Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Madhyamika in Tibet"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
Line 6: Line 6:
  
  
However effective Chandrakirti may have been in vindicating the method of Buddhapalita and refuting Bhavaviveka, it is clear that he did not succeed in convincing all his contemporaries. There is no doubt that the Svatantrika method remained popular. Shantarakshita himself, who in his synthesis of the  
+
However effective [[Chandrakirti]] may have been in vindicating the method of [[Buddhapalita]] and refuting [[Bhavaviveka]], it is clear that he did not succeed in convincing all his contemporaries. There is no [[doubt]] that the [[Svatantrika]] method remained popular. [[Shantarakshita]] himself, who in his {{Wiki|synthesis}} of the  
  
Madhyamika and Yogachara schools represents the last great stage in the development of Buddhist philosophy in India, made use of independent syllogisms as Bhavaviveka had done several centuries before. He is therefore classified as a Svatantrika, although, as we shall see, this question is more complex than it appears. It was, in any case, Shantarakshita and his disciple Kamalashila who, at the invitation of King Trisong Detsen, carried the Buddhist sutra  
+
[[Madhyamika]] and [[Yogachara]] schools represents the last great stage in the [[development]] of [[Buddhist philosophy]] in [[India]], made use of {{Wiki|independent}} [[syllogisms]] as [[Bhavaviveka]] had done several centuries before. He is therefore classified as a [[Svatantrika]], although, as we shall see, this question is more complex than it appears. It was, in any case, [[Shantarakshita]] and his [[disciple]] [[Kamalashila]] who, at the invitation of [[King Trisong Detsen]], carried the [[Buddhist]] [[sutra teachings]] to [[Tibet]], with the result that the [[Madhyamika]] [[doctrine]] first established there was [[Yogachara-Svatantrika]], in which [[form]] it was to flourish for approximately four hundred years. Only in the twelfth century, when [[Patsap Nyima Drak]] translated the works of [[Chandrakirti]], did the [[Prasangika]] really take hold [[in Tibet]].
  
teachings to Tibet, with the result that the Madhyamika doctrine first established there was Yogachara-Svatantrika, in which form it was to flourish for approximately four hundred years. Only in the twelfth century, when Patsap Nyima Drak translated the works of Chandrakirti, did the Prasangika really take hold in Tibet.
 
  
 +
According to The [[Blue Annals]], Patsap was born in [[Penyul]] but left [[Tibet]] while still a child. He grew up in [[Kashmir]] and [[India]], where he studied at the feet of numerous famous and important [[scholars]]. He returned to [[Tibet]] around 1160 and embarked on a career of translation and [[teaching]]. He expounded in
 +
particular the six [[logical]] treatises ([[rigs tshogs]]) of [[Nagarjuna]] and, in collaboration with the [[Indian]] [[pandita]] [[Kanakavarman]], translated Chandrakirti5s [[Prasannapada]] and the [[Madhyamakavatara]], together with its autocommentary, as well as the commentary on the Yuktishastika by the same author. From slender beginnings he became an influential [[teacher]], and his return home marked a turning point in the study of [[Madhyamika]] [[in Tibet]].
  
According to The Blue Annals, Patsap was born in Penyul but left Tibet while still a child. He grew up in Kashmir and India, where he studied at the feet of numerous famous and important scholars. He returned to Tibet around 1160 and embarked on a career of translation and teaching. He expounded in
 
particular the six logical treatises (rigs tshogs) of Nagarjuna and, in collaboration with the Indian pandita Kanakavarman, translated Chandrakirti5s Prasannapada and the Madhyamakavatara, together with its autocommentary, as well as the commentary on the Yuktishastika by the same author. From slender beginnings he became an influential teacher, and his return home marked a turning point in the study of Madhyamika in Tibet.
 
  
 +
The introduction of [[Prasangika]] [[ideas]] was the focus of intense [[interest]]. Convinced that they were in possession of a more accurate and profound [[understanding]] of Nagarjuna5s [[doctrine]], the early [[Tibetan]] [[Prasangikas]] attacked the [[Svatantrika]] establishment with the [[enthusiasm]] of [[missionaries]]. They
  
The introduction of Prasangika ideas was the focus of intense interest. Convinced that they were in possession of a more accurate and profound understanding of Nagarjuna5s doctrine, the early Tibetan Prasangikas attacked the Svatantrika establishment with the enthusiasm of missionaries. They
+
encountered a sturdy resistance. The period of persecution inflicted by [[King Langdarma]] (836-841) had been followed by an intense [[religious]] and {{Wiki|scholastic}} renewal. And in the intervening period, before the return of Patsap, the [[Madhyamika]] had been closely studied, mainly according to the [[tradition]] laid down by [[Shantarakshita]] and [[Kamalashila]], but also following the works of [[Bhavaviveka]], which had also been translated in the early period. A number of great [[scholars]] had been involved in this enterprise, and by the twelfth century the [[Svatantrika]] view was well able to resist, at least for the time being, the
 +
wave of novelty. The [[master]] [[Chapa Chokyi Senge]], for example, whose [[interpretation]] of [[Dignaga]] and [[Dharmakirti]] was to [[form]]
 +
the basis of the [[logic]] [[tradition]] still upheld by the [[Gelugpa school]], was a formidable debater and defended with [[brilliance]] the [[Svatantrika]] view against [[Prasangika]] innovation. He composed several [[expositions]] of the [[Madhyamika]] system and numerous refutations of [[Chandrakirti]]. It is recorded that, on one occasion, he encountered in [[debate]], and defeated, the celebrated [[Indian]] [[Prasangika]] [[master]] [[Jayananda]].-
  
encountered a sturdy resistance. The period of persecution inflicted by King Langdarma (836-841) had been followed by an intense religious and scholastic renewal. And in the intervening period, before the return of Patsap, the Madhyamika had been closely studied, mainly according to the tradition laid down by Shantarakshita and Kamalashila, but also following the works of Bhavaviveka, which had also been translated in the early period. A number of great scholars had been involved in this enterprise, and by the twelfth century the Svatantrika view was well able to resist, at least for the time being, the
 
wave of novelty. The master Chapa Chokyi Senge, for example, whose interpretation of Dignaga and Dharmakirti was to form
 
the basis of the logic tradition still upheld by the Gelugpa school, was a formidable debater and defended with brilliance the Svatantrika view against Prasangika innovation. He composed several expositions of the Madhyamika system and numerous refutations of Chandrakirti. It is recorded that, on one occasion, he encountered in debate, and defeated, the celebrated Indian Prasangika master Jayananda.-
 
  
 +
Be that as it may, the [[Prasangika view]] gained ground [[in Tibet]] and eventually triumphed. Even before the translation of [[Chandrakirti]] by Patsap, the [[Prasangika view]] was advocated by [[Atisha]], whose role in the [[development]] of [[Tibetan Buddhism]] can scarcely be exaggerated; and it became intimately associated with the [[mind-training]] [[teaching]] of the [[Kadampas]], which exerted a {{Wiki|pervasive}} influence throughout the [[tradition]]. In their different ways, all [[four schools of Tibetan Buddhism]] have adopted the [[Prasangika]] approach一the [[teaching]] of [[Nagarjuna]], as interpreted by Chandrakirti一as the [[highest]] view on the [[sutra]] level. [[Svatantrika]] was driven into the shade, and nowadays, especially in the [[New Translation schools]], it is relegated to the d oxographic al {{Wiki|literature}}, in the context of which it is studied largely as a lower view to be examined and surmounted by students on their way to [[mastery]] of the [[Prasangika]] system. It is comparatively rare for the original writings of [[Svatantrika]] authors一even of Shantarakshita一to be studied at first hand.
 +
[[Mipham Rinpoche]] and the Prasangika-Svatantrika Distinction
  
Be that as it may, the Prasangika view gained ground in Tibet and eventually triumphed. Even before the translation of Chandrakirti by Patsap, the Prasangika view was advocated by Atisha, whose role in the development of Tibetan Buddhism can scarcely be exaggerated; and it became intimately associated with the mind-training teaching of the Kadampas, which exerted a pervasive influence throughout the tradition. In their different ways, all four schools of
 
  
Tibetan Buddhism have adopted the Prasangika approach一the teaching of Nagarjuna, as interpreted by Chandrakirti一as the highest view on the sutra level. Svatantrika was driven into the shade, and nowadays, especially in the New Translation schools, it is relegated to the d oxographic al literature, in the context of which it is studied largely as a lower view to be examined and surmounted by students on their way to mastery of the Prasangika system. It is comparatively rare for the original writings of Svatantrika authors一even of Shantarakshita一to be studied at first hand.
+
It is therefore of some [[interest]], before finishing with this topic, to advert to the [[attitude]] of [[Mipham Rinpoche]] toward the [[Svatantrika]] [[teaching]], specifically in the [[form]] advocated by [[Shantarakshita]]. Naturally, this finds its full expression in the [[great commentary]] on the [[Madhyamakalankara]], which is one of [[Mipham's]] great masterpieces, but it is appropriate to mention it briefly here, since not only does the view of [[Shantarakshita]] represent the final [[development]] of [[Madhyamika]] in [[India]], but it also profoundly qualifies the [[Nyingma]] [[understanding]] of the relationship between [[Prasangika]] and [[Svatantrika]], and of [[Madhyamika]] in general.
Mipham Rinpoche and the Prasangika-Svatantrika Distinction
 
  
 +
In the context of {{Wiki|modern}} [[Madhyamika]] {{Wiki|scholarship}}, dominated as it is by the [[Gelugpa]] and [[Sakyapa]] schools, the position of [[Mipham Rinpoche]] is liable to appear unusual, certainly unfamiliar. It is not, however, a personal eccentricity. One of the main [[reasons]] for [[Mipham's]] [[scholarly]] work was to revive and reexpress the teachings [[characteristic]] of the [[Nyingma school]]; his [[understanding]] of [[Madhyamika]] is rooted in the [[tradition]] of the Old Translations. Without going into
  
It is therefore of some interest, before finishing with this topic, to advert to the attitude of Mipham Rinpoche toward the Svatantrika teaching, specifically in the form advocated by Shantarakshita. Naturally, this finds its full expression in the great commentary on the Madhyamakalankara, which is one of Mipham's great masterpieces, but it is appropriate to mention it briefly here, since not only does the view of Shantarakshita represent the final development of Madhyamika in India, but it also profoundly qualifies the Nyingma understanding of the relationship between Prasangika and Svatantrika, and of Madhyamika in general.
+
excessive detail, it is possible to summarize the [[Nyingma]] [[attitude]] (as expressed by [[Mipham Rinpoche]]) toward [[Madhyamika]] by saying that it accommodates the [[Prasangika]] approach current [[in Tibet]] after the translation of ChandrakirtPs works, without betraying its original allegiance to the [[teaching]] of [[Shantarakshita]]. And in this [[connection]], one may advert to the [[paradox]], with regard to the works of these two [[masters]], occasioned by the fact that
  
In the context of modern Madhyamika scholarship, dominated as it is by the Gelugpa and Sakyapa schools, the position of Mipham Rinpoche is liable to appear unusual, certainly unfamiliar. It is not, however, a personal eccentricity. One of the main reasons for Mipham's scholarly work was to revive and reexpress the teachings characteristic of the Nyingma school; his understanding of Madhyamika is rooted in the tradition of the Old Translations. Without going into
+
chronologically the order of translation [[in Tibet]] was the reverse of the order of composition in [[India]]. After Patsap, [[Chandrakirti]] seemed "new" [[in Tibet]] and [[Shantarakshita]] seemed "old," whereas it was the [[teaching]] of the [[latter]] that represented the final [[development]] of [[Madhyamika]] in [[India]] at a time when [[Buddhism]] was still at its [[zenith]].
  
excessive detail, it is possible to summarize the Nyingma attitude (as expressed by Mipham Rinpoche) toward Madhyamika by saying that it accommodates the Prasangika approach current in Tibet after the translation of ChandrakirtPs works, without betraying its original allegiance to the teaching of Shantarakshita. And in this connection, one may advert to the paradox, with regard to the works of these two masters, occasioned by the fact that
 
  
chronologically the order of translation in Tibet was the reverse of the order of composition in India. After Patsap, Chandrakirti seemed "new" in Tibet and Shantarakshita seemed "old," whereas it was the teaching of the latter that represented the final development of Madhyamika in India at a time when Buddhism was still at its zenith.
+
So far in this introduction, in distinguishing the teachings of [[Buddhapalita]], [[Bhavaviveka]], and [[Chandrakirti]] and their followers, we have followed the common convention of {{Wiki|speaking}} about [[Svatantrikas]] and [[Prasangikas]]. These terms are the [[Sanskrit]] renditions, contrived by [[Western]] [[scholars]], of two [[Tibetan]] terms ([[rang rgyud pa]] and [[thal]] fgyur pa respectively). It is important to realize that the [[Svatantrika-Prasangika]] {{Wiki|distinction}}, as such, is the invention of  
  
 +
[[Tibetan]] {{Wiki|scholarship}}, created as a convenient method for cataloging the different viewpoints evident in [[Madhyamika]] authors subsequent to Chandrakirti5s critique of [[Bhavaviveka]]. There is no {{Wiki|evidence}} that these two terms were ever used by the {{Wiki|ancient Indian}} [[Madhyamikas]] to refer either to themselves or to
  
So far in this introduction, in distinguishing the teachings of Buddhapalita, Bhavaviveka, and Chandrakirti and their followers, we have followed the common convention of speaking about Svatantrikas and Prasangikas. These terms are the Sanskrit renditions, contrived by Western scholars, of two Tibetan terms (rang rgyud pa and thal fgyur pa respectively). It is important to realize that the Svatantrika-Prasangika distinction, as such, is the invention of
+
their opponents. Moreover, although the [[Svatantrika]] and [[Prasangika]] viewpoints differ on a number of interconnected issues, the actual {{Wiki|terminology}} refers, as we have seen, to the [[characteristic]] method of [[debate]] adopted when the question of the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] {{Wiki|status}} of [[phenomena]] is at issue. This divergence was emphasized by [[Chandrakirti]] in the first [[chapter]] of the [[Prasannapada]], from which it follows that the terminological {{Wiki|distinction}} "[[Svatantrika-Prasangika]]" became current [[in Tibet]] only from the twelfth century onward. Convenient as it may be, it is not without its difficulties.
  
Tibetan scholarship, created as a convenient method for cataloging the different viewpoints evident in Madhyamika authors subsequent to Chandrakirti5s critique of Bhavaviveka. There is no evidence that these two terms were ever used by the ancient Indian Madhyamikas to refer either to themselves or to
 
  
their opponents. Moreover, although the Svatantrika and Prasangika viewpoints differ on a number of interconnected issues, the actual terminology refers, as we have seen, to the characteristic method of debate adopted when the question of the ultimate status of phenomena is at issue. This divergence was emphasized by Chandrakirti in the first chapter of the Prasannapada, from which it follows that the terminological distinction "Svatantrika-Prasangika" became current in Tibet only from the twelfth century onward. Convenient as it may be, it is not without its difficulties.
+
If the [[Madhyamikas]] are differentiated solely according to whether they use {{Wiki|independent}} [[syllogisms]] or confine themselves to {{Wiki|consequences}}, a twofold [[division]] results, with [[Buddhapalita]] and [[Chandrakirti]] on one side and [[Bhavaviveka]] and [[Shantarakshita]] on the other. The identification of the view of [[Chandrakirti]] and [[Buddhapalita]] is natural, but the placing of [[Bhavaviveka]] and [[Shantarakshita]] in one undifferentiated category is problematic. Historically, [[Bhavaviveka]] and
  
 +
[[Shantarakshita]] are separated by a period of about two hundred years, while [[Chandrakirti]] appeared approximately midway between them. Given that these three [[masters]] were [[scholars]] of the first magnitude, and given [[Shantarakshita's]] [[knowledge]] of the entire [[philosophical]] and [[religious]] field, as evidenced in the [[Tattvasamgraha]], it is difficult to explain how, if [[Shantarakshita]] is merely continuing the [[Svatantrika]] stance of [[Bhavaviveka]], he should have been so oblivious of Chandrakirti5s critique一a [[development]] in the history of [[Madhyamika]] of which he could not conceivably have been [[ignorant]]. However convenient, the [[Svatantrika-Prasangika]] {{Wiki|distinction}}, made exclusively in terms of [[debate]] procedure, is not wholly adequate as an account of the [[evolution]] of [[Madhyamika]] or as a general description.
  
If the Madhyamikas are differentiated solely according to whether they use independent syllogisms or confine themselves to consequences, a twofold division results, with Buddhapalita and Chandrakirti on one side and Bhavaviveka and Shantarakshita on the other. The identification of the view of Chandrakirti and Buddhapalita is natural, but the placing of Bhavaviveka and Shantarakshita in one undifferentiated category is problematic. Historically, Bhavaviveka and
 
  
Shantarakshita are separated by a period of about two hundred years, while Chandrakirti appeared approximately midway between them. Given that these three masters were scholars of the first magnitude, and given Shantarakshita's knowledge of the entire philosophical and religious field, as evidenced in the Tattvasamgraha, it is difficult to explain how, if Shantarakshita is merely continuing the Svatantrika stance of Bhavaviveka, he should have been so oblivious of Chandrakirti5s critique一a development in the history of Madhyamika of which he could not conceivably have been ignorant. However convenient, the Svatantrika-Prasangika distinction, made exclusively in terms of debate procedure, is not wholly adequate as an account of the evolution of Madhyamika or as a general description.
+
There is, however, another set of criteria for distinguishing between the approaches of these three [[Madhyamika]] [[masters]], namely, their way of {{Wiki|speaking}} about the [[conventional truth]]. We have seen that one of the [[reasons]] [[Chandrakirti]] objected to Bhavaviveka5s innovation was that, according to the {{Wiki|rules}} of [[logic]],  
  
 +
{{Wiki|independent}} [[syllogisms]] commit their user to an implicit and compromising acquiescence in the [[existence]] of the [[elements]] referred to. [[Bhavaviveka]] was apparently {{Wiki|aware}} of this, and we have seen that, in the interests of consistency, his use of the {{Wiki|independent}} [[syllogism]] went hand in hand with a view that, on the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level, [[phenomena]] do indeed enjoy a certain [[existence]] "according to
  
There is, however, another set of criteria for distinguishing between the approaches of these three Madhyamika masters, namely, their way of speaking about the conventional truth. We have seen that one of the reasons Chandrakirti objected to Bhavaviveka5s innovation was that, according to the rules of logic,
 
  
independent syllogisms commit their user to an implicit and compromising acquiescence in the existence of the elements referred to. Bhavaviveka was apparently aware of this, and we have seen that, in the interests of consistency, his use of the independent syllogism went hand in hand with a view that, on the conventional level, phenomena do indeed enjoy a certain existence "according to
+
their [[characteristics]].^^ By contrast, Chandrakirti5s quite different [[attitude]] toward the role of [[pramana]] in establishing [[emptiness]] reflects his rejection of any kind of [[existence]] at any level. In the doxologies written [[in Tibet]] during the earlier period 一that is, before the discovery of the [[teaching]] of
 +
Chandrakirti一the two kinds of [[Madhyamika]] known to [[Tibetans]] at that time were defined not according to [[debate]] procedure but on the basis of the [[attitude]] evinced toward the [[conventional truth]], namely, the [[Sautrantika-Madhyamika]] and the [[Yogachara-Madhyamika]].- This method of {{Wiki|classification}} could theoretically be enlarged to accommodate the position of [[Chandrakirti]], namely, that of the [[Madhyamika]] that accepts the common consensus as the [[conventional truth]]/
  
 +
The [[conventional truth]] corresponds to the [[world]] of everyday [[experience]]. It is the [[dimension]], the field of [[perception]], so to speak, in which [[ordinary beings]] live and interact. Viewed in the {{Wiki|light}} of their [[soteriological]] aims, the [[attitude]] of [[Madhyamikas]] toward the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] is largely a {{Wiki|matter}} of
  
their characteristics.^^ By contrast, Chandrakirti5s quite different attitude toward the role of pramana in establishing emptiness reflects his rejection of any kind of existence at any level. In the doxologies written in Tibet during the earlier period 一that is, before the discovery of the teaching of
+
[[communication]]. In trying to introduce [[beings]] to the [[Middle Way]] (the [[wisdom of the Buddha]] as expressed by [[Nagarjuna]], by which alone [[samsara]] is destroyed and [[liberation]] gained), different approaches are both possible and necessary. This is what we would expect of any [[Buddhist]] system. [[Beings]] differ in their capacities and requirements; the [[form]] in which the teachings are expressed varies accordingly.
Chandrakirti一the two kinds of Madhyamika known to Tibetans at that time were defined not according to debate procedure but on the basis of the attitude evinced toward the conventional truth, namely, the Sautrantika-Madhyamika and the Yogachara-Madhyamika.- This method of classification could theoretically be enlarged to accommodate the position of Chandrakirti, namely, that of the Madhyamika that accepts the common consensus as the conventional truth/
 
  
The conventional truth corresponds to the world of everyday experience. It is the dimension, the field of perception, so to speak, in which ordinary beings live and interact. Viewed in the light of their soteriological aims, the attitude of Madhyamikas toward the conventional is largely a matter of
 
  
communication. In trying to introduce beings to the Middle Way (the wisdom of the Buddha as expressed by Nagarjuna, by which alone samsara is destroyed and liberation gained), different approaches are both possible and necessary. This is what we would expect of any Buddhist system. Beings differ in their capacities and requirements; the form in which the teachings are expressed varies accordingly.
+
The [[characteristic]] approach of [[Chandrakirti]] and [[Buddhapalita]] is clear. When [[debating]] the final {{Wiki|status}} of [[phenomena]], they are content merely to deconstruct the false opinion; they refrain from verbalizing a position of their [[own]]. In the same way, they abstain from elaborating a {{Wiki|theory}} of the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]].  
  
 +
Ultimately, [[phenomena]] are [[empty]] by their [[nature]]; {{Wiki|conventionally}}, they appear by the force of [[dependent arising]]. The [[appearances]] of the common consensus are accepted, without analysis, as the [[conventional truth]]. No {{Wiki|theory}} is advocated as to the [[nature]] of [[phenomena]], and no sort of [[existence]] is attributed to them on a provisional basis. This approach seems simple and straightforward. In practice, it is less so.
  
The characteristic approach of Chandrakirti and Buddhapalita is clear. When debating the final status of phenomena, they are content merely to deconstruct the false opinion; they refrain from verbalizing a position of their own. In the same way, they abstain from elaborating a theory of the conventional.  
+
A realist may hold to the view, let us say, that [[phenomena]] truly [[exist]] in the way that they appear. But in undermining this notion, the [[Prasangika]] does not intend to show that [[phenomena]] do not [[exist]]. On the contrary, the true {{Wiki|status}} of [[phenomena]] lies wholly beyond both [[existence]] and [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]]. It is {{Wiki|subtle}},
  
Ultimately, phenomena are empty by their nature; conventionally, they appear by the force of dependent arising. The appearances of the common consensus are accepted, without analysis, as the conventional truth. No theory is advocated as to the nature of phenomena, and no sort of existence is attributed to them on a provisional basis. This approach seems simple and straightforward. In practice, it is less so.
+
inexpressible in [[thought]] and [[word]]. The [[Prasangika]] method, whereby the consequence is adduced without further comment, offers few concessions to the slow-witted and is obviously not without an [[element]] of [[risk]]. Admittedly, the destruction of one position, by reduction to absurdity, is not taken in isolation; it is accompanied by the {{Wiki|negation}} of the other alternatives of the [[tetralemma]]. Nevertheless, the [[Prasangika]] does no more than expose the inadequacy of the
  
A realist may hold to the view, let us say, that phenomena truly exist in the way that they appear. But in undermining this notion, the Prasangika does not intend to show that phenomena do not exist. On the contrary, the true status of phenomena lies wholly beyond both existence and nonexistence. It is subtle,
+
opponent's position. The effectiveness of the consequential method depends as much on the acuity and [[honesty]] of the opponent as it does on the accuracy and cogency of the argument. Whether or not the opponent "gets it" and realizes the point that the [[Madhyamika]] is making, and whether or not he or she is then able to apply it to good {{Wiki|purpose}}, depends not only on [[intelligence]] but also on [[merit]], the positive orientation and receptiveness of the [[mind]], which is the result of {{Wiki|training}} in [[virtue]] on the [[path]]. It is [[merit]] that [[empowers]] the [[mind]] and renders it apt not
  
inexpressible in thought and word. The Prasangika method, whereby the consequence is adduced without further comment, offers few concessions to the slow-witted and is obviously not without an element of risk. Admittedly, the destruction of one position, by reduction to absurdity, is not taken in isolation; it is accompanied by the negation of the other alternatives of the tetralemma. Nevertheless, the Prasangika does no more than expose the inadequacy of the  
+
only to understand in an [[intellectual]] [[sense]], but also to progress into the direct [[experience]] of [[wisdom]] itself. It is therefore said that the [[Prasangika]] approach, which, by a process of [[austere]] annulment of all [[intellectual]] positions, constitutes a direct introduction to [[the ultimate truth]] in itself, is appropriate for persons of the [[highest]] [[spiritual faculties]], a qualification, incidentally, that is not to be confused with mere [[intellectual]] acumen.
  
opponent's position. The effectiveness of the consequential method depends as much on the acuity and honesty of the opponent as it does on the accuracy and cogency of the argument. Whether or not the opponent "gets it" and realizes the point that the Madhyamika is making, and whether or not he or she is then able to apply it to good purpose, depends not only on intelligence but also on merit, the positive orientation and receptiveness of the mind, which is the result of training in virtue on the path. It is merit that empowers the mind and renders it apt not
 
  
only to understand in an intellectual sense, but also to progress into the direct experience of wisdom itself. It is therefore said that the Prasangika approach, which, by a process of austere annulment of all intellectual positions, constitutes a direct introduction to the ultimate truth in itself, is appropriate for persons of the highest spiritual faculties, a qualification, incidentally, that is not to be confused with mere intellectual acumen.
+
By contrast, the [[Svatantrikas]] make use of {{Wiki|independent}} [[syllogisms]] and thus adopt a "position" with which to interpret [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[experience]] ([[Sautrantika]] in the case of [[Bhavaviveka]], [[Yogachara]] in the case of [[Shantarakshita]]). Their approach is [[gradual]]; it makes allowances for the needs of [[beings]] who must be  
  
 +
led along the [[path]]. In such a context, the [[two truths]] must be {{Wiki|distinguished}}, unpacked, and presented in terms of words and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. In the [[nature]] of things, this {{Wiki|distinction}}, whereby the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] is contrasted with the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] is一can only be一 confined to the level of [[conventional truth]]. From the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] point of view, no {{Wiki|distinctions}} of any kind can be made; it is only on the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level that the analytical [[investigation]] of [[phenomena]] takes
  
By contrast, the Svatantrikas make use of independent syllogisms and thus adopt a "position" with which to interpret conventional experience (Sautrantika in the case of Bhavaviveka, Yogachara in the case of Shantarakshita). Their approach is gradual; it makes allowances for the needs of beings who must be
+
place. Furthermore, two kinds of analysis are differentiated, depending on their [[object]]. On the one hand, there is [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] or [[absolutist]] {{Wiki|reasoning}}, which investigates and establishes the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] {{Wiki|status}} or [[emptiness of phenomena]]. On the other hand, there is [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] {{Wiki|reasoning}}, which determines whether a given [[object]] is "real" or "[[illusory]]" according to the general scheme of things accepted in the common consensus.
  
led along the path. In such a context, the two truths must be distinguished, unpacked, and presented in terms of words and concepts. In the nature of things, this distinction, whereby the conventional is contrasted with the ultimate is一can only be一 confined to the level of conventional truth. From the ultimate point of view, no distinctions of any kind can be made; it is only on the conventional level that the analytical investigation of phenomena takes
 
  
place. Furthermore, two kinds of analysis are differentiated, depending on their object. On the one hand, there is ultimate or absolutist reasoning, which investigates and establishes the ultimate status or emptiness of phenomena. On the other hand, there is conventional reasoning, which determines whether a given object is "real" or "illusory" according to the general scheme of things accepted in the common consensus.
+
It is on the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level also that a further important {{Wiki|distinction}} is made, this time with regard to [[the ultimate truth]]. In itself, the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] is utterly {{Wiki|ineffable}}. It is beyond the [[ordinary mind]] and cannot become the [[object]] of a [[cognition]] in which there is a separation between [[subject]] and [[object]].  
  
 +
This is the "[[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] in itself.,,s It is [[experienced]] by [[nondual wisdom]] and can never be expressed in [[thought]] and [[word]], themselves the preserve of the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]. The [[ordinary mind]] can, however, point to the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] indirectly, describing it, for example, as the counterpart of the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]. This is the approximate ultimate.-It is the concordant image of, or gateway to, [[the ultimate truth]] in itself.
  
It is on the conventional level also that a further important distinction is made, this time with regard to the ultimate truth. In itself, the ultimate is utterly ineffable. It is beyond the ordinary mind and cannot become the object of a cognition in which there is a separation between subject and object.
 
  
This is the "ultimate in itself.,,s It is experienced by nondual wisdom and can never be expressed in thought and word, themselves the preserve of the conventional. The ordinary mind can, however, point to the ultimate indirectly, describing it, for example, as the counterpart of the conventional. This is the approximate ultimate.-It is the concordant image of, or gateway to, the ultimate truth in itself.
+
As [[methods]] of introduction to [[emptiness]], the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[condition]] of [[phenomena]] and of the [[mind]], the [[Prasangika]] and [[Svatantrika]] approaches are adapted to two kinds of [[beings]]: those who are able to enter into [[the ultimate truth]] in itself directly, without the intermediary step of the [[approximate ultimate]] [[truth]] (cig char pa), and those who must progress toward it gradually (rim bsl<yed pa). It may be [[thought]] that [[Prasangika]] is {{Wiki|superior}} to [[Svatantrika]], but if there
  
 +
is a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} of levels, this refers only to the respective capacities of the [[disciples]] concerned, where the difference is one of [[merit]]. It is not a {{Wiki|reflection}} on the [[quality]] of the approaches themselves, which, [[Mipham Rinpoche]] argues, are both indispensable and equally valuable. Neither are they interchangeable. The [[direct approach]] is useless for someone who must progress gradually; the [[gradualist]] approach is unnecessary for one who is able to {{Wiki|perceive}} directly.
  
As methods of introduction to emptiness, the ultimate condition of phenomena and of the mind, the Prasangika and Svatantrika approaches are adapted to two kinds of beings: those who are able to enter into the ultimate truth in itself directly, without the intermediary step of the approximate ultimate truth (cig char pa), and those who must progress toward it gradually (rim bsl<yed pa). It may be thought that Prasangika is superior to Svatantrika, but if there
 
  
is a hierarchy of levels, this refers only to the respective capacities of the disciples concerned, where the difference is one of merit. It is not a reflection on the quality of the approaches themselves, which, Mipham Rinpoche argues, are both indispensable and equally valuable. Neither are they interchangeable. The direct approach is useless for someone who must progress gradually; the gradualist approach is unnecessary for one who is able to perceive directly.
+
Furthermore, the adoption of these different [[methods]] reflects the [[compassionate]] [[activity]] of the [[masters]] concerned, not their [[own]] personal [[realization]]. With regard to [[the ultimate truth]], all [[Madhyamikas]], of whatever complexion, are in full
  
  
Furthermore, the adoption of these different methods reflects the compassionate activity of the masters concerned, not their own personal realization. With regard to the ultimate truth, all Madhyamikas, of whatever complexion, are in full
+
agreement. [[Mipham Rinpoche]] observes that the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] in itself, beyond the domain of words or [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], is what the [[Aryas]] see by stainless [[wisdom]] in their [[meditative equipoise]]; on this level, neither [[Prasangikas]] nor [[Svatantrikas]] make assertions of any kind, and there is no differentiating them. The {{Wiki|distinction}} comes only with regard to the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], for it is here alone that the [[Svatantrikas]] make their statements about the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] (the
  
 +
[[approximate ultimate]]). UA [[person]] who, by dint of practice, thus attains the [[experience]] of [[the ultimate truth]] in itself may be called either [[Prasangika]] or [[Svatantrika]] depending on the way he or she makes assertions with regard to the postmeditation period. But one should know that in the [[ultimate realization]] there is no difference between them. They both enjoy the [[wisdom]] of the Aryas.5- It is thus meaningless to place the [[Madhyamika]] [[masters]] themselves in a {{Wiki|hierarchy}} according to the manner in which they instruct [[beings]]. In their [[own]] right, [[Buddhapalita]], [[Bhavaviveka]], [[Chandrakirti]], [[Shantarakshita]] and so on are all equal一they are all, we might say, [[Prasangikas]], possessed of the [[highest]] view.
  
agreement. Mipham Rinpoche observes that the ultimate in itself, beyond the domain of words or concepts, is what the Aryas see by stainless wisdom in their meditative equipoise; on this level, neither Prasangikas nor Svatantrikas make assertions of any kind, and there is no differentiating them. The distinction comes only with regard to the conventional, for it is here alone that the Svatantrikas make their statements about the ultimate (the
 
  
approximate ultimate). UA person who, by dint of practice, thus attains the experience of the ultimate truth in itself may be called either Prasangika or Svatantrika depending on the way he or she makes assertions with regard to the postmeditation period. But one should know that in the ultimate realization there is no difference between them. They both enjoy the wisdom of the Aryas.5- It is thus meaningless to place the Madhyamika masters themselves in a hierarchy according to the manner in which they instruct beings. In their own right, Buddhapalita, Bhavaviveka, Chandrakirti, Shantarakshita and so on are all equal一they are all, we might say, Prasangikas, possessed of the highest view.
+
For [[Mipham]], therefore, [[Prasangika]] and [[Svatantrika]] are two approaches to be understood in [[harmony]]; they are not diverging [[views]]. This point is brought out very clearly in the introduction to his commentary on the [[Madhyamakalankara]], which has been described as one of the most profound texts on [[Madhyamika]] ever written. Having referred to the eighty-ninth [[stanza]] in the sixth [[chapter]] of the [[Madhyamakavatara]], where [[Chandrakirti]] says that the source of [[phenomenal]] [[experience]] is the [[mind]] itself, [[Mipham Rinpoche]] comments:
  
  
For Mipham, therefore, Prasangika and Svatantrika are two approaches to be understood in harmony; they are not diverging views. This point is brought out very clearly in the introduction to his commentary on the Madhyamakalankara, which has been described as one of the most profound texts on Madhyamika ever written. Having referred to the eighty-ninth stanza in the sixth chapter of the Madhyamakavatara, where Chandrakirti says that the source of phenomenal experience is the mind itself, Mipham Rinpoche comments:
+
To say [on the contrary] that the [[phenomenal world]] does not arise from one's [[mind]] necessarily implies the [[belief]] that it is [[caused]] by something else. And since this involves the [[assertion]] that [[beings]] are [[bound]] in [[samsara]] or delivered from it through [[causes]] other than their [[own minds]], it will doubtless [[cause]] one to fall into [[non-Buddhist]] [[tenet]] systems. It is therefore established step by step that if there is no external creator and no [[external world]], extramental [[objects]] are but the [[mind's]] projection. This [[assertion]] that conventionalities are "only the [[mind]]" [[exists]] in all the [[Mahayana schools]].
  
  
To say [on the contrary] that the phenomenal world does not arise from one's mind necessarily implies the belief that it is caused by something else. And since this involves the assertion that beings are bound in samsara or delivered from it through causes other than their own minds, it will doubtless cause one to fall into non-Buddhist tenet systems. It is therefore established step by step that if there is no external creator and no external world, extramental objects are but the mind's projection. This assertion that conventionalities are "only the mind" exists in all the Mahayana schools.
+
Why is it then that glorious [[Chandrakirti]] and others do not posit the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level in this way? As was explained above, when he establishes the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] in itself, which accords with the field of [[wisdom]] of [[Aryas]] while they are in [[meditative equipoise]], it is sufficient for him to have, as the [[object]] of assessment, the [[phenomena]] of [[samsara and nirvana]] as they appear and are referred to on the [[empirical]] level, without examining them. Since, from the very
  
 +
beginning, these [[phenomena]] are beyond the four {{Wiki|conceptual}} extremes, it is not necessary for him to enter into a close [[philosophical]] [[investigation]] of the way [[phenomena]] appear on the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level. When one assesses [[appearances]] with words and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]], one may, for instance, say that [[phenomena]] [[exist]] or do not [[exist]], that [[phenomena]] are or are not the [[mind]]. But however one may assert them, they do not [[exist]] in that way on the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] level. Therefore, with the {{Wiki|consequences}} of the [[Prasanga]] {{Wiki|reasoning}}, which investigates the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]], [[Chandrakirti]] is merely refuting the incorrect [[ideas]] of the opponents. And given that his [[own]] stance is free from every {{Wiki|conceptual}}
  
Why is it then that glorious Chandrakirti and others do not posit the conventional level in this way? As was explained above, when he establishes the ultimate in itself, which accords with the field of wisdom of Aryas while they are in meditative equipoise, it is sufficient for him to have, as the object of assessment, the phenomena of samsara and nirvana as they appear and are referred to on the empirical level, without examining them. Since, from the very
 
  
beginning, these phenomena are beyond the four conceptual extremes, it is not necessary for him to enter into a close philosophical investigation of the way phenomena appear on the conventional level. When one assesses appearances with words and concepts, one may, for instance, say that phenomena exist or do not exist, that phenomena are or are not the mind. But however one may assert them, they do not exist in that way on the ultimate level. Therefore, with the consequences of the Prasanga reasoning, which investigates the ultimate, Chandrakirti is merely refuting the incorrect ideas of the opponents. And given that his own stance is free from every conceptual
+
reference, how could he assert a {{Wiki|theory}}? He does not. In this way, he can refute, without needing to separate the [[two truths]], whatever assertions are made as to [[existence]] and [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]]. In the {{Wiki|present}} [[Svatantrika]] context, since assessments are made with the {{Wiki|reasoning}} specific to each of the [[two truths]], one cannot refute or establish anything without separating these same [[two truths]]. But in Chandrakirti5s [[tradition]], assessment is made using the valid {{Wiki|reasoning}}, which investigates the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[nature]] of the two truths一the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] in itself. As [[Chandrakirti]] quotes from a [[scripture]] in his autocommentary to the [[Madhyamakavatara]]: "On the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] level, 0 [[monks]], there are no [[two truths]]. This [[ultimate truth]] is one."
  
  
reference, how could he assert a theory? He does not. In this way, he can refute, without needing to separate the two truths, whatever assertions are made as to existence and nonexistence. In the present Svatantrika context, since assessments are made with the reasoning specific to each of the two truths, one cannot refute or establish anything without separating these same two truths. But in Chandrakirti5s tradition, assessment is made using the valid reasoning, which investigates the ultimate nature of the two truths一the ultimate in itself. As Chandrakirti quotes from a scripture in his autocommentary to the Madhyamakavatara: "On the ultimate level, 0 monks, there are no two truths. This ultimate truth is one."
+
Therefore from the beginning, the honorable [[Chandrakirti]] emphasizes and establishes the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] in itself. He does not do away with mere [[appearances]], for these are the ground for his [[absolutist]] type of [[investigation]], the means or gateway to the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]]. He therefore takes them as a basis of [[debate]] and establishes them as being beyond all {{Wiki|conceptual}} extremes. Then, in the postmeditation period, he establishes or refutes all the propositions concerning the  
  
 +
[[path and result]] in accordance with the way they are assessed by the two kinds of {{Wiki|reasoning}}. And thus even the [[Prasangikas]] do not invalidate the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level. They assert [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[phenomena]] as mere [[appearances]] (rl<yen [[nyid]] (di pa) or simply as dependent arisings. If, with regard to these
  
Therefore from the beginning, the honorable Chandrakirti emphasizes and establishes the ultimate in itself. He does not do away with mere appearances, for these are the ground for his absolutist type of investigation, the means or gateway to the ultimate. He therefore takes them as a basis of debate and establishes them as being beyond all conceptual extremes. Then, in the postmeditation period, he establishes or refutes all the propositions concerning the
+
mere [[appearances]], an [[investigation]] is made using [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] {{Wiki|reasoning}}, the [[Prasangikas]] do not deny the manner in which [[samsara and nirvana]] are produced through the forward and backward progression of the twelve [[interdependent]] links of [[existence]]. They show that [[phenomena]] arise dependently through the power of the [[pure]] or impure [[mind]]. And in this way they clearly express the [[tenet]] of [[mind-only]].
  
path and result in accordance with the way they are assessed by the two kinds of reasoning. And thus even the Prasangikas do not invalidate the conventional level. They assert conventional phenomena as mere appearances (rl<yen nyid (di pa) or simply as dependent arisings. If, with regard to these
 
  
mere appearances, an investigation is made using conventional reasoning, the Prasangikas do not deny the manner in which samsara and nirvana are produced through the forward and backward progression of the twelve interdependent links of existence. They show that phenomena arise dependently through the power of the pure or impure mind. And in this way they clearly express the tenet of mind-only.
+
In the {{Wiki|present}} text ([[Madhyamakalankara]]) by the [[great abbot]] [[Shantarakshita]], {{Wiki|emphasis}} is placed on the [[approximate ultimate]]. The [[two truths]] are, to begin with, {{Wiki|distinguished}}; each of them is assessed with the appropriate kind of valid [[cognition]] and each is established as having assertions proper to it. Finally, [[the ultimate truth]] in itself, which is completely free from all [[assertion]], is reached. These two approaches ([[Svatantrika]] and [[Prasangika]]) belong
  
 
+
respectively to those who follow the [[gradual path]] and those whose [[realization]] is not [[gradual]] but immediate. And since the [[essence]] of Shantarakshita5s approach is the ultimate-in-itself, he does indeed possess the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] and [[essential]] view of the [[Prasangikas]]. And what he says in the text itself is in {{Wiki|perfect}} agreement with the view of the glorious [[Chandrakirti]].
In the present text (Madhyamakalankara) by the great abbot Shantarakshita, emphasis is placed on the approximate ultimate. The two truths are, to begin with, distinguished; each of them is assessed with the appropriate kind of valid cognition and each is established as having assertions proper to it. Finally, the ultimate truth in itself, which is completely free from all assertion, is reached. These two approaches (Svatantrika and Prasangika) belong
 
 
 
respectively to those who follow the gradual path and those whose realization is not gradual but immediate. And since the essence of Shantarakshita5s approach is the ultimate-in-itself, he does indeed possess the ultimate and essential view of the Prasangikas. And what he says in the text itself is in perfect agreement with the view of the glorious Chandrakirti.
 
  
  

Latest revision as of 05:42, 1 February 2020




However effective Chandrakirti may have been in vindicating the method of Buddhapalita and refuting Bhavaviveka, it is clear that he did not succeed in convincing all his contemporaries. There is no doubt that the Svatantrika method remained popular. Shantarakshita himself, who in his synthesis of the

Madhyamika and Yogachara schools represents the last great stage in the development of Buddhist philosophy in India, made use of independent syllogisms as Bhavaviveka had done several centuries before. He is therefore classified as a Svatantrika, although, as we shall see, this question is more complex than it appears. It was, in any case, Shantarakshita and his disciple Kamalashila who, at the invitation of King Trisong Detsen, carried the Buddhist sutra teachings to Tibet, with the result that the Madhyamika doctrine first established there was Yogachara-Svatantrika, in which form it was to flourish for approximately four hundred years. Only in the twelfth century, when Patsap Nyima Drak translated the works of Chandrakirti, did the Prasangika really take hold in Tibet.


According to The Blue Annals, Patsap was born in Penyul but left Tibet while still a child. He grew up in Kashmir and India, where he studied at the feet of numerous famous and important scholars. He returned to Tibet around 1160 and embarked on a career of translation and teaching. He expounded in particular the six logical treatises (rigs tshogs) of Nagarjuna and, in collaboration with the Indian pandita Kanakavarman, translated Chandrakirti5s Prasannapada and the Madhyamakavatara, together with its autocommentary, as well as the commentary on the Yuktishastika by the same author. From slender beginnings he became an influential teacher, and his return home marked a turning point in the study of Madhyamika in Tibet.


The introduction of Prasangika ideas was the focus of intense interest. Convinced that they were in possession of a more accurate and profound understanding of Nagarjuna5s doctrine, the early Tibetan Prasangikas attacked the Svatantrika establishment with the enthusiasm of missionaries. They

encountered a sturdy resistance. The period of persecution inflicted by King Langdarma (836-841) had been followed by an intense religious and scholastic renewal. And in the intervening period, before the return of Patsap, the Madhyamika had been closely studied, mainly according to the tradition laid down by Shantarakshita and Kamalashila, but also following the works of Bhavaviveka, which had also been translated in the early period. A number of great scholars had been involved in this enterprise, and by the twelfth century the Svatantrika view was well able to resist, at least for the time being, the wave of novelty. The master Chapa Chokyi Senge, for example, whose interpretation of Dignaga and Dharmakirti was to form the basis of the logic tradition still upheld by the Gelugpa school, was a formidable debater and defended with brilliance the Svatantrika view against Prasangika innovation. He composed several expositions of the Madhyamika system and numerous refutations of Chandrakirti. It is recorded that, on one occasion, he encountered in debate, and defeated, the celebrated Indian Prasangika master Jayananda.-


Be that as it may, the Prasangika view gained ground in Tibet and eventually triumphed. Even before the translation of Chandrakirti by Patsap, the Prasangika view was advocated by Atisha, whose role in the development of Tibetan Buddhism can scarcely be exaggerated; and it became intimately associated with the mind-training teaching of the Kadampas, which exerted a pervasive influence throughout the tradition. In their different ways, all four schools of Tibetan Buddhism have adopted the Prasangika approach一the teaching of Nagarjuna, as interpreted by Chandrakirti一as the highest view on the sutra level. Svatantrika was driven into the shade, and nowadays, especially in the New Translation schools, it is relegated to the d oxographic al literature, in the context of which it is studied largely as a lower view to be examined and surmounted by students on their way to mastery of the Prasangika system. It is comparatively rare for the original writings of Svatantrika authors一even of Shantarakshita一to be studied at first hand. Mipham Rinpoche and the Prasangika-Svatantrika Distinction


It is therefore of some interest, before finishing with this topic, to advert to the attitude of Mipham Rinpoche toward the Svatantrika teaching, specifically in the form advocated by Shantarakshita. Naturally, this finds its full expression in the great commentary on the Madhyamakalankara, which is one of Mipham's great masterpieces, but it is appropriate to mention it briefly here, since not only does the view of Shantarakshita represent the final development of Madhyamika in India, but it also profoundly qualifies the Nyingma understanding of the relationship between Prasangika and Svatantrika, and of Madhyamika in general.

In the context of modern Madhyamika scholarship, dominated as it is by the Gelugpa and Sakyapa schools, the position of Mipham Rinpoche is liable to appear unusual, certainly unfamiliar. It is not, however, a personal eccentricity. One of the main reasons for Mipham's scholarly work was to revive and reexpress the teachings characteristic of the Nyingma school; his understanding of Madhyamika is rooted in the tradition of the Old Translations. Without going into

excessive detail, it is possible to summarize the Nyingma attitude (as expressed by Mipham Rinpoche) toward Madhyamika by saying that it accommodates the Prasangika approach current in Tibet after the translation of ChandrakirtPs works, without betraying its original allegiance to the teaching of Shantarakshita. And in this connection, one may advert to the paradox, with regard to the works of these two masters, occasioned by the fact that

chronologically the order of translation in Tibet was the reverse of the order of composition in India. After Patsap, Chandrakirti seemed "new" in Tibet and Shantarakshita seemed "old," whereas it was the teaching of the latter that represented the final development of Madhyamika in India at a time when Buddhism was still at its zenith.


So far in this introduction, in distinguishing the teachings of Buddhapalita, Bhavaviveka, and Chandrakirti and their followers, we have followed the common convention of speaking about Svatantrikas and Prasangikas. These terms are the Sanskrit renditions, contrived by Western scholars, of two Tibetan terms (rang rgyud pa and thal fgyur pa respectively). It is important to realize that the Svatantrika-Prasangika distinction, as such, is the invention of

Tibetan scholarship, created as a convenient method for cataloging the different viewpoints evident in Madhyamika authors subsequent to Chandrakirti5s critique of Bhavaviveka. There is no evidence that these two terms were ever used by the ancient Indian Madhyamikas to refer either to themselves or to

their opponents. Moreover, although the Svatantrika and Prasangika viewpoints differ on a number of interconnected issues, the actual terminology refers, as we have seen, to the characteristic method of debate adopted when the question of the ultimate status of phenomena is at issue. This divergence was emphasized by Chandrakirti in the first chapter of the Prasannapada, from which it follows that the terminological distinction "Svatantrika-Prasangika" became current in Tibet only from the twelfth century onward. Convenient as it may be, it is not without its difficulties.


If the Madhyamikas are differentiated solely according to whether they use independent syllogisms or confine themselves to consequences, a twofold division results, with Buddhapalita and Chandrakirti on one side and Bhavaviveka and Shantarakshita on the other. The identification of the view of Chandrakirti and Buddhapalita is natural, but the placing of Bhavaviveka and Shantarakshita in one undifferentiated category is problematic. Historically, Bhavaviveka and

Shantarakshita are separated by a period of about two hundred years, while Chandrakirti appeared approximately midway between them. Given that these three masters were scholars of the first magnitude, and given Shantarakshita's knowledge of the entire philosophical and religious field, as evidenced in the Tattvasamgraha, it is difficult to explain how, if Shantarakshita is merely continuing the Svatantrika stance of Bhavaviveka, he should have been so oblivious of Chandrakirti5s critique一a development in the history of Madhyamika of which he could not conceivably have been ignorant. However convenient, the Svatantrika-Prasangika distinction, made exclusively in terms of debate procedure, is not wholly adequate as an account of the evolution of Madhyamika or as a general description.


There is, however, another set of criteria for distinguishing between the approaches of these three Madhyamika masters, namely, their way of speaking about the conventional truth. We have seen that one of the reasons Chandrakirti objected to Bhavaviveka5s innovation was that, according to the rules of logic,

independent syllogisms commit their user to an implicit and compromising acquiescence in the existence of the elements referred to. Bhavaviveka was apparently aware of this, and we have seen that, in the interests of consistency, his use of the independent syllogism went hand in hand with a view that, on the conventional level, phenomena do indeed enjoy a certain existence "according to


their characteristics.^^ By contrast, Chandrakirti5s quite different attitude toward the role of pramana in establishing emptiness reflects his rejection of any kind of existence at any level. In the doxologies written in Tibet during the earlier period 一that is, before the discovery of the teaching of Chandrakirti一the two kinds of Madhyamika known to Tibetans at that time were defined not according to debate procedure but on the basis of the attitude evinced toward the conventional truth, namely, the Sautrantika-Madhyamika and the Yogachara-Madhyamika.- This method of classification could theoretically be enlarged to accommodate the position of Chandrakirti, namely, that of the Madhyamika that accepts the common consensus as the conventional truth/

The conventional truth corresponds to the world of everyday experience. It is the dimension, the field of perception, so to speak, in which ordinary beings live and interact. Viewed in the light of their soteriological aims, the attitude of Madhyamikas toward the conventional is largely a matter of

communication. In trying to introduce beings to the Middle Way (the wisdom of the Buddha as expressed by Nagarjuna, by which alone samsara is destroyed and liberation gained), different approaches are both possible and necessary. This is what we would expect of any Buddhist system. Beings differ in their capacities and requirements; the form in which the teachings are expressed varies accordingly.


The characteristic approach of Chandrakirti and Buddhapalita is clear. When debating the final status of phenomena, they are content merely to deconstruct the false opinion; they refrain from verbalizing a position of their own. In the same way, they abstain from elaborating a theory of the conventional.

Ultimately, phenomena are empty by their nature; conventionally, they appear by the force of dependent arising. The appearances of the common consensus are accepted, without analysis, as the conventional truth. No theory is advocated as to the nature of phenomena, and no sort of existence is attributed to them on a provisional basis. This approach seems simple and straightforward. In practice, it is less so.

A realist may hold to the view, let us say, that phenomena truly exist in the way that they appear. But in undermining this notion, the Prasangika does not intend to show that phenomena do not exist. On the contrary, the true status of phenomena lies wholly beyond both existence and nonexistence. It is subtle,

inexpressible in thought and word. The Prasangika method, whereby the consequence is adduced without further comment, offers few concessions to the slow-witted and is obviously not without an element of risk. Admittedly, the destruction of one position, by reduction to absurdity, is not taken in isolation; it is accompanied by the negation of the other alternatives of the tetralemma. Nevertheless, the Prasangika does no more than expose the inadequacy of the

opponent's position. The effectiveness of the consequential method depends as much on the acuity and honesty of the opponent as it does on the accuracy and cogency of the argument. Whether or not the opponent "gets it" and realizes the point that the Madhyamika is making, and whether or not he or she is then able to apply it to good purpose, depends not only on intelligence but also on merit, the positive orientation and receptiveness of the mind, which is the result of training in virtue on the path. It is merit that empowers the mind and renders it apt not

only to understand in an intellectual sense, but also to progress into the direct experience of wisdom itself. It is therefore said that the Prasangika approach, which, by a process of austere annulment of all intellectual positions, constitutes a direct introduction to the ultimate truth in itself, is appropriate for persons of the highest spiritual faculties, a qualification, incidentally, that is not to be confused with mere intellectual acumen.


By contrast, the Svatantrikas make use of independent syllogisms and thus adopt a "position" with which to interpret conventional experience (Sautrantika in the case of Bhavaviveka, Yogachara in the case of Shantarakshita). Their approach is gradual; it makes allowances for the needs of beings who must be

led along the path. In such a context, the two truths must be distinguished, unpacked, and presented in terms of words and concepts. In the nature of things, this distinction, whereby the conventional is contrasted with the ultimate is一can only be一 confined to the level of conventional truth. From the ultimate point of view, no distinctions of any kind can be made; it is only on the conventional level that the analytical investigation of phenomena takes

place. Furthermore, two kinds of analysis are differentiated, depending on their object. On the one hand, there is ultimate or absolutist reasoning, which investigates and establishes the ultimate status or emptiness of phenomena. On the other hand, there is conventional reasoning, which determines whether a given object is "real" or "illusory" according to the general scheme of things accepted in the common consensus.


It is on the conventional level also that a further important distinction is made, this time with regard to the ultimate truth. In itself, the ultimate is utterly ineffable. It is beyond the ordinary mind and cannot become the object of a cognition in which there is a separation between subject and object.

This is the "ultimate in itself.,,s It is experienced by nondual wisdom and can never be expressed in thought and word, themselves the preserve of the conventional. The ordinary mind can, however, point to the ultimate indirectly, describing it, for example, as the counterpart of the conventional. This is the approximate ultimate.-It is the concordant image of, or gateway to, the ultimate truth in itself.


As methods of introduction to emptiness, the ultimate condition of phenomena and of the mind, the Prasangika and Svatantrika approaches are adapted to two kinds of beings: those who are able to enter into the ultimate truth in itself directly, without the intermediary step of the approximate ultimate truth (cig char pa), and those who must progress toward it gradually (rim bsl<yed pa). It may be thought that Prasangika is superior to Svatantrika, but if there

is a hierarchy of levels, this refers only to the respective capacities of the disciples concerned, where the difference is one of merit. It is not a reflection on the quality of the approaches themselves, which, Mipham Rinpoche argues, are both indispensable and equally valuable. Neither are they interchangeable. The direct approach is useless for someone who must progress gradually; the gradualist approach is unnecessary for one who is able to perceive directly.


Furthermore, the adoption of these different methods reflects the compassionate activity of the masters concerned, not their own personal realization. With regard to the ultimate truth, all Madhyamikas, of whatever complexion, are in full


agreement. Mipham Rinpoche observes that the ultimate in itself, beyond the domain of words or concepts, is what the Aryas see by stainless wisdom in their meditative equipoise; on this level, neither Prasangikas nor Svatantrikas make assertions of any kind, and there is no differentiating them. The distinction comes only with regard to the conventional, for it is here alone that the Svatantrikas make their statements about the ultimate (the

approximate ultimate). UA person who, by dint of practice, thus attains the experience of the ultimate truth in itself may be called either Prasangika or Svatantrika depending on the way he or she makes assertions with regard to the postmeditation period. But one should know that in the ultimate realization there is no difference between them. They both enjoy the wisdom of the Aryas.5- It is thus meaningless to place the Madhyamika masters themselves in a hierarchy according to the manner in which they instruct beings. In their own right, Buddhapalita, Bhavaviveka, Chandrakirti, Shantarakshita and so on are all equal一they are all, we might say, Prasangikas, possessed of the highest view.


For Mipham, therefore, Prasangika and Svatantrika are two approaches to be understood in harmony; they are not diverging views. This point is brought out very clearly in the introduction to his commentary on the Madhyamakalankara, which has been described as one of the most profound texts on Madhyamika ever written. Having referred to the eighty-ninth stanza in the sixth chapter of the Madhyamakavatara, where Chandrakirti says that the source of phenomenal experience is the mind itself, Mipham Rinpoche comments:


To say [on the contrary] that the phenomenal world does not arise from one's mind necessarily implies the belief that it is caused by something else. And since this involves the assertion that beings are bound in samsara or delivered from it through causes other than their own minds, it will doubtless cause one to fall into non-Buddhist tenet systems. It is therefore established step by step that if there is no external creator and no external world, extramental objects are but the mind's projection. This assertion that conventionalities are "only the mind" exists in all the Mahayana schools.


Why is it then that glorious Chandrakirti and others do not posit the conventional level in this way? As was explained above, when he establishes the ultimate in itself, which accords with the field of wisdom of Aryas while they are in meditative equipoise, it is sufficient for him to have, as the object of assessment, the phenomena of samsara and nirvana as they appear and are referred to on the empirical level, without examining them. Since, from the very

beginning, these phenomena are beyond the four conceptual extremes, it is not necessary for him to enter into a close philosophical investigation of the way phenomena appear on the conventional level. When one assesses appearances with words and concepts, one may, for instance, say that phenomena exist or do not exist, that phenomena are or are not the mind. But however one may assert them, they do not exist in that way on the ultimate level. Therefore, with the consequences of the Prasanga reasoning, which investigates the ultimate, Chandrakirti is merely refuting the incorrect ideas of the opponents. And given that his own stance is free from every conceptual


reference, how could he assert a theory? He does not. In this way, he can refute, without needing to separate the two truths, whatever assertions are made as to existence and nonexistence. In the present Svatantrika context, since assessments are made with the reasoning specific to each of the two truths, one cannot refute or establish anything without separating these same two truths. But in Chandrakirti5s tradition, assessment is made using the valid reasoning, which investigates the ultimate nature of the two truths一the ultimate in itself. As Chandrakirti quotes from a scripture in his autocommentary to the Madhyamakavatara: "On the ultimate level, 0 monks, there are no two truths. This ultimate truth is one."


Therefore from the beginning, the honorable Chandrakirti emphasizes and establishes the ultimate in itself. He does not do away with mere appearances, for these are the ground for his absolutist type of investigation, the means or gateway to the ultimate. He therefore takes them as a basis of debate and establishes them as being beyond all conceptual extremes. Then, in the postmeditation period, he establishes or refutes all the propositions concerning the

path and result in accordance with the way they are assessed by the two kinds of reasoning. And thus even the Prasangikas do not invalidate the conventional level. They assert conventional phenomena as mere appearances (rl<yen nyid (di pa) or simply as dependent arisings. If, with regard to these

mere appearances, an investigation is made using conventional reasoning, the Prasangikas do not deny the manner in which samsara and nirvana are produced through the forward and backward progression of the twelve interdependent links of existence. They show that phenomena arise dependently through the power of the pure or impure mind. And in this way they clearly express the tenet of mind-only.


In the present text (Madhyamakalankara) by the great abbot Shantarakshita, emphasis is placed on the approximate ultimate. The two truths are, to begin with, distinguished; each of them is assessed with the appropriate kind of valid cognition and each is established as having assertions proper to it. Finally, the ultimate truth in itself, which is completely free from all assertion, is reached. These two approaches (Svatantrika and Prasangika) belong

respectively to those who follow the gradual path and those whose realization is not gradual but immediate. And since the essence of Shantarakshita5s approach is the ultimate-in-itself, he does indeed possess the ultimate and essential view of the Prasangikas. And what he says in the text itself is in perfect agreement with the view of the glorious Chandrakirti.




Source