Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Kira Kōyō’s Inmyō Interpretations and Western Logic

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search




Introduction Kira Kōyō 雲英晃耀 (1831–1910) was a scholar priest of the Jōdo Shin Ōtani sect from the end of the Edo period to the Meiji period. He is known as the author of Gohō sōron 護 法総論 (1869) , which criticizes Christianity, as well as a researcher, educator, and popularizer of inmyō 因明, the East Asian transmission of DignAgean logic. His works include introductions to inmyō, such as Inmyō shoho 因明初歩 (1881) and Inmyō taii 因明大意 (1881)

Although significant recent research has been conducted on modern Japanese Buddhist history, little is known about the practice of inmyō at that time. The only overview of Buddhist logic in the Meiji era is the work by Funayama Shin’ichi (Funayama 1998) . Funayama summarizes inmyō studies in the context of the logical history of the Meiji era and states that Kira Kōyō, Ōnishi Hajime 大西祝 (1864–1900) , and Murakami Senjō 村上専精 (1851–1929) played

prominent roles as inmyō scholars. Murakami is famed as a modern Buddhist scholar, but his work as a Buddhist logician is not well known. Kira was Murakami’s teacher in this field and influenced Murakami’s inmyō studies. Recently, Ōnishi’s works have once again gained recognition, but Ronrigaku (Ōnishi

1903) , one of his most important works, has not been considerably investigated. Ōnishi advanced his study of logic, which includes inmyō studies, in discussions with Kira. Funayama notes another feature of Kira’s inmyō studies: He was a logician who adhered to the national sovereignty theory. He used inmyō to represent his political ideas and actively cultivated popularity and awareness of inmyō among politicians and lawyers. This study examines the characteristics of Kira Kōyō’s inmyō studies.


Kira Kōyō’s Inmyō Interpretations and Western Logic


Moro Shigeki


Popularization Activities of Inmyō Kira began to write inmyō works aggressively from 1881, when the imperial edict to establish the Imperial Diet was issued: Inmyō nisshōriron sho hōgUroku 因明入正理論疏方 隅録, Inmyō sanjUsanka hōgUroku 因明三十三過方隅録, Inmyō shoho, and Inmyō taii were published in 1881, followed by Inmyō sanjUsanka honsahō kahon 因明三十三過本 作法科本, Inmyō shoho, 2nd ed., Inmyō taii, 2nd ed., and Inmyō katsugen 因明活眼 in 1884. He

went on to write Inmyō sanjUsanka honsahō kōgi 因明三十三過本作法講義 (1885) , Tōyō shinshin inmyō hakki: Ichimei Nihon katsu ronri 東洋新々因明発揮: 一名 日本活論理 (1889) , and Tōyō shinshin inmyō ippan 東洋新々因明一斑 (1890) . According to Kira et al. (1890) , on December 14, 1882, he gave an inmyō

lecture at the request of Matsuoka Yasukowa 松岡康毅, who was the president of the appellate court of Hiroshima, and started actively lecturing on inmyō to politicians and lawyers throughout Japan. After 1890, the year of the first general election of the members of the House of Representatives, his writing

activity for promoting inmyō seemed to end, except for Inmyō nisshōriron kōgi 因明入正理論講義 (1893) . In the opening section of Inmyō nisshōriron sho hōgUroku, a traditional commentary of Yinming ruzhengli lun shu 因明入正理論疏, Kira claimed the applicability of inmyō to debates in parliament and courts:

Originally, inmyō was an Indian logic. When the proponent and the opponent confront each other to assert their own opinions, a logical sequence is needed. If [a proponent] has the logical sequence, his speech will be steady and full of spirit wherever he is, such as in the crowds of the government, the

parliament, or the court, or in the presence of sages. And with fearless mind, undaunted tongue, and no waste of words, [he will make his opponent] understand [his opinion] by a simple expression, and he will carry his opinion by concise words. [Inmyō is] a marvelous technique for winning arguments

and an essential golden rule in both the ultimate reality and the mundane truth, whether one is Buddhist or not, especially in the world of discussion, like today’s. (Inmyō nisshōriron sho hōgUroku, 1) It is reasonable to suppose that Kira used the words “the government, the parliament, or the court” and

“the world of discussion” in the above statement, echoing the imperial edict. Kira’s beliefs, noted above, were shared not only by Murakami Senjō, who was a disciple of Kira, but also by logicians. In his autobiography, Murakami recalled that around 1877, Kira was deeply saddened that inmyō was being forgotten, and invited him to study


inmyō and introduce it to the society of open speech soon to emerge (Murakami 1914: 167–169) . Asō Yoshiteru (Asō 2008) noted that the logicians in the Meiji era tended to use syllogisms to solve current problems or real issues. Asō also introduced Nishi Amane’s 西周 classification of logic: the logic of

kanmon 観門 (gate of observation) or scholastic logic and the logic of gyōmon 行門 (gate of practice) or applied logic. It may be presumed that Kira’s activities to popularize inmyō were influenced by Nishi’s classification. Kira’s inmyō lectures were not neutral presentations, but rather, reflected his political beliefs. In Inmyō taii (Summary of inmyō) , which was often used in his lectures, Kira expressed his political thought through inmyō while emphasizing the practical applications of inmyō. For instance, Kira used a three-part formula to criticize unequal treaties between


Japan and Europe (Inmyō nisshōriron sho hōgUroku, 6–7) :   Thesis: Japan and so forth can punish a person who has broken the law, based on their own laws.  Reason: Because they are independent empires.  Homologous example: Like Russian Empire.  Heterologous example: Like British Empire in India. Another example from Inmyō katsugen (Piercing eyes of inmyō) expressed opposition to the introduction of the republicanism in terms of sonnō 尊王 thought

(a view that advocates reverence for the Emperor)

(Inmyō nisshōriron sho hōgUroku, 24) .   Thesis: The principle of our country [namely Japan] that the imperial lineage should determine the ruler [of Japan] should not ever be changed.  Reason: Because it is an imperial order of an ancestor of the Emperor.   Homologous example: Like heaven and earth

which were apprehended as the eternal by the ancestor] .  Heterologous example: Like the game of go 碁. His sonnō thought is surely irrelevant to his criticism of Christianity in his early life. His thought was possibly influenced by his studying Buddhism under Kōzan’in RyUon 香山院 龍温 (1800–1885) , who wanted to enhance and teach the method of haja kenshō 破邪顕 正 or the refutation of non-Buddhist teachings and the revelation of correct thought

(Nanjō 1979) . In addition, Murakami also gave examples implicating a critique of Christianity in his inmyō survey Katsuyō kōjutsu inmyōgaku zensho 活用講述因明学全書 (Murakami 1891) , although he claimed to have no intention of criticizing Christianity.


To promote inmyō, Kira and his family established Inmyōgaku Kyōkai 因明学協会 (the Association for Inmyō Studies) at Isshiki-chō of Aichi prefecture, where his temple was located. However, he reported that it did not become widespread (Kira et al. 1890) . Reinterpretation of Inmyō on the Basis of Western Logic


Another important aspect of Kira’s inmyō studies is the reinterpretation of inmyō in terms of Western logic. Kira repeatedly claimed the superiority of inmyō over Western

logic. Logic for Oneself or Others? The opening verse of NyAyapravezaka states the purpose of the Buddhist logic (Yinming ruzhengli lun shu, T 32, 11a) : Proof (sAdhana) , refutation (dUSaNa) , and pseudo [of these two] are for making others aware (parasaMvid) . Perception (pratyakSa) , inference

(anumAna) , and pseudo [of these two] are for attaining insight oneself (AtmasaMvid) . Kira’s criticism of Western logic was based on this verse. He regarded it as kyUrijutsu 究 理術 or the art of seeking truth for attaining insight into oneself (AtmasaMvid) , since it had no examples to demonstrate to others. On the other hand, he emphasized that the example (dRSTAnta) made inmyō the method of arguing truth with others, that is, ronrijutsu 論理術

(Inmyō taii, 4–5. See also Funayama 1998: 305–306) . Therefore, he claimed that ronri 論理 was a mistranslation of the term “logic.” It should be clear that there is a close relationship between this understanding and his previously mentioned activities to popularize inmyō. Inoue Enryō 井上円了 made a similar comment in 1897 (Inoue 2003: 180– 181) . Deduction and Induction Logic in the Meiji era was based on J. S. Mill’s A System of Logic (1843) ,

which includes both inductive and deductive reasoning. Kira compared inmyō with these two systems and discussed the correspondence between them. The inductive method is of course the observation, because it is a method to discover the theory of nature. . . The deductive method doesn’t correspond to either the observation or the experimentation. (Tōyō shinshin inmyō hakki, 39–40) At first, since the observation, which is the most important expedient for experience in the Western

logical method, is the accurate recognition of all things, it corresponds to the perception (pratyakSa)

in the eight categories of inmyō. And the experimentation . . . corresponds to the inference

(anumAna) in the eight categories of inmyō. . . Therefore the logic is merely the perception and inference, which are a part of the eight categories of inmyō. (Tōyō shinshin inmyō hakki, 46–47. See also Funayama 1998: 331)

Comparing deduction, induction, and inmyō, Kira regarded the last of these as the most comprehensive and superior logic. It is reasonable to think that such an evaluation is similar to the traditional categorization of the Buddhist teachings or kyōsō hanjaku 教相判釈 in East Asia. This understanding was

adopted by Murakami, while scholars of Western logic criticized it. Ōnishi equally criticized these three logics and proposed to develop a new logic by critically integrating them (Ōnishi 1903) . Even today, the problem of the relationship among the three logics has been passed on to present-day scholars of Buddhist logic (e.g., Katsura 1998) . New-new Inmyō Kira pointed out the similarity between the form of a syllogism and the formula for inmyō:


The syllogism in logic is very similar to the adaptation (upanaya) and the conclusion (nigamana) , the last two parts of the five-part reasoning of the old inmyō. Now, I would like to demonstrate the form of the adaptation and conclusion of the old inmyō:  • Adaptation: The vase is produced. The vase is non-eternal. The sound is produced. The sound is also non-eternal.  • Conclusion: Therefore, the sound is non-eternal.  Next, I would like to illustrate the form of the syllogism of logic:  • First step: What is produced is non-eternal.  • Second step: A sound is produced.  • Third step: Therefore, the

sound is non-eternal. (Tōyō shinshin inmyō hakki, 43–44) Although Kira asserted the superiority of inmyō, in Tōyō shinshin inmyō hakki he stated that the simplicity of the syllogism was superior to the complexity of inmyō, and he suggested restructuring inmyō in the style of a syllogism. He called it shin-shin inmyō 新々因 明 (new-new inmyō) , compared with DignAgean logic being called shin inmyō 新因明 (new inmyō) . It consists of two groups of syllogism: hyōken shiki 表顕式 (positive syllogism) and hanken shiki 反顕式 (contradictory syllogism) . For demonstration, he used the following political examples:


A police officer, confronting a public speaker, argues:  • Hyōken shiki First step: Like a certain public speech by Kō 甲 (homologous example) , all public speeches recognized as sedition (reason) should be ordered canceled and dissolved (thesis) . Second step: Your public speech (thesis) is recognized as sedition (reason) . Third step: Therefore, your public speech should be ordered canceled and dissolved (whole thesis) .  • Hanken shiki

First step: Like a certain public speech by Otsu 乙 (heterologous example) , all speeches that should not be ordered canceled and dissolved (thesis) are not public speeches recognized as sedition (reason) . Second step: Your public speech (thesis) is recognized as sedition (reason) . Third step:

Therefore, your public speech should be ordered canceled and dissolved (whole thesis) . (Tōyō shinshin inmyō hakki, 90–92) It is reasonable to suppose that the term “public speech” alluded to JiyU minken undō 自 由民権運動 or the Movement for Civic Rights and Freedom in the 1880s. The shin-shin inmyō was criticized by Ōnishi and Murakami. Ōnishi claimed that shin-shin inmyō had no unique value, since there was little difference between shin-shin inmyō and the syllogism (Ōnishi 1889) . Murakami also criticized a person who wanted to change the order of inmyō based on

that of the syllogism, because the change would kill the feature of inmyō (Murakami 1891: 22) . It is easy to suppose that the person was Kira. Conclusion In its long history, inmyō has been studied as a part of Buddhist studies, although DignAga intended to develop a logical system independent from any school of thought (Katsura 1998) . It might be Kira’s contribution to remove inmyō from the Buddhist context, even if this was motivated by his xenophobia and nationalism. Moreover, it should be noted that his awareness of the inmyō problem, especially in comparison with the Western logic, has had

a wide influence through the ages, although his attempts to popularize inmyō failed. ―――――――――――――――― References Asō Yoshiteru 麻生義輝. 2008. Kinsei Nihon tetsugakushi: Bakumatsu kara Meiji Ishin no keimō shisō 近世日本哲学史: 幕末から明治維新の啓蒙思想 [History of philosophy in modern Japan: Enlightenment thought from the end of Edo period to the Meiji period] . Tokyo: Shoshi Shinsui.


Funayama Shin’ichi 舩山信一. 1998. Funayama Shin’ichi chosakushU 舩山信一著作集. Vol. 8. Tokyo: Kobushi Shobō. Inoue Enryō 井上円了. 2003. Inoue Enryō, gedō tetsugaku: Kan’yaku kyōten ni yoru Indo tetsugaku kenkyU 井上円了・外道哲学: 漢訳経典によるインド哲学研究 [Inoue Enryō’s study on nonBuddhist philosophies: Study of Indian philosophies based on the Chinese Buddhist translations] . Tokyo: Kashiwa Shobō. Katsura ShōryU 桂紹隆. 1998. Indojin no ronrigaku インド人

の論理学 [Indian logic] . Tokyo: ChUō Kōronsha. Kira Kōyō 雲英晃耀 et al. 1890. Inmyōgaku Kyōkai hōkoku 因明学協会報告 [Report on the Association for Inmyō Studies] . Aichi: Inmyōgaku Kyōkai. Murakami Senjō 村上専精. 1891. Katsuyō kōjutsu inmyōgaku zensho 活用講述因明学全書 [Utilization guide to inmyō] . Tokyo: Testugaku Shoin. —. 1914. RokujUichi nen 六十一年 [61 years] . Tokyo: Heigo Shuppansha. Nanjō Bun’yU 南條文雄. 1979. KaikyUroku: Sansukuritto koto

hajime 懐旧録: サンスクリット事 始め [Memoirs: Start of Sanskrit] . Tokyo: Heibonsha. Ōnishi Hajime 大西祝. 1889. “Inmyō ni tsukite” 因明につきて [On inmyō] . Tetsugakukai zasshi 哲 学会雑誌 3-29, 31, 32. —. 1890. “Kira Kōyō shi no doku Tetsugakukai zasshi inmyō ron. 雲英晃耀氏の読哲学会雑誌 因明論 [On Mr. Kira Kōyō’s paper on inmyō published in Tetsugakukai zasshi] .” Tetsugakukai zasshi 哲学会雑誌 4-42, 44. —. 1903. Ronrigaku. 論理学 [Logic] . Tokyo: Keiseisha.

This research is supported in part by a Grant-in-Aid for Scientific Research (C) from JSPS Grant Number 25370054)


Key words〉 Kira Kōyō, deductive reasoning, inductive reasoning, new-new inmyō (Associate Professor, Hanazono University, PhD)




Source