Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "What is the "logic" in Buddhist logic? By R. Lance Factor"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
Line 1: Line 1:
 
[[File:Bud 0.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Bud 0.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
The history of Indian logic is usually  divided into
+
The {{Wiki|history}} of [[Indian]] [[logic]] is usually  divided into
 
         three  periods,  Old  Nyaaya  (circa  250  B.C.  ) ,
 
         three  periods,  Old  Nyaaya  (circa  250  B.C.  ) ,
         Buddhist  logic (sixth century A.D.) and New Nyaaya.
+
         [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] (sixth century A.D.) and New Nyaaya.
         The    Buddhist    logic    text,    Nyaayaprave`sa
+
         The    [[Buddhist]]     [[logic]]   text,    Nyaayaprave`sa
 
         (Introduction  to  Logical  Methods) ,  had  great
 
         (Introduction  to  Logical  Methods) ,  had  great
         influence  upon Indian and Chinese Buddhism and also
+
         [[influence]] upon [[Indian]] and [[Chinese Buddhism]] and also
         among  the  Jains.  As  a  pivotal  work,  the
+
         among  the  {{Wiki|Jains}}.  As  a  pivotal  work,  the
         Nyaayaprave`sa  has received critical attention from
+
         Nyaayaprave`sa  has received critical [[attention]] from
         historians  of religion, philologists, philosophers,
+
         historians  of [[religion]], philologists, [[philosophers]],
         and logicians.  As with all advances in scholarship,
+
         and [[logicians]].  As with all advances in {{Wiki|scholarship}},
 
         there is controversy over interpretation, but in the
 
         there is controversy over interpretation, but in the
         case of Buddhist logic, the controversy  cuts to the
+
         case of [[Buddhist]] [[logic]], the controversy  cuts to the
         very heart of the issue of whether Buddhist logic is
+
         very [[heart]] of the issue of whether [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] is
         in any recognizable  contemporary  sense  a "logic."
+
         in any recognizable  contemporary  [[sense]] a "[[logic]]."
         The received  view holds  that Buddhist  logic bears
+
         The received  [[view]] holds  that [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] bears
 
         very close  similarities  to syllogistic  forms  and
 
         very close  similarities  to syllogistic  forms  and
 
         that it can be represented  and analyzed by standard
 
         that it can be represented  and analyzed by standard
 
         deductive  techniques.(1)  A  much  different  and
 
         deductive  techniques.(1)  A  much  different  and
         opposing  view has been argued by Professor  Douglas
+
         opposing  [[view]] has been argued by Professor  Douglas
 
         Daye in a series of papers. Daye maintains that "...
 
         Daye in a series of papers. Daye maintains that "...
         the descriptive  utility of mathematical  logic with
+
         the descriptive  utility of {{Wiki|mathematical}} [[logic]] with
 
         early  Nyaaya  texts has simply  been overrated";(2)
 
         early  Nyaaya  texts has simply  been overrated";(2)
 
         that although  the Nyaaya texts contain  metalogical
 
         that although  the Nyaaya texts contain  metalogical
Line 28: Line 28:
 
         validity  and  invalidity  does  not  apply;(3) that
 
         validity  and  invalidity  does  not  apply;(3) that
 
         Nyaaya  models are not inferences  but  "formalistic
 
         Nyaaya  models are not inferences  but  "formalistic
         explanations";  and that "...  Buddhist logic is not
+
         explanations";  and that "...  [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] is not
 
         deductive, nor can it be formally valid nor is it an
 
         deductive, nor can it be formally valid nor is it an
 
         inference."(4)
 
         inference."(4)
 
[[File:Buddha 2sw.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddha 2sw.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
             The  cumulative  effect  of these  claims  is to
 
             The  cumulative  effect  of these  claims  is to
         assert that Buddhist  logic is not a "logic" at all,
+
         assert that [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] is not a "[[logic]]" at all,
         at least  not in any sense  which  is recognized  by
+
         at least  not in any [[sense]] which  is recognized  by
         Western    philosophers.    There  is  a  radical
+
         Western    [[philosophers]].    There  is  a  radical
         incompatibility  between the Nyaaya methods of logic
+
         incompatibility  between the Nyaaya methods of [[logic]]
 
         and  those  of  the  Prior  Analytics  or  Principia
 
         and  those  of  the  Prior  Analytics  or  Principia
 
         Mathematica.  Of course, there  will be differences,
 
         Mathematica.  Of course, there  will be differences,
 
         possibly  very  great  differences, between  any two
 
         possibly  very  great  differences, between  any two
         traditions  so  diverse  as  fourth  century  (B.C.)
+
         [[traditions]] so  diverse  as  fourth  century  (B.C.)
         Greece and sixth century (A.D.) India, but are we to
+
         Greece and sixth century (A.D.) [[India]], but are we to
 
         go so far as to say that the Nyaaya does not contain
 
         go so far as to say that the Nyaaya does not contain
 
         inferences? The radical incompatibility thesis is, I
 
         inferences? The radical incompatibility thesis is, I
Line 48: Line 48:
 
         Nyaaya inference scheme. Of the notion that a Nyaaya
 
         Nyaaya inference scheme. Of the notion that a Nyaaya
 
         scheme  could  be  a  "formalistic  explanation"
 
         scheme  could  be  a  "formalistic  explanation"
         without  being an inference, I shall say very little
+
         without  [[being]] an inference, I shall say very little
 
         because I do not see how anything which functions as
 
         because I do not see how anything which functions as
 
         an explanation  could not involve inferences of some
 
         an explanation  could not involve inferences of some
         kind or other.  It is important  to know whether the
+
         kind or other.  It is important  [[to know]] whether the
 
         Nyaaya  scheme  is deductive  or not, and  if it is,
 
         Nyaaya  scheme  is deductive  or not, and  if it is,
         whether  all  of its  parts  are  essential  to  the
+
         whether  all  of its  parts  are  [[essential]] to  the
 
         deduction.  I will demonstrate  that  there  are two
 
         deduction.  I will demonstrate  that  there  are two
         ways  of  reading  the  Nyaaya  form: one  which  is
+
         ways  of  reading  the  Nyaaya  [[form]]: one  which  is
 
         straightforwardly  deductive  and a second  which is
 
         straightforwardly  deductive  and a second  which is
 
         best  understood  by what  the American  pragmatist,
 
         best  understood  by what  the American  pragmatist,
Line 64: Line 64:
 
         example from the Nyaaya:(5)
 
         example from the Nyaaya:(5)
  
             1. pak.sa (thesis) Sound is imprrmanrne
+
             1. pak.sa (thesis) [[Sound]] is imprrmanrne
  
             2. hetu (mark  or  Reason)  -  Because  of  its
+
             2. [[hetu]] (mark  or  [[Reason]])  -  Because  of  its
               property of being produced
+
               property of [[being]] produced
  
 
                                 P.184
 
                                 P.184
Line 73: Line 73:
  
 
             3.  d.r.s.taanta  (Exemplification)--Whatever is
 
             3.  d.r.s.taanta  (Exemplification)--Whatever is
                 produced, is impermanent
+
                 produced, is [[impermanent]]
 
             4.  sapak.sa (similar case)-  As with a pot, and
 
             4.  sapak.sa (similar case)-  As with a pot, and
 
                 so forth
 
                 so forth
 
             5.  vipak.sa (dissimilar case)- As (not with the
 
             5.  vipak.sa (dissimilar case)- As (not with the
                 case) of space, and so forth
+
                 case) of [[space]], and so forth
  
 
             Tachikawa proposes the following scheme for what
 
             Tachikawa proposes the following scheme for what
         he calls the "three-membered Indian syllogism:(6)
+
         he calls the "three-membered [[Indian]] syllogism:(6)
  
 
             6.  There is property p in locus L
 
             6.  There is property p in locus L
Line 93: Line 93:
  
 
             9.  d.r.s.taanta  -  Whatever  is  created  is
 
             9.  d.r.s.taanta  -  Whatever  is  created  is
                 impermanent.
+
                 [[impermanent]].
             10. hetu - Sound is created.
+
             10. [[hetu]] - [[Sound]] is created.
             11. pak.sa - Sound is impermanent.
+
             11. pak.sa - [[Sound]] is [[impermanent]].
  
 
             Why is this instance of modus ponens a matter of
 
             Why is this instance of modus ponens a matter of
 
         dispute? The incompatibilists  point  out  that  the
 
         dispute? The incompatibilists  point  out  that  the
 
         relationship  between  the  thesis  (pak.sa) and the
 
         relationship  between  the  thesis  (pak.sa) and the
         justification  (hetu) is  always  expressed  in  the
+
         justification  ([[hetu]]) is  always  expressed  in  the
         Sanskrit  ablative  case and that this  relationship
+
         [[Sanskrit]] ablative  case and that this  relationship
 
         cannot be represented  or translated  as the English
 
         cannot be represented  or translated  as the English
 
         "therefore"  (or  ergo).  Its  best  translation  is
 
         "therefore"  (or  ergo).  Its  best  translation  is
         "because."  Thus,  for  the  incompatibilist,  the
+
         "because."  [[Thus]],  for  the  incompatibilist,  the
         primary objection  to identifying  the Nyaaya scheme
+
         [[primary]] objection  to identifying  the Nyaaya scheme
 
         as a deductive  inference  is the  familiar  one  of
 
         as a deductive  inference  is the  familiar  one  of
         ordinary  language  philosophers  who  resist  the
+
         ordinary  [[language]] [[philosophers]]   who  resist  the
 
         translation  of expressions as `q because p' into `p
 
         translation  of expressions as `q because p' into `p
         ) q' on the  grounds  that  the causal or explanatory
+
         ) q' on the  grounds  that  the [[causal]] or explanatory
 
         meaning    of    "because"    is  lost    in  the
 
         meaning    of    "because"    is  lost    in  the
 
         truth-functional conditional.
 
         truth-functional conditional.
Line 120: Line 120:
 
         deductive relationship  between propositions  within
 
         deductive relationship  between propositions  within
 
         the  Nyaaya  scheme.  It  is the  latter  which  the
 
         the  Nyaaya  scheme.  It  is the  latter  which  the
         received  view upholds: it is the former  which  the
+
         received  [[view]] upholds: it is the former  which  the
 
         incompatibilist vehemently opposes. The issue is not
 
         incompatibilist vehemently opposes. The issue is not
 
         joined, because  surely one can maintain  that there
 
         joined, because  surely one can maintain  that there
Line 127: Line 127:
 
         meaning  of or even  approaches  synonymy  with  the
 
         meaning  of or even  approaches  synonymy  with  the
 
         original.  In sum, the issue  between  the  received
 
         original.  In sum, the issue  between  the  received
         view and the incompatibilist  pivots on the former's
+
         [[view]] and the incompatibilist  pivots on the former's
         willingness to invert the Nyaaya form and read it as
+
         willingness to invert the Nyaaya [[form]] and read it as
 
         a valid deduction  and the latter's insistence  that
 
         a valid deduction  and the latter's insistence  that
         the form cannot be so reversed  without  losing  the
+
         the [[form]] cannot be so reversed  without  losing  the
         special relationship  of the hetu.  Given the merits
+
         special relationship  of the [[hetu]].  Given the [[merits]]
         of both views and given the fact that both positions
+
         of both [[views]] and given the fact that both positions
 
         are  not explicit  contradictories  of one  another,
 
         are  not explicit  contradictories  of one  another,
         there is a way to understand the Nyaaya scheme which
+
         there is a way [[to understand]] the Nyaaya scheme which
 
         allows both sides to have their cake and eat it too.
 
         allows both sides to have their cake and eat it too.
 
         I believe  that  the three-membered  Nyaaya  is best
 
         I believe  that  the three-membered  Nyaaya  is best
Line 143: Line 143:
 
                                 P.185
 
                                 P.185
  
         Norwood  Hansonl  is a pattern  of  reasoning  which
+
         Norwood  Hansonl  is a pattern  of  {{Wiki|reasoning}} which
         leads  from  some  phenomenon  or perception  to  an
+
         leads  from  some  [[phenomenon]] or [[perception]] to  an
         explanatory hypothesis of that phenomenon.  Its form
+
         explanatory {{Wiki|hypothesis}} of that [[phenomenon]].  Its [[form]]
 
         is not truth-functional nor are the relationships of
 
         is not truth-functional nor are the relationships of
 
         that premises completely rulegoverned.  Peirce said,
 
         that premises completely rulegoverned.  Peirce said,
 
         "It must be remembered  that  retroduction, although
 
         "It must be remembered  that  retroduction, although
         hampered very little by logical rules, nevertheless,
+
         hampered very little by [[logical]] rules, nevertheless,
         is logical inference, asserting its conclusion  only
+
         is [[logical]] inference, asserting its conclusion  only
 
         problematically or conjecturally...."(7)
 
         problematically or conjecturally...."(7)
  
 
             Retroduction  does have a recognizable  pattern,
 
             Retroduction  does have a recognizable  pattern,
 
         and indeed  it is very  close  to the three-membered
 
         and indeed  it is very  close  to the three-membered
         syllogism  of Indian logic.  Its form,  according to
+
         [[syllogism]] of [[Indian]] [[logic]].  Its [[form]],  according to
 
         Peirce, is:
 
         Peirce, is:
  
Line 163: Line 163:
 
                 course.
 
                 course.
  
             14. Hence, there is reason to suspect  that P is
+
             14. Hence, there is [[reason]] to suspect  that P is
 
                 true.
 
                 true.
  
Line 173: Line 173:
  
 
         which  is isomorphic  with that of the Nyaaya  (that
 
         which  is isomorphic  with that of the Nyaaya  (that
         is, pak.sa, because  hetu  and  d.r.s.taanta;  hence
+
         is, pak.sa, because  [[hetu]] and  d.r.s.taanta;  hence
 
         there  is evidence  for the pak.sa).  The similarity
 
         there  is evidence  for the pak.sa).  The similarity
 
         (sapak.sa) and dissimilarity  (vipak.sa) cases serve
 
         (sapak.sa) and dissimilarity  (vipak.sa) cases serve
Line 179: Line 179:
 
         justification.
 
         justification.
  
             The  philosopher  of  science,  Norwood  Hanson,
+
             The  [[philosopher]] of  [[science]],  Norwood  Hanson,
         argued that retroduction  was a "logic of discovery"
+
         argued that retroduction  was a "[[logic]] of discovery"
 
         which  led  to  deductive-nomological  explanations.
 
         which  led  to  deductive-nomological  explanations.
 
         Like Peirce, Hanson pointed out that the reversal of
 
         Like Peirce, Hanson pointed out that the reversal of
Line 186: Line 186:
 
         because p', becomes 'p, if p, then q, hence q'.  The
 
         because p', becomes 'p, if p, then q, hence q'.  The
 
         notion of reversal" or inverting" a retroduction  is
 
         notion of reversal" or inverting" a retroduction  is
         not a technique  or rule of formal logic, but rather
+
         not a technique  or rule of formal [[logic]], but rather
         a simple psychological  description  of changing the
+
         a simple [[psychological]] description  of changing the
         order of premises.
+
         [[order]] of premises.
 
[[File:Buddhagarden.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhagarden.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
             If the three-membered  syllogism is retroduction
+
             If the three-membered  [[syllogism]] is retroduction
 
         and    if  a  retroduction    is  part    of    a
 
         and    if  a  retroduction    is  part    of    a
 
         retroductive-deductive  pair, one should  expect  to
 
         retroductive-deductive  pair, one should  expect  to
 
         find internal evidence  for the presence  or absence
 
         find internal evidence  for the presence  or absence
 
         of a deductive fragment. To return to the Nyaaya and
 
         of a deductive fragment. To return to the Nyaaya and
         its commentary on this three-membered  syllogism, is
+
         its commentary on this three-membered  [[syllogism]], is
 
         there  internal  evidence  to  treat  it  as  a
 
         there  internal  evidence  to  treat  it  as  a
 
         retroduction-cum-deduction?  A  crucial  point  of
 
         retroduction-cum-deduction?  A  crucial  point  of
         philological  interpretation  is the function of the
+
         philological  interpretation  is the [[function]] of the
         ablative  "because"    and  the  meaning  of  "hetu"
+
         ablative  "because"    and  the  meaning  of  "[[hetu]]"
         itself. The weakness of the standard view is that it
+
         itself. The weakness of the standard [[view]] is that it
 
         disregards  the  special  features  of the  ablative
 
         disregards  the  special  features  of the  ablative
 
         "because"  and  translates    the  three-membered
 
         "because"  and  translates    the  three-membered
         syllogism as if it contained conditionals. Following
+
         [[syllogism]] as if it contained conditionals. Following
 
         Daye, I suggest  that  that  move  is too hasty, and
 
         Daye, I suggest  that  that  move  is too hasty, and
 
         that  we must regard  the ablative  "because"  as an
 
         that  we must regard  the ablative  "because"  as an
         operator connecting the hetu and d.r.s.taanta to the
+
         operator connecting the [[hetu]] and d.r.s.taanta to the
         thesis.  Since  the Sanskrit  ablative  expresses  a
+
         thesis.  Since  the [[Sanskrit]] ablative  expresses  a
         relation  of  physical  or  conceptual  removal,
+
         relation  of  [[physical]]   or  {{Wiki|conceptual}}   removal,
 
         separation, distinction, or origin, it was  used  to
 
         separation, distinction, or origin, it was  used  to
         convey  the notion of causal explanation.  This fact
+
         convey  the notion of [[causal]] explanation.  This fact
 
         gives  prima facie evidence  for interpreting  it in
 
         gives  prima facie evidence  for interpreting  it in
         the sense  of "a reason  for." Such an understanding
+
         the [[sense]] of "a [[reason]] for." Such an understanding
         is reinforced by the meaning of "hetu," which is the
+
         is reinforced by the meaning of "[[hetu]]," which is the
 
         name of the explanatory part of the three-
 
         name of the explanatory part of the three-
  
 
[[File:Buddhas.jpg|thumb|250px|]]                              P.186
 
[[File:Buddhas.jpg|thumb|250px|]]                              P.186
  
         membered syllogism.  According  to Tachikawa, "hetu"
+
         membered [[syllogism]].  According  to Tachikawa, "[[hetu]]"
 
         primarily  means  'reason'.(8) This is solid  ground
 
         primarily  means  'reason'.(8) This is solid  ground
         for reading  'q because  p' as: 'p is the reason for
+
         for reading  'q because  p' as: 'p is the [[reason]] for
         q', 'p is the explanatory hypothesis for q', or even
+
         q', 'p is the explanatory {{Wiki|hypothesis}} for q', or even
 
         the Peircean 'if p were true, q would be a matter of
 
         the Peircean 'if p were true, q would be a matter of
 
         course'.
 
         course'.
  
 
             Beyond  points  of  translation,  one  of  the
 
             Beyond  points  of  translation,  one  of  the
         strongest  reasons  for  seeing the  three-membered
+
         strongest  [[reasons]] for  [[seeing]] the  three-membered
         syllogism    of    the    Nyaayaprave`sa    as    a
+
         [[syllogism]]   of    the    Nyaayaprave`sa    as    a
         retroduction-deduction  is  the  existence  of  the
+
         retroduction-deduction  is  the  [[existence]] of  the
         five-membered  syllogism  in  the  earlier  Nyaaya
+
         five-membered  [[syllogism]]   in  the  earlier  Nyaaya
         tradition, particularly  the  Nyaaya  Suutra.(9) The
+
         [[tradition]], particularly  the  Nyaaya  Suutra.(9) The
         five-membered  syllogism  of the  Nyaaya  Suutra  is
+
         five-membered  [[syllogism]] of the  Nyaaya  Suutra  is
 
         perfectly  symmetrical  between  its  three  initial
 
         perfectly  symmetrical  between  its  three  initial
 
         retroductive steps and its two culminating deductive
 
         retroductive steps and its two culminating deductive
Line 238: Line 238:
  
 
             15. Thesis(pratij~naa)  for  example, there  is
 
             15. Thesis(pratij~naa)  for  example, there  is
                 fire on the mountain.
+
                 [[fire]] on the mountain.
  
             16. Reason (hetu)- The mountain smokes.
+
             16. [[Reason]] ([[hetu]])- The mountain smokes.
  
 
             17. Exemplification  (d.r.s.taata) -  Wherever
 
             17. Exemplification  (d.r.s.taata) -  Wherever
                 there  is  smoke.  there  is  fire, as  (for
+
                 there  is  smoke.  there  is  [[fire]], as  (for
 
                 example) on the hearth in the kitchen.
 
                 example) on the hearth in the kitchen.
  
             18. Recapitulation of the reason (upanaya) - The
+
             18. Recapitulation of the [[reason]] (upanaya) - The
 
                 mountain smokes.
 
                 mountain smokes.
  
             19. Conclusion (nigamana) There is fire on the
+
             19. Conclusion (nigamana) There is [[fire]] on the
 
                 mountain.
 
                 mountain.
 
[[File:BuddhaTwang.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:BuddhaTwang.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
Line 255: Line 255:
 
         If one were to picture  this pattern as an isosceles
 
         If one were to picture  this pattern as an isosceles
 
         triangle, one side would represent  the retroduction
 
         triangle, one side would represent  the retroduction
         from [15] the pratij~naa  reasoning through the [16]
+
         from [15] the pratij~naa  {{Wiki|reasoning}} through the [16]
         hetu to [17] the d.r.s.taanta, and the opposing side
+
         [[hetu]] to [17] the d.r.s.taanta, and the opposing side
 
         of  the  triangle  would  represent  the  deduction
 
         of  the  triangle  would  represent  the  deduction
 
         beginning with [17] the d.r.s.taanta to [18] upanaya
 
         beginning with [17] the d.r.s.taanta to [18] upanaya
 
         and inferring the nigamana.
 
         and inferring the nigamana.
  
             The French  Indologist  Rene Guenon pointed  out
+
             The French  {{Wiki|Indologist}} Rene Guenon pointed  out
 
         that  after  the appearance  of the  Nyaaya  Suutra,
 
         that  after  the appearance  of the  Nyaaya  Suutra,
 
         there  were two abridged  forms of the five-membered
 
         there  were two abridged  forms of the five-membered
         syllogism, (10) in  which  either  the  first  three
+
         [[syllogism]], (10) in  which  either  the  first  three
 
         [15-17] or the  last  three  [17-19] parts  appeared
 
         [15-17] or the  last  three  [17-19] parts  appeared
 
         alone.  Gutnon  also  pointed  out that  the  latter
 
         alone.  Gutnon  also  pointed  out that  the  latter
         abridgment resembles the syllogism of Aristolle; the
+
         abridgment resembles the [[syllogism]] of Aristolle; the
 
         former  abridgment, of course, is precisely  the one
 
         former  abridgment, of course, is precisely  the one
 
         found in the 6th century  Nyaayaprave`sa  and indeed
 
         found in the 6th century  Nyaayaprave`sa  and indeed
 
         the same smoke-fire example occurs there also. Given
 
         the same smoke-fire example occurs there also. Given
         the  interpretation  I  have  offered,  it  is  not
+
         the  interpretation  I  have  [[offered]],  it  is  not
 
         surprising  that there should be two abridgments  of
 
         surprising  that there should be two abridgments  of
         the five-membered syllogism. One abridgment captures
+
         the five-membered [[syllogism]]. One abridgment captures
 
         the  retroductive  move;  the  second  captures  the
 
         the  retroductive  move;  the  second  captures  the
 
         deductive  move.  Deduction  and  retroduction  are
 
         deductive  move.  Deduction  and  retroduction  are
 
         inversions of one another, and they can be separated
 
         inversions of one another, and they can be separated
 
         by positioning  the  property-locus  statement.  One
 
         by positioning  the  property-locus  statement.  One
         abridgment  reasons from the thesis statement  to an
+
         abridgment  [[reasons]] from the thesis statement  to an
 
         explanatory  generalization;  the  other  abridgment
 
         explanatory  generalization;  the  other  abridgment
 
         deduces  the  thesis  from  the generalization.  The
 
         deduces  the  thesis  from  the generalization.  The
         Buddhist  logicians  Mere quite emphatic about which
+
         [[Buddhist]] [[logicians]] Mere quite emphatic about which
 
         abridgment they favored. The Nyaaya quite explicitly
 
         abridgment they favored. The Nyaaya quite explicitly
 
         says, "We say that these three  statements  make the
 
         says, "We say that these three  statements  make the
         members  of  the  syllogism  and  no  more!  "(11)
+
         members  of  the  [[syllogism]]   and  no  more!  "(11)
 
         Tachikwa's gloss on this statement indicates that it
 
         Tachikwa's gloss on this statement indicates that it
 
         is  an assertion  that  only  three  statements  are
 
         is  an assertion  that  only  three  statements  are
Line 290: Line 290:
 
[[File:Buddhism-2.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhism-2.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
             We may conclude that what "inference"  primarily
 
             We may conclude that what "inference"  primarily
         meant to the Buddhist logicians was "reasoning to an
+
         meant to the [[Buddhist]] [[logicians]] was "{{Wiki|reasoning}} to an
         explanatory causal hypothesis"; however, it would be
+
         explanatory [[causal]] {{Wiki|hypothesis}}"; however, it would be
 
         wrong  to  further  conclude  that  they  had  no
 
         wrong  to  further  conclude  that  they  had  no
         appreciation of the
+
         [[appreciation]] of the
  
 
                                 P.187
 
                                 P.187
  
  
         deductive  abridgment.  To them logic was a means  of
+
         deductive  abridgment.  To them [[logic]] was a means  of
         bringing  others  to  a  recognition  of  particular
+
         bringing  others  to  a  [[recognition]]   of  particular
         statements;  it was  an upaaya, a heuristic  teaching
+
         statements;  it was  an upaaya, a heuristic  [[teaching]]
 
         device.    The  retroductive  abridgment  of  the
 
         device.    The  retroductive  abridgment  of  the
         five-membered  syllogism clearly teaches in the sence
+
         five-membered  [[syllogism]] clearly teaches in the sence
         that it brings the hearer to an awareness of a causal
+
         that it brings the [[hearer]] to an [[awareness]] of a [[causal]]
         or conceptual  connection.  The deductive  abridgment
+
         or {{Wiki|conceptual}} connection.  The deductive  abridgment
         does  not "teach"  in this  sense  because  like  all
+
         does  not "teach"  in this  [[sense]] because  like  all
 
         deductions    its  conclusion  does  not  contain
 
         deductions    its  conclusion  does  not  contain
         information  nor already found in the premises, Thus,
+
         [[information]] nor already found in the premises, [[Thus]],
 
         from  the  standpoint  of an upaaya  the retroductive
 
         from  the  standpoint  of an upaaya  the retroductive
 
         inference  is  enough,  or,  as  the  author  of  the
 
         inference  is  enough,  or,  as  the  author  of  the
 
         Nyaayaprave`sa  put it, "...these  three members make
 
         Nyaayaprave`sa  put it, "...these  three members make
         the [retroductive] syllogism and no more."
+
         the [retroductive] [[syllogism]] and no more."
 
[[File:Buddhism-Mongolia.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhism-Mongolia.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
             A further  point in favour of reading the Nyaaya
 
             A further  point in favour of reading the Nyaaya
 
         inference schema as a retroduction  is that it makes
 
         inference schema as a retroduction  is that it makes
         the  remainder  of the  manual  on logical  methods,
+
         the  remainder  of the  manual  on [[logical]] methods,
 
         especially  the  detailed  sections  on  kinds  of
 
         especially  the  detailed  sections  on  kinds  of
 
         fallacies, more intelligible and enljghtening.  More
 
         fallacies, more intelligible and enljghtening.  More
Line 325: Line 325:
 
         notions  of  an  informal  fallacy.  Fallacies  of
 
         notions  of  an  informal  fallacy.  Fallacies  of
 
         irrelevance  such  as the  ad  hominem  or post  hoc
 
         irrelevance  such  as the  ad  hominem  or post  hoc
         propter  hoc call  attention  to the lack of support
+
         propter  hoc call  [[attention]] to the lack of support
 
         between  premises  and  putative  conclusion.  In
 
         between  premises  and  putative  conclusion.  In
         Buddhist logic the classification  of fallacies does
+
         [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] the classification  of fallacies does
 
         not attempt to circumscribe the ways premises can be
 
         not attempt to circumscribe the ways premises can be
 
         irrelevant;  on the contrary  it fives criteria  for
 
         irrelevant;  on the contrary  it fives criteria  for
Line 333: Line 333:
 
         hypotheses.  This is precisely  what is required for
 
         hypotheses.  This is precisely  what is required for
 
         retroductive  accuracy.  Weak hypotheses  emerge  in
 
         retroductive  accuracy.  Weak hypotheses  emerge  in
         three circumstances: (1) the hetu is unrecognized by
+
         three circumstances: (1) the [[hetu]] is unrecognized by
         proponent or opponent, (2) the hetu is inconclusive,
+
         proponent or opponent, (2) the [[hetu]] is inconclusive,
         or (3) it is contradicted.  Inconclusive  hetus  are
+
         or (3) it is contradicted.  Inconclusive  [[hetus]] are
 
         those  which are not supported  by further  evidence
 
         those  which are not supported  by further  evidence
 
         from  the  similarity  and  dissimilarity  cases;
 
         from  the  similarity  and  dissimilarity  cases;
         contradicted  hetus  are  those  which  prove  the
+
         contradicted  [[hetus]] are  those  which  prove  the
 
         opposite  of the  pak.sa.  Such  a contradiction  is
 
         opposite  of the  pak.sa.  Such  a contradiction  is
 
         established  by deducing the opposite property-locus
 
         established  by deducing the opposite property-locus
         assertion.  A hetu  can fail  to be recognized, that
+
         assertion.  A [[hetu]] can fail  to be recognized, that
         is,  it can fail as a teaching  device by not making
+
         is,  it can fail as a [[teaching]] device by not making
 
         the  auditor  (or speaker) aware  of the  connection
 
         the  auditor  (or speaker) aware  of the  connection
 
         between the assertion  statement  and its warranting
 
         between the assertion  statement  and its warranting
         hetu.  Thus, when hypotheses  fail to be understood,
+
         [[hetu]][[Thus]], when hypotheses  fail to be understood,
         they engender fallacies of recognition, but when they
+
         they engender fallacies of [[recognition]], but when they
 
         fail in evidential  support they engender  fallacies
 
         fail in evidential  support they engender  fallacies
 
         of contradiction  or inconclusivity.  On the  whole,
 
         of contradiction  or inconclusivity.  On the  whole,
Line 352: Line 352:
 
         sophisticated, but also  a commonsensical, means  of
 
         sophisticated, but also  a commonsensical, means  of
 
         evaluating  hypotheses.  It  is  open  textured  as
 
         evaluating  hypotheses.  It  is  open  textured  as
         retroductive reasoning must be, and more importantly
+
         retroductive {{Wiki|reasoning}} must be, and more importantly
 
         it does not attempt (as the Western notion of fallac
 
         it does not attempt (as the Western notion of fallac
         does) to classify fallacious  reasoning as a kind of
+
         does) to classify fallacious  {{Wiki|reasoning}} as a kind of
 
         deductive argument gone awry.
 
         deductive argument gone awry.
 
[[File:Buddhism.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhism.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
             In this paper  I have attempted  to enlarge  the
 
             In this paper  I have attempted  to enlarge  the
         dialogue  about  the  nature  of Buddhist  logic  by
+
         dialogue  about  the  nature  of [[Buddhist]] [[logic]] by
         arguing  that  it is  essentially  retroductive.  As
+
         arguing  that  it is  [[essentially]] retroductive.  As
         philosophers    and  psychologists    continue  to
+
         [[philosophers]]   and  {{Wiki|psychologists}}   continue  to
         investigate  the conceptual  and factual aspects  of
+
         investigate  the {{Wiki|conceptual}} and factual aspects  of
         hypothesis  formation, the study  of Buddhist  logic
+
         {{Wiki|hypothesis}} formation, the study  of [[Buddhist]] [[logic]]
 
         will increase  in importance  because, unlike  other
 
         will increase  in importance  because, unlike  other
         logical  treatises,  the  Nyaayaprave`sa  is  an
+
         [[logical]]   treatises,  the  Nyaayaprave`sa  is  an
 
         historyically  significant  document  about  ways of
 
         historyically  significant  document  about  ways of
         reasoning  and  misreasoning  to  an  explanatory
+
         {{Wiki|reasoning}}   and  misreasoning  to  an  explanatory
         hypothesis.
+
         {{Wiki|hypothesis}}.
  
 
                                 P.188
 
                                 P.188
Line 374: Line 374:
  
 
             1. Daniel H. H.  Ingalls, Material for the Study
 
             1. Daniel H. H.  Ingalls, Material for the Study
         of Navya-Nyaya  Logic, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
+
         of Navya-Nyaya  [[Logic]], Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
         40  (Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1951);
+
         40  ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}:  Harvard  University  Press,  1951);
         Hajime Nakamura, "Buddhist Logic Expounded  by Means
+
         [[Hajime Nakamura]], "[[Buddhist]] [[Logic]] Expounded  by Means
         of  Symbolic  Logic," Indogku  Bukkyogaku  Kenkyu  7
+
         of  [[Symbolic]] [[Logic]]," Indogku  Bukkyogaku  Kenkyu  7
 
         (1958) :  375-395;  J.  F.  Staal,  "Means  of
 
         (1958) :  375-395;  J.  F.  Staal,  "Means  of
         Formalization of Indian and Western Thought," Logic,
+
         Formalization of [[Indian]] and Western [[Thought]]," [[Logic]],
         Metlzodology  and Philosophy of Science, Proceedings
+
         Metlzodology  and [[Philosophy]] of [[Science]], Proceedings
         of the XIIth International  Congress  of Philosophy,
+
         of the XIIth International  Congress  of [[Philosophy]],
 
         Venice,  1958;  H.  Kitagawa,  "A  Note  on  the
 
         Venice,  1958;  H.  Kitagawa,  "A  Note  on  the
         Methodology  in the Study of Indian Logic," Indogaku
+
         Methodology  in the Study of [[Indian]] [[Logic]]," Indogaku
 
         Bukkyogaku  Kenkyu  8  (1960) :  380-390;  S.  S.
 
         Bukkyogaku  Kenkyu  8  (1960) :  380-390;  S.  S.
         Barlingay, A Modern  Introduction  to  Indian  Logic
+
         Barlingay, A Modern  Introduction  to  [[Indian]] [[Logic]]
 
         (Delhi:  National  Publishing  House,  1965) :  A.
 
         (Delhi:  National  Publishing  House,  1965) :  A.
         Charlene S.  McDermott, An Eleventh-Century Buddhist
+
         Charlene S.  McDermott, An Eleventh-Century [[Buddhist]]
         Logic  of  "Exists,  "  Foundations  of  Language,
+
         [[Logic]]   of  "[[Exists]],  "  Foundations  of  [[Language]],
 
         Supplementary Series, vol. 2 (Dordrecht, Holland: D.
 
         Supplementary Series, vol. 2 (Dordrecht, Holland: D.
 
         Reidel,  1970);  B.  K.  Matilal,  The  Navya-Nyaaya
 
         Reidel,  1970);  B.  K.  Matilal,  The  Navya-Nyaaya
         Doctrine  of Negation, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
+
         [[Doctrine]] of Negation, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
         46 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press.  1968): and
+
         46 ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: Harvard University Press.  1968): and
         particularly  Epistemology,  Logic  and  Grammar  in
+
         particularly  {{Wiki|Epistemology}}[[Logic]] and  [[Grammar]] in
         Indian  Philosophical  Analysis,  Janua  Linguarum,
+
         [[Indian]] [[Philosophical]]   Analysis,  Janua  Linguarum,
 
         Series Minor, 111 (Mouton: The Hague, 1971).
 
         Series Minor, 111 (Mouton: The Hague, 1971).
 
[[File:Buddhism47gf.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Buddhism47gf.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
             2.  Douglas Daye, "Metalogical Incompatibilities
 
             2.  Douglas Daye, "Metalogical Incompatibilities
         In  the  Formal  Description  of  Buddhist  Logic
+
         In  the  Formal  Description  of  [[Buddhist]]   [[Logic]]
         (Nyaaya)," Notre  Dame Journal  of Logic  28, no.  2
+
         (Nyaaya)," Notre  Dame Journal  of [[Logic]] 28, no.  2
 
         (1977): 231.
 
         (1977): 231.
  
             3.  Douglas Daye, "Empirical Falsifiability  and
+
             3.  Douglas Daye, "[[Empirical]] Falsifiability  and
 
         the  Frequence  of Dar`sana  Relevance  in the Sixth
 
         the  Frequence  of Dar`sana  Relevance  in the Sixth
         Century Buddhist  Logic of Sankaravamin," Logique et
+
         Century [[Buddhist]] [[Logic]] of Sankaravamin," Logique et
 
         Analyse 86 (June 1979): 221.
 
         Analyse 86 (June 1979): 221.
  
             4.  Douglas Daye, Comparative Issues in Buddhist
+
             4.  Douglas Daye, Comparative Issues in [[Buddhist]]
 
         and  Angle-European  Formal  Logics  (unpublished
 
         and  Angle-European  Formal  Logics  (unpublished
 
         manuscript), p. 121.
 
         manuscript), p. 121.
  
 
             5.  Musashi  Tachikawa, trans., "A Sixth Century
 
             5.  Musashi  Tachikawa, trans., "A Sixth Century
         Manual  of  Indian  Logic  (the  Nyaayaprave`sa) ,"
+
         Manual  of  [[Indian]] [[Logic]] (the  Nyaayaprave`sa) ,"
         Journal of Indian Philosophy 1, no. 2 (1971): 114.
+
         Journal of [[Indian Philosophy]] 1, no. 2 (1971): 114.
  
 
             6. Ibid., p. 115, Norwood R. Hanson, Patterns of
 
             6. Ibid., p. 115, Norwood R. Hanson, Patterns of
         Discovery  (Cambridge: Cambridge  University  Press,
+
         Discovery  ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: {{Wiki|Cambridge}} University  Press,
 
         1958), pp. 93-105.
 
         1958), pp. 93-105.
  
             "Is There A Logic of Discovery," Current  Issues
+
             "Is There A [[Logic]] of Discovery," Current  Issues
         in Philosophy of Science, edited by H.  Fergland and
+
         in [[Philosophy]] of [[Science]], edited by H.  Fergland and
         G.  Maxwell  (New York:  Holt-Rinehart  &  Winston,
+
         G.  Maxwell  ({{Wiki|New York}}:  Holt-Rinehart  &  Winston,
         1961), pp. 20-35. Also Aristotle, Prior Analytics II,
+
         1961), pp. 20-35. Also {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, Prior Analytics II,
 
         25.
 
         25.
 
[[File:BuddhistTriad.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:BuddhistTriad.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
             7.  C.  S.  Peirce, Collected  Works (Cambridge:
+
             7.  C.  S.  Peirce, Collected  Works ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}:
 
         Harvard  University  Press, 1933), vol.  1, p.  188.
 
         Harvard  University  Press, 1933), vol.  1, p.  188.
 
         Also vol. 6, pp. 522-28.
 
         Also vol. 6, pp. 522-28.
Line 431: Line 431:
 
             8. Tachikawa, p. 116.
 
             8. Tachikawa, p. 116.
  
             9.  A.  B.  Keith,  Indian  Logic  and  Atomism
+
             9.  A.  B.  Keith,  [[Indian]] [[Logic]] and  Atomism
 
         (Oxford: 1921), p.  21.  The author dates the Nyaaya
 
         (Oxford: 1921), p.  21.  The author dates the Nyaaya
 
         Suutra at 200-450 A.D.
 
         Suutra at 200-450 A.D.
  
 
             10. Rene Guenon, Introduction generale a l'etude
 
             10. Rene Guenon, Introduction generale a l'etude
         des doctrines hindous(Paris: 1930), pp. 226-227.
+
         des [[doctrines]] hindous(Paris: 1930), pp. 226-227.
  
 
             11. Tachikawa, p. 122.
 
             11. Tachikawa, p. 122.

Revision as of 22:44, 1 September 2013

Bud 0.jpg

The history of Indian logic is usually divided into
        three periods, Old Nyaaya (circa 250 B.C. ) ,
        Buddhist logic (sixth century A.D.) and New Nyaaya.
        The Buddhist logic text, Nyaayaprave`sa
        (Introduction to Logical Methods) , had great
        influence upon Indian and Chinese Buddhism and also
        among the Jains. As a pivotal work, the
        Nyaayaprave`sa has received critical attention from
        historians of religion, philologists, philosophers,
        and logicians. As with all advances in scholarship,
        there is controversy over interpretation, but in the
        case of Buddhist logic, the controversy cuts to the
        very heart of the issue of whether Buddhist logic is
        in any recognizable contemporary sense a "logic."
        The received view holds that Buddhist logic bears
        very close similarities to syllogistic forms and
        that it can be represented and analyzed by standard
        deductive techniques.(1) A much different and
        opposing view has been argued by Professor Douglas
        Daye in a series of papers. Daye maintains that "...
        the descriptive utility of mathematical logic with
        early Nyaaya texts has simply been overrated";(2)
        that although the Nyaaya texts contain metalogical
        rules for evaluating the "legitimacy or
        illegitimacy" of arguments, the distinction between
        validity and invalidity does not apply;(3) that
        Nyaaya models are not inferences but "formalistic
        explanations"; and that "... Buddhist logic is not
        deductive, nor can it be formally valid nor is it an
        inference."(4)

Buddha 2sw.jpg

            The cumulative effect of these claims is to
        assert that Buddhist logic is not a "logic" at all,
        at least not in any sense which is recognized by
        Western philosophers. There is a radical
        incompatibility between the Nyaaya methods of logic
        and those of the Prior Analytics or Principia
        Mathematica. Of course, there will be differences,
        possibly very great differences, between any two
        traditions so diverse as fourth century (B.C.)
        Greece and sixth century (A.D.) India, but are we to
        go so far as to say that the Nyaaya does not contain
        inferences? The radical incompatibility thesis is, I
        maintain, a mistake; moreover, it is a mistake which
        can readily be uncovered by examining the typical
        Nyaaya inference scheme. Of the notion that a Nyaaya
        scheme could be a "formalistic explanation"
        without being an inference, I shall say very little
        because I do not see how anything which functions as
        an explanation could not involve inferences of some
        kind or other. It is important to know whether the
        Nyaaya scheme is deductive or not, and if it is,
        whether all of its parts are essential to the
        deduction. I will demonstrate that there are two
        ways of reading the Nyaaya form: one which is
        straightforwardly deductive and a second which is
        best understood by what the American pragmatist,
        C.S. Peirce, and later Norwood Hanson,
        call "retroduction."

Bud4.jpeg

            To begin with, consider this representative
        example from the Nyaaya:(5)

            1. pak.sa (thesis) Sound is imprrmanrne

            2. hetu (mark or Reason) - Because of its
               property of being produced

                                P.184


            3. d.r.s.taanta (Exemplification)--Whatever is
                produced, is impermanent
            4. sapak.sa (similar case)- As with a pot, and
                so forth
            5. vipak.sa (dissimilar case)- As (not with the
                case) of space, and so forth

            Tachikawa proposes the following scheme for what
        he calls the "three-membered Indian syllogism:(6)

            6. There is property p in locus L
            7. (because) there is property q (in L).
            8. Wherever there is property q, there is
                property p, as in locus w

Buddha 21226.jpg

        Clearly, if this schema is reversed, (8) and (7)
        become premises for a valid deductive inference of
        (6) as the conclusion. The reverse of our example
        becomes an instance of modus ponens.

            9. d.r.s.taanta - Whatever is created is
                impermanent.
            10. hetu - Sound is created.
            11. pak.sa - Sound is impermanent.

            Why is this instance of modus ponens a matter of
        dispute? The incompatibilists point out that the
        relationship between the thesis (pak.sa) and the
        justification (hetu) is always expressed in the
        Sanskrit ablative case and that this relationship
        cannot be represented or translated as the English
        "therefore" (or ergo). Its best translation is
        "because." Thus, for the incompatibilist, the
        primary objection to identifying the Nyaaya scheme
        as a deductive inference is the familiar one of
        ordinary language philosophers who resist the
        translation of expressions as `q because p' into `p
        ) q' on the grounds that the causal or explanatory
        meaning of "because" is lost in the
        truth-functional conditional.

Buddha121xs.JPG

            This objection has force, but one must
        distinguish between the assertion that
        truth-functional connectives preserve or capture the
        meaning of `q because p' and the claim that
        truth-functional connectives can represent a
        deductive relationship between propositions within
        the Nyaaya scheme. It is the latter which the
        received view upholds: it is the former which the
        incompatibilist vehemently opposes. The issue is not
        joined, because surely one can maintain that there
        is a deductive inference in the inversion Nyaaya
        scheme without maintaining that it captures the
        meaning of or even approaches synonymy with the
        original. In sum, the issue between the received
        view and the incompatibilist pivots on the former's
        willingness to invert the Nyaaya form and read it as
        a valid deduction and the latter's insistence that
        the form cannot be so reversed without losing the
        special relationship of the hetu. Given the merits
        of both views and given the fact that both positions
        are not explicit contradictories of one another,
        there is a way to understand the Nyaaya scheme which
        allows both sides to have their cake and eat it too.
        I believe that the three-membered Nyaaya is best
        understood as a retroductivc inference. A
        retroduction, as it has been described by C. S.
        Peirce and

Buddha20i.jpg

                                P.185

        Norwood Hansonl is a pattern of reasoning which
        leads from some phenomenon or perception to an
        explanatory hypothesis of that phenomenon. Its form
        is not truth-functional nor are the relationships of
        that premises completely rulegoverned. Peirce said,
        "It must be remembered that retroduction, although
        hampered very little by logical rules, nevertheless,
        is logical inference, asserting its conclusion only
        problematically or conjecturally...."(7)

            Retroduction does have a recognizable pattern,
        and indeed it is very close to the three-membered
        syllogism of Indian logic. Its form, according to
        Peirce, is:

            12. The surprizing fact Q is observed.

            13. But if P were true, Q would be a matter of
                course.

            14. Hence, there is reason to suspect that P is
                true.

        As a schema, for retroduction we have:

Buddha444.jpg

            (12') q
            (13') q because p
            (14')p

        which is isomorphic with that of the Nyaaya (that
        is, pak.sa, because hetu and d.r.s.taanta; hence
        there is evidence for the pak.sa). The similarity
        (sapak.sa) and dissimilarity (vipak.sa) cases serve
        as further evidence in support of the explanatory
        justification.

            The philosopher of science, Norwood Hanson,
        argued that retroduction was a "logic of discovery"
        which led to deductive-nomological explanations.
        Like Peirce, Hanson pointed out that the reversal of
        a retroduction was a deductive inference 'q, q
        because p', becomes 'p, if p, then q, hence q'. The
        notion of reversal" or inverting" a retroduction is
        not a technique or rule of formal logic, but rather
        a simple psychological description of changing the
        order of premises.

Buddhagarden.jpg

            If the three-membered syllogism is retroduction
        and if a retroduction is part of a
        retroductive-deductive pair, one should expect to
        find internal evidence for the presence or absence
        of a deductive fragment. To return to the Nyaaya and
        its commentary on this three-membered syllogism, is
        there internal evidence to treat it as a
        retroduction-cum-deduction? A crucial point of
        philological interpretation is the function of the
        ablative "because" and the meaning of "hetu"
        itself. The weakness of the standard view is that it
        disregards the special features of the ablative
        "because" and translates the three-membered
        syllogism as if it contained conditionals. Following
        Daye, I suggest that that move is too hasty, and
        that we must regard the ablative "because" as an
        operator connecting the hetu and d.r.s.taanta to the
        thesis. Since the Sanskrit ablative expresses a
        relation of physical or conceptual removal,
        separation, distinction, or origin, it was used to
        convey the notion of causal explanation. This fact
        gives prima facie evidence for interpreting it in
        the sense of "a reason for." Such an understanding
        is reinforced by the meaning of "hetu," which is the
        name of the explanatory part of the three-

Buddhas.jpg
P.186


        membered syllogism. According to Tachikawa, "hetu"
        primarily means 'reason'.(8) This is solid ground
        for reading 'q because p' as: 'p is the reason for
        q', 'p is the explanatory hypothesis for q', or even
        the Peircean 'if p were true, q would be a matter of
        course'.

            Beyond points of translation, one of the
        strongest reasons for seeing the three-membered
        syllogism of the Nyaayaprave`sa as a
        retroduction-deduction is the existence of the
        five-membered syllogism in the earlier Nyaaya
        tradition, particularly the Nyaaya Suutra.(9) The
        five-membered syllogism of the Nyaaya Suutra is
        perfectly symmetrical between its three initial
        retroductive steps and its two culminating deductive
        steps:


            15. Thesis(pratij~naa) for example, there is
                fire on the mountain.

            16. Reason (hetu)- The mountain smokes.

            17. Exemplification (d.r.s.taata) - Wherever
                there is smoke. there is fire, as (for
                example) on the hearth in the kitchen.

            18. Recapitulation of the reason (upanaya) - The
                mountain smokes.

            19. Conclusion (nigamana) There is fire on the
                mountain.

BuddhaTwang.jpg


        If one were to picture this pattern as an isosceles
        triangle, one side would represent the retroduction
        from [15] the pratij~naa reasoning through the [16]
        hetu to [17] the d.r.s.taanta, and the opposing side
        of the triangle would represent the deduction
        beginning with [17] the d.r.s.taanta to [18] upanaya
        and inferring the nigamana.

            The French Indologist Rene Guenon pointed out
        that after the appearance of the Nyaaya Suutra,
        there were two abridged forms of the five-membered
        syllogism, (10) in which either the first three
        [15-17] or the last three [17-19] parts appeared
        alone. Gutnon also pointed out that the latter
        abridgment resembles the syllogism of Aristolle; the
        former abridgment, of course, is precisely the one
        found in the 6th century Nyaayaprave`sa and indeed
        the same smoke-fire example occurs there also. Given
        the interpretation I have offered, it is not
        surprising that there should be two abridgments of
        the five-membered syllogism. One abridgment captures
        the retroductive move; the second captures the
        deductive move. Deduction and retroduction are
        inversions of one another, and they can be separated
        by positioning the property-locus statement. One
        abridgment reasons from the thesis statement to an
        explanatory generalization; the other abridgment
        deduces the thesis from the generalization. The
        Buddhist logicians Mere quite emphatic about which
        abridgment they favored. The Nyaaya quite explicitly
        says, "We say that these three statements make the
        members of the syllogism and no more! "(11)
        Tachikwa's gloss on this statement indicates that it
        is an assertion that only three statements are
        necessary for an inference.

Buddhism-2.jpg

            We may conclude that what "inference" primarily
        meant to the Buddhist logicians was "reasoning to an
        explanatory causal hypothesis"; however, it would be
        wrong to further conclude that they had no
        appreciation of the

                                P.187


        deductive abridgment. To them logic was a means of
        bringing others to a recognition of particular
        statements; it was an upaaya, a heuristic teaching
        device. The retroductive abridgment of the
        five-membered syllogism clearly teaches in the sence
        that it brings the hearer to an awareness of a causal
        or conceptual connection. The deductive abridgment
        does not "teach" in this sense because like all
        deductions its conclusion does not contain
        information nor already found in the premises, Thus,
        from the standpoint of an upaaya the retroductive
        inference is enough, or, as the author of the
        Nyaayaprave`sa put it, "...these three members make
        the [retroductive] syllogism and no more."

Buddhism-Mongolia.jpg

            A further point in favour of reading the Nyaaya
        inference schema as a retroduction is that it makes
        the remainder of the manual on logical methods,
        especially the detailed sections on kinds of
        fallacies, more intelligible and enljghtening. More
        than two thirds of the text covers identification
        and classification of fallacies, but none bear any
        resemblance to the formal fallacies of deduction
        such as affirming the consequent or denying the
        antecedent, nor does the system resemble Western
        notions of an informal fallacy. Fallacies of
        irrelevance such as the ad hominem or post hoc
        propter hoc call attention to the lack of support
        between premises and putative conclusion. In
        Buddhist logic the classification of fallacies does
        not attempt to circumscribe the ways premises can be
        irrelevant; on the contrary it fives criteria for
        grading the strength or weakness of the explanatory
        hypotheses. This is precisely what is required for
        retroductive accuracy. Weak hypotheses emerge in
        three circumstances: (1) the hetu is unrecognized by
        proponent or opponent, (2) the hetu is inconclusive,
        or (3) it is contradicted. Inconclusive hetus are
        those which are not supported by further evidence
        from the similarity and dissimilarity cases;
        contradicted hetus are those which prove the
        opposite of the pak.sa. Such a contradiction is
        established by deducing the opposite property-locus
        assertion. A hetu can fail to be recognized, that
        is, it can fail as a teaching device by not making
        the auditor (or speaker) aware of the connection
        between the assertion statement and its warranting
        hetu. Thus, when hypotheses fail to be understood,
        they engender fallacies of recognition, but when they
        fail in evidential support they engender fallacies
        of contradiction or inconclusivity. On the whole,
        this classification of fallacies reflects a
        sophisticated, but also a commonsensical, means of
        evaluating hypotheses. It is open textured as
        retroductive reasoning must be, and more importantly
        it does not attempt (as the Western notion of fallac
        does) to classify fallacious reasoning as a kind of
        deductive argument gone awry.

Buddhism.jpg

            In this paper I have attempted to enlarge the
        dialogue about the nature of Buddhist logic by
        arguing that it is essentially retroductive. As
        philosophers and psychologists continue to
        investigate the conceptual and factual aspects of
        hypothesis formation, the study of Buddhist logic
        will increase in importance because, unlike other
        logical treatises, the Nyaayaprave`sa is an
        historyically significant document about ways of
        reasoning and misreasoning to an explanatory
        hypothesis.

                                P.188

        NOTES

            1. Daniel H. H. Ingalls, Material for the Study
        of Navya-Nyaya Logic, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
        40 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1951);
        Hajime Nakamura, "Buddhist Logic Expounded by Means
        of Symbolic Logic," Indogku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu 7
        (1958) : 375-395; J. F. Staal, "Means of
        Formalization of Indian and Western Thought," Logic,
        Metlzodology and Philosophy of Science, Proceedings
        of the XIIth International Congress of Philosophy,
        Venice, 1958; H. Kitagawa, "A Note on the
        Methodology in the Study of Indian Logic," Indogaku
        Bukkyogaku Kenkyu 8 (1960) : 380-390; S. S.
        Barlingay, A Modern Introduction to Indian Logic
        (Delhi: National Publishing House, 1965) : A.
        Charlene S. McDermott, An Eleventh-Century Buddhist
        Logic of "Exists, " Foundations of Language,
        Supplementary Series, vol. 2 (Dordrecht, Holland: D.
        Reidel, 1970); B. K. Matilal, The Navya-Nyaaya
        Doctrine of Negation, Harvard Oriental Series, vol.
        46 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 1968): and
        particularly Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in
        Indian Philosophical Analysis, Janua Linguarum,
        Series Minor, 111 (Mouton: The Hague, 1971).

Buddhism47gf.jpg

            2. Douglas Daye, "Metalogical Incompatibilities
        In the Formal Description of Buddhist Logic
        (Nyaaya)," Notre Dame Journal of Logic 28, no. 2
        (1977): 231.

            3. Douglas Daye, "Empirical Falsifiability and
        the Frequence of Dar`sana Relevance in the Sixth
        Century Buddhist Logic of Sankaravamin," Logique et
        Analyse 86 (June 1979): 221.

            4. Douglas Daye, Comparative Issues in Buddhist
        and Angle-European Formal Logics (unpublished
        manuscript), p. 121.

            5. Musashi Tachikawa, trans., "A Sixth Century
        Manual of Indian Logic (the Nyaayaprave`sa) ,"
        Journal of Indian Philosophy 1, no. 2 (1971): 114.

            6. Ibid., p. 115, Norwood R. Hanson, Patterns of
        Discovery (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
        1958), pp. 93-105.

            "Is There A Logic of Discovery," Current Issues
        in Philosophy of Science, edited by H. Fergland and
        G. Maxwell (New York: Holt-Rinehart & Winston,
        1961), pp. 20-35. Also Aristotle, Prior Analytics II,
        25.

BuddhistTriad.JPG

            7. C. S. Peirce, Collected Works (Cambridge:
        Harvard University Press, 1933), vol. 1, p. 188.
        Also vol. 6, pp. 522-28.

            8. Tachikawa, p. 116.

            9. A. B. Keith, Indian Logic and Atomism
        (Oxford: 1921), p. 21. The author dates the Nyaaya
        Suutra at 200-450 A.D.

            10. Rene Guenon, Introduction generale a l'etude
        des doctrines hindous(Paris: 1930), pp. 226-227.

            11. Tachikawa, p. 122.

Source

ccbs.ntu.edu.tw