Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Précis of Perceiving Reality: Consciousness, Intentionality, and Cognition in Buddhist Philosophy"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " by Christian Coseru Introduction The central idea of this book is the continuity of perception and the world as perceived. To perceive is to open up to a horizon o...")
 
 
Line 6: Line 6:
  
  
by Christian Coseru  
+
by [[Christian Coseru]]
  
  
  
  
Introduction The central idea of this book is the continuity of perception and the world as perceived. To perceive is to open up to a horizon of elements or unique particulars (e.g. textures, arrays, intensities, magnitudes, etc.) that are inseparable from their mode of presentation. Perception is thus at once, and fundamentally, about an object of its own, which reflects its intentional structure, and endowed with a specific phenomenal character, which captures its affective and dispositional saliences. I take a twofold approach to these ideas in Perceiving Reality. On the one hand, I try to show that Indian Buddhist thought is the source of a distinctive and influential philosophy of  
+
Introduction The central [[idea]] of this [[book]] is the continuity of [[perception]] and the [[world]] as [[perceived]]. To {{Wiki|perceive}} is to open up to a horizon of [[elements]] or unique particulars (e.g. textures, arrays, intensities, magnitudes, etc.) that are [[inseparable]] from their mode of presentation. [[Perception]] is thus at once, and fundamentally, about an [[object]] of its [[own]], which reflects its intentional {{Wiki|structure}}, and endowed with a specific [[phenomenal]] [[character]], which captures its affective and dispositional saliences. I take a twofold approach to these [[ideas]] in Perceiving [[Reality]]. On the one hand, I try to show that [[Indian Buddhist]] [[thought]] is the source of a {{Wiki|distinctive}} and influential [[philosophy]] of  
  
perception — one that entails that empirical awareness is intrinsically perspectival. On this account, perception does not simply manifest a given object, a particular, but is also in some sense self-manifesting, self-given. On the other hand, I try to develop a methodological framework that renders these Buddhist insights continuous with contemporary philosophical concerns in both phenomenology and analytic philosophy of mind. The emphasis on ‘continuity’ over the standard ‘comparative’ approach reflects a specific intuition about the scope of philosophical enquiry: one which says that its problems, though often couched in historically and culturally contingent terms, are nonetheless grounded in all aspects of conscious experience for a person at any given time. Correspondence: Email: christian.coseruc@cofc.edu  
+
[[perception]] — one that entails that [[empirical]] [[awareness]] is intrinsically perspectival. On this account, [[perception]] does not simply [[manifest]] a given [[object]], a particular, but is also in some [[sense]] [[self-manifesting]], self-given. On the other hand, I try to develop a {{Wiki|methodological}} framework that renders these [[Buddhist]] [[insights]] continuous with contemporary [[philosophical]] concerns in both [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] and {{Wiki|analytic philosophy}} of [[mind]]. The {{Wiki|emphasis}} on ‘continuity’ over the standard ‘comparative’ approach reflects a specific [[intuition]] about the scope of [[philosophical]] enquiry: one which says that its problems, though often couched in historically and culturally contingent terms, are nonetheless grounded in all aspects of [[conscious]] [[experience]] for a [[person]] at any given time. Correspondence: Email: christian.coseruc@cofc.edu  
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2016 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
+
Copyright (c) Imprint {{Wiki|Academic}} 2016 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
  
Furthermore, in so far as philosophical enquiry aims to get at the nature of things or perhaps at the things themselves, its arguments must be experientially and/or empirically grounded. As the book’s subtitle indicates, the material under discussion is drawn primarily from Buddhist philosophy, specifically from the Indian Buddhist philosophical tradition. But the analysis engages with, and is intended to contribute to, a number of contemporary debates in phenomenology and analytic philosophy of mind. Indeed, the central argument of the book is that Indian Buddhist epistemology — the main focus of the book — shares a common orientation towards the analysis of experience with  
+
Furthermore, in so far as [[philosophical]] enquiry aims to get at the [[nature]] of things or perhaps at the things themselves, its arguments must be experientially and/or [[empirically]] grounded. As the book’s subtitle indicates, the material under [[discussion]] is drawn primarily from [[Buddhist philosophy]], specifically from the [[Indian Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]]. But the analysis engages with, and is intended to contribute to, a number of contemporary [[debates]] in [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] and {{Wiki|analytic philosophy}} of [[mind]]. Indeed, the central argument of the [[book]] is that [[Indian Buddhist]] epistemology — the main focus of the [[book]] — shares a common orientation towards the analysis of [[experience]] with  
  
naturalistic approaches in epistemology and philosophy of mind, and in many respects is continuous with some of the phenomenological theories of Edmund Husserl and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. Three concepts in particular provide the axis around which the book’s theoretical landscape is mapped out: consciousness, which stands for the phenomenal or experiential dimension under scrutiny, intentionality, as a particular feature that concerns the structure of experience, and cognition, which captures the broader epistemic issues at work in Buddhist and contemporary phenomenology and philosophy of mind. Any attempt to draw together such different and seemingly disparate philosophical programmes faces two obvious challenges. On the one hand, the concerns of pre-modern Buddhist philosophers reflect exegetical and even soteriological considerations and are seemingly at odds with the open-ended and scientifically informed modes of enquiry of contemporary western philosophy. On the other hand, there is the question of compatibility, first,  
+
{{Wiki|naturalistic}} approaches in epistemology and {{Wiki|philosophy of mind}}, and in many respects is continuous with some of the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} theories of {{Wiki|Edmund Husserl}} and {{Wiki|Maurice Merleau-Ponty}}. Three [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] in particular provide the axis around which the book’s {{Wiki|theoretical}} landscape is mapped out: [[consciousness]], which stands for the [[phenomenal]] or experiential [[dimension]] under {{Wiki|scrutiny}}, {{Wiki|intentionality}}, as a particular feature that concerns the {{Wiki|structure}} of [[experience]], and [[cognition]], which captures the broader {{Wiki|epistemic}} issues at work in [[Buddhist]] and contemporary [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] and {{Wiki|philosophy of mind}}. Any attempt to draw together such different and seemingly disparate [[philosophical]] programmes faces two obvious challenges. On the one hand, the concerns of pre-modern [[Buddhist philosophers]] reflect {{Wiki|exegetical}} and even [[soteriological]] considerations and are seemingly at odds with the open-ended and {{Wiki|scientifically}} informed modes of enquiry of contemporary {{Wiki|western philosophy}}. On the other hand, there is the question of compatibility, first,  
  
between the positions of Buddhist epistemologists — narrowly focused here on the school of thought associated with Dignāga, Dharmakīrti, and their successors — variously interpreted as endorsing either idealism or global antirealism, and the causal theories of knowledge of naturalistic epistemology; and second, between the anti-essentialism of Buddhist metaphysics and its no-self view, and Husserlian phenomenology with its commitment to eidetic essences. Hence, my book also aims to showcase the importance of constructive engagements with Buddhist ideas and methods by treating them not merely as exegetical materials, but rather as valuable conceptual resources and positions that can, and in my view do, advance our understanding of what there is, and the means by which we achieve epistemic certainty. I pursue this task especially in the last three chapters of the book, through an exploration of foundationalism and the phenomenology of perception  
+
between the positions of [[Buddhist]] [[epistemologists]] — narrowly focused here on the school of [[thought]] associated with [[Dignāga]], [[Dharmakīrti]], and their successors — variously interpreted as endorsing either [[idealism]] or global antirealism, and the causal theories of [[knowledge]] of {{Wiki|naturalistic}} epistemology; and second, between the anti-essentialism of [[Buddhist metaphysics]] and its [[no-self]] view, and Husserlian [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] with its commitment to eidetic [[essences]]. Hence, my [[book]] also aims to showcase the importance of constructive engagements with [[Buddhist]] [[ideas]] and [[methods]] by treating them not merely as {{Wiki|exegetical}} materials, but rather as valuable {{Wiki|conceptual}} resources and positions that can, and in my view do, advance our [[understanding]] of what there is, and the means by which we achieve {{Wiki|epistemic}} {{Wiki|certainty}}. I pursue this task especially in the last three chapters of the [[book]], through an exploration of {{Wiki|foundationalism}} and the [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] of [[perception]]
  
(Chapter 7), of the relation between perception, self-awareness, and intentionality (Chapter 8), and a defence of epistemological optimism (Chapter 9). In lieu of a summary of the various theoretical proposals and their supporting arguments, the Précis will provide a guide to the book’s main ideas as foregrounded by its stated aim. A Working Premise The point of departure for Perceiving Reality is the idea that perception is an embodied structural feature of consciousness whose function is determined by phenomenal experiences in a corresponding domain (of visible, tangibles, etc.). This view is in sharp contrast with the notion, common among philosophers who espouse some version or  
+
([[Chapter]] 7), of the [[relation]] between [[perception]], [[self-awareness]], and {{Wiki|intentionality}} ([[Chapter]] 8), and a defence of [[epistemological]] {{Wiki|optimism}} ([[Chapter]] 9). In lieu of a summary of the various {{Wiki|theoretical}} proposals and their supporting arguments, the Précis will provide a guide to the book’s main [[ideas]] as foregrounded by its stated aim. A Working Premise The point of departure for Perceiving [[Reality]] is the [[idea]] that [[perception]] is an [[embodied]] structural feature of [[consciousness]] whose function is determined by [[phenomenal]] [[experiences]] in a [[corresponding]] domain (of [[visible]], tangibles, etc.). This view is in sharp contrast with the notion, common among [[philosophers]] who espouse some version or  
  
another of direct realism, that ‘perception’ is simply a descriptive category whose meaning can be established by definition. As a phenomenal experience, perception can become the intentional object of a specific mode of cognitive awareness: call it direct, nonconceptual awareness (Skt. nirvikalpa-jñāna). As some Buddhist philosophers recognized a long time ago, phenomenal concepts (that is, concepts of experience, e.g. ‘seeing’ or ‘discerning’) are conceptually irreducible: thus, one does not acquire the notion of ‘the which is before the eye’ (the literal meaning of the Sanskrit technical term ‘pratyakṣa’ or ‘perception’) by a priori postulation or definition. On this view, it is impossible to provide an account of phenomenal concepts in non-phenomenal terms. One cannot explain the experience of blue, the pitch of Middle C, or the attitude of concern in terms that  
+
another of [[direct realism]], that ‘[[perception]]’ is simply a descriptive category whose meaning can be established by [[definition]]. As a [[phenomenal]] [[experience]], [[perception]] can become the intentional [[object]] of a specific mode of [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[awareness]]: call it direct, [[nonconceptual awareness]] (Skt. [[nirvikalpa-jñāna]]). As some [[Buddhist philosophers]] [[recognized]] a long time ago, [[phenomenal]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] (that is, [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of [[experience]], e.g. ‘[[seeing]]’ or ‘discerning’) are conceptually irreducible: thus, one does not acquire the notion of ‘the which is before the [[eye]]’ (the literal meaning of the [[Sanskrit]] technical term ‘[[pratyakṣa]]’ or ‘[[perception]]’) by {{Wiki|a priori}} postulation or [[definition]]. On this view, it is impossible to provide an account of [[phenomenal]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] in non-phenomenal terms. One cannot explain the [[experience]] of blue, the pitch of Middle C, or the [[attitude]] of [[concern]] in terms that  
  
make no reference to their phenomenal qualities. If perception is continuous with what it apprehends how can it get to the things themselves? How can it acquaint us with the world, and guarantee effective action? To answer this question we need to recall the Buddhist’s austere and highly fragmented ontology of partless atoms. As Vasubandhu, a key forerunner of the Buddhist epistemological programme, notes, the senses are not the instruments of some internal agent (a self or mind), extending the latter’s reach into the natural world. Rather, the concreteness of sense experience discloses a world of objects as defined by specific phenomenal properties such as resistance, transformation, and dissolution. In a distinctly phenomenological idiom developed centuries before Husserl, Vasubandhu clarifies that the nature of materiality (rūpa or ‘form’) is such that it can be disrupted as a result of impact with an agent or as something  
+
make no reference to their [[phenomenal]] qualities. If [[perception]] is continuous with what it apprehends how can it get to the things themselves? How can it acquaint us with the [[world]], and guarantee effective [[action]]? To answer this question we need to recall the [[Buddhist’s]] [[austere]] and highly fragmented {{Wiki|ontology}} of partless [[atoms]]. As [[Vasubandhu]], a key forerunner of the [[Buddhist]] [[epistemological]] programme, notes, the [[senses]] are not the instruments of some internal agent (a [[self]] or [[mind]]), extending the latter’s reach into the natural [[world]]. Rather, the concreteness of [[sense]] [[experience]] discloses a [[world]] of [[objects]] as defined by specific [[phenomenal]] properties such as resistance, [[transformation]], and dissolution. In a distinctly {{Wiki|phenomenological}} idiom developed centuries before [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], [[Vasubandhu]] clarifies that the [[nature]] of [[materiality]] ([[rūpa]] or ‘[[form]]’) is such that it can be disrupted as a result of impact with an agent or as something  
  
that can oppose resistance. These properties (e.g. alteration, resistance), however, do not extend to the atoms themselves, which form the building blocks of materiality. As monadic units, the atoms are regarded as lacking any formal properties, which they can only acquire as atomic compounds. The difficulty of reconciling atomism, a fundamental tenet of Buddhist ontology, with the phenomenology of perception is apparent in early debates between various schools of thought (chiefly those of the Vaibhāṣikas and the Sautrāntikas) on the issue of whether the sensible qualities of objects (e.g. shape, colour) supervene on the atoms. On some accounts colour, for instance, is treated as a  
+
that can oppose resistance. These properties (e.g. [[alteration]], resistance), however, do not extend to the [[atoms]] themselves, which [[form]] the building blocks of [[materiality]]. As monadic units, the [[atoms]] are regarded as lacking any formal properties, which they can only acquire as [[atomic]] compounds. The difficulty of reconciling [[atomism]], a fundamental [[tenet]] of [[Buddhist ontology]], with the [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] of [[perception]] is apparent in early [[debates]] between various schools of [[thought]] (chiefly those of the [[Vaibhāṣikas]] and the [[Sautrāntikas]]) on the issue of whether the sensible qualities of [[objects]] (e.g. shape, {{Wiki|colour}}) supervene on the [[atoms]]. On some accounts {{Wiki|colour}}, for instance, is treated as a  
  
substance, while on others merely as a potentiality to occasion different types of experience. The line of thought that gets most traction is the one that regards atoms not as substantial impartite entities, but as the subtlest conceivable collection of elements (see de la Vallee Poussin, 1971, II, 22ab.). These subtle elements, when compounded, acquire emergent properties, but their apprehension as aggregated wholes also reflects the constitution and function of the perceptual systems. Consider, for instance, fluidity. It is not a primary property of water atoms (those atoms that, when compounded, manifest as water), but rather a secondary property of water elements. The structure of emergent phenomena reflects this elemental level of organization, which depends on a vast array of causal and conditioning factors. A different configuration of the same  
+
[[substance]], while on others merely as a potentiality to occasion different types of [[experience]]. The line of [[thought]] that gets most traction is the one that regards [[atoms]] not as substantial impartite entities, but as the subtlest conceivable collection of [[elements]] (see de la Vallee [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Poussin]], 1971, II, 22ab.). These [[subtle elements]], when [[compounded]], acquire emergent properties, but their apprehension as aggregated wholes also reflects the constitution and function of the {{Wiki|perceptual systems}}. Consider, for instance, [[fluidity]]. It is not a primary property of [[water]] [[atoms]] (those [[atoms]] that, when [[compounded]], [[manifest]] as [[water]]), but rather a secondary property of [[water elements]]. The {{Wiki|structure}} of emergent [[phenomena]] reflects this [[elemental]] level of [[organization]], which depends on a vast array of causal and {{Wiki|conditioning}} factors. A different configuration of the same  
  
elements may produce the sensation of hardness and coldness, as is the case with ice. With Dignāga and Dharmakīrti — the key protagonists of the Buddhist epistemological enterprise — there is an important shift of emphasis from ontological to epistemological concerns. The ‘real’ is described in pragmatic rather than ontological terms. If reality were made up of changeless and enduring entities, the argument goes, the effects produced by such entities would be equally changeless and enduring. But what does not change cannot produce any effect, for the effect in this case would either be identical with the generating cause or consist in a perpetual reiteration of it. Such is, then, the conclusion that Dharmakīrti draws following his appraisal of Vasubandhu’s notion that only partless entities are ultimately real. For Dharmakīrti, causal efficacy, essentially the ability of an object to perform a function (arthakriyāsamartha), is the true mark of the real: This particular alone constitutes an object of perception; others (viz., universals and the like) are concealed from the purview of perception. This particular is referred to as ‘cause and effect’ and is what we mean  
+
[[elements]] may produce the [[sensation]] of {{Wiki|hardness}} and coldness, as is the case with ice. With [[Dignāga]] and [[Dharmakīrti]] — the key protagonists of the [[Buddhist]] [[epistemological]] enterprise — there is an important shift of {{Wiki|emphasis}} from [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] to [[epistemological]] concerns. The ‘real’ is described in {{Wiki|pragmatic}} rather than [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] terms. If [[reality]] were made up of changeless and enduring entities, the argument goes, the effects produced by such entities would be equally changeless and enduring. But what does not change cannot produce any effect, for the effect in this case would either be [[identical]] with the generating [[cause]] or consist in a [[perpetual]] reiteration of it. Such is, then, the conclusion that [[Dharmakīrti]] draws following his appraisal of [[Vasubandhu’s]] notion that only partless entities are [[ultimately real]]. For [[Dharmakīrti]], causal efficacy, [[essentially]] the ability of an [[object]] to perform a function (arthakriyāsamartha), is the [[true mark]] of the real: This particular alone constitutes an [[object]] of [[perception]]; others (viz., universals and the like) are concealed from the purview of [[perception]]. This particular is referred to as ‘[[cause and effect]]’ and is what we mean  
  
by the notion of ‘particular.’ As we have said, only an entity that has causal efficacy is deemed a real object of perception. And it is this specific particular that we have called an individual object. (Pandeya, 1989, p. 258) The language of particulars and universals, claims Dharmakīrti, applies to objects only in terms of their specific phenomenal qualities (qualities that reflect the efficacy of the entities that produce them). These are not external referents, but defining characteristics of singles, types of which there can be any number of tokens. But even if the Buddhist epistemologist shifts the focus of perception from unique particulars (tokens) to phenomenal properties (types), the ‘uniqueness’ of the perceived as perceived also stems from its mode of presentation. Where at one time the unique and irreducible elements of Buddhist ontology  
+
by the notion of ‘particular.’ As we have said, only an [[entity]] that has causal efficacy is deemed a [[real object]] of [[perception]]. And it is this specific particular that we have called an {{Wiki|individual}} [[object]]. (Pandeya, 1989, p. 258) The [[language]] of particulars and universals, claims [[Dharmakīrti]], applies to [[objects]] only in terms of their specific [[phenomenal]] qualities (qualities that reflect the efficacy of the entities that produce them). These are not external referents, but [[defining characteristics]] of singles, types of which there can be any number of tokens. But even if the [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|epistemologist}} shifts the focus of [[perception]] from unique particulars (tokens) to [[phenomenal]] properties (types), the ‘[[uniqueness]]’ of the [[perceived]] as [[perceived]] also stems from its mode of presentation. Where at one time the unique and irreducible [[elements]] of [[Buddhist ontology]]
  
were related to conceptually cognate terms such as ‘unique particular’ (svalakṣaṇa) and ‘intrinsic nature’ (svabhāva), now they are seen as embedded in the very cognitive structures that manifest them: feelings and thoughts, for instance, are unique particulars too, but their apprehension is continuous with their mode of disclosure; as specific kinds of self-awareness (e.g. of painful, pleasant, or alert states). The content of a particular mental state may be momentary and discrete, but recurrent, and reflective of the dynamics of the psychophysical aggregates that sustain human experience. Ultimately, however, the phenomenal content of experience reflects our condition of embodiment to which perceptual awareness provides constant, uninterrupted, and unmediated access. In Perceiving Reality, I try to develop a way of conceiving of our most basic mode of being in the world that resists attempts to cleave reality into an inner and outer, a mental and a physical domain (Chapter 1 through 3). I argue that what we apprehend in perception are not, to paraphrase J.L. Austin, the external, mind-independent, medium-sized dry goods that populate the realist’s ontology (Chapter 4). Rather, to paraphrase Husserl and a group of Buddhist philosophers in league with Dignāga and Dharmakīrti, the objects in question are the intentional or aspectual objects: the blue sky as seen, the pot as grasped, and pain as felt. As a fundamental experience that grounds our sense of being and what there is, perception marks the beginning and end of our conscious lives. Charting out the structure, content, and character of this perceptual awareness is therefore both an epistemic good in its own right and key to advancing any metaphysical claim (Chapters 5 through to 9). After all, as Peter Strawson famously wrote more than thirty years ago: ‘a philosopher’s views on  
+
were related to conceptually {{Wiki|cognate}} terms such as ‘unique particular’ ([[svalakṣaṇa]]) and ‘[[intrinsic nature]]’ ([[svabhāva]]), now they are seen as embedded in the very [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] structures that [[manifest]] them: [[feelings]] and [[thoughts]], for instance, are unique particulars too, but their apprehension is continuous with their mode of disclosure; as specific kinds of [[self-awareness]] (e.g. of [[painful]], [[pleasant]], or alert states). The content of a particular [[mental state]] may be momentary and discrete, but recurrent, and reflective of the dynamics of the {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[aggregates]] that sustain [[human experience]]. Ultimately, however, the [[phenomenal]] content of [[experience]] reflects our [[condition]] of [[embodiment]] to which [[perceptual awareness]] provides [[constant]], uninterrupted, and unmediated access. In Perceiving [[Reality]], I try to develop a way of [[conceiving]] of our most basic mode of being in the [[world]] that resists attempts to cleave [[reality]] into an inner and outer, a [[mental]] and a [[physical]] domain ([[Chapter]] 1 through 3). I argue that what we apprehend in [[perception]] are not, to {{Wiki|paraphrase}} J.L. [[Austin]], the external, mind-independent, medium-sized dry goods that populate the realist’s {{Wiki|ontology}} ([[Chapter]] 4). Rather, to {{Wiki|paraphrase}} [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] and a group of [[Buddhist philosophers]] in league with [[Dignāga]] and [[Dharmakīrti]], the [[objects]] in question are the intentional or aspectual [[objects]]: the blue sky as seen, the pot as grasped, and [[pain]] as felt. As a fundamental [[experience]] that grounds our [[sense]] of being and what there is, [[perception]] marks the beginning and end of our [[conscious]] [[lives]]. Charting out the {{Wiki|structure}}, content, and [[character]] of this [[perceptual awareness]] is therefore both an {{Wiki|epistemic}} good in its [[own]] right and key to advancing any [[metaphysical]] claim (Chapters 5 through to 9). After all, as Peter [[Strawson]] famously wrote more than thirty years ago: ‘a philosopher’s [[views]] on  
  
[perception] are a key to his theory of knowledge and to his metaphysics’ (Strawson, 1979, p. 141). An Enduring Dispute A central problem in contemporary discussions of consciousness is the problem of determining precisely what a mental state’s being conscious consists in. This problem raises a range of conceptual issues about the nature and structure of consciousness. Of particular importance here is the relation between consciousness and selfawareness. The key question is: does consciousness imply selfconsciousness or is self-consciousness the result of a higher-order cognition (a metacognition) co-occurrent with, and taking a previous instance of cognition as, its object? In perceiving an object, is the content of perception the exclusive focus of attention or is there an implicit awareness of the perceiving act itself? The analysis of  
+
[[[perception]]] are a key to his [[theory of knowledge]] and to his [[metaphysics]]’ ([[Strawson]], 1979, p. 141). An Enduring Dispute A central problem in contemporary discussions of [[consciousness]] is the problem of determining precisely what a [[mental]] state’s being [[conscious]] consists in. This problem raises a range of {{Wiki|conceptual}} issues about the [[nature]] and {{Wiki|structure}} of [[consciousness]]. Of particular importance here is the [[relation]] between [[consciousness]] and selfawareness. The key question is: does [[consciousness]] imply selfconsciousness or is [[self-consciousness]] the result of a higher-order [[cognition]] (a {{Wiki|metacognition}}) co-occurrent with, and taking a previous instance of [[cognition]] as, its [[object]]? In perceiving an [[object]], is the content of [[perception]] the exclusive focus of [[attention]] or is there an implicit [[awareness]] of the perceiving act itself? The analysis of  
  
this issue typically divides between those that take conscious cognition to be a ‘one-state’ and those that regard it as a ‘two-state’ process. One-state proponents argue that a mental state can be deemed conscious if and only if it possesses a specific character: it is reflexive or self-reflexive. This view finds its clearest modern articulation in Franz Brentano: ‘Every consciousness upon whatever object it is primarily directed, is constantly directed upon itself’ (Brentano, 1982, p. 25). This thesis of the unity of consciousness as reflexive awareness, which we encounter in various forms in Descartes, Kant and, following Brentano, in Husserl, Sartre, and many contemporary philosophers working in the phenomenological tradition, has its roots not only in Greek philosophy (specifically in Aristotle), but also in classical Indian philosophy. As Dharmakīrti, one of the strongest defenders of this thesis, declares in his Drop of Reasoning (Nyāya-bindu): ‘every mental state is reflexively aware of itself’ (Malvania, 1971, p. 64). In Perceiving Reality I offer a detailed reworking of this Buddhist defence of the reflexivity thesis, presenting its arguments as live options for ongoing dialogue and debate. Critics of the reflexivity thesis of consciousness in both India and the west have traditionally pointed to such issues as the conceptual problem of other minds, and more recently to the findings of cognitive science about the opacity of most of our conscious mental states. Proposing an alternative, two-state (or higher-order thought, or HOT) conception of consciousness, they argue that a mental state is conscious in virtue of a distinct second-order state that is directed toward  
+
this issue typically divides between those that take [[conscious]] [[cognition]] to be a ‘one-state’ and those that regard it as a ‘two-state’ process. One-state proponents argue that a [[mental state]] can be deemed [[conscious]] if and only if it possesses a specific [[character]]: it is reflexive or self-reflexive. This view finds its clearest {{Wiki|modern}} articulation in Franz Brentano: ‘Every [[consciousness]] upon whatever [[object]] it is primarily directed, is constantly directed upon itself’ (Brentano, 1982, p. 25). This {{Wiki|thesis}} of the [[unity of consciousness]] as [[reflexive awareness]], which we encounter in various [[forms]] in {{Wiki|Descartes}}, {{Wiki|Kant}} and, following Brentano, in [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], {{Wiki|Sartre}}, and many contemporary [[philosophers]] working in the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} [[tradition]], has its [[roots]] not only in {{Wiki|Greek philosophy}} (specifically in {{Wiki|Aristotle}}), but also in classical [[Indian philosophy]]. As [[Dharmakīrti]], one of the strongest defenders of this {{Wiki|thesis}}, declares in his [[Drop of Reasoning]] (Nyāya-bindu): ‘every [[mental state]] is reflexively {{Wiki|aware}} of itself’ (Malvania, 1971, p. 64). In Perceiving [[Reality]] I offer a detailed reworking of this [[Buddhist]] defence of the reflexivity {{Wiki|thesis}}, presenting its arguments as live options for ongoing {{Wiki|dialogue}} and [[debate]]. Critics of the reflexivity {{Wiki|thesis}} of [[consciousness]] in both [[India]] and the [[west]] have [[traditionally]] pointed to such issues as the {{Wiki|conceptual}} problem of other [[minds]], and more recently to the findings of [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[science]] about the opacity of most of our [[conscious]] [[mental states]]. Proposing an alternative, two-state (or higher-order [[thought]], or HOT) {{Wiki|conception}} of [[consciousness]], they argue that a [[mental state]] is [[conscious]] in [[virtue]] of a {{Wiki|distinct}} second-order [[state]] that is directed toward  
 
   
 
   
it. This later group includes, among others, David Armstrong (1968; 1981/1997), David Rosenthal (1986; 2004), William Lycan (1996), and Rocco Gennaro (1996; 2006). Like the one-state model, the higher-order thought view too has antecedents in the Indian philosophical tradition. Indeed, Nyāya philosophers and notable Buddhist thinkers like Candrakīrti and Śāntideva (fl. eighth century) defend versions of the higher-order view. For Candrakīrti in particular, who critically engages Dignāga’s thought, consciousness cannot be thought of as reflexive, even on a conventional level, for that would imply that consciousness is selfvalidating (de la Vallée Poussin, 1970, VI, pp. 74–6). What Candrakīrti takes issue with is the view (typically associated with the ‘Practice of Yoga’ or Yogācāra School) that the object of cognition is not extrinsic to cognition but is  
+
it. This later group includes, among others, David Armstrong (1968; 1981/1997), David Rosenthal (1986; 2004), William Lycan (1996), and Rocco Gennaro (1996; 2006). Like the one-state model, the higher-order [[thought]] view too has antecedents in the [[Indian]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]]. Indeed, [[Nyāya]] [[philosophers]] and notable [[Buddhist]] thinkers like [[Candrakīrti]] and [[Śāntideva]] (fl. eighth century) defend versions of the higher-order view. For [[Candrakīrti]] in particular, who critically engages [[Dignāga’s]] [[thought]], [[consciousness]] cannot be [[thought]] of as reflexive, even on a [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] level, for that would imply that [[consciousness]] is selfvalidating (de la [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Vallée Poussin]], 1970, VI, pp. 74–6). What [[Candrakīrti]] takes issue with is the view (typically associated with the ‘Practice of [[Yoga]]’ or [[Yogācāra School]]) that the [[object]] of [[cognition]] is not extrinsic to [[cognition]] but is  
  
an aspect of cognition itself. As I write (p. 239): ‘Candrakīrti’s critique of reflexive awareness, then, targets this notion that there is a class of cognitive events that are essentially self-characterizing: they reveal their own content without recourse to an additional instance of cognitive awareness, an object, or the positing of a subject of experience. More to the point, Candrakīrti rejects the notion that reflexive awareness has this unique property of giving access to the pure datum of experience.’ The contemporary version of this view is that for a given mental state to be conscious a subject must have an appropriate higher-order belief, thought, or judgment that he or she is in that mental state. Take, for instance, Rosenthal’s influential defence of the higher-order view: ‘Conscious states are simply mental states we are conscious of being in. And, in general, our being conscious of something is just a matter of our having a thought of some sort about it’ (Rosenthal, 1986, p. 465). According to Rosenthal, for consciousness to be intelligible and analysable, one must assume it to be an external, relational property of mental states, and of having something like an articulable structure. Here’s what I see as the main difficulty with this theory. Rosenthal argues that it is possible, in principle, that I be persuaded of my being angry through someone else’s testimony. Thus, I may realize that I am angry in the absence of any conscious feeling of anger, that is, without feeling angry much like a depressive might learn about her condition from a therapist without having any awareness of it. This example underscores the inferential character of one’s access to subjective experience. On the higher-order theory, an individual must have a suitably unmediated higher-order thought about being in that state. But this higher-order state will not itself be conscious unless subject to  
+
an aspect of [[cognition]] itself. As I write (p. 239): ‘[[Candrakīrti’s]] critique of [[reflexive awareness]], then, targets this notion that there is a class of [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] events that are [[essentially]] self-characterizing: they reveal their [[own]] content without recourse to an additional instance of [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[awareness]], an [[object]], or the positing of a [[subject]] of [[experience]]. More to the point, [[Candrakīrti]] rejects the notion that [[reflexive awareness]] has this unique property of giving access to the [[pure]] datum of [[experience]].’ The contemporary version of this view is that for a given [[mental state]] to be [[conscious]] a [[subject]] must have an appropriate higher-order [[belief]], [[thought]], or [[judgment]] that he or she is in that [[mental state]]. Take, for instance, Rosenthal’s influential defence of the higher-order view: ‘[[Conscious]] states are simply [[mental states]] we are [[conscious]] of being in. And, in general, our being [[conscious]] of something is just a {{Wiki|matter}} of our having a [[thought]] of some sort about it’ (Rosenthal, 1986, p. 465). According to Rosenthal, for [[consciousness]] to be intelligible and analysable, one must assume it to be an external, relational property of [[mental states]], and of having something like an articulable {{Wiki|structure}}. Here’s what I see as the main difficulty with this {{Wiki|theory}}. Rosenthal argues that it is possible, in [[principle]], that I be persuaded of my being [[angry]] through someone else’s testimony. Thus, I may realize that I am [[angry]] in the absence of any [[conscious]] [[feeling]] of [[anger]], that is, without [[feeling]] [[angry]] much like a depressive might learn about her [[condition]] from a {{Wiki|therapist}} without having any [[awareness]] of it. This example underscores the inferential [[character]] of one’s access to [[subjective]] [[experience]]. On the higher-order {{Wiki|theory}}, an {{Wiki|individual}} must have a suitably unmediated higher-order [[thought]] about being in that [[state]]. But this higher-order [[state]] will not itself be [[conscious]] unless [[subject]] to  
  
another higher-order thought about it (thus leading to infinite regress). That means, a fairly large number of these higher-order thoughts are in fact unconscious. How exactly series of unconscious cognitive events generate conscious apprehension is not at all clear. As Dharmakīrti, a critic of the regress argument, famously puts it his Ascertainment of the Sources of Reliable Cognition (Pramāṇaviniścaya): Awaiting the end of a series of successive cognitions, a person does not comprehend any object, because a cognition cannot be established as cognition when that cognition which is first-personally known (i.e. selfawareness) has not been first established. And since there is no end to the arising of cognitions, the whole world would be blind and deaf. (Steinkellner, 1973, p. 41) How, might we ask, can an unconscious mental state operate to confer consciousness  
+
another higher-order [[thought]] about it (thus leading to [[infinite]] regress). That means, a fairly large number of these higher-order [[thoughts]] are in fact [[unconscious]]. How exactly series of [[unconscious]] [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] events generate [[conscious]] apprehension is not at all clear. As [[Dharmakīrti]], a critic of the regress argument, famously puts it his Ascertainment of the Sources of Reliable [[Cognition]] ([[Pramāṇaviniścaya]]): Awaiting the end of a series of successive [[cognitions]], a [[person]] does not comprehend any [[object]], because a [[cognition]] cannot be established as [[cognition]] when that [[cognition]] which is first-personally known (i.e. selfawareness) has not been first established. And since there is no end to the [[arising]] of [[cognitions]], the whole [[world]] would be [[blind]] and [[deaf]]. ([[Steinkellner]], 1973, p. 41) How, might we ask, can an [[unconscious]] [[mental state]] operate to confer [[consciousness]]
  
on another unconscious mental state? In other words, if the HOT theory claims that the thoughts required for consciousness can themselves be unconscious, we are owed an explanation of how the unconscious mental states can be a source for consciousness. Given these problematic issues, defenders of the higher-order view should not be allowed to gloss over the question of the phenomenal character of consciousness by assuming that consciousness owes its phenomenal character, indeed its very subjectivity, to an external relation of some sort. Instead, the relational scenario ought to be unpacked in considerable detail so as to explain how it is possible for there to be such a thing as pain that is unconscious or unknown until it becomes the object of a suitably co-occurrent cognition. Indeed, on the view that ‘pain’ is a phenomenal concept that can only be  
+
on another [[unconscious]] [[mental state]]? In other words, if the HOT {{Wiki|theory}} claims that the [[thoughts]] required for [[consciousness]] can themselves be [[unconscious]], we are owed an explanation of how the [[unconscious]] [[mental states]] can be a source for [[consciousness]]. Given these problematic issues, defenders of the higher-order view should not be allowed to gloss over the question of the [[phenomenal]] [[character]] of [[consciousness]] by assuming that [[consciousness]] owes its [[phenomenal]] [[character]], indeed its very [[subjectivity]], to an external [[relation]] of some sort. Instead, the relational scenario ought to be unpacked in considerable detail so as to explain how it is possible for there to be such a thing as [[pain]] that is [[unconscious]] or unknown until it becomes the [[object]] of a suitably co-occurrent [[cognition]]. Indeed, on the view that ‘[[pain]]’ is a [[phenomenal]] {{Wiki|concept}} that can only be  
  
acquired experientially, talk of ‘unconscious pain’ would be akin to committing a category mistake. Someone who has suffered no injury, discomfort, or distress cannot in principle grasp the concept of pain. Furthermore, assuming that one can learn the concept by definition does not entail that one grasps the property expressed by the concept (Nida-Rümelin, 2007, p. 312). One need only point to conditions typically associated with various kinds of psychopathy and sociopathy to provide critical evidence for the relevance of phenomenal experience to phenomenal knowledge. These considerations should give pause and raise concerns that the higher-order theories, in view of their commitment to grounding consciousness in non-conscious mental (and even physical) states, are both more problematic and less equipped to handle analyses of phenomenal consciousness. Specifically, these considerations invite us  
+
acquired experientially, talk of ‘[[unconscious]] [[pain]]’ would be akin to committing a category mistake. Someone who has [[suffered]] no injury, discomfort, or {{Wiki|distress}} cannot in [[principle]] [[grasp]] the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[pain]]. Furthermore, assuming that one can learn the {{Wiki|concept}} by [[definition]] does not entail that one [[grasps]] the property expressed by the {{Wiki|concept}} (Nida-Rümelin, 2007, p. 312). One need only point to [[conditions]] typically associated with various kinds of psychopathy and sociopathy to provide critical {{Wiki|evidence}} for the relevance of [[phenomenal]] [[experience]] to [[phenomenal]] [[knowledge]]. These considerations should give pause and raise concerns that the higher-order theories, in view of their commitment to grounding [[consciousness]] in non-conscious [[mental]] (and even [[physical]]) states, are both more problematic and less equipped to handle analyses of {{Wiki|phenomenal consciousness}}. Specifically, these considerations invite us  
  
to go beyond traditional positions in metaphysics concerning the relation between mind and world, and corresponding debates in epistemology concerning externalist accounts of mental content. For these reasons, in Perceiving Reality I offer an alternative account of experience that requires a completely new vocabulary for its expression, one capable of capturing the specific ways of our being in the world. Perception and Causation The Buddhist epistemologist’s broadly empirical approach to knowledge means that reasons are meant to provide an account of how things are before we set out to theorize about them. For the Buddhist, this theorizing accords with the phenomenological stance that perception represents a form of implicit knowing that cannot be improved upon by inferential reasoning. There is no cognitive penetrability of perception for the Buddhist, only  
+
to go beyond [[traditional]] positions in [[metaphysics]] concerning the [[relation]] between [[mind]] and [[world]], and [[corresponding]] [[debates]] in epistemology concerning [[externalist]] accounts of [[mental]] content. For these [[reasons]], in Perceiving [[Reality]] I offer an alternative account of [[experience]] that requires a completely new vocabulary for its expression, one capable of capturing the specific ways of our being in the [[world]]. [[Perception]] and [[Causation]] The [[Buddhist]] epistemologist’s broadly [[empirical]] approach to [[knowledge]] means that [[reasons]] are meant to provide an account of how things are before we set out to theorize about them. For the [[Buddhist]], this theorizing accords with the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} stance that [[perception]] represents a [[form]] of implicit [[knowing]] that cannot be improved upon by inferential {{Wiki|reasoning}}. There is no [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] penetrability of [[perception]] for the [[Buddhist]], only  
  
discoverable salient features of perceptual phenomenology. In so grounding our enquiries we can think along with (rather that simply about) these Buddhist philosophers, guided by a principle that most phenomenologists and many philosophers of mind today share: our considerations about what perception can and does disclose trump ontological assumptions about what there is. The leading question is not whether the dress is blue and black or white and gold. Rather, the question is just what it is about the structure of awareness that causes things to appears as such: that is, as occasioning different types of experience. This picture of the structure of awareness and its underlying causal factors has deep roots in the Buddhist canonical literature. The Buddhist, like Hume, is a bundle theorist. But what is it that holds together the aggregates (of body,  
+
discoverable salient features of {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]]. In so grounding our enquiries we can think along with (rather that simply about) these [[Buddhist philosophers]], guided by a [[principle]] that most [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologists]] and many [[philosophers]] of [[mind]] today share: our considerations about what [[perception]] can and does disclose trump [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|assumptions}} about what there is. The leading question is not whether the dress is blue and black or white and {{Wiki|gold}}. Rather, the question is just what it is about the {{Wiki|structure}} of [[awareness]] that [[causes]] things to appears as such: that is, as occasioning different types of [[experience]]. This picture of the {{Wiki|structure}} of [[awareness]] and its underlying causal factors has deep [[roots]] in the [[Buddhist canonical]] {{Wiki|literature}}. The [[Buddhist]], like [[Hume]], is a bundle theorist. But what is it that holds together the [[aggregates]] (of [[body]],  
  
sensation, apperception, volition, and consciousness), and generates the sense of personal identity? Answer: the proliferating tendencies (prapañca) of a reflecting and deliberating (vitarka-vicāra) mind. On this standard picture, perception and causation are locked in a dynamic, recursive, and coemergent process: Dependent on the eye and forms, visual-consciousness arises. The meeting of the three is contact. With contact as condition there is feeling. What one feels, that one perceives. What one perceives, that one thinks about. What one thinks about, that one mentally proliferates (papañceti). With what one has mentally proliferated as the source, perception and notions resulting from mental proliferation beset a man  
+
[[sensation]], {{Wiki|apperception}}, [[Wikipedia:Volition (psychology)|volition]], and [[consciousness]]), and generates the [[sense]] of personal [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]? Answer: the proliferating {{Wiki|tendencies}} ([[prapañca]]) of a {{Wiki|reflecting}} and deliberating (vitarka-vicāra) [[mind]]. On this standard picture, [[perception]] and [[causation]] are locked in a dynamic, recursive, and coemergent process: Dependent on the [[eye]] and [[forms]], [[visual-consciousness]] arises. The meeting of the three is [[contact]]. With [[contact]] as [[condition]] there is [[feeling]]. What one [[feels]], that one [[perceives]]. What one [[perceives]], that one [[thinks]] about. What one [[thinks]] about, that one [[mentally]] proliferates ([[papañceti]]). With what one has [[mentally]] proliferated as the source, [[perception]] and notions resulting from [[mental]] {{Wiki|proliferation}} beset a man  
  
with respect to past, future, and present forms cognizable through the eye. (Ñāṇamoli and Bodhi, 2001, p. 203) In mapping out the co-arising of perception, object perceived, and perceptual awareness, the Buddhist puts forth a different conception of naturalism: specifically, one that regards empirical awareness as grounding our sense of being and what there is. This is a naturalism that takes cognition to be a constitutive feature of the world, not merely a by-product of it. Although a discerning type of consciousness (e.g. visual, tactile, etc.) accompanies each of the sensory modalities, ultimately the relation between perception and its content, while determined by features that are inherent to perception itself, is driven by habitual practices. This notion that the ordinary mind is characterized by habitual modes of thinking becomes crucial in the  
+
with [[respect]] to {{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|future}}, and {{Wiki|present}} [[forms]] cognizable through the [[eye]]. ([[Ñāṇamoli]] and [[Bodhi]], 2001, p. 203) In mapping out the co-arising of [[perception]], [[object]] [[perceived]], and [[perceptual awareness]], the [[Buddhist]] puts forth a different {{Wiki|conception}} of [[naturalism]]: specifically, one that regards [[empirical]] [[awareness]] as grounding our [[sense]] of being and what there is. This is a [[naturalism]] that takes [[cognition]] to be a constitutive feature of the [[world]], not merely a by-product of it. Although a discerning type of [[consciousness]] (e.g. [[visual]], {{Wiki|tactile}}, etc.) accompanies each of the sensory modalities, ultimately the [[relation]] between [[perception]] and its content, while determined by features that are [[inherent]] to [[perception]] itself, is driven by habitual practices. This notion that the [[ordinary mind]] is characterized by habitual modes of [[thinking]] becomes crucial in the  
  
Abhidharma analyses of consciousness and cognition. As I write, (p. 63): in the Discourses, this tendency toward the proliferation of mental imagery is more closely associated with sensation and is connected with consciousness only in so far as perception is considered to be proliferating and constructive in its character, that is, in so far as perception is taken to primarily refer to perceptual judgments. Because the six spheres of contact furnish the mind, its dynamics are sustained by the constant flow of mental and sensory impressions. Ordinarily, one is constantly assailed by proliferating thoughts and desires, which compromise the capacity for having veridical perceptual experiences. The psychological impact of this proliferating process on perception is significant: due to ongoing mental activity (pondering, judging, recollecting, etc.), perceptual objects are apprehended only as grasped by our conceptual and categorizing practices. In short, ordinary, untutored perception is laden with judgment. Thus, although  
+
[[Abhidharma]] analyses of [[consciousness]] and [[cognition]]. As I write, (p. 63): in the [[Discourses]], this tendency toward the {{Wiki|proliferation}} of [[mental]] [[imagery]] is more closely associated with [[sensation]] and is connected with [[consciousness only]] in so far as [[perception]] is considered to be proliferating and constructive in its [[character]], that is, in so far as [[perception]] is taken to primarily refer to {{Wiki|perceptual}} judgments. Because the [[six spheres]] of [[contact]] furnish the [[mind]], its dynamics are sustained by the [[constant]] flow of [[mental]] and sensory [[impressions]]. Ordinarily, one is constantly assailed by proliferating [[thoughts]] and [[desires]], which compromise the capacity for having veridical {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[experiences]]. The [[psychological]] impact of this proliferating process on [[perception]] is significant: due to ongoing [[mental activity]] ([[pondering]], judging, recollecting, etc.), {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[objects]] are apprehended only as grasped by our {{Wiki|conceptual}} and categorizing practices. In short, ordinary, untutored [[perception]] is laden with [[judgment]]. Thus, although  
  
at the basic, functional level the perceptual systems present the world in its immediacy, what an individual apprehends also depends upon his or her discerning and attentional capacities. There are no fixed markers, no system of checks and balances to ensure the reliability of perception even under optimal circumstances. And since the domain of sensory phenomena is in constant flux, there are no independent entities either, only textures or clusters of sensory impressions that ebb and flow depending at once upon the level of attentiveness and the intensity and vividness of the manifest object. At first blush, it may seem as though the notion of a minddependent world — or simply a world as experienced — is suggestive of idealism. But neither the Buddha nor the Abhidharma philosophers  
+
at the basic, functional level the {{Wiki|perceptual systems}} {{Wiki|present}} the [[world]] in its {{Wiki|immediacy}}, what an {{Wiki|individual}} apprehends also depends upon his or her discerning and attentional capacities. There are no fixed markers, no system of checks and balances to ensure the reliability of [[perception]] even under optimal circumstances. And since the domain of sensory [[phenomena]] is in [[constant]] flux, there are no {{Wiki|independent}} entities either, only textures or [[clusters]] of sensory [[impressions]] that ebb and flow depending at once upon the level of attentiveness and the intensity and vividness of the [[manifest]] [[object]]. At first blush, it may seem as though the notion of a minddependent [[world]] — or simply a [[world]] as [[experienced]] — is suggestive of [[idealism]]. But neither the [[Buddha]] nor the [[Abhidharma]] [[philosophers]]
  
deny the reality of the elements of existence and/or experience (dharma-s) and their causal efficacy. Rather, what is put forward here is the view that we cannot properly discern the phenomenal character and content of experience in a way that makes no reference to the aggregates of consciousness. Likewise, we cannot properly understand the aggregates of form or body if we don’t realize that, as an instrument (karaṇa) of sensory activity, the body is both the medium of contact with the world and the world with which it comes in contact. Such a view, I argue, finds an interesting parallel in Husserl’s account of the paradoxical nature of the body as revealed through phenomenological reduction. For Husserl, phenomenological reduction (époche) — essentially a method of bracketing ontological assumptions about the natural world in order to examine the  
+
deny the [[reality]] of the [[elements of existence]] and/or [[experience]] ([[dharma-s]]) and their causal efficacy. Rather, what is put forward here is the view that we cannot properly discern the [[phenomenal]] [[character]] and content of [[experience]] in a way that makes no reference to the [[aggregates]] of [[consciousness]]. Likewise, we cannot properly understand the [[aggregates]] of [[form]] or [[body]] if we don’t realize that, as an instrument ([[karaṇa]]) of sensory [[activity]], the [[body]] is both the {{Wiki|medium}} of [[contact]] with the [[world]] and the [[world]] with which it comes in [[contact]]. Such a view, I argue, finds an [[interesting]] parallel in Husserl’s account of the {{Wiki|paradoxical}} [[nature]] of the [[body]] as revealed through {{Wiki|phenomenological}} reduction. For [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], {{Wiki|phenomenological}} reduction (époche) — [[essentially]] a method of bracketing [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|assumptions}} about the natural [[world]] in order to examine the  
  
intentional structures of consciousness — reveals the twofold appearance of the body, first as a biological entity (Körper) connected to the continuum of life, and second as a medium for the expression of life (Leib). The body is thus the locus of lived experience and, as such, has the capacity for both exploration and receptivity. It is this intuition about the dual nature of sensation, in its transitive and intransitive aspects, which led Husserl to the concept of the life-world (die Lebenswelt): a world of lived experience whose boundaries are not fixed but constantly shifting in relation to the desires, actions, and attitudes of an agent (Husserl, 1970, Part III, A). As Merleau-Ponty, who appropriates Husserl’s notion of the lifeworld as the lived-world (le monde vécu), clearly suggests, ‘I cannot understand the function of living body except by enacting it myself’, for ‘my body appears to me as an attitude with a view to a certain actual or possible task’ (Merleau-Ponty, 2002, pp. 87, 114). For Merleau-Ponty, the world or, better still, the environment is not just a structured domain of causally nested objects and relations, but a meaningful realm of experience. This world qua world, as Taylor Carman (echoing Merleau-Ponty) has recently argued, ‘affords, invites, and facilitates, just as it obtrudes, resists, thwarts, eludes, and coerces’ (Carman, 2005, p. 86). The model of phenomenal consciousness put forward in Perceiving Reality is thus that of a non-reductive, one-state theory of consciousness: a theory which proposes that consciousness is essentially a matter of being or having an awareness of a world that does not presuppose a prior (representational) awareness of its own mental states.  
+
intentional structures of [[consciousness]] — reveals the twofold [[appearance]] of the [[body]], first as a {{Wiki|biological}} [[entity]] (Körper) connected to the {{Wiki|continuum}} of [[life]], and second as a {{Wiki|medium}} for the expression of [[life]] (Leib). The [[body]] is thus the locus of lived [[experience]] and, as such, has the capacity for both exploration and receptivity. It is this [[intuition]] about the dual [[nature]] of [[sensation]], in its transitive and intransitive aspects, which led [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]] to the {{Wiki|concept}} of the life-world ([[die]] Lebenswelt): a [[world]] of lived [[experience]] whose [[boundaries]] are not fixed but constantly shifting in [[relation]] to the [[desires]], [[actions]], and attitudes of an agent ([[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], 1970, Part III, A). As {{Wiki|Merleau-Ponty}}, who appropriates Husserl’s notion of the lifeworld as the lived-world (le monde vécu), clearly suggests, ‘I cannot understand the function of living [[body]] except by enacting it myself’, for ‘my [[body]] appears to me as an [[attitude]] with a view to a certain actual or possible task’ ({{Wiki|Merleau-Ponty}}, 2002, pp. 87, 114). For {{Wiki|Merleau-Ponty}}, the [[world]] or, better still, the {{Wiki|environment}} is not just a structured domain of [[causally]] nested [[objects]] and relations, but a meaningful [[realm]] of [[experience]]. This [[world]] qua [[world]], as Taylor Carman (echoing {{Wiki|Merleau-Ponty}}) has recently argued, ‘affords, invites, and facilitates, just as it obtrudes, resists, thwarts, eludes, and coerces’ (Carman, 2005, p. 86). The model of {{Wiki|phenomenal consciousness}} put forward in Perceiving [[Reality]] is thus that of a non-reductive, one-state {{Wiki|theory}} of [[consciousness]]: a {{Wiki|theory}} which proposes that [[consciousness]] is [[essentially]] a {{Wiki|matter}} of being or having an [[awareness]] of a [[world]] that does not presuppose a prior (representational) [[awareness]] of its [[own]] [[mental states]].  
  
Phenomenology, Buddhist Epistemology, and the Project of Naturalization A central argument of Perceiving Reality is that epistemological enquiries in India, unlike those in the west that follow Descartes’ and Kant’s a priori framework of justification, show a strong commitment to naturalist accounts of belief formation. The return to naturalism in contemporary epistemology, hence to understanding cognition in embodied and causal terms, is good news for Buddhist epistemology. Indeed, a focus on causal accounts of cognition is shared by all Indian epistemological theories, Buddhist or otherwise. But it is Dharmakīrti in particular who focuses on the ways in which the underlying processes of cognition become instrumental in determining which epistemic practices are conducive to effective action. If, indeed, Buddhist epistemological enquiries are driven by  
+
{{Wiki|Phenomenology}}, [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Epistemology}}, and the Project of Naturalization A central argument of Perceiving [[Reality]] is that [[epistemological]] enquiries in [[India]], unlike those in the [[west]] that follow {{Wiki|Descartes}}’ and [[Kant’s]] {{Wiki|a priori}} framework of {{Wiki|justification}}, show a strong commitment to naturalist accounts of [[belief]] formation. The return to [[naturalism]] in contemporary epistemology, hence to [[understanding]] [[cognition]] in [[embodied]] and causal terms, is good news for [[Buddhist epistemology]]. Indeed, a focus on causal accounts of [[cognition]] is shared by all [[Indian]] [[epistemological]] theories, [[Buddhist]] or otherwise. But it is [[Dharmakīrti]] in particular who focuses on the ways in which the underlying {{Wiki|processes}} of [[cognition]] become instrumental in determining which {{Wiki|epistemic}} practices are conducive to effective [[action]]. If, indeed, [[Buddhist]] [[epistemological]] enquiries are driven by  
  
pragmatic rather than normative concerns (that is, by concerns about how we come to believe something rather than why might we be justified in believing it) then we have a better way of explaining our epistemic dispositions (one that reflects our embodied cognition rather than a disembodied cogito). Perhaps the methodological framework best suited to translate and incorporate the Buddhist contribution to philosophy of mind is one that closely aligns with embodied approaches to cognition such as have been developed in the past three decades by Hubert Dreyfus (1979), Varela, Thompson and Rosch (1991), Edwin Hutchins (1995), Andy Clark (1997), Susan Hurley (1998), Alva Noë (2004), Shaun Gallagher (2006), and Evan Thompson (2007). On this model, cognitive awareness is to be thought not as an internal state of mind or brain locked into linear causal chains of  
+
{{Wiki|pragmatic}} rather than normative concerns (that is, by concerns about how we come to believe something rather than why might we be justified in believing it) then we have a better way of explaining our {{Wiki|epistemic}} dispositions (one that reflects our [[embodied]] [[cognition]] rather than a disembodied cogito). Perhaps the {{Wiki|methodological}} framework best suited to translate and incorporate the [[Buddhist]] contribution to {{Wiki|philosophy of mind}} is one that closely aligns with [[embodied]] approaches to [[cognition]] such as have been developed in the {{Wiki|past}} three decades by Hubert [[Dreyfus]] (1979), Varela, Thompson and Rosch (1991), Edwin Hutchins (1995), Andy Clark (1997), Susan Hurley (1998), Alva Noë (2004), Shaun Gallagher (2006), and [[Evan Thompson]] (2007). On this model, [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[awareness]] is to be [[thought]] not as an internal [[state of mind]] or {{Wiki|brain}} locked into linear causal chains of  
  
sensory input and behavioural output. Rather, it is to be understood as a structure of comportment, an intentional orientation and attunement to a world of actions, objects, and meaning. I call this approach phenomenological naturalism. I am well aware that, on some accounts, stringing together ‘phenomenology’ and ‘naturalism’ can seem confusing, paradoxical, or even oxymoronic. Phenomenology, as Dan Zahavi (2004; 2013) reminds us, is at its core an apodictic and transcendental enterprise. On the other hand, scientific naturalism rests on the assumption that nature is all there is. For the naturalist, consciousness, if it is to belong in our ultimate ontology, must be part of the natural world. But the natural world, claims the phenomenologist, is only as described, and as made  
+
sensory input and behavioural output. Rather, it is to be understood as a {{Wiki|structure}} of comportment, an intentional orientation and [[attunement]] to a [[world]] of [[actions]], [[objects]], and meaning. I call this approach {{Wiki|phenomenological}} [[naturalism]]. I am well {{Wiki|aware}} that, on some accounts, stringing together ‘[[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]]’ and ‘[[naturalism]]’ can seem confusing, {{Wiki|paradoxical}}, or even oxymoronic. {{Wiki|Phenomenology}}, as Dan Zahavi (2004; 2013) reminds us, is at its core an apodictic and [[transcendental]] enterprise. On the other hand, [[scientific]] [[naturalism]] rests on the assumption that [[nature]] is all there is. For the naturalist, [[consciousness]], if it is to belong in our [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] {{Wiki|ontology}}, must be part of the natural [[world]]. But the natural [[world]], claims the [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologist]], is only as described, and as made  
  
available by and for a conscious mind. Phenomenological naturalism is one way to spell out the relation between phenomenology and the project of naturalization that neither eliminates the givenness of experience, nor collapses all of nature into what is experientially available. I will have more to say about this issue in my response to the commentators. Furthermore, I take the view that perception plays a far greater role in any theory of consciousness, intentionality, and cognition than hitherto acknowledged. Specifically, I defend the view that perception is in effect normative: how an object appears depends in large measure on there being an optimal context for its apprehension.  
+
available by and for a [[conscious mind]]. {{Wiki|Phenomenological}} [[naturalism]] is one way to spell out the [[relation]] between [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] and the project of naturalization that neither eliminates the givenness of [[experience]], nor collapses all of [[nature]] into what is experientially available. I will have more to say about this issue in my response to the commentators. Furthermore, I take the view that [[perception]] plays a far greater role in any {{Wiki|theory}} of [[consciousness]], {{Wiki|intentionality}}, and [[cognition]] than hitherto [[acknowledged]]. Specifically, I defend the view that [[perception]] is in effect normative: how an [[object]] appears depends in large measure on there being an optimal context for its apprehension.  
  
When Buddhist philosophers insist on taking ‘clarity’ (spaṣṭa) as a criterion for differentiating perceptual apprehension from other, more indirect modes of apprehension, they have in mind its proprietary phenomenology. An effective account of perception’s epistemic role, therefore, cannot ignore its complex phenomenology, the concrete ways in which each perceptual occasion also entails an engagement and entanglement with situations, attitutes, and things. If perception is a type of embodied action, a view that is most often associated with Merleau-Ponty, then questions about what it is like to see, hear, or feel cannot be pursued in isolation from questions about nature and character of action and agency, and ultimately about the structure of awareness itself. The language Buddhist epistemologists use to discuss the phenomenology of perception suggests a similar account: take the example of hearing a string of successive sounds rhythmically rendered (Dhin Dhin Dha Dha Tin Na, the six beat dadratala of classical Indian music) or the twirling of a firebrand by a performer at a country fair. It might seem as though perception represents the datum of experience as a particular event with shared, discoverable features: simultaneity for the sounds and sameness for the circle of fire. But, argue Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla, two of the key figures in this tradition of thought (whose arguments are examined at length in Chapter 6), simultaneity is not a characteristic of the perceptual occasion, but a conceptual construct. It is obvious that the sounds are discerned as different auditory events and, as such, have different phonetic markers, and that circularity is a construct of quick spinning. Assuming otherwise leads to undesirable outcomes, such as the notion that all perceptual phenomena are type identical.  
+
When [[Buddhist philosophers]] insist on taking ‘clarity’ (spaṣṭa) as a criterion for differentiating {{Wiki|perceptual}} apprehension from other, more indirect modes of apprehension, they have in [[mind]] its proprietary [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]]. An effective account of perception’s {{Wiki|epistemic}} role, therefore, cannot ignore its complex [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], the concrete ways in which each {{Wiki|perceptual}} occasion also entails an engagement and entanglement with situations, attitutes, and things. If [[perception]] is a type of [[embodied]] [[action]], a view that is most often associated with {{Wiki|Merleau-Ponty}}, then questions about what it is like to see, hear, or [[feel]] cannot be pursued in isolation from questions about [[nature]] and [[character]] of [[action]] and agency, and ultimately about the {{Wiki|structure}} of [[awareness]] itself. The [[language]] [[Buddhist]] [[epistemologists]] use to discuss the [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] of [[perception]] suggests a similar account: take the example of hearing a string of successive {{Wiki|sounds}} rhythmically rendered (Dhin Dhin [[Dha]] [[Dha]] Tin [[Na]], the six beat dadratala of classical [[Indian]] [[music]]) or the twirling of a firebrand by a performer at a country fair. It might seem as though [[perception]] represents the datum of [[experience]] as a particular event with shared, discoverable features: simultaneity for the {{Wiki|sounds}} and [[sameness]] for the circle of [[fire]]. But, argue [[Śāntarakṣita]] and [[Kamalaśīla]], two of the key figures in this [[tradition]] of [[thought]] (whose arguments are examined at length in [[Chapter]] 6), simultaneity is not a [[characteristic]] of the {{Wiki|perceptual}} occasion, but a {{Wiki|conceptual}} construct. It is obvious that the {{Wiki|sounds}} are discerned as different [[auditory]] events and, as such, have different phonetic markers, and that circularity is a construct of quick spinning. Assuming otherwise leads to undesirable outcomes, such as the notion that all {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[phenomena]] are type [[identical]].  
  
Conclusion Perceiving Reality seeks to make headway on the problem of epistemic authority in the context of the phenomenology of perception. Against the charge that Buddhist epistemology is committed to some version of the ‘Myth of the Given’, that is, to the view that all knowledge ultimately rests on a self-justifying foundation of noninferential, belief-based knowledge, I argue that the epistemic justification of perception is not intrinsically ascertained (svataḥ prāmāṇya). The mere occurrence of a perceptual event does not suffice to ascertain its epistemic status. Only the pragmatic attainment of the objects they present confirms their veridicality, attainment that must  
+
Conclusion Perceiving [[Reality]] seeks to make headway on the problem of {{Wiki|epistemic}} authority in the context of the [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] of [[perception]]. Against the charge that [[Buddhist epistemology]] is committed to some version of the ‘[[Myth]] of the Given’, that is, to the view that all [[knowledge]] ultimately rests on a self-justifying foundation of noninferential, belief-based [[knowledge]], I argue that the {{Wiki|epistemic}} {{Wiki|justification}} of [[perception]] is not intrinsically ascertained ([[svataḥ prāmāṇya]]). The mere occurrence of a {{Wiki|perceptual}} event does not suffice to ascertain its {{Wiki|epistemic}} {{Wiki|status}}. Only the {{Wiki|pragmatic}} [[attainment]] of the [[objects]] they {{Wiki|present}} confirms their veridicality, [[attainment]] that must  
  
consider the causal totality and the phenomenal character of the perceptual occasion. On this account, perceptions are intrinsically ascertained only with regard to their mode of self-presentation as experiences of a certain kind, even though on its own the reflexivity of awareness does not establish the epistemic status of perception with regard to its content. In other words, that an instance of cognitive awareness is of seeing as opposed to, say, of imagining is ascertained independently of the ontological status of its contents. That an instance of cognitive awareness is of resistance or of passage is ascertained on the basis of considerations about the causal efficacy of these obstructing or facilitating factors. Causal efficacy on this model is the true mark of the real. Perception is not a passive relay of sensory input, not even the apprehension of an internal  
+
consider the causal {{Wiki|totality}} and the [[phenomenal]] [[character]] of the {{Wiki|perceptual}} occasion. On this account, [[perceptions]] are intrinsically ascertained only with regard to their mode of self-presentation as [[experiences]] of a certain kind, even though on its [[own]] the reflexivity of [[awareness]] does not establish the {{Wiki|epistemic}} {{Wiki|status}} of [[perception]] with regard to its content. In other words, that an instance of [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[awareness]] is of [[seeing]] as opposed to, say, of [[Wikipedia:Imagination|imagining]] is ascertained {{Wiki|independently}} of the [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] {{Wiki|status}} of its contents. That an instance of [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[awareness]] is of resistance or of passage is ascertained on the basis of considerations about the causal efficacy of these obstructing or facilitating factors. Causal efficacy on this model is the [[true mark]] of the real. [[Perception]] is not a passive relay of sensory input, not even the apprehension of an internal  
  
representation of external reality. It is not something that happens to us; rather it is something we do. Objects are apprehended depending on the perceiver’s orientation and situatedness: before statements such as ‘the hill has smoke which is invariably accompanied by fire’ (a common premise in evidence-based modes of reasoning) can serve as a reason (hetu) for ascertaining the invariable concomitance with the predicate as stated in the exemplification, the subject must be located within reach of the relevant domain: ‘I see the fire on the hill from afar.’ The book pursues three interrelated themes. First, it argues that the complex analyses of mental states in the early Abhidharma and the discourses of the Buddha inform a sui generis phenomenalism that rejects external realism: what we perceive, on this account, is constituted at once by the activity of our sensory and cognitive systems, underlying causal factors, and an attentive capacity that gives sentience its distinctive intentional character. Second, it recognizes in the  
+
[[representation]] of [[external reality]]. It is not something that happens to us; rather it is something we do. [[Objects]] are apprehended depending on the perceiver’s orientation and situatedness: before statements such as ‘the [[hill]] has smoke which is invariably accompanied by [[fire]]’ (a common premise in evidence-based modes of {{Wiki|reasoning}}) can serve as a [[reason]] ([[hetu]]) for ascertaining the [[invariable concomitance]] with the predicate as stated in the {{Wiki|exemplification}}, the [[subject]] must be located within reach of the relevant domain: ‘I see the [[fire]] on the [[hill]] from afar.’ The [[book]] pursues three {{Wiki|interrelated}} themes. First, it argues that the complex analyses of [[mental states]] in the early [[Abhidharma]] and the [[discourses]] of the [[Buddha]] inform a {{Wiki|sui generis}} {{Wiki|phenomenalism}} that rejects external [[realism]]: what we {{Wiki|perceive}}, on this account, is constituted at once by the [[activity]] of our sensory and [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] systems, underlying causal factors, and an attentive capacity that gives [[sentience]] its {{Wiki|distinctive}} intentional [[character]]. Second, it [[recognizes]] in the  
  
notion of ākāra (‘phenomenal aspect’) a key conceptual framework for mapping out the dual-aspect nature of mental states that informs the Buddhist epistemological project: each episode of awareness, on this account, has two aspects, the ‘objective’ or ‘intentional’, which presents the object or content toward which awareness is directed, and the ‘subjective’, which captures the qualitative character of that object-directed awareness as first-personally given. Third, it claims that these two aspects are best understood as capturing the phenomenal content and character of experience. As such they are continuous with Husserl’s understanding of the nature of noematic content: an object of  
+
notion of [[ākāra]] (‘[[phenomenal aspect]]’) a key {{Wiki|conceptual}} framework for mapping out the dual-aspect [[nature]] of [[mental states]] that informs the [[Buddhist]] [[epistemological]] project: each episode of [[awareness]], on this account, has two aspects, the ‘[[objective]]’ or ‘intentional’, which presents the [[object]] or content toward which [[awareness]] is directed, and the ‘[[subjective]]’, which captures the qualitative [[character]] of that object-directed [[awareness]] as first-personally given. Third, it claims that these two aspects are best understood as capturing the [[phenomenal]] content and [[character]] of [[experience]]. As such they are continuous with Husserl’s [[understanding]] of the [[nature]] of noematic content: an [[object]] of  
  
intentional awareness is constituted by its manner of conscious presentation. The systematic claim is that intentionality cannot be understood apart from phenomenality: the Buddhist notion that awareness is reflexive or implicitly self-aware (svasaṃvedana) is thus meant to capture both the phenomenal content and character of conscious mental states. In this Précis, I have focused on the book’s main themes with the intention of orientating the readers to the commentaries and my replies, rather than providing a detailed summary of its contents and arguments. It is my hope that readers find this presentation sufficiently compelling to be motivated to delve deeper into the critical discussion that follows. References Armstrong, D. (1968) A Materialist Theory of Mind, London: Routledge. Armstrong. D. (1981/1997) What is consciousness?, in Block, N., Flanagan, O. & Güzeldere, G. (eds.) The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. 721–728, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Brentano, F. (1982) Descriptive Psychology,  
+
intentional [[awareness]] is constituted by its manner of [[conscious]] presentation. The systematic claim is that {{Wiki|intentionality}} cannot be understood apart from phenomenality: the [[Buddhist]] notion that [[awareness]] is reflexive or implicitly [[self-aware]] ([[svasaṃvedana]]) is thus meant to capture both the [[phenomenal]] content and [[character]] of [[conscious]] [[mental states]]. In this Précis, I have focused on the book’s main themes with the [[intention]] of orientating the readers to the commentaries and my replies, rather than providing a detailed summary of its contents and arguments. It is my {{Wiki|hope}} that readers find this presentation sufficiently compelling to be motivated to delve deeper into the critical [[discussion]] that follows. References Armstrong, D. (1968) A {{Wiki|Materialist}} {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Mind]], [[London]]: Routledge. Armstrong. D. (1981/1997) What is [[consciousness]]?, in Block, N., Flanagan, O. & Güzeldere, G. (eds.) The [[Nature]] of [[Consciousness]]: [[Philosophical]] [[Debates]], pp. 721–728, [[Cambridge]], MA: MIT Press. Brentano, F. (1982) Descriptive {{Wiki|Psychology}},  
  
Muller, B. (ed. and trans.), London: Routledge. Carman, T. (2005) On the inescapability of phenomenology, in Smith, D.W. & Thomasson, A.L. (eds.) Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind, pp. 67–89, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Clark, A. (1997) Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. de la Vallée Poussin, L. (1970) Madhyamakāvatāra par Candrakīrti, Bibliotheca Buddhica IX, Osnabrück: Biblio Verlag. de la Vallée Poussin, L. (1971) L’Abhidharmakakośa de Vasubandhu, Bruxelles: Institut Belge des Hautes Etudes Chinoise. Dreyfus, H.L. (1979) What Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Intelligence, New York: Harper and Row. Gallagher, S. (2006) How the Body Shapes the Mind, New York: Oxford University Press.  
+
Muller, B. (ed. and trans.), [[London]]: Routledge. Carman, T. (2005) On the inescapability of [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], in Smith, D.W. & Thomasson, A.L. (eds.) {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and [[Philosophy]] of [[Mind]], pp. 67–89, [[Oxford]]: [[Oxford University Press]]. Clark, A. (1997) Being There: Putting {{Wiki|Brain}}, [[Body]], and [[World]] Together Again, [[Cambridge]], MA: MIT Press. de la [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Vallée Poussin]], L. (1970) [[Madhyamakāvatāra]] par [[Candrakīrti]], [[Bibliotheca Buddhica]] IX, Osnabrück: Biblio Verlag. de la [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Vallée Poussin]], L. (1971) L’Abhidharmakakośa de [[Vasubandhu]], Bruxelles: Institut Belge des Hautes Etudes Chinoise. [[Dreyfus]], H.L. (1979) What Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of {{Wiki|Artificial Intelligence}}, [[New York]]: Harper and Row. Gallagher, S. (2006) How the [[Body]] Shapes the [[Mind]], [[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]].  
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2016 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
+
Copyright (c) Imprint {{Wiki|Academic}} 2016 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
  
  
Gennaro, R. (1996) Consciousness and Self-Consciousness: A Defense of the Higher-Order Thought Theory of Consciousness, Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Gennaro. R. (2011) The Consciousness Paradox: Consciousness, Concepts, and Higher-Order Thoughts, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hurley, S.L. (1998) Consciousness in Action, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Husserl, E. (1970) The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, Carr, D. (trans.), Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. Hutchins, E. (1995) Cognition in the Wild, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Lycan, W.G. (1996) Consciousness and Experience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Malvania, D.D. (ed.) (1971) Dharmottara-
+
Gennaro, R. (1996) [[Consciousness]] and [[Self-Consciousness]]: A Defense of the Higher-Order [[Thought]] {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Consciousness]], {{Wiki|Amsterdam}}: John Benjamins. Gennaro. R. (2011) The [[Consciousness]] [[Paradox]]: [[Consciousness]], Concepts, and Higher-Order [[Thoughts]], [[Cambridge]], MA: MIT Press. Hurley, S.L. (1998) [[Consciousness]] in [[Action]], [[Cambridge]], MA: [[Harvard University]] Press. [[Wikipedia:Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl|Husserl]], E. (1970) The Crisis of {{Wiki|European}} [[Sciences]] and [[Transcendental]] {{Wiki|Phenomenology}}, Carr, D. (trans.), Evanston, IL: Northwestern {{Wiki|University}} Press. Hutchins, E. (1995) [[Cognition]] in the Wild, [[Cambridge]], MA: MIT Press. Lycan, W.G. (1996) [[Consciousness]] and [[Experience]], [[Cambridge]], MA: MIT Press. Malvania, D.D. (ed.) (1971) [[Dharmottara]]-
  
pradīpa. Pandita Durveka Miśra’s Dharmottara- pradīpa. Being subcommentary on Dharmottara’s Nyāya-binduṭīkā, a commentary on Dharmakīrti’s Nyāya-bindu, Patna: Kashi Prasad Jayaswal Research Institute. Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002) Phenomenology of Perception, Smith, C. (trans.), London: Routledge. Ñāṇamoli, B. & Bodhi, B. (2001) The Middle Length Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Majjhima Nikāya, Boston, MA: Wisdom. Nida-Rümelin, M. (2007) Grasping phenomenal properties, in Alter, T. & Walter, S. (eds.) Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge, pp. 307–336, New York: Oxford University Press. Noë, A. (2004) Action in Perception, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pandeya, R.C. (ed.) (1989) The Pramāṇavārttikam of Ācārya Dharmakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. Rosenthal, D. (1986) Two concepts of consciousness, Philosophical Studies, 49, pp. 329–359.  
+
[[pradīpa]]. [[Pandita]] Durveka Miśra’s [[Dharmottara]]- [[pradīpa]]. Being subcommentary on [[Dharmottara’s]] Nyāya-binduṭīkā, a commentary on [[Dharmakīrti’s]] Nyāya-bindu, [[Patna]]: [[Kashi Prasad Jayaswal Research Institute]]. {{Wiki|Merleau-Ponty}}, M. (2002) {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} of [[Perception]], Smith, C. (trans.), [[London]]: Routledge. [[Ñāṇamoli]], B. & [[Bodhi]], B. (2001) The [[Middle Length Discourses]] of the [[Buddha]]: A Translation of the [[Majjhima Nikāya]], [[Boston]], MA: [[Wisdom]]. Nida-Rümelin, M. (2007) [[Grasping]] [[phenomenal]] properties, in Alter, T. & Walter, S. (eds.) [[Phenomenal]] Concepts and [[Phenomenal]] [[Knowledge]], pp. 307–336, [[New York]]: [[Oxford University Press]]. Noë, A. (2004) [[Action]] in [[Perception]], [[Cambridge]], MA: MIT Press. Pandeya, R.C. (ed.) (1989) The [[Pramāṇavārttikam]] of [[Ācārya]] [[Dharmakīrti]], [[Delhi]]: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}. Rosenthal, D. (1986) Two [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of [[consciousness]], [[Philosophical Studies]], 49, pp. 329–359.  
  
Rosenthal, D. (2004) Varieties of higher-order theory, in Gennaro, R. (ed.) HigherOrder Theories of Consciousness: An Anthology, pp. 17–44, Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Steinkellner, E. (1973) Dharmakīrti’s Pramāṇaviniścaya. Chapter 1 and 2, Critically Edited, Vienna: Austrian Academy of Sciences. Strawson, P.F. (1979) Perception and its objects, in MacDonald, G.F. (ed.) Perception and Identity: Essays Presented to A.J. Ayer with His Replies to Them, pp. 41–40, London: Macmillan. Thompson, E. (2007) Mind in  
+
Rosenthal, D. (2004) Varieties of higher-order {{Wiki|theory}}, in Gennaro, R. (ed.) HigherOrder Theories of [[Consciousness]]: An {{Wiki|Anthology}}, pp. 17–44, {{Wiki|Amsterdam}}: John Benjamins. [[Steinkellner]], E. (1973) [[Dharmakīrti’s]] [[Pramāṇaviniścaya]]. [[Chapter]] 1 and 2, Critically Edited, {{Wiki|Vienna}}: [[Austrian]] {{Wiki|Academy}} of [[Sciences]]. [[Strawson]], P.F. (1979) [[Perception]] and its [[objects]], in MacDonald, G.F. (ed.) [[Perception]] and {{Wiki|Identity}}: Essays Presented to A.J. Ayer with His Replies to Them, pp. 41–40, [[London]]: Macmillan. Thompson, E. (2007) [[Mind]] in  
  
Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Varela, F.J., Thompson, E. & Rosch, E. (1991) The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Zahavi, D. (2004) Phenomenology and the project of naturalization, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3, pp. 331–347. Zahavi, D. (2013) Naturalized phenomenology: A desideratum or a category mistake?, in Carel, H. & Meacham, D. (eds.) Phenomenology and Naturalism, pp. 23–42, Cambridge:  
+
[[Life]]: {{Wiki|Biology}}, {{Wiki|Phenomenology}}, and the [[Sciences]] of [[Mind]], [[Cambridge]], MA: [[Harvard University]] Press. Varela, F.J., Thompson, E. & Rosch, E. (1991) The [[Embodied]] [[Mind]]: [[Cognitive]] [[Science]] and [[Human]] [[Experience]], [[Cambridge]], MA: MIT Press. Zahavi, D. (2004) {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and the project of naturalization, {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and the [[Cognitive]] [[Sciences]], 3, pp. 331–347. Zahavi, D. (2013) Naturalized [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]]: A desideratum or a category mistake?, in Carel, H. & Meacham, D. (eds.) {{Wiki|Phenomenology}} and [[Naturalism]], pp. 23–42, [[Cambridge]]:  
  
  

Latest revision as of 21:40, 2 February 2020




by Christian Coseru



Introduction The central idea of this book is the continuity of perception and the world as perceived. To perceive is to open up to a horizon of elements or unique particulars (e.g. textures, arrays, intensities, magnitudes, etc.) that are inseparable from their mode of presentation. Perception is thus at once, and fundamentally, about an object of its own, which reflects its intentional structure, and endowed with a specific phenomenal character, which captures its affective and dispositional saliences. I take a twofold approach to these ideas in Perceiving Reality. On the one hand, I try to show that Indian Buddhist thought is the source of a distinctive and influential philosophy of

perception — one that entails that empirical awareness is intrinsically perspectival. On this account, perception does not simply manifest a given object, a particular, but is also in some sense self-manifesting, self-given. On the other hand, I try to develop a methodological framework that renders these Buddhist insights continuous with contemporary philosophical concerns in both phenomenology and analytic philosophy of mind. The emphasis on ‘continuity’ over the standard ‘comparative’ approach reflects a specific intuition about the scope of philosophical enquiry: one which says that its problems, though often couched in historically and culturally contingent terms, are nonetheless grounded in all aspects of conscious experience for a person at any given time. Correspondence: Email: christian.coseruc@cofc.edu Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2016 For personal use only -- not for reproduction

Furthermore, in so far as philosophical enquiry aims to get at the nature of things or perhaps at the things themselves, its arguments must be experientially and/or empirically grounded. As the book’s subtitle indicates, the material under discussion is drawn primarily from Buddhist philosophy, specifically from the Indian Buddhist philosophical tradition. But the analysis engages with, and is intended to contribute to, a number of contemporary debates in phenomenology and analytic philosophy of mind. Indeed, the central argument of the book is that Indian Buddhist epistemology — the main focus of the book — shares a common orientation towards the analysis of experience with

naturalistic approaches in epistemology and philosophy of mind, and in many respects is continuous with some of the phenomenological theories of Edmund Husserl and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. Three concepts in particular provide the axis around which the book’s theoretical landscape is mapped out: consciousness, which stands for the phenomenal or experiential dimension under scrutiny, intentionality, as a particular feature that concerns the structure of experience, and cognition, which captures the broader epistemic issues at work in Buddhist and contemporary phenomenology and philosophy of mind. Any attempt to draw together such different and seemingly disparate philosophical programmes faces two obvious challenges. On the one hand, the concerns of pre-modern Buddhist philosophers reflect exegetical and even soteriological considerations and are seemingly at odds with the open-ended and scientifically informed modes of enquiry of contemporary western philosophy. On the other hand, there is the question of compatibility, first,

between the positions of Buddhist epistemologists — narrowly focused here on the school of thought associated with Dignāga, Dharmakīrti, and their successors — variously interpreted as endorsing either idealism or global antirealism, and the causal theories of knowledge of naturalistic epistemology; and second, between the anti-essentialism of Buddhist metaphysics and its no-self view, and Husserlian phenomenology with its commitment to eidetic essences. Hence, my book also aims to showcase the importance of constructive engagements with Buddhist ideas and methods by treating them not merely as exegetical materials, but rather as valuable conceptual resources and positions that can, and in my view do, advance our understanding of what there is, and the means by which we achieve epistemic certainty. I pursue this task especially in the last three chapters of the book, through an exploration of foundationalism and the phenomenology of perception

(Chapter 7), of the relation between perception, self-awareness, and intentionality (Chapter 8), and a defence of epistemological optimism (Chapter 9). In lieu of a summary of the various theoretical proposals and their supporting arguments, the Précis will provide a guide to the book’s main ideas as foregrounded by its stated aim. A Working Premise The point of departure for Perceiving Reality is the idea that perception is an embodied structural feature of consciousness whose function is determined by phenomenal experiences in a corresponding domain (of visible, tangibles, etc.). This view is in sharp contrast with the notion, common among philosophers who espouse some version or

another of direct realism, that ‘perception’ is simply a descriptive category whose meaning can be established by definition. As a phenomenal experience, perception can become the intentional object of a specific mode of cognitive awareness: call it direct, nonconceptual awareness (Skt. nirvikalpa-jñāna). As some Buddhist philosophers recognized a long time ago, phenomenal concepts (that is, concepts of experience, e.g. ‘seeing’ or ‘discerning’) are conceptually irreducible: thus, one does not acquire the notion of ‘the which is before the eye’ (the literal meaning of the Sanskrit technical term ‘pratyakṣa’ or ‘perception’) by a priori postulation or definition. On this view, it is impossible to provide an account of phenomenal concepts in non-phenomenal terms. One cannot explain the experience of blue, the pitch of Middle C, or the attitude of concern in terms that

make no reference to their phenomenal qualities. If perception is continuous with what it apprehends how can it get to the things themselves? How can it acquaint us with the world, and guarantee effective action? To answer this question we need to recall the Buddhist’s austere and highly fragmented ontology of partless atoms. As Vasubandhu, a key forerunner of the Buddhist epistemological programme, notes, the senses are not the instruments of some internal agent (a self or mind), extending the latter’s reach into the natural world. Rather, the concreteness of sense experience discloses a world of objects as defined by specific phenomenal properties such as resistance, transformation, and dissolution. In a distinctly phenomenological idiom developed centuries before Husserl, Vasubandhu clarifies that the nature of materiality (rūpa or ‘form’) is such that it can be disrupted as a result of impact with an agent or as something

that can oppose resistance. These properties (e.g. alteration, resistance), however, do not extend to the atoms themselves, which form the building blocks of materiality. As monadic units, the atoms are regarded as lacking any formal properties, which they can only acquire as atomic compounds. The difficulty of reconciling atomism, a fundamental tenet of Buddhist ontology, with the phenomenology of perception is apparent in early debates between various schools of thought (chiefly those of the Vaibhāṣikas and the Sautrāntikas) on the issue of whether the sensible qualities of objects (e.g. shape, colour) supervene on the atoms. On some accounts colour, for instance, is treated as a

substance, while on others merely as a potentiality to occasion different types of experience. The line of thought that gets most traction is the one that regards atoms not as substantial impartite entities, but as the subtlest conceivable collection of elements (see de la Vallee Poussin, 1971, II, 22ab.). These subtle elements, when compounded, acquire emergent properties, but their apprehension as aggregated wholes also reflects the constitution and function of the perceptual systems. Consider, for instance, fluidity. It is not a primary property of water atoms (those atoms that, when compounded, manifest as water), but rather a secondary property of water elements. The structure of emergent phenomena reflects this elemental level of organization, which depends on a vast array of causal and conditioning factors. A different configuration of the same

elements may produce the sensation of hardness and coldness, as is the case with ice. With Dignāga and Dharmakīrti — the key protagonists of the Buddhist epistemological enterprise — there is an important shift of emphasis from ontological to epistemological concerns. The ‘real’ is described in pragmatic rather than ontological terms. If reality were made up of changeless and enduring entities, the argument goes, the effects produced by such entities would be equally changeless and enduring. But what does not change cannot produce any effect, for the effect in this case would either be identical with the generating cause or consist in a perpetual reiteration of it. Such is, then, the conclusion that Dharmakīrti draws following his appraisal of Vasubandhu’s notion that only partless entities are ultimately real. For Dharmakīrti, causal efficacy, essentially the ability of an object to perform a function (arthakriyāsamartha), is the true mark of the real: This particular alone constitutes an object of perception; others (viz., universals and the like) are concealed from the purview of perception. This particular is referred to as ‘cause and effect’ and is what we mean

by the notion of ‘particular.’ As we have said, only an entity that has causal efficacy is deemed a real object of perception. And it is this specific particular that we have called an individual object. (Pandeya, 1989, p. 258) The language of particulars and universals, claims Dharmakīrti, applies to objects only in terms of their specific phenomenal qualities (qualities that reflect the efficacy of the entities that produce them). These are not external referents, but defining characteristics of singles, types of which there can be any number of tokens. But even if the Buddhist epistemologist shifts the focus of perception from unique particulars (tokens) to phenomenal properties (types), the ‘uniqueness’ of the perceived as perceived also stems from its mode of presentation. Where at one time the unique and irreducible elements of Buddhist ontology

were related to conceptually cognate terms such as ‘unique particular’ (svalakṣaṇa) and ‘intrinsic nature’ (svabhāva), now they are seen as embedded in the very cognitive structures that manifest them: feelings and thoughts, for instance, are unique particulars too, but their apprehension is continuous with their mode of disclosure; as specific kinds of self-awareness (e.g. of painful, pleasant, or alert states). The content of a particular mental state may be momentary and discrete, but recurrent, and reflective of the dynamics of the psychophysical aggregates that sustain human experience. Ultimately, however, the phenomenal content of experience reflects our condition of embodiment to which perceptual awareness provides constant, uninterrupted, and unmediated access. In Perceiving Reality, I try to develop a way of conceiving of our most basic mode of being in the world that resists attempts to cleave reality into an inner and outer, a mental and a physical domain (Chapter 1 through 3). I argue that what we apprehend in perception are not, to paraphrase J.L. Austin, the external, mind-independent, medium-sized dry goods that populate the realist’s ontology (Chapter 4). Rather, to paraphrase Husserl and a group of Buddhist philosophers in league with Dignāga and Dharmakīrti, the objects in question are the intentional or aspectual objects: the blue sky as seen, the pot as grasped, and pain as felt. As a fundamental experience that grounds our sense of being and what there is, perception marks the beginning and end of our conscious lives. Charting out the structure, content, and character of this perceptual awareness is therefore both an epistemic good in its own right and key to advancing any metaphysical claim (Chapters 5 through to 9). After all, as Peter Strawson famously wrote more than thirty years ago: ‘a philosopher’s views on

[[[perception]]] are a key to his theory of knowledge and to his metaphysics’ (Strawson, 1979, p. 141). An Enduring Dispute A central problem in contemporary discussions of consciousness is the problem of determining precisely what a mental state’s being conscious consists in. This problem raises a range of conceptual issues about the nature and structure of consciousness. Of particular importance here is the relation between consciousness and selfawareness. The key question is: does consciousness imply selfconsciousness or is self-consciousness the result of a higher-order cognition (a metacognition) co-occurrent with, and taking a previous instance of cognition as, its object? In perceiving an object, is the content of perception the exclusive focus of attention or is there an implicit awareness of the perceiving act itself? The analysis of

this issue typically divides between those that take conscious cognition to be a ‘one-state’ and those that regard it as a ‘two-state’ process. One-state proponents argue that a mental state can be deemed conscious if and only if it possesses a specific character: it is reflexive or self-reflexive. This view finds its clearest modern articulation in Franz Brentano: ‘Every consciousness upon whatever object it is primarily directed, is constantly directed upon itself’ (Brentano, 1982, p. 25). This thesis of the unity of consciousness as reflexive awareness, which we encounter in various forms in Descartes, Kant and, following Brentano, in Husserl, Sartre, and many contemporary philosophers working in the phenomenological tradition, has its roots not only in Greek philosophy (specifically in Aristotle), but also in classical Indian philosophy. As Dharmakīrti, one of the strongest defenders of this thesis, declares in his Drop of Reasoning (Nyāya-bindu): ‘every mental state is reflexively aware of itself’ (Malvania, 1971, p. 64). In Perceiving Reality I offer a detailed reworking of this Buddhist defence of the reflexivity thesis, presenting its arguments as live options for ongoing dialogue and debate. Critics of the reflexivity thesis of consciousness in both India and the west have traditionally pointed to such issues as the conceptual problem of other minds, and more recently to the findings of cognitive science about the opacity of most of our conscious mental states. Proposing an alternative, two-state (or higher-order thought, or HOT) conception of consciousness, they argue that a mental state is conscious in virtue of a distinct second-order state that is directed toward

it. This later group includes, among others, David Armstrong (1968; 1981/1997), David Rosenthal (1986; 2004), William Lycan (1996), and Rocco Gennaro (1996; 2006). Like the one-state model, the higher-order thought view too has antecedents in the Indian philosophical tradition. Indeed, Nyāya philosophers and notable Buddhist thinkers like Candrakīrti and Śāntideva (fl. eighth century) defend versions of the higher-order view. For Candrakīrti in particular, who critically engages Dignāga’s thought, consciousness cannot be thought of as reflexive, even on a conventional level, for that would imply that consciousness is selfvalidating (de la Vallée Poussin, 1970, VI, pp. 74–6). What Candrakīrti takes issue with is the view (typically associated with the ‘Practice of Yoga’ or Yogācāra School) that the object of cognition is not extrinsic to cognition but is

an aspect of cognition itself. As I write (p. 239): ‘Candrakīrti’s critique of reflexive awareness, then, targets this notion that there is a class of cognitive events that are essentially self-characterizing: they reveal their own content without recourse to an additional instance of cognitive awareness, an object, or the positing of a subject of experience. More to the point, Candrakīrti rejects the notion that reflexive awareness has this unique property of giving access to the pure datum of experience.’ The contemporary version of this view is that for a given mental state to be conscious a subject must have an appropriate higher-order belief, thought, or judgment that he or she is in that mental state. Take, for instance, Rosenthal’s influential defence of the higher-order view: ‘Conscious states are simply mental states we are conscious of being in. And, in general, our being conscious of something is just a matter of our having a thought of some sort about it’ (Rosenthal, 1986, p. 465). According to Rosenthal, for consciousness to be intelligible and analysable, one must assume it to be an external, relational property of mental states, and of having something like an articulable structure. Here’s what I see as the main difficulty with this theory. Rosenthal argues that it is possible, in principle, that I be persuaded of my being angry through someone else’s testimony. Thus, I may realize that I am angry in the absence of any conscious feeling of anger, that is, without feeling angry much like a depressive might learn about her condition from a therapist without having any awareness of it. This example underscores the inferential character of one’s access to subjective experience. On the higher-order theory, an individual must have a suitably unmediated higher-order thought about being in that state. But this higher-order state will not itself be conscious unless subject to

another higher-order thought about it (thus leading to infinite regress). That means, a fairly large number of these higher-order thoughts are in fact unconscious. How exactly series of unconscious cognitive events generate conscious apprehension is not at all clear. As Dharmakīrti, a critic of the regress argument, famously puts it his Ascertainment of the Sources of Reliable Cognition (Pramāṇaviniścaya): Awaiting the end of a series of successive cognitions, a person does not comprehend any object, because a cognition cannot be established as cognition when that cognition which is first-personally known (i.e. selfawareness) has not been first established. And since there is no end to the arising of cognitions, the whole world would be blind and deaf. (Steinkellner, 1973, p. 41) How, might we ask, can an unconscious mental state operate to confer consciousness

on another unconscious mental state? In other words, if the HOT theory claims that the thoughts required for consciousness can themselves be unconscious, we are owed an explanation of how the unconscious mental states can be a source for consciousness. Given these problematic issues, defenders of the higher-order view should not be allowed to gloss over the question of the phenomenal character of consciousness by assuming that consciousness owes its phenomenal character, indeed its very subjectivity, to an external relation of some sort. Instead, the relational scenario ought to be unpacked in considerable detail so as to explain how it is possible for there to be such a thing as pain that is unconscious or unknown until it becomes the object of a suitably co-occurrent cognition. Indeed, on the view that ‘pain’ is a phenomenal concept that can only be

acquired experientially, talk of ‘unconscious pain’ would be akin to committing a category mistake. Someone who has suffered no injury, discomfort, or distress cannot in principle grasp the concept of pain. Furthermore, assuming that one can learn the concept by definition does not entail that one grasps the property expressed by the concept (Nida-Rümelin, 2007, p. 312). One need only point to conditions typically associated with various kinds of psychopathy and sociopathy to provide critical evidence for the relevance of phenomenal experience to phenomenal knowledge. These considerations should give pause and raise concerns that the higher-order theories, in view of their commitment to grounding consciousness in non-conscious mental (and even physical) states, are both more problematic and less equipped to handle analyses of phenomenal consciousness. Specifically, these considerations invite us

to go beyond traditional positions in metaphysics concerning the relation between mind and world, and corresponding debates in epistemology concerning externalist accounts of mental content. For these reasons, in Perceiving Reality I offer an alternative account of experience that requires a completely new vocabulary for its expression, one capable of capturing the specific ways of our being in the world. Perception and Causation The Buddhist epistemologist’s broadly empirical approach to knowledge means that reasons are meant to provide an account of how things are before we set out to theorize about them. For the Buddhist, this theorizing accords with the phenomenological stance that perception represents a form of implicit knowing that cannot be improved upon by inferential reasoning. There is no cognitive penetrability of perception for the Buddhist, only

discoverable salient features of perceptual phenomenology. In so grounding our enquiries we can think along with (rather that simply about) these Buddhist philosophers, guided by a principle that most phenomenologists and many philosophers of mind today share: our considerations about what perception can and does disclose trump ontological assumptions about what there is. The leading question is not whether the dress is blue and black or white and gold. Rather, the question is just what it is about the structure of awareness that causes things to appears as such: that is, as occasioning different types of experience. This picture of the structure of awareness and its underlying causal factors has deep roots in the Buddhist canonical literature. The Buddhist, like Hume, is a bundle theorist. But what is it that holds together the aggregates (of body,

sensation, apperception, volition, and consciousness), and generates the sense of personal identity? Answer: the proliferating tendencies (prapañca) of a reflecting and deliberating (vitarka-vicāra) mind. On this standard picture, perception and causation are locked in a dynamic, recursive, and coemergent process: Dependent on the eye and forms, visual-consciousness arises. The meeting of the three is contact. With contact as condition there is feeling. What one feels, that one perceives. What one perceives, that one thinks about. What one thinks about, that one mentally proliferates (papañceti). With what one has mentally proliferated as the source, perception and notions resulting from mental proliferation beset a man

with respect to past, future, and present forms cognizable through the eye. (Ñāṇamoli and Bodhi, 2001, p. 203) In mapping out the co-arising of perception, object perceived, and perceptual awareness, the Buddhist puts forth a different conception of naturalism: specifically, one that regards empirical awareness as grounding our sense of being and what there is. This is a naturalism that takes cognition to be a constitutive feature of the world, not merely a by-product of it. Although a discerning type of consciousness (e.g. visual, tactile, etc.) accompanies each of the sensory modalities, ultimately the relation between perception and its content, while determined by features that are inherent to perception itself, is driven by habitual practices. This notion that the ordinary mind is characterized by habitual modes of thinking becomes crucial in the

Abhidharma analyses of consciousness and cognition. As I write, (p. 63): in the Discourses, this tendency toward the proliferation of mental imagery is more closely associated with sensation and is connected with consciousness only in so far as perception is considered to be proliferating and constructive in its character, that is, in so far as perception is taken to primarily refer to perceptual judgments. Because the six spheres of contact furnish the mind, its dynamics are sustained by the constant flow of mental and sensory impressions. Ordinarily, one is constantly assailed by proliferating thoughts and desires, which compromise the capacity for having veridical perceptual experiences. The psychological impact of this proliferating process on perception is significant: due to ongoing mental activity (pondering, judging, recollecting, etc.), perceptual objects are apprehended only as grasped by our conceptual and categorizing practices. In short, ordinary, untutored perception is laden with judgment. Thus, although

at the basic, functional level the perceptual systems present the world in its immediacy, what an individual apprehends also depends upon his or her discerning and attentional capacities. There are no fixed markers, no system of checks and balances to ensure the reliability of perception even under optimal circumstances. And since the domain of sensory phenomena is in constant flux, there are no independent entities either, only textures or clusters of sensory impressions that ebb and flow depending at once upon the level of attentiveness and the intensity and vividness of the manifest object. At first blush, it may seem as though the notion of a minddependent world — or simply a world as experienced — is suggestive of idealism. But neither the Buddha nor the Abhidharma philosophers

deny the reality of the elements of existence and/or experience (dharma-s) and their causal efficacy. Rather, what is put forward here is the view that we cannot properly discern the phenomenal character and content of experience in a way that makes no reference to the aggregates of consciousness. Likewise, we cannot properly understand the aggregates of form or body if we don’t realize that, as an instrument (karaṇa) of sensory activity, the body is both the medium of contact with the world and the world with which it comes in contact. Such a view, I argue, finds an interesting parallel in Husserl’s account of the paradoxical nature of the body as revealed through phenomenological reduction. For Husserl, phenomenological reduction (époche) — essentially a method of bracketing ontological assumptions about the natural world in order to examine the

intentional structures of consciousness — reveals the twofold appearance of the body, first as a biological entity (Körper) connected to the continuum of life, and second as a medium for the expression of life (Leib). The body is thus the locus of lived experience and, as such, has the capacity for both exploration and receptivity. It is this intuition about the dual nature of sensation, in its transitive and intransitive aspects, which led Husserl to the concept of the life-world (die Lebenswelt): a world of lived experience whose boundaries are not fixed but constantly shifting in relation to the desires, actions, and attitudes of an agent (Husserl, 1970, Part III, A). As Merleau-Ponty, who appropriates Husserl’s notion of the lifeworld as the lived-world (le monde vécu), clearly suggests, ‘I cannot understand the function of living body except by enacting it myself’, for ‘my body appears to me as an attitude with a view to a certain actual or possible task’ (Merleau-Ponty, 2002, pp. 87, 114). For Merleau-Ponty, the world or, better still, the environment is not just a structured domain of causally nested objects and relations, but a meaningful realm of experience. This world qua world, as Taylor Carman (echoing Merleau-Ponty) has recently argued, ‘affords, invites, and facilitates, just as it obtrudes, resists, thwarts, eludes, and coerces’ (Carman, 2005, p. 86). The model of phenomenal consciousness put forward in Perceiving Reality is thus that of a non-reductive, one-state theory of consciousness: a theory which proposes that consciousness is essentially a matter of being or having an awareness of a world that does not presuppose a prior (representational) awareness of its own mental states.

Phenomenology, Buddhist Epistemology, and the Project of Naturalization A central argument of Perceiving Reality is that epistemological enquiries in India, unlike those in the west that follow Descartes’ and Kant’s a priori framework of justification, show a strong commitment to naturalist accounts of belief formation. The return to naturalism in contemporary epistemology, hence to understanding cognition in embodied and causal terms, is good news for Buddhist epistemology. Indeed, a focus on causal accounts of cognition is shared by all Indian epistemological theories, Buddhist or otherwise. But it is Dharmakīrti in particular who focuses on the ways in which the underlying processes of cognition become instrumental in determining which epistemic practices are conducive to effective action. If, indeed, Buddhist epistemological enquiries are driven by

pragmatic rather than normative concerns (that is, by concerns about how we come to believe something rather than why might we be justified in believing it) then we have a better way of explaining our epistemic dispositions (one that reflects our embodied cognition rather than a disembodied cogito). Perhaps the methodological framework best suited to translate and incorporate the Buddhist contribution to philosophy of mind is one that closely aligns with embodied approaches to cognition such as have been developed in the past three decades by Hubert Dreyfus (1979), Varela, Thompson and Rosch (1991), Edwin Hutchins (1995), Andy Clark (1997), Susan Hurley (1998), Alva Noë (2004), Shaun Gallagher (2006), and Evan Thompson (2007). On this model, cognitive awareness is to be thought not as an internal state of mind or brain locked into linear causal chains of

sensory input and behavioural output. Rather, it is to be understood as a structure of comportment, an intentional orientation and attunement to a world of actions, objects, and meaning. I call this approach phenomenological naturalism. I am well aware that, on some accounts, stringing together ‘phenomenology’ and ‘naturalism’ can seem confusing, paradoxical, or even oxymoronic. Phenomenology, as Dan Zahavi (2004; 2013) reminds us, is at its core an apodictic and transcendental enterprise. On the other hand, scientific naturalism rests on the assumption that nature is all there is. For the naturalist, consciousness, if it is to belong in our ultimate ontology, must be part of the natural world. But the natural world, claims the phenomenologist, is only as described, and as made

available by and for a conscious mind. Phenomenological naturalism is one way to spell out the relation between phenomenology and the project of naturalization that neither eliminates the givenness of experience, nor collapses all of nature into what is experientially available. I will have more to say about this issue in my response to the commentators. Furthermore, I take the view that perception plays a far greater role in any theory of consciousness, intentionality, and cognition than hitherto acknowledged. Specifically, I defend the view that perception is in effect normative: how an object appears depends in large measure on there being an optimal context for its apprehension.

When Buddhist philosophers insist on taking ‘clarity’ (spaṣṭa) as a criterion for differentiating perceptual apprehension from other, more indirect modes of apprehension, they have in mind its proprietary phenomenology. An effective account of perception’s epistemic role, therefore, cannot ignore its complex phenomenology, the concrete ways in which each perceptual occasion also entails an engagement and entanglement with situations, attitutes, and things. If perception is a type of embodied action, a view that is most often associated with Merleau-Ponty, then questions about what it is like to see, hear, or feel cannot be pursued in isolation from questions about nature and character of action and agency, and ultimately about the structure of awareness itself. The language Buddhist epistemologists use to discuss the phenomenology of perception suggests a similar account: take the example of hearing a string of successive sounds rhythmically rendered (Dhin Dhin Dha Dha Tin Na, the six beat dadratala of classical Indian music) or the twirling of a firebrand by a performer at a country fair. It might seem as though perception represents the datum of experience as a particular event with shared, discoverable features: simultaneity for the sounds and sameness for the circle of fire. But, argue Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla, two of the key figures in this tradition of thought (whose arguments are examined at length in Chapter 6), simultaneity is not a characteristic of the perceptual occasion, but a conceptual construct. It is obvious that the sounds are discerned as different auditory events and, as such, have different phonetic markers, and that circularity is a construct of quick spinning. Assuming otherwise leads to undesirable outcomes, such as the notion that all perceptual phenomena are type identical.

Conclusion Perceiving Reality seeks to make headway on the problem of epistemic authority in the context of the phenomenology of perception. Against the charge that Buddhist epistemology is committed to some version of the ‘Myth of the Given’, that is, to the view that all knowledge ultimately rests on a self-justifying foundation of noninferential, belief-based knowledge, I argue that the epistemic justification of perception is not intrinsically ascertained (svataḥ prāmāṇya). The mere occurrence of a perceptual event does not suffice to ascertain its epistemic status. Only the pragmatic attainment of the objects they present confirms their veridicality, attainment that must

consider the causal totality and the phenomenal character of the perceptual occasion. On this account, perceptions are intrinsically ascertained only with regard to their mode of self-presentation as experiences of a certain kind, even though on its own the reflexivity of awareness does not establish the epistemic status of perception with regard to its content. In other words, that an instance of cognitive awareness is of seeing as opposed to, say, of imagining is ascertained independently of the ontological status of its contents. That an instance of cognitive awareness is of resistance or of passage is ascertained on the basis of considerations about the causal efficacy of these obstructing or facilitating factors. Causal efficacy on this model is the true mark of the real. Perception is not a passive relay of sensory input, not even the apprehension of an internal

representation of external reality. It is not something that happens to us; rather it is something we do. Objects are apprehended depending on the perceiver’s orientation and situatedness: before statements such as ‘the hill has smoke which is invariably accompanied by fire’ (a common premise in evidence-based modes of reasoning) can serve as a reason (hetu) for ascertaining the invariable concomitance with the predicate as stated in the exemplification, the subject must be located within reach of the relevant domain: ‘I see the fire on the hill from afar.’ The book pursues three interrelated themes. First, it argues that the complex analyses of mental states in the early Abhidharma and the discourses of the Buddha inform a sui generis phenomenalism that rejects external realism: what we perceive, on this account, is constituted at once by the activity of our sensory and cognitive systems, underlying causal factors, and an attentive capacity that gives sentience its distinctive intentional character. Second, it recognizes in the

notion of ākāra (‘phenomenal aspect’) a key conceptual framework for mapping out the dual-aspect nature of mental states that informs the Buddhist epistemological project: each episode of awareness, on this account, has two aspects, the ‘objective’ or ‘intentional’, which presents the object or content toward which awareness is directed, and the ‘subjective’, which captures the qualitative character of that object-directed awareness as first-personally given. Third, it claims that these two aspects are best understood as capturing the phenomenal content and character of experience. As such they are continuous with Husserl’s understanding of the nature of noematic content: an object of

intentional awareness is constituted by its manner of conscious presentation. The systematic claim is that intentionality cannot be understood apart from phenomenality: the Buddhist notion that awareness is reflexive or implicitly self-aware (svasaṃvedana) is thus meant to capture both the phenomenal content and character of conscious mental states. In this Précis, I have focused on the book’s main themes with the intention of orientating the readers to the commentaries and my replies, rather than providing a detailed summary of its contents and arguments. It is my hope that readers find this presentation sufficiently compelling to be motivated to delve deeper into the critical discussion that follows. References Armstrong, D. (1968) A Materialist Theory of Mind, London: Routledge. Armstrong. D. (1981/1997) What is consciousness?, in Block, N., Flanagan, O. & Güzeldere, G. (eds.) The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, pp. 721–728, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Brentano, F. (1982) Descriptive Psychology,

Muller, B. (ed. and trans.), London: Routledge. Carman, T. (2005) On the inescapability of phenomenology, in Smith, D.W. & Thomasson, A.L. (eds.) Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind, pp. 67–89, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Clark, A. (1997) Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. de la Vallée Poussin, L. (1970) Madhyamakāvatāra par Candrakīrti, Bibliotheca Buddhica IX, Osnabrück: Biblio Verlag. de la Vallée Poussin, L. (1971) L’Abhidharmakakośa de Vasubandhu, Bruxelles: Institut Belge des Hautes Etudes Chinoise. Dreyfus, H.L. (1979) What Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Intelligence, New York: Harper and Row. Gallagher, S. (2006) How the Body Shapes the Mind, New York: Oxford University Press. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2016 For personal use only -- not for reproduction


Gennaro, R. (1996) Consciousness and Self-Consciousness: A Defense of the Higher-Order Thought Theory of Consciousness, Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Gennaro. R. (2011) The Consciousness Paradox: Consciousness, Concepts, and Higher-Order Thoughts, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hurley, S.L. (1998) Consciousness in Action, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Husserl, E. (1970) The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, Carr, D. (trans.), Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. Hutchins, E. (1995) Cognition in the Wild, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Lycan, W.G. (1996) Consciousness and Experience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Malvania, D.D. (ed.) (1971) Dharmottara-

pradīpa. Pandita Durveka Miśra’s Dharmottara- pradīpa. Being subcommentary on Dharmottara’s Nyāya-binduṭīkā, a commentary on Dharmakīrti’s Nyāya-bindu, Patna: Kashi Prasad Jayaswal Research Institute. Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002) Phenomenology of Perception, Smith, C. (trans.), London: Routledge. Ñāṇamoli, B. & Bodhi, B. (2001) The Middle Length Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Majjhima Nikāya, Boston, MA: Wisdom. Nida-Rümelin, M. (2007) Grasping phenomenal properties, in Alter, T. & Walter, S. (eds.) Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge, pp. 307–336, New York: Oxford University Press. Noë, A. (2004) Action in Perception, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pandeya, R.C. (ed.) (1989) The Pramāṇavārttikam of Ācārya Dharmakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. Rosenthal, D. (1986) Two concepts of consciousness, Philosophical Studies, 49, pp. 329–359.

Rosenthal, D. (2004) Varieties of higher-order theory, in Gennaro, R. (ed.) HigherOrder Theories of Consciousness: An Anthology, pp. 17–44, Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Steinkellner, E. (1973) Dharmakīrti’s Pramāṇaviniścaya. Chapter 1 and 2, Critically Edited, Vienna: Austrian Academy of Sciences. Strawson, P.F. (1979) Perception and its objects, in MacDonald, G.F. (ed.) Perception and Identity: Essays Presented to A.J. Ayer with His Replies to Them, pp. 41–40, London: Macmillan. Thompson, E. (2007) Mind in

Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Varela, F.J., Thompson, E. & Rosch, E. (1991) The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Zahavi, D. (2004) Phenomenology and the project of naturalization, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3, pp. 331–347. Zahavi, D. (2013) Naturalized phenomenology: A desideratum or a category mistake?, in Carel, H. & Meacham, D. (eds.) Phenomenology and Naturalism, pp. 23–42, Cambridge:





Source