Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "What is the "logic" in Buddhist logic? By R. Lance Factor"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
(9 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 
[[File:Bud 0.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Bud 0.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
The history of Indian logic is usually divided into
+
The {{Wiki|history}} of [[Indian]] [[logic]] is usually divided into [[three periods]], Old [[Nyaaya]] (circa 250 B.C. ) , [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] (sixth century A.D.) and New [[Nyaaya]].  
        three periods, Old Nyaaya (circa 250 B.C. ) ,
+
 
        Buddhist logic (sixth century A.D.) and New Nyaaya.
+
The [[Buddhist logic]] text, [[Nyaayaprave`sa]] ([[Introduction to Logical Methods]]) , had great [[influence]] upon [[Indian]] and [[Chinese Buddhism]] and also among the {{Wiki|Jains}}.  
        The   Buddhist     logic   text,   Nyaayaprave`sa
+
 
        (Introduction   to Logical   Methods) , had great
+
As a pivotal work, the [[Nyaayaprave`sa]] has received critical [[attention]] from {{Wiki|historians}} of [[religion]], philologists, [[philosophers]], and [[logicians]].  
        influence upon Indian and Chinese Buddhism and also
+
 
        among   the   Jains.   As   a   pivotal   work, the
+
As with all advances in {{Wiki|scholarship}}, there is [[controversy]] over [[interpretation]], but in the case of [[Buddhist]] [[logic]], the [[controversy]] cuts to the very [[heart]] of the issue of whether [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] is in any recognizable contemporary [[sense]] a "[[logic]]."  
        Nyaayaprave`sa has received critical attention from
+
 
        historians of religion, philologists, philosophers,
+
The received [[view]] holds that [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] bears very close similarities to {{Wiki|syllogistic}} [[forms]] and that it can be represented and analyzed by standard {{Wiki|deductive}} techniques.(1)  
        and logicians. As with all advances in scholarship,
+
 
        there is controversy over interpretation, but in the
+
A much different and opposing [[view]] has been argued by {{Wiki|Professor}} [[Douglas Daye]] in a series of papers.  
        case of Buddhist logic, the controversy cuts to the
+
 
        very heart of the issue of whether Buddhist logic is
+
Daye maintains that "... the descriptive utility of {{Wiki|mathematical}} [[logic]] with early [[Nyaaya]] texts has simply been overrated";
        in any recognizable contemporary sense a "logic."
+
 
        The received view holds that Buddhist logic bears
+
(2) that although the [[Nyaaya]] texts contain [[Wikipedia:metalogic|metalogical]] {{Wiki|rules}} for evaluating the "legitimacy or illegitimacy" of arguments, the {{Wiki|distinction}} between validity and invalidity does not apply;
        very close similarities to syllogistic forms and
+
 
        that it can be represented and analyzed by standard
+
(3) that [[Nyaaya]] models are not inferences but "formalistic explanations"; and that "... [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] is not {{Wiki|deductive}}, nor can it be formally valid nor is it an {{Wiki|inference}}."
        deductive   techniques.(1) A much different   and
+
 
        opposing view has been argued by Professor Douglas
+
(4) [[File:Buddha 2sw.jpg|thumb|250px|]] The cumulative effect of these claims is to assert that [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] is not a "[[logic]]" at all, at least not in any [[sense]] which is [[recognized]] by {{Wiki|Western}} [[philosophers]].  
        Daye in a series of papers. Daye maintains that "...
+
 
        the descriptive utility of mathematical logic with
+
 
        early Nyaaya texts has simply been overrated";(2)
+
 
        that although the Nyaaya texts contain metalogical
+
There is a radical incompatibility between the [[Nyaaya]] methods of [[logic]] and those of the Prior Analytics or Principia Mathematica.  
        rules   for   evaluating   the   "legitimacy   or
+
 
        illegitimacy" of arguments, the distinction between
+
Of course, there will be differences, possibly very great differences, between any two [[traditions]] so diverse as fourth century (B.C.) {{Wiki|Greece}} and sixth century (A.D.) [[India]], but are we to go so far as to say that the [[Nyaaya]] does not contain inferences?  
        validity and invalidity does not apply;(3) that
+
 
        Nyaaya models are not inferences but "formalistic
+
The radical incompatibility {{Wiki|thesis}} is, I maintain, a mistake; moreover, it is a mistake which can readily be uncovered by examining the typical [[Nyaaya]] {{Wiki|inference}} scheme.  
        explanations"; and that "... Buddhist logic is not
+
 
        deductive, nor can it be formally valid nor is it an
+
Of the notion that a [[Nyaaya]] scheme could be a "formalistic explanation" without [[being]] an {{Wiki|inference}}, I shall say very little because I do not see how anything which functions as an explanation could not involve inferences of some kind or other.  
        inference."(4)
+
 
[[File:Buddha 2sw.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
+
It is important to know whether the [[Nyaaya]] scheme is {{Wiki|deductive}} or not, and if it is, whether all of its parts are [[essential]] to the deduction.  
            The cumulative effect of these claims is to
+
 
        assert that Buddhist logic is not a "logic" at all,
+
I will demonstrate that there are two ways of reading the [[Nyaaya]] [[form]]: one which is straightforwardly {{Wiki|deductive}} and a second which is best understood by what the American {{Wiki|pragmatist}}, [[.S. Peirce]], and later [[Norwood Hanson]], call "retroduction."
        at least not in any sense which is recognized by
+
 
        Western   philosophers.   There   is   a   radical
+
 
        incompatibility between the Nyaaya methods of logic
 
        and those of the Prior Analytics or Principia
 
        Mathematica. Of course, there will be differences,
 
        possibly very great differences, between any two
 
        traditions so diverse as fourth century (B.C.)
 
        Greece and sixth century (A.D.) India, but are we to
 
        go so far as to say that the Nyaaya does not contain
 
        inferences? The radical incompatibility thesis is, I
 
        maintain, a mistake; moreover, it is a mistake which
 
        can readily be uncovered by examining the typical
 
        Nyaaya inference scheme. Of the notion that a Nyaaya
 
        scheme   could be a   "formalistic   explanation"
 
        without being an inference, I shall say very little
 
        because I do not see how anything which functions as
 
        an explanation could not involve inferences of some
 
        kind or other. It is important to know whether the
 
        Nyaaya scheme is deductive or not, and if it is,
 
        whether all of its parts are essential to the
 
        deduction. I will demonstrate that there are two
 
        ways of reading the Nyaaya form: one which is
 
        straightforwardly deductive and a second which is
 
        best understood by what the American pragmatist,
 
        C.S.   Peirce,   and   later   Norwood   Hanson,
 
        call "retroduction."
 
 
[[File:Bud4.jpeg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Bud4.jpeg|thumb|250px|]]
 
             To  begin  with,  consider  this  representative
 
             To  begin  with,  consider  this  representative
         example from the Nyaaya:(5)
+
         example from the [[Nyaaya]]:(5)
  
             1. pak.sa (thesis) Sound is imprrmanrne
+
             1. [[pak.sa]] ({{Wiki|thesis}}) [[Sound]] is imprrmanrne
  
             2. hetu (mark  or  Reason)  -  Because  of  its
+
             2. [[hetu]] (mark  or  [[Reason]])  -  Because  of  its
               property of being produced
+
               property of [[being]] produced
  
                                P.184
+
                           
  
  
 
             3.  d.r.s.taanta  (Exemplification)--Whatever is
 
             3.  d.r.s.taanta  (Exemplification)--Whatever is
                 produced, is impermanent
+
                 produced, is [[impermanent]]
             4.  sapak.sa (similar case)-  As with a pot, and
+
             4.  [[sapak.sa]] (similar case)-  As with a pot, and
 
                 so forth
 
                 so forth
             5.  vipak.sa (dissimilar case)- As (not with the
+
             5.  [[vipak.sa]] (dissimilar case)- As (not with the
                 case) of space, and so forth
+
                 case) of [[space]], and so forth
  
             Tachikawa proposes the following scheme for what
+
             [[Tachikawa]] proposes the following scheme for what
         he calls the "three-membered Indian syllogism:(6)
+
         he calls the "three-membered [[Indian]] syllogism:(6)
  
 
             6.  There is property p in locus L
 
             6.  There is property p in locus L
Line 87: Line 63:
 
                 property p, as in locus w
 
                 property p, as in locus w
 
[[File:Buddha 21226.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddha 21226.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
         Clearly, if this  schema  is  reversed, (8) and  (7)
+
         Clearly, if this  {{Wiki|schema}} is  reversed, (8) and  (7)
         become premises for a valid deductive  inference  of
+
         become premises for a valid {{Wiki|deductive}} {{Wiki|inference}} of
 
         (6) as the conclusion.  The reverse  of our  example
 
         (6) as the conclusion.  The reverse  of our  example
 
         becomes an instance of modus ponens.
 
         becomes an instance of modus ponens.
  
 
             9.  d.r.s.taanta  -  Whatever  is  created  is
 
             9.  d.r.s.taanta  -  Whatever  is  created  is
                 impermanent.
+
                 [[impermanent]].
             10. hetu - Sound is created.
+
             10. [[hetu]] - [[Sound]] is created.
             11. pak.sa - Sound is impermanent.
+
             11. [[pak.sa]] - [[Sound]] is [[impermanent]].
 +
 
 +
            Why is this instance of modus ponens a {{Wiki|matter}} of dispute?
  
            Why is this instance of modus ponens a matter of
+
The incompatibilists point out that the relationship between the {{Wiki|thesis}} ([[pak.sa]]) and the {{Wiki|justification}} ([[hetu]]) is always expressed in the [[Sanskrit]] {{Wiki|ablative}} case and that this relationship cannot be represented or translated as the English "therefore" (or ergo).  
        dispute? The incompatibilists point out that the
+
 
        relationship between the thesis (pak.sa) and the
+
Its best translation is "because."  
        justification (hetu) is always expressed in the
+
 
        Sanskrit ablative case and that this relationship
+
[[Thus]], for the incompatibilist, the [[primary]] objection to identifying the [[Nyaaya]] scheme as a {{Wiki|deductive}} {{Wiki|inference}} is the familiar one of ordinary [[language]] [[philosophers]] who resist the translation of {{Wiki|expressions}} as `q because p' into `p ) q' on the grounds that the [[causal]] or explanatory meaning of "because" is lost in the truth-functional [[conditional]].
        cannot be represented or translated as the English
 
        "therefore" (or ergo). Its best translation is
 
        "because."   Thus, for   the incompatibilist, the
 
        primary objection to identifying the Nyaaya scheme
 
        as a deductive inference is the familiar one of
 
        ordinary   language philosophers   who resist the
 
        translation of expressions as `q because p' into `p
 
        ) q' on the grounds that the causal or explanatory
 
        meaning   of   "because"   is   lost   in   the
 
        truth-functional conditional.
 
 
[[File:Buddha121xs.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddha121xs.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
             This   objection   has force, but   one   must
+
 
        distinguish     between   the   assertion     that
+
 
        truth-functional connectives preserve or capture the
+
             This objection has force, but one must distinguish between the [[assertion]] that truth-functional connectives preserve or capture the meaning of `q because p' and the claim that truth-functional connectives can represent a {{Wiki|deductive}} relationship between propositions within the [[Nyaaya]] scheme. It is the [[latter]] which the received [[view]] upholds: it is the former which the incompatibilist vehemently opposes.  
        meaning   of `q because p' and the claim that
+
 
        truth-functional   connectives   can   represent   a
+
The issue is not joined, because surely one can maintain that there is a {{Wiki|deductive}} {{Wiki|inference}} in the [[inversion]] [[Nyaaya]] scheme without maintaining that it captures the meaning of or even approaches synonymy with the original.  
        deductive relationship between propositions within
+
 
        the Nyaaya scheme. It is the latter which the
+
In sum, the issue between the received [[view]] and the incompatibilist pivots on the former's willingness to invert the [[Nyaaya]] [[form]] and read it as a valid deduction and the latter's insistence that the [[form]] cannot be so reversed without losing the special relationship of the [[hetu]].  
        received view upholds: it is the former which the
+
 
        incompatibilist vehemently opposes. The issue is not
+
Given the [[merits]] of both [[views]] and given the fact that both positions are not explicit contradictories of one another, there is a way to understand the [[Nyaaya]] scheme which allows both sides to have their cake and eat it too.  
        joined, because surely one can maintain that there
+
 
        is a deductive inference in the inversion Nyaaya
+
I believe that the three-membered [[Nyaaya]] is best understood as a retroductivc {{Wiki|inference}}.  
        scheme without maintaining that it captures the
+
 
        meaning of or even approaches synonymy with the
+
A retroduction, as it has been described by [[C. S. Peirce]] and
        original. In sum, the issue between the received
 
        view and the incompatibilist pivots on the former's
 
        willingness to invert the Nyaaya form and read it as
 
        a valid deduction and the latter's insistence that
 
        the form cannot be so reversed without losing the
 
        special relationship of the hetu. Given the merits
 
        of both views and given the fact that both positions
 
        are not explicit contradictories of one another,
 
        there is a way to understand the Nyaaya scheme which
 
        allows both sides to have their cake and eat it too.
 
        I believe that the three-membered Nyaaya is best
 
        understood   as   a   retroductivc   inference.   A
 
        retroduction, as it has been described by C. S.
 
        Peirce and
 
 
[[File:Buddha20i.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddha20i.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
                                P.185
+
                             
  
        Norwood Hansonl  is a pattern of reasoning which
+
        [[Norwood Hanson]] is a pattern of {{Wiki|reasoning}} which leads from some [[phenomenon]] or [[perception]] to an explanatory {{Wiki|hypothesis}} of that [[phenomenon]].  
        leads from some phenomenon or perception to an
 
        explanatory hypothesis of that phenomenon. Its form
 
        is not truth-functional nor are the relationships of
 
        that premises completely rulegoverned.  Peirce said,
 
        "It must be remembered  that  retroduction, although
 
        hampered very little by logical rules, nevertheless,
 
        is logical inference, asserting its conclusion  only
 
        problematically or conjecturally...."(7)
 
  
            Retroduction does have a recognizable pattern,
+
Its [[form]] is not truth-functional nor are the relationships of that premises completely rulegoverned.
        and indeed it is very close to the three-membered
+
 
        syllogism of Indian logic. Its form, according to
+
Peirce said, "It must be remembered that retroduction, although hampered very little by [[logical]] {{Wiki|rules}}, nevertheless, is [[logical]] {{Wiki|inference}}, asserting its conclusion only problematically or conjecturally...."(7)
        Peirce, is:
+
 
 +
Retroduction does have a recognizable pattern, and indeed it is very close to the three-membered [[syllogism]] of [[Indian]] [[logic]].  
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
Its [[form]], according to Peirce, is:
  
 
             12. The surprizing fact Q is observed.
 
             12. The surprizing fact Q is observed.
  
             13.  But  if P were true, Q would be a matter of
+
             13.  But  if P were true, Q would be a {{Wiki|matter}} of
 
                 course.
 
                 course.
  
             14. Hence, there is reason to suspect  that P is
+
             14. Hence, there is [[reason]] to suspect  that P is
 
                 true.
 
                 true.
  
         As a schema, for retroduction we have:
+
         As a {{Wiki|schema}}, for retroduction we have:
 
[[File:Buddha444.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddha444.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
             (12') q
 
             (12') q
Line 172: Line 123:
 
             (14')p
 
             (14')p
  
        which is isomorphic with that of the Nyaaya (that
+
        which is {{Wiki|isomorphic}} with that of the [[Nyaaya]] (that is, [[pak.sa]], because [[hetu]] and d.r.s.taanta; hence there is {{Wiki|evidence}} for the [[pak.sa]]).  
        is, pak.sa, because hetu and d.r.s.taanta; hence
+
 
        there is evidence for the pak.sa). The similarity
+
The similarity ([[sapak.sa]]) and dissimilarity ([[vipak.sa]]) cases serve as further {{Wiki|evidence}} in support of the explanatory {{Wiki|justification}}.
        (sapak.sa) and dissimilarity (vipak.sa) cases serve
+
 
        as further evidence in support of the explanatory
+
The [[philosopher]] of [[science]], [[Norwood Hanson]], argued that retroduction was a "[[logic]] of discovery" which led to deductive-nomological explanations.
        justification.
+
 
 +
Like Peirce, Hanson pointed out that the [[reversal]] of a retroduction was a {{Wiki|deductive}} {{Wiki|inference}} 'q, q because p', becomes 'p, if p, then q, hence q'.
 +
 
 +
The notion of [[reversal]]" or inverting" a retroduction is not a technique or {{Wiki|rule}} of formal [[logic]], but rather a simple [[psychological]] description of changing the [[order]] of premises.
 +
 
 +
 
  
            The  philosopher  of  science,  Norwood  Hanson,
 
        argued that retroduction  was a "logic of discovery"
 
        which  led  to  deductive-nomological  explanations.
 
        Like Peirce, Hanson pointed out that the reversal of
 
        a  retroduction  was  a  deductive  inference  'q, q
 
        because p', becomes 'p, if p, then q, hence q'.  The
 
        notion of reversal" or inverting" a retroduction  is
 
        not a technique  or rule of formal logic, but rather
 
        a simple psychological  description  of changing the
 
        order of premises.
 
 
[[File:Buddhagarden.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhagarden.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
             If the three-membered syllogism is retroduction
+
             If the three-membered [[syllogism]] is retroduction and if a retroduction is part of a retroductive-deductive pair, one should expect to find internal {{Wiki|evidence}} for the presence or absence of a {{Wiki|deductive}} fragment.  
        and   if   a   retroduction   is   part   of   a
+
 
        retroductive-deductive pair, one should expect to
+
To return to the [[Nyaaya]] and its commentary on this three-membered [[syllogism]], is there internal {{Wiki|evidence}} to treat it as a retroduction-cum-deduction?  
        find internal evidence for the presence or absence
+
 
        of a deductive fragment. To return to the Nyaaya and
+
A crucial point of philological [[interpretation]] is the [[function]] of the {{Wiki|ablative}} "because" and the meaning of "[[hetu]]" itself.  
        its commentary on this three-membered syllogism, is
+
 
        there   internal   evidence   to   treat   it as a
+
 
        retroduction-cum-deduction? A crucial   point   of
 
        philological interpretation is the function of the
 
        ablative "because"   and the meaning of "hetu"
 
        itself. The weakness of the standard view is that it
 
        disregards  the  special  features  of the  ablative
 
        "because"  and  translates    the  three-membered
 
        syllogism as if it contained conditionals. Following
 
        Daye, I suggest  that  that  move  is too hasty, and
 
        that  we must regard  the ablative  "because"  as an
 
        operator connecting the hetu and d.r.s.taanta to the
 
        thesis.  Since  the Sanskrit  ablative  expresses  a
 
        relation  of  physical  or  conceptual  removal,
 
        separation, distinction, or origin, it was  used  to
 
        convey  the notion of causal explanation.  This fact
 
        gives  prima facie evidence  for interpreting  it in
 
        the sense  of "a reason  for." Such an understanding
 
        is reinforced by the meaning of "hetu," which is the
 
        name of the explanatory part of the three-
 
  
[[File:Buddhas.jpg|thumb|250px|]]                               P.186
+
The weakness of the standard [[view]] is that it disregards the special features of the {{Wiki|ablative}} "because" and translates the three-membered [[syllogism]] as if it contained conditionals.  
  
        membered syllogism.  According  to Tachikawa, "hetu"
+
Following Daye, I suggest that that move is too hasty, and that we must regard the {{Wiki|ablative}} "because" as an operator connecting the [[hetu]] and d.r.s.taanta to the {{Wiki|thesis}}.  
        primarily  means  'reason'.(8) This is solid  ground
 
        for reading  'q because  p' as: 'p is the reason for
 
        q', 'p is the explanatory hypothesis for q', or even
 
        the Peircean 'if p were true, q would be a matter of
 
        course'.
 
  
            Beyond  points  of translation, one  of the
+
Since the [[Sanskrit]] {{Wiki|ablative}} expresses a [[relation]] of [[physical]] or {{Wiki|conceptual}} removal, separation, {{Wiki|distinction}}, or origin, it was used to convey the notion of [[causal]] explanation.
        strongest  reasons  for seeing the three-membered
+
[[File:Buddhas.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
        syllogism    of   the    Nyaayaprave`sa    as    a
+
This fact gives [[Wikipedia:Prima facie|prima facie]] {{Wiki|evidence}} for interpreting it in the [[sense]] of "a [[reason]] for." Such an [[understanding]] is reinforced by the meaning of "[[hetu]]," which is the [[name]] of the explanatory part of the three membered [[syllogism]].
        retroduction-deduction  is the existence  of the
 
        five-membered  syllogism  in  the earlier  Nyaaya
 
        tradition, particularly  the Nyaaya  Suutra.(9) The
 
        five-membered syllogism of the  Nyaaya  Suutra  is
 
        perfectly  symmetrical  between  its  three  initial
 
        retroductive steps and its two culminating deductive
 
        steps:
 
  
 +
According to [[Tachikawa]], "[[hetu]]" primarily means 'reason'.(8)
  
            15. Thesis(pratij~naa)  for example, there  is
+
This is solid ground for reading 'q because p' as: 'p is the [[reason]] for q', 'p is the explanatory {{Wiki|hypothesis}} for q', or even the Peircean 'if p were true, q would be a {{Wiki|matter}} of course'.  
                fire on the mountain.
 
  
            16. Reason (hetu)- The mountain smokes.
+
Beyond points of translation, one of the strongest [[reasons]] for [[seeing]] the three-membered [[syllogism]] of the [[Nyaayaprave`sa]] as a retroduction-deduction is the [[existence]] of the five-membered [[syllogism]] in the earlier [[Nyaaya tradition]], particularly the [[Nyaaya Suutra]].(9)  
  
             17. Exemplification  (d.r.s.taata) -  Wherever
+
The five-membered [[syllogism]] of the [[Nyaaya Suutra]] is perfectly symmetrical between its three initial retroductive steps and its two culminating {{Wiki|deductive}} steps:
                 there  is  smoke.  there  is  fire, as  (for
+
 
 +
 
 +
            15. {{Wiki|Thesis}}([[pratij~naa]])  for  example, there  is
 +
                [[fire]] on the mountain.
 +
 
 +
            16. [[Reason]] ([[hetu]])- The mountain smokes.
 +
 
 +
             17. {{Wiki|Exemplification}}   (d.r.s.taata) -  Wherever
 +
                 there  is  smoke.  there  is  [[fire]], as  (for
 
                 example) on the hearth in the kitchen.
 
                 example) on the hearth in the kitchen.
  
             18. Recapitulation of the reason (upanaya) - The
+
             18. Recapitulation of the [[reason]] ([[upanaya]]) - The
 
                 mountain smokes.
 
                 mountain smokes.
  
             19. Conclusion (nigamana) There is fire on the
+
             19. Conclusion ([[nigamana]]) There is [[fire]] on the
 
                 mountain.
 
                 mountain.
 
[[File:BuddhaTwang.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:BuddhaTwang.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
        If one were to picture this pattern as an isosceles
+
        If one were to picture this pattern as an isosceles triangle, one side would represent the retroduction from [15] the pratij~naa {{Wiki|reasoning}} through the [16] [[hetu]] to [17] the d.r.s.taanta, and the opposing side of the triangle would represent the deduction beginning with [17] the d.r.s.taanta to [18] [[upanaya]] and inferring the [[nigamana]].  
        triangle, one side would represent the retroduction
 
        from [15] the pratij~naa reasoning through the [16]
 
        hetu to [17] the d.r.s.taanta, and the opposing side
 
        of the triangle would represent   the deduction
 
        beginning with [17] the d.r.s.taanta to [18] upanaya
 
        and inferring the nigamana.
 
  
            The French Indologist Rene Guenon pointed out
+
The {{Wiki|French}} {{Wiki|Indologist}} [[Wikipedia:René Guénon|Rene Guenon]] pointed out that after the [[appearance]] of the [[Nyaaya Suutra]], there were two abridged [[forms]] of the five-membered [[syllogism]], (10) in which either the first three [15-17] or the last three [17-19] parts appeared alone.  
        that after the appearance of the Nyaaya Suutra,
+
 
        there were two abridged forms of the five-membered
+
Gutnon also pointed out that the [[latter]] {{Wiki|abridgment}} resembles the [[syllogism]] of Aristolle; the former {{Wiki|abridgment}}, of course, is precisely the one found in the 6th century [[Nyaayaprave`sa]] and indeed the same smoke-fire example occurs there also.  
        syllogism, (10) in which either the first three
+
 
        [15-17] or the last three [17-19] parts appeared
+
Given the [[interpretation]] I have [[offered]], it is not surprising that there should be two abridgments of the five-membered [[syllogism]].  
        alone. Gutnon also pointed out that the latter
+
 
        abridgment resembles the syllogism of Aristolle; the
+
One {{Wiki|abridgment}} captures the retroductive move; the second captures the {{Wiki|deductive}} move. Deduction and retroduction are inversions of one another, and they can be separated by positioning the property-locus statement. One {{Wiki|abridgment}} [[reasons]] from the {{Wiki|thesis}} statement to an explanatory generalization; the other {{Wiki|abridgment}} deduces the {{Wiki|thesis}} from the generalization.  
        former abridgment, of course, is precisely the one
+
 
        found in the 6th century Nyaayaprave`sa and indeed
+
The [[Buddhist]] [[logicians]] Mere quite emphatic about which {{Wiki|abridgment}} they favored. The [[Nyaaya]] quite explicitly says, "We say that these three statements make the members of the [[syllogism]] and no more! "(11) [[Tachikwa's]] gloss on this statement indicates that it is an [[assertion]] that only three statements are necessary for an {{Wiki|inference}}.
        the same smoke-fire example occurs there also. Given
 
        the interpretation   I have offered, it is not
 
        surprising that there should be two abridgments of
 
        the five-membered syllogism. One abridgment captures
 
        the retroductive move; the second captures the
 
        deductive move.   Deduction and retroduction are
 
        inversions of one another, and they can be separated
 
        by positioning the property-locus statement. One
 
        abridgment reasons from the thesis statement to an
 
        explanatory generalization; the other abridgment
 
        deduces the thesis from the generalization. The
 
        Buddhist logicians Mere quite emphatic about which
 
        abridgment they favored. The Nyaaya quite explicitly
 
        says, "We say that these three statements make the
 
        members   of the syllogism   and no more! "(11)
 
        Tachikwa's gloss on this statement indicates that it
 
        is an assertion that only three statements are
 
        necessary for an inference.
 
 
[[File:Buddhism-2.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhism-2.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
            We may conclude that what "inference"  primarily
 
        meant to the Buddhist logicians was "reasoning to an
 
        explanatory causal hypothesis"; however, it would be
 
        wrong  to  further  conclude  that  they  had  no
 
        appreciation of the
 
  
                                P.187
 
  
 +
            We may conclude that what "{{Wiki|inference}}" primarily meant to the [[Buddhist]] [[logicians]] was "{{Wiki|reasoning}} to an explanatory [[causal]] {{Wiki|hypothesis}}"; however, it would be wrong to further conclude that they had no [[appreciation]] of the {{Wiki|deductive}} {{Wiki|abridgment}}.
  
        deductive  abridgment.  To them logic was a means of
+
To them [[logic]] was a means of bringing others to a [[recognition]] of particular statements; it was an [[upaaya]], a {{Wiki|heuristic}} [[teaching]] device.  
        bringing others to a recognition   of particular
+
 
        statements; it was an upaaya, a heuristic teaching
+
The retroductive {{Wiki|abridgment}} of the [[five-membered syllogism]] clearly teaches in the sence that it brings the [[hearer]] to an [[awareness]] of a [[causal]] or {{Wiki|conceptual}} connection.  
        device.   The   retroductive   abridgment   of   the
+
 
        five-membered syllogism clearly teaches in the sence
+
The {{Wiki|deductive}} {{Wiki|abridgment}} does not "teach" in this [[sense]] because like all deductions its conclusion does not contain [[information]] nor already found in the premises,  
        that it brings the hearer to an awareness of a causal
+
 
        or conceptual connection. The deductive abridgment
+
[[Thus]], from the standpoint of an [[upaaya]] the retroductive {{Wiki|inference}} is enough, or, as the author of the [[Nyaayaprave`sa]] put it, "...these three members make the [retroductive] [[syllogism]] and no more."
        does not "teach" in this sense because like all
 
        deductions   its   conclusion   does   not   contain
 
        information nor already found in the premises, Thus,
 
        from the standpoint of an upaaya the retroductive
 
        inference is enough, or, as the author of the
 
        Nyaayaprave`sa put it, "...these three members make
 
        the [retroductive] syllogism and no more."
 
 
[[File:Buddhism-Mongolia.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhism-Mongolia.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
             A further point in favour of reading the Nyaaya
+
 
        inference schema as a retroduction is that it makes
+
 
        the remainder of the manual on logical methods,
+
 
        especially   the detailed   sections on kinds of
+
 
        fallacies, more intelligible and enljghtening. More
+
             A further point in favour of reading the [[Nyaaya]] {{Wiki|inference}} {{Wiki|schema}} as a retroduction is that it makes the remainder of the manual on [[logical]] methods, especially the detailed [[sections]] on kinds of fallacies, more intelligible and [[enlightening]].  
        than two thirds of the text covers identification
+
 
        and classification of fallacies, but none bear any
+
More than two thirds of the text covers identification and {{Wiki|classification}} of fallacies, but none bear any resemblance to the formal fallacies of deduction such as [[affirming]] the consequent or denying the antecedent, nor does the system resemble {{Wiki|Western}} notions of an informal [[fallacy]].  
        resemblance to the formal fallacies of deduction
+
 
        such as affirming the consequent or denying the
+
Fallacies of irrelevance such as the ad hominem or post hoc propter hoc call [[attention]] to the lack of support between premises and putative conclusion. In [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] the {{Wiki|classification}} of fallacies does not attempt to circumscribe the ways premises can be irrelevant; on the contrary it fives criteria for grading the strength or weakness of the explanatory {{Wiki|hypotheses}}.  
        antecedent, nor does the system resemble Western
+
 
        notions of an informal fallacy.   Fallacies   of
+
This is precisely what is required for retroductive accuracy.  
        irrelevance such as the ad hominem or post hoc
+
 
        propter hoc call attention to the lack of support
+
Weak {{Wiki|hypotheses}} emerge in three circumstances:  
        between premises   and putative   conclusion.   In
+
 
        Buddhist logic the classification of fallacies does
+
(1) the [[hetu]] is unrecognized by proponent or opponent,  
        not attempt to circumscribe the ways premises can be
+
 
        irrelevant; on the contrary it fives criteria for
+
(2) the [[hetu]] is inconclusive, or
        grading the strength or weakness of the explanatory
+
 
        hypotheses. This is precisely what is required for
+
(3) it is contradicted. Inconclusive [[hetus]] are those which are not supported by further {{Wiki|evidence}} from the similarity and dissimilarity cases; contradicted [[hetus]] are those which prove the opposite of the [[pak.sa]].  
        retroductive accuracy. Weak hypotheses emerge in
+
 
        three circumstances: (1) the hetu is unrecognized by
+
Such a {{Wiki|contradiction}} is established by deducing the opposite property-locus [[assertion]].  
        proponent or opponent, (2) the hetu is inconclusive,
+
 
        or (3) it is contradicted. Inconclusive hetus are
+
 
        those which are not supported by further evidence
+
 
        from   the similarity   and dissimilarity   cases;
+
A [[hetu]] can fail to be [[recognized]], that is, it can fail as a [[teaching]] device by not making the auditor (or speaker) {{Wiki|aware}} of the connection between the [[assertion]] statement and its warranting [[hetu]].  
        contradicted   hetus are those which   prove the
+
 
        opposite of the pak.sa. Such a contradiction is
+
[[Thus]], when {{Wiki|hypotheses}} fail to be understood, they engender fallacies of [[recognition]], but when they fail in evidential support they engender fallacies of {{Wiki|contradiction}} or inconclusivity. On the whole, this {{Wiki|classification}} of fallacies reflects a sophisticated, but also a commonsensical, means of evaluating {{Wiki|hypotheses}}.  
        established by deducing the opposite property-locus
+
 
        assertion. A hetu can fail to be recognized, that
+
It is open textured as retroductive {{Wiki|reasoning}} must be, and more importantly it does not attempt (as the {{Wiki|Western}} notion of fallac does) to classify fallacious {{Wiki|reasoning}} as a kind of {{Wiki|deductive}} argument gone awry.
        is, it can fail as a teaching device by not making
 
        the auditor (or speaker) aware of the connection
 
        between the assertion statement and its warranting
 
        hetu. Thus, when hypotheses fail to be understood,
 
        they engender fallacies of recognition, but when they
 
        fail in evidential support they engender fallacies
 
        of contradiction or inconclusivity. On the whole,
 
        this   classification   of fallacies   reflects   a
 
        sophisticated, but also a commonsensical, means of
 
        evaluating hypotheses. It is open textured as
 
        retroductive reasoning must be, and more importantly
 
        it does not attempt (as the Western notion of fallac
 
        does) to classify fallacious reasoning as a kind of
 
        deductive argument gone awry.
 
 
[[File:Buddhism.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhism.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
            In this paper  I have attempted  to enlarge  the
 
        dialogue  about  the  nature  of Buddhist  logic  by
 
        arguing  that  it is  essentially  retroductive.  As
 
        philosophers    and  psychologists    continue  to
 
        investigate  the conceptual  and factual aspects  of
 
        hypothesis  formation, the study  of Buddhist  logic
 
        will increase  in importance  because, unlike  other
 
        logical  treatises,  the  Nyaayaprave`sa  is  an
 
        historyically  significant  document  about  ways of
 
        reasoning  and  misreasoning  to  an  explanatory
 
        hypothesis.
 
  
                                P.188
+
 
 +
            In this paper I have attempted to enlarge the {{Wiki|dialogue}} about the [[nature]] of [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] by arguing that it is [[essentially]] retroductive.  
 +
 
 +
As [[philosophers]] and {{Wiki|psychologists}} continue to investigate the {{Wiki|conceptual}} and {{Wiki|factual}} aspects of {{Wiki|hypothesis}} formation, the study of [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] will increase in importance because, unlike other [[logical]] treatises, the [[Nyaayaprave`sa]] is an historyically significant document about ways of {{Wiki|reasoning}} and misreasoning to an explanatory
 +
        {{Wiki|hypothesis}}.
 +
 
 +
                               
  
 
         NOTES
 
         NOTES
  
 
             1. Daniel H. H.  Ingalls, Material for the Study
 
             1. Daniel H. H.  Ingalls, Material for the Study
         of Navya-Nyaya  Logic, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
+
         of [[Navya-Nyaya]] [[Logic]], {{Wiki|Harvard}} {{Wiki|Oriental}} Series, vol.
         40  (Cambridge:  Harvard University  Press,  1951);
+
         40  ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}{{Wiki|Harvard University}} Press,  1951);
         Hajime Nakamura, "Buddhist Logic Expounded  by Means
+
         [[Hajime Nakamura]], "[[Buddhist]] [[Logic]] Expounded  by Means
         of  Symbolic  Logic," Indogku  Bukkyogaku  Kenkyu  7
+
         of  [[Symbolic]] [[Logic]]," Indogku  Bukkyogaku  Kenkyu  7
 
         (1958) :  375-395;  J.  F.  Staal,  "Means  of
 
         (1958) :  375-395;  J.  F.  Staal,  "Means  of
         Formalization of Indian and Western Thought," Logic,
+
         Formalization of [[Indian]] and {{Wiki|Western}} [[Thought]]," [[Logic]],
         Metlzodology  and Philosophy of Science, Proceedings
+
         Metlzodology  and [[Philosophy]] of [[Science]], Proceedings
         of the XIIth International  Congress  of Philosophy,
+
         of the XIIth International  Congress  of [[Philosophy]],
 
         Venice,  1958;  H.  Kitagawa,  "A  Note  on  the
 
         Venice,  1958;  H.  Kitagawa,  "A  Note  on  the
         Methodology  in the Study of Indian Logic," Indogaku
+
         {{Wiki|Methodology}} in the Study of [[Indian]] [[Logic]]," Indogaku
 
         Bukkyogaku  Kenkyu  8  (1960) :  380-390;  S.  S.
 
         Bukkyogaku  Kenkyu  8  (1960) :  380-390;  S.  S.
         Barlingay, A Modern  Introduction  to  Indian  Logic
+
         Barlingay, A {{Wiki|Modern}} Introduction  to  [[Indian]] [[Logic]]
         (Delhi:  National  Publishing  House,  1965) :  A.
+
         ({{Wiki|Delhi}}:  National  Publishing  House,  1965) :  A.
         Charlene S.  McDermott, An Eleventh-Century Buddhist
+
         Charlene S.  McDermott, An Eleventh-Century [[Buddhist]]
         Logic  of  "Exists,  "  Foundations  of  Language,
+
         [[Logic]]   of  "[[Exists]],  "  Foundations  of  [[Language]],
         Supplementary Series, vol. 2 (Dordrecht, Holland: D.
+
         Supplementary Series, vol. 2 (Dordrecht, [[Holland]]: D.
 
         Reidel,  1970);  B.  K.  Matilal,  The  Navya-Nyaaya
 
         Reidel,  1970);  B.  K.  Matilal,  The  Navya-Nyaaya
         Doctrine  of Negation, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
+
         [[Doctrine]] of {{Wiki|Negation}}, {{Wiki|Harvard}} {{Wiki|Oriental}} Series, vol.
         46 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press.  1968): and
+
         46 ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: {{Wiki|Harvard University}} Press.  1968): and
         particularly  Epistemology,  Logic  and  Grammar  in
+
         particularly  {{Wiki|Epistemology}}[[Logic]] and  [[Grammar]] in
         Indian  Philosophical  Analysis,  Janua  Linguarum,
+
         [[Indian]] [[Philosophical]]   Analysis,  Janua  Linguarum,
 
         Series Minor, 111 (Mouton: The Hague, 1971).
 
         Series Minor, 111 (Mouton: The Hague, 1971).
 
[[File:Buddhism47gf.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhism47gf.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
             2.  Douglas Daye, "Metalogical Incompatibilities
 
             2.  Douglas Daye, "Metalogical Incompatibilities
         In  the  Formal  Description  of  Buddhist  Logic
+
         In  the  Formal  Description  of  [[Buddhist]]   [[Logic]]
         (Nyaaya)," Notre  Dame Journal  of Logic  28, no.  2
+
         ([[Nyaaya]])," Notre  Dame Journal  of [[Logic]] 28, no.  2
 
         (1977): 231.
 
         (1977): 231.
  
             3.  Douglas Daye, "Empirical Falsifiability  and
+
             3.  Douglas Daye, "[[Empirical]] Falsifiability  and
 
         the  Frequence  of Dar`sana  Relevance  in the Sixth
 
         the  Frequence  of Dar`sana  Relevance  in the Sixth
         Century Buddhist  Logic of Sankaravamin," Logique et
+
         Century [[Buddhist]] [[Logic]] of Sankaravamin," Logique et
 
         Analyse 86 (June 1979): 221.
 
         Analyse 86 (June 1979): 221.
  
             4.  Douglas Daye, Comparative Issues in Buddhist
+
             4.  Douglas Daye, Comparative Issues in [[Buddhist]]
         and  Angle-European  Formal  Logics  (unpublished
+
         and  Angle-European  Formal  [[Logics]]   (unpublished
         manuscript), p. 121.
+
         {{Wiki|manuscript}}), p. 121.
  
             5.  Musashi  Tachikawa, trans., "A Sixth Century
+
             5.  [[Musashi]] [[Tachikawa]], trans., "A Sixth Century
         Manual  of  Indian  Logic  (the  Nyaayaprave`sa) ,"
+
         Manual  of  [[Indian]] [[Logic]] (the  [[Nyaayaprave`sa]]) ,"
         Journal of Indian Philosophy 1, no. 2 (1971): 114.
+
         Journal of [[Indian Philosophy]] 1, no. 2 (1971): 114.
  
 
             6. Ibid., p. 115, Norwood R. Hanson, Patterns of
 
             6. Ibid., p. 115, Norwood R. Hanson, Patterns of
         Discovery  (Cambridge: Cambridge  University  Press,
+
         Discovery  ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: {{Wiki|Cambridge}} {{Wiki|University}} Press,
 
         1958), pp. 93-105.
 
         1958), pp. 93-105.
  
             "Is There A Logic of Discovery," Current  Issues
+
             "Is There A [[Logic]] of Discovery," Current  Issues
         in Philosophy of Science, edited by H.  Fergland and
+
         in [[Philosophy]] of [[Science]], edited by H.  Fergland and
         G.  Maxwell  (New York:  Holt-Rinehart  &  Winston,
+
         G.  Maxwell  ({{Wiki|New York}}:  Holt-Rinehart  &  Winston,
         1961), pp. 20-35. Also Aristotle, Prior Analytics II,
+
         1961), pp. 20-35. Also {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, Prior Analytics II,
 
         25.
 
         25.
 
[[File:BuddhistTriad.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:BuddhistTriad.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
             7.  C.  S.  Peirce, Collected  Works (Cambridge:
+
             7.  C.  S.  Peirce, Collected  Works ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}:
         Harvard University  Press, 1933), vol.  1, p.  188.
+
         {{Wiki|Harvard University}} Press, 1933), vol.  1, p.  188.
 
         Also vol. 6, pp. 522-28.
 
         Also vol. 6, pp. 522-28.
  
             8. Tachikawa, p. 116.
+
             8. [[Tachikawa]], p. 116.
  
             9.  A.  B.  Keith,  Indian  Logic  and  Atomism
+
             9.  A.  B.  Keith,  [[Indian]] [[Logic]] and  {{Wiki|Atomism}}
         (Oxford: 1921), p.  21.  The author dates the Nyaaya
+
         ({{Wiki|Oxford}}: 1921), p.  21.  The author dates the [[Nyaaya Suutra]] at 200-450 A.D.
        Suutra at 200-450 A.D.
 
  
             10. Rene Guenon, Introduction generale a l'etude
+
             10. [[Wikipedia:René Guénon|Rene Guenon]], Introduction generale a l'etude
         des doctrines hindous(Paris: 1930), pp. 226-227.
+
         des [[doctrines]] hindous(Paris: 1930), pp. 226-227.
  
             11. Tachikawa, p. 122.
+
             11. [[Tachikawa]], p. 122.
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
 
{{R}}
 
{{R}}

Latest revision as of 15:08, 8 March 2015

Bud 0.jpg

The history of Indian logic is usually divided into three periods, Old Nyaaya (circa 250 B.C. ) , Buddhist logic (sixth century A.D.) and New Nyaaya.

The Buddhist logic text, Nyaayaprave`sa (Introduction to Logical Methods) , had great influence upon Indian and Chinese Buddhism and also among the Jains.

As a pivotal work, the Nyaayaprave`sa has received critical attention from historians of religion, philologists, philosophers, and logicians.

As with all advances in scholarship, there is controversy over interpretation, but in the case of Buddhist logic, the controversy cuts to the very heart of the issue of whether Buddhist logic is in any recognizable contemporary sense a "logic."

The received view holds that Buddhist logic bears very close similarities to syllogistic forms and that it can be represented and analyzed by standard deductive techniques.(1)

A much different and opposing view has been argued by Professor Douglas Daye in a series of papers.

Daye maintains that "... the descriptive utility of mathematical logic with early Nyaaya texts has simply been overrated";

(2) that although the Nyaaya texts contain metalogical rules for evaluating the "legitimacy or illegitimacy" of arguments, the distinction between validity and invalidity does not apply;

(3) that Nyaaya models are not inferences but "formalistic explanations"; and that "... Buddhist logic is not deductive, nor can it be formally valid nor is it an inference."

(4)
Buddha 2sw.jpg
The cumulative effect of these claims is to assert that Buddhist logic is not a "logic" at all, at least not in any sense which is recognized by Western philosophers.




There is a radical incompatibility between the Nyaaya methods of logic and those of the Prior Analytics or Principia Mathematica.

Of course, there will be differences, possibly very great differences, between any two traditions so diverse as fourth century (B.C.) Greece and sixth century (A.D.) India, but are we to go so far as to say that the Nyaaya does not contain inferences?

The radical incompatibility thesis is, I maintain, a mistake; moreover, it is a mistake which can readily be uncovered by examining the typical Nyaaya inference scheme.

Of the notion that a Nyaaya scheme could be a "formalistic explanation" without being an inference, I shall say very little because I do not see how anything which functions as an explanation could not involve inferences of some kind or other.

It is important to know whether the Nyaaya scheme is deductive or not, and if it is, whether all of its parts are essential to the deduction.

I will demonstrate that there are two ways of reading the Nyaaya form: one which is straightforwardly deductive and a second which is best understood by what the American pragmatist, .S. Peirce, and later Norwood Hanson, call "retroduction."


Bud4.jpeg

            To begin with, consider this representative
        example from the Nyaaya:(5)

            1. pak.sa (thesis) Sound is imprrmanrne

            2. hetu (mark or Reason) - Because of its
               property of being produced

                             


            3. d.r.s.taanta (Exemplification)--Whatever is
                produced, is impermanent
            4. sapak.sa (similar case)- As with a pot, and
                so forth
            5. vipak.sa (dissimilar case)- As (not with the
                case) of space, and so forth

            Tachikawa proposes the following scheme for what
        he calls the "three-membered Indian syllogism:(6)

            6. There is property p in locus L
            7. (because) there is property q (in L).
            8. Wherever there is property q, there is
                property p, as in locus w

Buddha 21226.jpg

        Clearly, if this schema is reversed, (8) and (7)
        become premises for a valid deductive inference of
        (6) as the conclusion. The reverse of our example
        becomes an instance of modus ponens.

            9. d.r.s.taanta - Whatever is created is
                impermanent.
            10. hetu - Sound is created.
            11. pak.sa - Sound is impermanent.

             Why is this instance of modus ponens a matter of dispute?

The incompatibilists point out that the relationship between the thesis (pak.sa) and the justification (hetu) is always expressed in the Sanskrit ablative case and that this relationship cannot be represented or translated as the English "therefore" (or ergo).

Its best translation is "because."

Thus, for the incompatibilist, the primary objection to identifying the Nyaaya scheme as a deductive inference is the familiar one of ordinary language philosophers who resist the translation of expressions as `q because p' into `p ) q' on the grounds that the causal or explanatory meaning of "because" is lost in the truth-functional conditional.

Buddha121xs.JPG



            This objection has force, but one must distinguish between the assertion that truth-functional connectives preserve or capture the meaning of `q because p' and the claim that truth-functional connectives can represent a deductive relationship between propositions within the Nyaaya scheme. It is the latter which the received view upholds: it is the former which the incompatibilist vehemently opposes.

The issue is not joined, because surely one can maintain that there is a deductive inference in the inversion Nyaaya scheme without maintaining that it captures the meaning of or even approaches synonymy with the original.

In sum, the issue between the received view and the incompatibilist pivots on the former's willingness to invert the Nyaaya form and read it as a valid deduction and the latter's insistence that the form cannot be so reversed without losing the special relationship of the hetu.

Given the merits of both views and given the fact that both positions are not explicit contradictories of one another, there is a way to understand the Nyaaya scheme which allows both sides to have their cake and eat it too.

I believe that the three-membered Nyaaya is best understood as a retroductivc inference.

A retroduction, as it has been described by C. S. Peirce and

Buddha20i.jpg

                              

         Norwood Hanson is a pattern of reasoning which leads from some phenomenon or perception to an explanatory hypothesis of that phenomenon.

Its form is not truth-functional nor are the relationships of that premises completely rulegoverned.

Peirce said, "It must be remembered that retroduction, although hampered very little by logical rules, nevertheless, is logical inference, asserting its conclusion only problematically or conjecturally...."(7)

Retroduction does have a recognizable pattern, and indeed it is very close to the three-membered syllogism of Indian logic.



Its form, according to Peirce, is:

            12. The surprizing fact Q is observed.

            13. But if P were true, Q would be a matter of
                course.

            14. Hence, there is reason to suspect that P is
                true.

        As a schema, for retroduction we have:

Buddha444.jpg

            (12') q
            (13') q because p
            (14')p

         which is isomorphic with that of the Nyaaya (that is, pak.sa, because hetu and d.r.s.taanta; hence there is evidence for the pak.sa).

The similarity (sapak.sa) and dissimilarity (vipak.sa) cases serve as further evidence in support of the explanatory justification.

The philosopher of science, Norwood Hanson, argued that retroduction was a "logic of discovery" which led to deductive-nomological explanations.

Like Peirce, Hanson pointed out that the reversal of a retroduction was a deductive inference 'q, q because p', becomes 'p, if p, then q, hence q'.

The notion of reversal" or inverting" a retroduction is not a technique or rule of formal logic, but rather a simple psychological description of changing the order of premises.



Buddhagarden.jpg

            If the three-membered syllogism is retroduction and if a retroduction is part of a retroductive-deductive pair, one should expect to find internal evidence for the presence or absence of a deductive fragment.

To return to the Nyaaya and its commentary on this three-membered syllogism, is there internal evidence to treat it as a retroduction-cum-deduction?

A crucial point of philological interpretation is the function of the ablative "because" and the meaning of "hetu" itself.



The weakness of the standard view is that it disregards the special features of the ablative "because" and translates the three-membered syllogism as if it contained conditionals.

Following Daye, I suggest that that move is too hasty, and that we must regard the ablative "because" as an operator connecting the hetu and d.r.s.taanta to the thesis.

Since the Sanskrit ablative expresses a relation of physical or conceptual removal, separation, distinction, or origin, it was used to convey the notion of causal explanation.

Buddhas.jpg

This fact gives prima facie evidence for interpreting it in the sense of "a reason for." Such an understanding is reinforced by the meaning of "hetu," which is the name of the explanatory part of the three membered syllogism.

According to Tachikawa, "hetu" primarily means 'reason'.(8)

This is solid ground for reading 'q because p' as: 'p is the reason for q', 'p is the explanatory hypothesis for q', or even the Peircean 'if p were true, q would be a matter of course'.

Beyond points of translation, one of the strongest reasons for seeing the three-membered syllogism of the Nyaayaprave`sa as a retroduction-deduction is the existence of the five-membered syllogism in the earlier Nyaaya tradition, particularly the Nyaaya Suutra.(9)

The five-membered syllogism of the Nyaaya Suutra is perfectly symmetrical between its three initial retroductive steps and its two culminating deductive steps:


            15. Thesis(pratij~naa) for example, there is
                fire on the mountain.

            16. Reason (hetu)- The mountain smokes.

            17. Exemplification (d.r.s.taata) - Wherever
                there is smoke. there is fire, as (for
                example) on the hearth in the kitchen.

            18. Recapitulation of the reason (upanaya) - The
                mountain smokes.

            19. Conclusion (nigamana) There is fire on the
                mountain.

BuddhaTwang.jpg


         If one were to picture this pattern as an isosceles triangle, one side would represent the retroduction from [15] the pratij~naa reasoning through the [16] hetu to [17] the d.r.s.taanta, and the opposing side of the triangle would represent the deduction beginning with [17] the d.r.s.taanta to [18] upanaya and inferring the nigamana.

The French Indologist Rene Guenon pointed out that after the appearance of the Nyaaya Suutra, there were two abridged forms of the five-membered syllogism, (10) in which either the first three [15-17] or the last three [17-19] parts appeared alone.

Gutnon also pointed out that the latter abridgment resembles the syllogism of Aristolle; the former abridgment, of course, is precisely the one found in the 6th century Nyaayaprave`sa and indeed the same smoke-fire example occurs there also.

Given the interpretation I have offered, it is not surprising that there should be two abridgments of the five-membered syllogism.

One abridgment captures the retroductive move; the second captures the deductive move. Deduction and retroduction are inversions of one another, and they can be separated by positioning the property-locus statement. One abridgment reasons from the thesis statement to an explanatory generalization; the other abridgment deduces the thesis from the generalization.

The Buddhist logicians Mere quite emphatic about which abridgment they favored. The Nyaaya quite explicitly says, "We say that these three statements make the members of the syllogism and no more! "(11) Tachikwa's gloss on this statement indicates that it is an assertion that only three statements are necessary for an inference.

Buddhism-2.jpg



            We may conclude that what "inference" primarily meant to the Buddhist logicians was "reasoning to an explanatory causal hypothesis"; however, it would be wrong to further conclude that they had no appreciation of the deductive abridgment.

To them logic was a means of bringing others to a recognition of particular statements; it was an upaaya, a heuristic teaching device.

The retroductive abridgment of the five-membered syllogism clearly teaches in the sence that it brings the hearer to an awareness of a causal or conceptual connection.

The deductive abridgment does not "teach" in this sense because like all deductions its conclusion does not contain information nor already found in the premises,

Thus, from the standpoint of an upaaya the retroductive inference is enough, or, as the author of the Nyaayaprave`sa put it, "...these three members make the [retroductive] syllogism and no more."

Buddhism-Mongolia.jpg





            A further point in favour of reading the Nyaaya inference schema as a retroduction is that it makes the remainder of the manual on logical methods, especially the detailed sections on kinds of fallacies, more intelligible and enlightening.

More than two thirds of the text covers identification and classification of fallacies, but none bear any resemblance to the formal fallacies of deduction such as affirming the consequent or denying the antecedent, nor does the system resemble Western notions of an informal fallacy.

Fallacies of irrelevance such as the ad hominem or post hoc propter hoc call attention to the lack of support between premises and putative conclusion. In Buddhist logic the classification of fallacies does not attempt to circumscribe the ways premises can be irrelevant; on the contrary it fives criteria for grading the strength or weakness of the explanatory hypotheses.

This is precisely what is required for retroductive accuracy.

Weak hypotheses emerge in three circumstances:

(1) the hetu is unrecognized by proponent or opponent,

(2) the hetu is inconclusive, or

(3) it is contradicted. Inconclusive hetus are those which are not supported by further evidence from the similarity and dissimilarity cases; contradicted hetus are those which prove the opposite of the pak.sa.

Such a contradiction is established by deducing the opposite property-locus assertion.



A hetu can fail to be recognized, that is, it can fail as a teaching device by not making the auditor (or speaker) aware of the connection between the assertion statement and its warranting hetu.

Thus, when hypotheses fail to be understood, they engender fallacies of recognition, but when they fail in evidential support they engender fallacies of contradiction or inconclusivity. On the whole, this classification of fallacies reflects a sophisticated, but also a commonsensical, means of evaluating hypotheses.

It is open textured as retroductive reasoning must be, and more importantly it does not attempt (as the Western notion of fallac does) to classify fallacious reasoning as a kind of deductive argument gone awry.

Buddhism.jpg



            In this paper I have attempted to enlarge the dialogue about the nature of Buddhist logic by arguing that it is essentially retroductive.

As philosophers and psychologists continue to investigate the conceptual and factual aspects of hypothesis formation, the study of Buddhist logic will increase in importance because, unlike other logical treatises, the Nyaayaprave`sa is an historyically significant document about ways of reasoning and misreasoning to an explanatory
        hypothesis.

                                 

        NOTES

            1. Daniel H. H. Ingalls, Material for the Study
        of Navya-Nyaya Logic, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
        40 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1951);
        Hajime Nakamura, "Buddhist Logic Expounded by Means
        of Symbolic Logic," Indogku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu 7
        (1958) : 375-395; J. F. Staal, "Means of
        Formalization of Indian and Western Thought," Logic,
        Metlzodology and Philosophy of Science, Proceedings
        of the XIIth International Congress of Philosophy,
        Venice, 1958; H. Kitagawa, "A Note on the
        Methodology in the Study of Indian Logic," Indogaku
        Bukkyogaku Kenkyu 8 (1960) : 380-390; S. S.
        Barlingay, A Modern Introduction to Indian Logic
        (Delhi: National Publishing House, 1965) : A.
        Charlene S. McDermott, An Eleventh-Century Buddhist
        Logic of "Exists, " Foundations of Language,
        Supplementary Series, vol. 2 (Dordrecht, Holland: D.
        Reidel, 1970); B. K. Matilal, The Navya-Nyaaya
        Doctrine of Negation, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
        46 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 1968): and
        particularly Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in
        Indian Philosophical Analysis, Janua Linguarum,
        Series Minor, 111 (Mouton: The Hague, 1971).

Buddhism47gf.jpg

            2. Douglas Daye, "Metalogical Incompatibilities
        In the Formal Description of Buddhist Logic
        (Nyaaya)," Notre Dame Journal of Logic 28, no. 2
        (1977): 231.

            3. Douglas Daye, "Empirical Falsifiability and
        the Frequence of Dar`sana Relevance in the Sixth
        Century Buddhist Logic of Sankaravamin," Logique et
        Analyse 86 (June 1979): 221.

            4. Douglas Daye, Comparative Issues in Buddhist
        and Angle-European Formal Logics (unpublished
        manuscript), p. 121.

            5. Musashi Tachikawa, trans., "A Sixth Century
        Manual of Indian Logic (the Nyaayaprave`sa) ,"
        Journal of Indian Philosophy 1, no. 2 (1971): 114.

            6. Ibid., p. 115, Norwood R. Hanson, Patterns of
        Discovery (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
        1958), pp. 93-105.

            "Is There A Logic of Discovery," Current Issues
        in Philosophy of Science, edited by H. Fergland and
        G. Maxwell (New York: Holt-Rinehart & Winston,
        1961), pp. 20-35. Also Aristotle, Prior Analytics II,
        25.

BuddhistTriad.JPG

            7. C. S. Peirce, Collected Works (Cambridge:
        Harvard University Press, 1933), vol. 1, p. 188.
        Also vol. 6, pp. 522-28.

            8. Tachikawa, p. 116.

            9. A. B. Keith, Indian Logic and Atomism
        (Oxford: 1921), p. 21. The author dates the Nyaaya Suutra at 200-450 A.D.

            10. Rene Guenon, Introduction generale a l'etude
        des doctrines hindous(Paris: 1930), pp. 226-227.

            11. Tachikawa, p. 122.

Source

ccbs.ntu.edu.tw