the case, although in both style and content the two trea­ tises are similar enough to assure that they were composed by the same author. In recent years the Seventy Stanzas has been translated into Danish 1 and Japanese.2 A number of stanzas of the Seventy Stanzas have been translated into English in various scholarly articles and popular books. 3 The first complete translation of the Seventy Stanzas into English was my own in 1 979.4 In 198 1 Luvsantseren published an English trans­ lation of the Seventy Stanzas5 which was followed by Lindt­ ner's in 1982 .6 Unfortunately, as Luvsantseren's transla­ tion was published in Mongolia I have been unable to obtain a copy. 206

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

207

Lindtner, in commenting on his translation of the Seven­ ty Stanzas states "Though I have consulted C[andrakirti] and P[arahita] my translation of the karikas strictly follows the svavrtti [autocommentary] which must, of course, re­ main the final authority in questions of interpretation. "7 I see no reason why the "autocommentary" should remain "the final authority. " As I have shown, the "autocommen­ tary" was translated several centuries prior to the Candra­ kirti and Parahita commentaries and independently of them. But this does not mean that it was authored prior to these commentaries, and there is some evidence to suggest that indeed it was not authored prior to them (cf. section 3-1). There also is no certainty that the "autocommentary" was actually authored by Nagarjuna. It may have been, but it may not have been; in the case of the "autocommentary" on the Mu/a (Akutobhayii) scholarly opinion leans in the direction of refuting the attribution of authorship to Nagar­ juna, as I also have suggested (cf. section 3-1) and as Lind­ tner suggests. 8 Though the original translation of the "auto­ commentary" certainly predates the translation of the Can­ drakirti and Parahita commentaries as well as the isolated karika(s) of the Seventy Stanzas in the bsTan 'gyur, there is no reason to assume that any one of the Sanskrit redactions of the Seventy Stanzas which were translated and worked into the Tibetan translations of the commentaries was a more faithful copy of the second or third century A.D. original. Nor is there any reason to presume that an earlier translation is more accurate than a later translation. There is thus no reason to presume the superiority of the "auto­ commentary" as a basis for establishing the text of the Seventy Stanzas or for making translations or interpreta­ tions. On the other hand, there is also no fundamental reason for not using the "autocommentary" for establishing the text of the Seventy Stanzas or for guidance in translating it or interpreting it. As I suggested in section 3-3, the "autocommentary" represents one transmission of the Seventy Stanzas while the Candrakirti and Parahita com­ mentaries represent another. The isolated karika(s) of the

208

Niigiirjuna's Seventy Stanzas

Seventy Stanzas in the bsTan 'gyur are probably connected to the Candrakirti and Parahita transmissions, and were certainly edited after these two commentaries were trans­ lated, but the "autocommentary" may also have been con­ sulted by the editor who prepared this redaction of the Seventy Stanzas. My aim in translating and presenting the Seventy Stanzas has been to document what the contemporary Tibetan tradition believes Nagarjuna to be saying, and to place this explication in the framework of the monastic educational curriculum because the texts studied in this curriculum determine the interpretations given to Na"garjuna. Since this tradition selfconsciously places itself in the lineage which follows Candrakirti's interpretation of Nagarjuna, it makes sense to use the Candrakirti commentary as the basis for making interpretations of the Seventy Stanzas. We have used all the available commentaries and versions of the Seventy Stanzas when clarifying obscurities and scrib­ al errors in the Tibetan text of the Seventy Stanzas. When discrepencies in the texts have gone beyond this and there has been no other way to establish the best reading of the text we have followed Candrakirti, both to establish the text and to translate it. In truth I can make no claim that the translation of the Seventy Stanzas in this volume is a com­ pletely accurate version of what Nagarjuna was saying when he wrote the Seventy Stanzas. There have been too many centuries of copying, editing and interpreting the karika(s) for any translator to make such a claim. Moreover, every translator brings certain philosophical assumptions into the activity of translating, and the resultant text bears the stamp of these assumptions. Different assumptions also effect the choice of redactions used as the bases for the translation. As we have followed the Candrakirti commen­ tary to clarify difficulties in the Seventy Stanzas text, our translation of the Seventy Stanzas differs in places from Lindtner's, who has followed the "autocommentary. " This does not make either translation superior to the other: each

Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness and its Transmission

209

is correct in what it translates. One claim that I can make, however, is that our translation is an accurate rendering of what contemporary Tibetans of the dGe lugs pa sect say Nagarjuna means, and this is all we had in mind. In a larger cultural sense, however, there is a problem with assuming that English speakers will be able to under­ stand what Tibetans say Nagarjuna means simply because they say it in English or because I have translated it into English. Concepts like "inherent existence" (svabhava; rang bzhin) or "emptiness" (shiinyata, stong pa nyid) or even "permanence" (nityatva, rtag pa nyid) all have special technical meanings in a treatise such as the Seventy Stanzas. These are familiar to a Tibetan monk who has engaged in many years of formal study of the various treatises which explain these terms and their significance in the larger Buddhist scriptural context. Most English speakers do not have the benefit of such an education, and so lacking the proper context for understanding the terms in the Seventy Stanzas, may misinterpret their meanings. We have sought to minimize this problem by interpolating many words into our translation of the Seventy Stanzas which do not appear in the Tibetan text and by providing a stanza by stanza commentary on it. To maintain a distinction between those words which do and do not appear in the Tibetan text, in section 2-2 we have italicized those English words which literally translate words in the Tibetan text, and left our interpolated words without italicization. For the scholar, the Tibetan text is also provided. I have already indicated how we established the text. To provide a more systematic insight into the scriptural context in which Tibetan monks function when reading Nagarjuna and to aid the reader in understanding the thrust of the arguments in the Seventy Stanzas I have written a chapter which outlines some fundamentals of Buddhist thought ( 1 -2), epistemology ( 1-3) and psychology ( 1 -4 and 1-5). I have also written a section which summarizes the basic elements of Nagarjuna's discourse ( 1 -6).

Footnotes FOOTNOTES, Preface 1 . I have discussed this issue and the value of Bud­ dhadharma for the practice of psychotherapy in the west in: Komito, "Tibetan Buddhism and Psychotherapy: A Con­ versation with the Dalai Lama," and "Tibetan Buddhism and Psychotherapy: Further Conversations with the Dalai Lama."

FOOTNOTES, Section 1 -2 1 . Majjhima Nikiiya, 1 .262; Samyutta Nikiiya, 2 . 28 . 2 . Conze, Buddhist Thought in India, p. 1 5 . 3 . Dhammasangani 1309. 4. Segal, "Sleep and The Inner Landscape: An interview with the Tibetan physician Dr. Yeshe Dhonden," p. 3 1 . FOOTNOTES, Section 1 -3 1 . Elaborated in Dharmakirti's Commentary to Ideal Mind, Pramiir}llviirttikiikiirikii, Tshad ma rnam 'grel gyi tshig le'ur byas pa. A complete outline of Dharmakirti's episte­ mology can be found in Rabten, The Mind and its Functions. In this section I only discuss those aspects of this episternal210

Footnotes

211

ogy that are directly relevant to understanding the Seventy Stanzas. This epistemology is also presented, in a somewhat different arrangement, in Akya Yong dzin, A Compendium of Ways of Knowing and Rinbochay and Napper, Mind in Tibetan Buddhism. 2. Cf. also stanza 62 .

FOOTNOTES, Section 1-4 1 . Especially Asarlga's Compendium of Abhidharma, Abhidharmasamuccaya, mNgon pa kun btus. Asarlga's system is summarized in Rabten, The Mind and its Functions. 2. Rabten, ibid. , p . 5 2 . 3 . Ibid. 4. Ibid. , p. 59. 5. Ibid. , p. 58. FOOTNOTES, Section 1 -5 1 . Taken from the Visuddhimagga as translated by Conze in Buddhist Meditation, p. 1 1 3-1 1 8 . I have substituted the term "dhyana" for "jhana" throughout. 2 . The description of the meditative path is extremely complex, and what follows is a mere thumbnail sketch which, for the sake of brevity, leaves out many important details. A full detailed description of these techniques of meditation can be found in Rinbochay et al. , Meditative States in Tibetan Buddhism. A detailed description of the path in regards to taking emptiness as the object of medita­ tion can be found in Hopkins, Meditation on Emptiness. 3 . The Tibetan view is that to obtain this final path one must take up the practice of tantra; cf. Hopkins, ibid. , p. 109- 123. FOOTNOTES, Section 1 -6 1 . Cf. section 1-2 and Hopkins' various discussions of ignorance listed on p. 996 of Meditation on Emptiness. Hop­ kins' book is the most complete exposition of the Tibetan interpretation of Candrakirti now available in English; it

212

Nagarjuna's Seventy Stanzas

expounds in detail many of the points I have summarized in this section. 2 . Prasannapada, folio 456-7; Sprung, Lucid Exposition of the Middle Way, p. 2 1 1 . Sprung's book is the most complete translation of Candrakirti's Prasannapada now available in English. 3 . Seventy Stanzas, stanza 2. Here nirvai].a refers to "in­ trinsic" or "natural" nirvai].a; cf. stanza 63.

FOOTNOTES, Section 3-1 1 . Hoffmann, Religions of Tibet, p. 32. 2. Lindtner, Nagarjuniana, p. 9- 1 7 . 3 . Obermiller, History of Buddhism, Vol. I, p. 50. 4. Ibid . , p. 5 1 . 5 . Obermiller, "The Doctrine of Prajiiaparamita as Ex­ posed in the Abhisamayalamkara of Maitreya," Acta Orient­ alia, XI, p. 4 . 6 . Tsong kha p a , rTsa she ti k a chen rigs pa'i rgya mtsho, p. 26-27. 7 . Chattopadhyaya, Taranatha's History of Buddhism in India, chapter on Nagarjuna. Walleser, Life of Nagarjuna, p. 434, as quoted in Robinson, Early Madhyamika in India and China, p . 26. 8 . Obermiller, "The Doctrine of Prajiiaparamita as Ex­ posed in the Abhisamayalamkara of Maitreya," in Acta Orientalia XI, p. 4 . 9 . Peking Ed. #5344, folio 276b. 10. Peking Ed. #5345 , folio 324a. 1 1 . Robinson, Early Madhyamika in India and China, p. 28. 1 2 . Murti, The Central Philosophy of Buddhism, p. 89; Lindtner, Nagarjuniana, p. 3 1-33 . 1 3 . la Vallee Poussin, Prasannapada, p. 89. 14. Ramanan, Nagarjuna's Philosophy, p. 36. 1 5 . Robinson, Early Madhyamika in India and China, p. 32; Hsueh-li Cheng, Nagarjuna's 'Twelve Gate Treatise,' translates Seventy Stanzas stanza 8 on p. 56 and stanza 19 on p. 85, but does not provide the text.

Footnotes

213

16. Ruegg, The Literature of The Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India, p. 2 1 . 17. Walleser, Die M ittlere des Niigiirjuna nach der tibetischen version ubertragen. 1 8 . De Jong, Cing Chapitres de la Prasannapadii, p. IX . 19. Lindtner, Nagarjuniana, p. 15-16. 20. Murti, The Central Philosophy of Buddhism, p . 89. 2 1 . Obermiller, "The Doctrine of Prajiiaparamita as Ex­ posed in the Abhisamayalamkara of Maitreya," Acta Orient­ alia XI, p . 4-5 . 22. Streng, Emptiness, p. 239. 23. Ruegg, The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India, p. 7 1 .

FOOTNOTES, Section 3-2 1 . 1953, p. 3 1 3 . 2 . Tucci, Minor Buddhist Texts, Part 11, p . 52-54. 3. Journal Asiatique, 1953, p. 3 1 5 . 4. Folio 27a, and also Inada, Niigiirjuna, p. 188. 5. Hoffmann, Tibet: A Handbook, p. 133. 6. Roerich, The Blue Annals, p. 45 , and also Wayman, Calming the Mind and Discerning the Real, p. 5 . See also section 3-3 note 19. 7. la Vallt!e Poussin, Catalogue of the Tibetan Manuscripts from the India Office Library, p. 204. 8. Lindtner, Nagarjuniana, p. 42-44. 9. Ibid. , p. 1 1 . 10. Robinson, Early Miidhyamika in India and China, p. 26-27. 1 1 . Hsueh-li Cheng, Niigiirjuna's 'Twelve Gate Treatise,' p. 56 and 85 . 12. Robinson, Early Miidhyamika in India and China, p. 32-33. 13. Lindtner, Nagarjuniana, p. 1 1 ; Cheng, Niigiirjuna's 'Twelve Gate Treatise,' p. 27. 14. Robinson, Early Miidhyamika in India and China, p. 72 . 1 5 . Inada, Niigiirjuna, p. 19 1 .

2 14

Niigiirjuna's Seventy Stanzas

FOOTNOTES, Section 3-3 1 . Peking Ed. #5344, folio 276b. 2 . Das, Journal of the Buddhist Text Society, p. 29. 3. See Komito, A Study of Niigiirjuna's 'Sunyatii-saptati­ kiirikii-niima,' p. 33-36 for further details concerning Para­ hita and gZhon nu mchog. 4. Ruegg, "The gotra, ekayana and tathagatagarbha theories of the Prajiiaparamita according to Dharmamitra and Abhayakaragupta," in Prajiiiipiiramitii and Related Sys­ tems, p. 284. 5. Vol. Ill , p. 5 1 1 . 6. Chattopadhyaya, Tiiriinatha's History of Buddhism in India, p. 329. 7 . "According to Sum pa Ye shes dpal 'byor('s) Re'u mig Abhayakaragupta died in shin sbrul 1 125." Ruegg, The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India, p . 1 14. 8. Roerich, The Blue Annals, p. 760. 9. The Life and Teaching of Niiropa, Introduction. 1 0 . Ibid . , note 2 . 1 1 . Das, "Indian Pandits in Tibet," in Journal of the Buddhist Text and Research Society, Vol. I, part 1 , p. 2 1 . 1 2 . Bacot, La Vie de Marpa, p . 34. 1 3 . See Komito, A Study of Niigiirjuna's 'Sunyatii-saptati­ kiirikii-niima , ' p . 3 6 - 4 3 for more information on Abhayakara. 14. Ibid . , p. 43-44. 1 5 . Roerich, The Blue Annals, p. 93-94 and p. 404. 16. Ibid. , p. 93 . 1 7 . Chattopadhyaya, Atisha and Tibet, p. 363. 1 8 . Cf. colophon to Peking Ed. #5028. 1 9 . "In his [rNgog lo tsa ba blo ldan shes rab, born 1059 A.D.] teaching he followed the traditions of the Prajiiapara­ mita as taught during the period of the early spread of the Doctrine and which had been preserved in Khams. " Roerich, The .Blue Annals, p . 328 and p. 330. 20. Ruegg, The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of =

Footnotes

215

Philosophy in India, p. 1 14. 2 1 . Roerich, The Blue Annals, p. 34 1-343 . 22. Ibid. , p. 342 . 23. Ibid . , p. 344-45. 24. Ibid. , p. 344. 2 5 . Ibid. , p. 342 . 26. Lindtner, Nagarjuniana, p. 32; Ruegg, The Litera­ ture of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India, p. 20. FOOTNOTES, Section 3-4 1 . Lindtner, Niigiirjuna's Filosofiske Voerker, 1982 . 2 . Uryuzu, Daijo Butten XIV. 3. Dalai Lama XIV and Hopkins, The Buddhism of Tibet and the Key to the Middle Way, 1 975 , translates Seventy Stanzas 5ab on p . 69 and stanza 64 on p. 75 . Wayman, Calming the Mind and Discerning the Real, 1978, translates stanza 1 on p. 276 and stanza 68 on p. 1 95 . Ruegg, The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India, 198 1 , translates stanzas 58, 69, 70, 7 1 and 72 on p . 2 1 . Cheng, Niigiirjuna's 'Twelve Gates Treatise,' 1982, translates stanza 19 from the Chinese on p. 85 and apparently, though there is no formal attribution to this effect, stanza 8 on p. 56. 4. Komito, A Study of N_iigiirjuna's 'Sunyatii-saptati­ kiirikii-niima,' 1979. 5 . Luvsantseren, Philosophical Views of Niigiirjuna, 198 1 . Reviewed in Buddhists for Peace, Journal of the Asian Buddhist Conference for Peace, Vol. 3 ( 198 1), p. 63. 6. Lindtner, Nagarjuniana, 1982 . 7. Ibid. , p. 32-33. 8 . Ibid. , p. 15-16.

Bibliography

Entries under "Peking Edition" refer to The Tibetan Tripi­ taka, D . T . Suzuki, ed. Tokyo: Otani University, 1962. Akya Yong dzin. Blo rigs kyi sdom tshig blang dor gsal ba'i me long. Translated by Geshe Ngawang Dhargyey et al. as A Compendium of Ways of Knowing. Dharamsala: Library of Tibetan Works and Archives, 1976. Asaiiga. Compendium of Abhidharma. Abhidharmasamuc­ caya, mNgon pa kun btus. Peking Edition #550. Atisha. Bodhipathapradipa, Byang chub lam gyi sgron ma and Bodhimargapradipapafljika, Byang chub lam gyi sgron ma'i dka' 'grel. Text in Sherburne, Richard F. A Study of AtiSa's 'Commentary' on His 'Lamp of the Enlightenment Path.' Ann Arbor: University Microfilms International, 1 976. Bacot, Jacques. La Vie de Marpa le "Traducteur. " Paris: Buddhica 1 , 7, 1937. Buddhaghosa, Bhadantacariya. Visuddhimagga. Selections translated by Conze, Edward in Buddhist Meditation. New York: Harper and Row, 1969. 216

Bibliography

217

Candrakirti. M ulamadhyamakavrttiprasannapadii, db U ma rtsa ba'i 'grel pa tshig gsal ba. Peking Edition #5260. Candrakirti. Shunyatiisaptativrtti, sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa'i 'grel pa. Peking Edition #5268 Chattopadhyaya, Alaka. Atisa and Tibet. Calcutta: Indian Studies, 1967. Chattopadhyaya, D. Tiiriinatha's History of Buddhism in India. Simla: Indian Institute of Advanced Study, 1970. Cheng, Hsueh-li. Niigiirjuna's 'Twelve Gates Treatise. ' Dor­ drecht: Reidel, 1982 . Conze, Edward. Buddhist Thought in India. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1973 . Das, Sarat C. "Indian Pandits in Tibet," Journal of the Buddhist Text and Research Society, Calcutta. Vol. I, part 1 , 1 893 . De Jong, J . W. Cing Chapitres de la Prasannapadii. Paris: Librarie Orientaliste Paul Geuthner, 1949. Dhammasangani. Translated by Caroline Rhys Davids as A Buddhist Manual of Psychological Ethics. New Delhi: Oriental Books Reprint Corporation, 1975 . Dharmakirti. Commentary to Ideal M ind, PramiirJ.a­ viirttikakiirikii, Tshad ma rnam 'grel gyi tshig le'ur byas pa. Peking Edition #5709. Guenther, Herbert. The Life and Teaching of Naropa. Lon­ don: Oxford University Press, 1974. Gyatso, Tenzin: The Fourteenth Dalai Lama. The Buddh­ ism of Tibet and the Key to the Middle Way. New York: Harper and Row, 1975 . Hoffmann, Helmut. Religions of Tibet. London: Alien and Unwin, 196 1 . Hoffmann, Helmut. Tibet: A Handbook. Bloomington: Re­ search Center for the Language Sciences, 1975 . Hopkins, Jeffrey. Meditation on Emptiness. London: Wis­ dom Publications, 1983. Inada, Kenneth . Nagiirjuna: Mulamadhyamakakiirikii. Tokyo: Hokuseido Press, 1970. Komito, David. A Study of Niigiirjuna's 'Sunyatii-saptati-

218

Niigiirjuna's Seventy Stanzas

kiirikii-niima.' Ann Arbor: University Microfilms Inter­ national, 1979. Komito, David. "Tibetan Buddhism and Psychotherapy: A Conversation with the Dalai Lama," The Journal of Transpersonal Psychology, Vol. XV, # 1 , 1983 . Komito, David. "Tibetan Buddhism and Psychotherapy: Further Conversations with the Dalai Lama," The Jour­ nal of Transpersonal Psychology, Vol. XVI, # 1 , 1984. la Vallee Poussin, Louis de. Mulamadhyamakakiirikiis de Niigiirjuna avec la Prasannapadii. St. Petersberg, 19031914. la Vallee Poussin, Louis de. Catalogue of the Tibetan Manu­ scripts from the India Office Library. London: Oxford University Press, 1962 . Lalou, Marcelle. "Les Textes Bouddhiques au Temps du Roi Khri-srong lde-bcan," Journal Asiatique, 1953. L i n d t n e r , C h r . N iigiirjuna's Filosofiske Voerk er. Copenhagen: (publisher unknown), 1982 . Lindtner, Chr. Nagarjuniana . Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag, 1982 . Luvsantseren, S . Philosophical Views of Niigiirjuna . (pub­ lisher unknown), 198 1 . Majjhima Nikiiya. Selections translated in David Kalupaha­ na. Buddhist Philosophy: A Historical Analysis. Honolulu: University Press of Hawaii, 1976. May, Jacques. Candrakirti Prasannapadii Madhyamakavrtti. Paris: Adrien Maisonneuve, 1959. Murti, Tirupattur. The Central Philosophy of Buddhism. London: Allen and Unwin, 1970. Nagarjuna. Shunyatiisaptatikiirikiiniima, sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa'i tshig le'ur byas pa zhes bya ba. Peking Edition #5227. Nagarjuna. ShUnyatiisaptativrtti, sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa'i 'grel pa. Peking Edition #523 1 . Obermiller, Eugene. "The Doctrine of Prajiiaparamita as Exposed in the Abhisamayalaf\lkiira of Maitreya," Acta Orientalia, XI, 1932 .

Bibliography

2 19

Obermiller, Eugene. History of Buddhism by Bu-ston. Suzu­ ki Research Foundation (no date given) . Parahita(bhadra). Shunyatasaptativivrtti, sTong pa nyid bdun cu pa'i rnam par bshad pa. Peking Edition #5269. Rabten, Geshe. The Mind and its Functions. Mt. Pelerin: Tharpa Choeling, 198 1 . Ramanan, K . Venkata. Nagarjuna's Philosophy as Presented in the Maha-Prajiiaparamita-Sastra. Rutland : Tuttle, 1 960. Rinbochay, Lati and Napper, Elizabeth. Mind in Tibetan Buddhism. Valois: Gabriel Press, 1980. Rinbochay, Lati, et al. Meditative States in Tibetan Buddh­ ism. London: Wisdom Publications, 1983. Robinson, Richard. Early Madhyamika in India and China. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1967 . Roerich, George N. The Blue Annals. Delhi: Banarsidass, 1976. Ruegg, David S. "The gotra, ekayana and tathagatagarbha theories of the Prajftaparamita according to Dharmamitra and Abhayakaragupta," in Prajiiaparamita· and Related Systems, Louis Lancaster, ed. Korea: .Berkeley Buddhist Studies Series, 1977 . Ruegg, David S . The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz, 198 1 . Samyutta Niktiya . Selections translated in David Kalupaha­ na. Buddhist Philosophy: A Historical Analysis. Honolulu: University Press of Hawaii, 1976. Segal, William and Segal, Marielle. "Sleep and The Inner Landscape: An interview with the Tibetan physician Dr. Yeshe Dhonden," Parabola, Vol. VII, # 1 , 1982 . Sprung, Mervyn. Lucid Exposition of the Middle Way. Lon­ don: Routledge, 1979. Streng, Frederick. Emptiness - A Study in Religious Mean­ ing. New York: Abingdon, 1967. Tsong kha pa. rTsa she ti ka chen rigs pa'i rgya mtsho. Varanasi: Pleasure of Elegant Sayings Press, 1973. Tucci, Giuseppe. Minor Buddhist Texts, Part 11. Rome:

220

Niigiirjuna's Seventy Stanzas

Serie Orientale Roma, 1958. Uryuzu, Ryushin. Daijo Butten XIV. (publisher unknown). Walleser, Max. Die Mitt/ere des Niigiirjuna nach der tibetis­ chen version ubertragen. Heidelberg, 191 1 . Walleser, Max. "The Life of Nagarjuna from Tibetan and Chinese Sources," Hirth Anniversary Volume, Bruno Schindler, ed. London: Probsthain, (no date given). Wayman, Alex. Calming the Mind and Discerning the Real. New York: Columbia University Press, 1978.

Index Abhayakara 201 Abhidharma 53, 97 action 56, 145-157 agent 15{}..- 1 5 1 , 154-155 aggregates 27, 33 aggregation 102 analytic meditation 62 - see also meditation annihilationist view 129 - see also extreme view appearances 66, 69, 7 1 , 120, 132 appearing object 40, 57, 66 - see also object appreciation S S Arhat 1 0 1 arising 9 8 , 105-107, 125, 127 - see also dependent arising arising, enduring, ceasing 1 25-143 Arya 56, 58, 64, 174 Asatiga 52, 66 aspiration S S Atisha 1 8 8 , 199 attention 52, SS, 56 attraction 3 1 auditory consciousness 37 - see also consciousness basis of imputation 98, 1 19, 154 - see also functional basis see also imputation -

becoming 26, 29 birth 26 birth and death 30 body 37, 148-151 Bu ston 187 Buddha 23-24, 97, 156 buddhahood 65 calm abiding 63 Candrakirti 157, 177, 189, 202 cause 102, 107, 138 - see also dependent arising - see also result cause-effect relationships 25, 107, 129-1 3 1 , 138-139 cessation 125, 127, 135 cognition 37 - see also conceptual cognition - see also deceived cognition - see also direct valid cognition - see also erroneous cognition - see also erroneous conceptual cognition - see also ideal cognition - see also mistaken conceptual cognition - see also mistaken sensory cognition see also perceptual cognition - see also perfect cognition -

221

222

Niigiirjuna's Sevenly Stanzas

- see also valid cognition - see also valid conceptual cognition - see also valid perceptual cognition compassion 1 8 1 composite phenomenon 142-144, 149 - see also phenomenon composite thing 105 - see also thing compounded phenomenon 104 - see also phenomenon concentration 5 5 , 56 - see also eight stages of con­ centration - see also meditation conception 36, 42, 50, 154 - see also extreme conception conception of self 14 7 - see also self concepts 37, 66 conceptual cognition 4 1 , 43 - see also cognition condition 102 - see also dominant condition - see also immediate condition - see also object condition consciousness 26, 30, 37-38, 52, 152, 164, 168-169, 1 72 - see also auditory conscious­ ness - see also gustatory conscious­ ness - see also mental consciousness - see also olfactory consciousness - see also primary conscious­ ness - see also tactile consciousness - see also visual consciousness consciousness limb 26, 52 consciousness skandha 38 contact 2&-28, 37, 5 5 , 16&-168 continuity 130 - see also moment conventional 146, 1 5 3 , 1 78 - see also truth

conventional existence 99, 1 56 - see also existence conventional "I " 100 - see also "I" - see also self conventional terms 178 - see also worldy convention conventional truth 65 , 7 1 , 178-179 - see also truth correct belief 47-48, 62, 67 craving 26, 28 cyclic existence 3 1 death, grief, suffering 26 - see also suffering deceived cognition 43 - see also cognition defined 137 definition 1 37 delusion 3 1 , 150 dependence 28, 120 dependent arising - see dependence - see also dependent origination dependent origination 2 5 , 1 101 2 1 , 172-178 devoid of inherent existence 69, 102 - see also empty of inherent existence Dharma 1 80 Dharma grags 1 8 1 , 20 1 Dharmaltirti 36, 50, 67 direct valid cognition 48 - see also cognition discernment 55-56 discernment without signs 5&-57 disintegration 127 - see also momentary disintegration distinctions 140 distorted traces 3 1 distortions 1 12 , 124, 170, 172 "does not exist" 69, 1 56 - see also existence "does not exist inherently" 70 - see also existence

Index dominant condition 38 - see also condition ear 37 eight stages of concentration 59 - see also concentration emanation 1 54 empty (emptiness) 62-65, 68-70, 102, 133, 176--178 - see also inherent existence - see also truth empty of inherent existence 69 - see also devoid of inherent existence - see also empty - see also existence enduring 127 entrances - see sense fields epistemology 37 erroneous cognition 44 - see also cognition erroneous conceptual cognition 41 - see also cognition eternalism 134, 1 7 5 , 1 77, 180 eternalist extreme 1 5 7 eternalist view 129 - see also extreme view existence 69, 99, 156 - see also conventional exist­ ence - see also devoid of inherent existence - see also "does not exist" - see also "does not exist inherently" - see also empty - see also empty of inherent existence - see also exists non-inherently - see also inherent existence - see also non-inherent existence - see also true existence existence and non-existence 103104, 125-129, 14�145 "exists-and-does-not-exist" 1 56 exists non-inherently 70

223

experience 1 5 1 extinction 134 extreme conception 170 - see also conception extreme view 73, 157 - see also annihilationist view - see also eternalist view - see also nihilistic view - see also overestimation - see also underestimation eye 37 feeling 26--27, S S , 1 38-139, 167 five aggregates 1 5 3 - see also aggregates form 1 5 7-167 four evil preconceptions - see distortions four great elements 32, 1 5 8-159 four noble truths 3 1 functional basis 1 4 1 - see also basis o f imputation functional phenomenon 68, 123, 126 - see also phenomenon functional thing 68, 99, 1 75 - see also thing gateways - see sense fields general examination S S , 57 generic image - see mental image grasping 26, 28 grasping at self 100 - see also self gustatory consciousness 37 - see also consciousness gZhon nu mchog 1 82 , 200 "I" 29, 33, 99-100 - see also conventional "I" ideal cognition 44 - see also cognition ignorance 26, 30, 1 1� 1 1 7 , 1 72 , 1 75-176 immediate condition 38 - see also condition impermanence 170

224

Nagarjuna's Seventy Stanzas

- see also permanence imputation 50, 66, 7�7 1 , 98 - see also basis of imputation - see also superimposition imputation by thought 1 5 3

inattentive perception 46 - see also perception individuality 102-103 infallible 45 inference 45 inherent existence 68-69, 99, 102 - see also devoid of inherent existence - see also empty - see also empty of inherent existence - see also existence inherently existing characteristics so, 1 1 3 initial moment 40 - see also moment innate conception of inherent ex­ istence 64 - see also existence intelligence/wisdom 55-56 intention 55-56, 1 5 7 karmic formations 2 6 , 30 Khu 182, 202-204 lDan kar catalog 192 liberation 1 32-133, 1 3 5 , 1 52 , 172 - see also peace main mind 1 16 - see also mind Manjushri 97 mark 1 10 - see also sign meditation 59, 1 73 - see also analytic meditation - see also concentration mental consciousness 37, 39, 1 5 2 - see also consciousness - see also mind mental factors 1 16 - see also secondary mental fac­ tors

mental (generic) image 40, 42, 50, 63, 156 mental image of emptiness 63, 178 middle way 1 79 mind 37-38, 16�162 - see also main mind - see also mental consciousness - see also moments of mind - see also unmistaken mind mistaken conceptual cognition 47, 62 - see also cognition - see also conception mistaken sensory perception 46 - see also perception moment 37 - see also initial moment momentary disintegration 132, 143 - see also disintegration moments of mind 1 1 1 , 162 - see also mind

Mula - see M ulamadhyamakaktirikti Mulamadhyamakaktirika 1 8 1 , 1 86 mutually dependent 137, 1 39

Nagiirjuna 17, 67-74, 156, 185187 name and form 26-27, 2 9 , 3 2 name 3 2 nihilism 1 7 5 , 1 7 7 nihilistic view 1 3 4 , 1 5 7, 1 79 - see also extreme view nirv8I].a - see peace non-composite phenomenon 142, 144 - see also phenomenon non-existing 99 - see also existence non-functional phenomenon 123, 126 - see also phenomenon non-functional thing 99, 175 - see also thing non-inherent existence 70, 74, 176 - see also existence nose 37

Index object 66, 120 - see also appearing object object condition 38, 68 - see also condition olfactory consciousness 37 - see also consciousness omniscience 65 - see also truth origination - see dependent origination overestimation 73, 129, 147, 170 - see also extreme view Parahita 177, 189, 200 path of accumulation 174 path of meditation 64 path of no more learning 65 path of preparation 64, 17 4 path of seeing 49, 64, 133, 174 peace 3 1 , 35, 1 0 1 , 1 32-136, 1 5 5 , 1 7 5 , 180-181 - see also liberation perception 36 - see also inattentive percep­ tion - see also mistaken sensory perception - see also valid direct percep­ tion - see also valid perceptual cognition perceptual cognition 41 - see also cognition perfect cognition 44 - see also cognition perfect reason - see inference permanence 129 - see also impermanence person 32-36, 74, 99, 104, 1 5 1 - see also conventional "I" - see also self phenomenon 68, 72, 124 - see also composite phe­ nomenon - see also functional phe­ nomenon - see also non-functional phe-

225

nomenon - see also produced and com­ pounded phenomena - see also thing

Prasannapadii 157, 189

precise analysis S S , 57 preconceptions 1 7 1 - see also distortions primary consciousness 38, 5 3 - see also consciousness produced and compounded phe­ nomena 1 04 - see also phenomenon

Ratniivali 1 8 1

reason 160 - see also inference rebirth 29, 35 - see also liberation recollection S S regret S S result 103, 107 , 1 38 - see also cause - see also cause-effect relationships revulsion 3 1 secondary mental factors 3 8 , 5 3 - see also mental factors seeing 1 39 - see also sense fields self 69, 175 - see also conception of self - see also conventional "I" - see also grasping at self - see also person - see also selflessness self-existent 165 selflessness 32-35, 49 - see also person self-sufficient 74 sense-fields 2fr.27, 165-166

Seventy Stanzas - see S hunyatiisaptatikiirikii­ niima

Seventy Stanzas Explaining How Phenomena Are Empty of Inhe-

226

Nagarjuna's Seventy Stanzas

rent Existence S hunyatasaptatikarika­ ndma Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness - see S hUnyatdsaptatikarika­ ndma S hunyatasaptatikarikanama 12-14, - see

79, 96, 200, 208--2 10

Shunyatasaptativivrtti 1 89, 200 Shunyatdsaptativrtti 1 89, 200-20 1 sign 56, 109

- see also mark simultaneously 1 1 8 six sense fields - see sense fields skandha - see aggregates sleep 5 5 smells 3 7 sounds 3 7 special insight 6 3 subsequent moments 40 - see also moment suchness 152 suffering 148 - see also death, grief, suf­ fering - see also liberation superimposition 49, 170 - see also imputation Sutra Pitaka 1 6 1 sutrasaniuccaya 1 8 1 tactile consciousness 3 7 - see also consciousness tangibles 37 tastes 37 Tathiigina 152, 1 79 thing 68 - see also composite thing - see also functional thing - see also non-functional thing - see also phenomemon thought-consciousness 172 - see also consciousness three poisons 3 1 three times 107, 140 time

- see three times tongue 37 true existence 99, 1 2 5 , 175 - see also existence truth - see conventional truth - see two truths - see ultimate truth Tsong kha pa 187 Tun-huang manuscripts 194-197 twelve limbs of dependent origination 26-32 - see also dependent origina­ tion Twelve Topic Treatise 189, 197-198 two truths 65 - see also truth ultimate 146, 173 - see also truth ultimate analysis 1 5 3 ultimate reality 1 78 - see also ultimate truth ultimate truth 65, 7 1 - see also truth underestimation 129 - see also extreme view unmistaken mind 1 73 - see also cognition - see also mind valid cognition 4 1 , 44-45, 67, 1 1 6 - see also cognition valid conceptual cognition 44, 48, 50, 62 - see also cognition valid direct perception 178 - see also perception valid perceptual cognition 44 - see also cognition - see also perception visual consciousness 37 - see also consciousness ways of knowing 52 wisdom - see intelligence/wisdom worldly convention 97-99 - see also conventional terms