Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "IMAGE OF TRUTH IN TRADITIONAL INDIAN PHILOSOPHY"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " N.A. Kanaeva Cathedra of the History of Philosophy Department of Philosophy National Research University “Higher School of Economics” Maliy Tryehsvyatitelsky Pereu...")
 
 
Line 7: Line 7:
 
N.A. Kanaeva  
 
N.A. Kanaeva  
  
Cathedra of the History of Philosophy Department of Philosophy National Research University “Higher School of Economics” Maliy Tryehsvyatitelsky Pereulok,  
+
Cathedra of the History of [[Philosophy]] Department of [[Philosophy]] National Research {{Wiki|University}} “Higher School of {{Wiki|Economics}}” Maliy Tryehsvyatitelsky Pereulok,  
  
  
  
  
Truth is one of the key values in Western culture, and in the History of Western Philosophy it had different images. The position of truth in the History of Indian Philosophy was similar. But sometimes in India it is very difficult to retrace the way from the word ‘truth’ to the philosophical category. In this article are traced main lines of discussions about the truth and principal senses of Indian terms (satya, jñāna, Dharma, prāmāхya). Buddhists were the  
+
[[Truth is one]] of the key values in {{Wiki|Western culture}}, and in the History of {{Wiki|Western Philosophy}} it had different images. The position of [[truth]] in the History of [[Indian Philosophy]] was similar. But sometimes in [[India]] it is very difficult to retrace the way from the [[word]] ‘[[truth]]’ to the [[philosophical]] category. In this article are traced main lines of discussions about the [[truth]] and [[principal]] [[senses]] of [[Indian]] terms ([[satya]], [[jñāna]], [[Dharma]], prāmāхya). [[Buddhists]] were the  
  
firsts who introduced the concept of truth, originally in a form of the Four noble truths doctrine then as Mahayana concept of the two truths (conventional and absolute). In Indian tradition, as well as in Western philosophy, truth was considered differently in existential, moral, ontological, soteriological, epistemological and logical perspectives. Indians also distinguished between inferential and semantic concepts of truth. From Western point of view their aspiration to build a theory of the World, which will explain the existence of its different natural and supernatural levels, which are cognizable by rational and super-rational means, brought Indians to paradoxical, contradictory results. Typical example of such contradictory theory of truth can be  
+
firsts who introduced the {{Wiki|concept}} of [[truth]], originally in a [[form]] of the [[Four noble truths]] [[doctrine]] then as [[Mahayana]] {{Wiki|concept}} of the [[two truths]] ([[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] and [[absolute]]). In [[Indian tradition]], as well as in {{Wiki|Western philosophy}}, [[truth]] was considered differently in [[existential]], [[moral]], [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]], [[soteriological]], [[epistemological]] and [[logical]] perspectives. {{Wiki|Indians}} also {{Wiki|distinguished}} between inferential and [[Wikipedia:Semantics|semantic]] [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of [[truth]]. From [[Western]] point of view their [[aspiration]] [[to build]] a {{Wiki|theory}} of the [[World]], which will explain the [[existence]] of its different natural and [[supernatural]] levels, which are cognizable by [[rational]] and super-rational means, brought {{Wiki|Indians}} to {{Wiki|paradoxical}}, [[contradictory]] results. Typical example of such [[contradictory]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[truth]] can be  
  
found in Jaina relative truth doctrine about impermanent and pluralistic reality (syādvāda or anekāntavāda). Key words: cognitive practice, epistemological truth, Indian epistemology, logical truth, requirements for truth, satya, stratification of being, truth in Indian philosophy.  
+
found in [[Jaina]] [[relative truth]] [[doctrine]] about [[impermanent]] and pluralistic [[reality]] ([[syādvāda]] or [[anekāntavāda]]). Key words: [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] practice, [[epistemological]] [[truth]], [[Indian]] epistemology, [[logical]] [[truth]], requirements for [[truth]], [[satya]], stratification of being, [[truth]] in [[Indian philosophy]].  
In Western culture truth is considered to be the ideal of cognition and as one of its basic values. In the History of Western Philosophy truth as well as other cultural values appeared in different images. In Antiquity it was viewed like Good, being (Plato, Aristotle), like ideal of inquiry and the way of  
+
In {{Wiki|Western culture}} [[truth]] is considered to be the {{Wiki|ideal}} of [[cognition]] and as one of its basic values. In the History of {{Wiki|Western Philosophy}} [[truth]] as well as other {{Wiki|cultural}} values appeared in different images. In Antiquity it was viewed like Good, being ({{Wiki|Plato}}, {{Wiki|Aristotle}}), like {{Wiki|ideal}} of inquiry and the way of  
  
its attainment or proving [1. C. 323] (in modern epistemology), like meanings of propositions (in Logic), the logical ontology (in ‘semantic conception of truth’ of A. Tarski) or even superfluous property of the propositions (in deflationary conception of truth by A. Ayer). Among current theories of truth one can choose between the correspondence theory, conventional and coherence theories of truth. Historically philosophers discussed the ideas of absolute truth and relative one, an empirical and theoretical truth, and now more frequently we are even hearing that notion ‘truth’ is not really a productive concept  
+
its [[attainment]] or proving [1. C. 323] (in {{Wiki|modern}} epistemology), like meanings of propositions (in [[Logic]]), the [[logical]] {{Wiki|ontology}} (in ‘[[Wikipedia:Semantics|semantic]] {{Wiki|conception}} of [[truth]]’ of A. Tarski) or even superfluous property of the propositions (in deflationary {{Wiki|conception}} of [[truth]] by A. Ayer). Among current theories of [[truth]] one can choose between the correspondence {{Wiki|theory}}, [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] and coherence theories of [[truth]]. Historically [[philosophers]] discussed the [[ideas]] of [[absolute truth]] and [[relative]] one, an [[empirical]] and {{Wiki|theoretical}} [[truth]], and now more frequently we are even hearing that notion ‘[[truth]]’ is not really a {{Wiki|productive}} {{Wiki|concept}}
  
and so there is no need in this notion at all. This list of the truth’s images transformations in the history of Western Philosophy is a vindication of its innate pluralism in comprehension and it compels us to perceive the truth pluralism as philosophical norm [2. C. 50]. Truth in India was also very significant category, but along of original character of Indian thought the word ‘truth’ had its own way for transforming to the philosophical category. Sometimes it is very difficult to retrace this transformation for the reason that truth in Paхуitas (1) discussions had divers names and sometimes wasn’t named explicitly at all. But it is necessary to identify the meaning of the Indian philosophers’ discussions as the discussions about truth, because this meaning provides understand
+
and so there is no need in this notion at all. This list of the truth’s images transformations in the history of {{Wiki|Western Philosophy}} is a vindication of its innate [[pluralism]] in [[comprehension]] and it compels us to {{Wiki|perceive}} the [[truth]] [[pluralism]] as [[philosophical]] norm [2. C. 50]. [[Truth]] in [[India]] was also very significant category, but along of original [[character]] of [[Indian]] [[thought]] the [[word]] ‘[[truth]]’ had its [[own]] way for [[transforming]] to the [[philosophical]] category. Sometimes it is very difficult to retrace this [[transformation]] for the [[reason]] that [[truth]] in Paхуitas (1) discussions had divers names and sometimes wasn’t named explicitly at all. But it is necessary to identify the meaning of the [[Indian]] [[philosophers]]’ discussions as the discussions about [[truth]], because this meaning provides understand
  
  
ing of the level Indian theoretical thought as very high and it helps to see the peculiarity of Indian philosophy. Such reasons became the foundations for the choice of our topic of study. I am planning to show the beginnings of truth question in Indian philosophy and how Indian thinkers began to use term ‘truth’ as the philosophical category. I’ll try to fetch out main lines of discussions about truth and principal senses of the term which are comparable with Western ones. Basic method of my research will be semantic analysis of the pre-philosophical and philosophical texts in Sanskrit where are present  
+
ing of the level [[Indian]] {{Wiki|theoretical}} [[thought]] as very high and it helps to see the peculiarity of [[Indian philosophy]]. Such [[reasons]] became the foundations for the choice of our topic of study. I am planning to show the beginnings of [[truth]] question in [[Indian philosophy]] and how [[Indian]] thinkers began to use term ‘[[truth]]’ as the [[philosophical]] category. I’ll try to fetch out main lines of discussions about [[truth]] and [[principal]] [[senses]] of the term which are comparable with [[Western]] ones. Basic method of my research will be [[Wikipedia:Semantics|semantic]] analysis of the pre-philosophical and [[philosophical]] texts in [[Sanskrit]] where are {{Wiki|present}}
  
different conceptions associated with the terms indicating truth.  Most correlative with term for ‘truth’ in Sanskrit is word ‘satya’. It was derived from ‘sat’ — ‘being’, ‘existing’. ‘good’, ‘right’, ‘venerable’, ‘reality’, ‘a sage’ and so on [3. P. 1134] and inherited from ‘sat’ some meanings: ‘truth’, ‘reality’, ‘entity’. They use ‘satya’ also as adjectival words: ‘true’, ‘real’, ‘actual’, ‘genuine’, ‘truthful’, ‘successful’, ‘pure’, ‘virtuous’, ‘good’,  
+
different conceptions associated with the terms indicating [[truth]].  Most correlative with term for ‘[[truth]]’ in [[Sanskrit]] is [[word]] ‘[[satya]]’. It was derived from ‘sat’ — ‘being’, ‘[[existing]]’. ‘good’, ‘right’, ‘[[venerable]]’, ‘[[reality]]’, ‘a [[Wikipedia:Sage (sophos|sage]]’ and so on [3. P. 1134] and inherited from ‘sat’ some meanings: ‘[[truth]]’, ‘[[reality]]’, ‘[[entity]]’. They use ‘[[satya]]’ also as adjectival words: ‘true’, ‘real’, ‘actual’, ‘genuine’, ‘truthful’, ‘successful’, ‘[[pure]]’, ‘[[virtuous]]’, ‘good’,  
  
‘valid’ an so on [3. P. 1135]. Word satya was employed in vedic literature from the Ancient time. иgveda teems with derivatives from satya, Upanisads and epic poems ‘Mahābhārata’ and ‘Rāmāyaхa’ include set of names and epithets for heroes which are secondary from ‘satya’ like Satyavatī (mother of Vyāsa), satyā (epithets of Durgā and Sitā), in purāхas (2) highest sky in the world structure, Brahma loka, was named Satya-loka (Sky of truth) and they told about  
+
‘valid’ an so on [3. P. 1135]. [[Word]] [[satya]] was employed in [[vedic literature]] from the [[Ancient]] time. иgveda teems with derivatives from [[satya]], Upanisads and {{Wiki|epic}} [[poems]] ‘[[Mahābhārata]]’ and ‘Rāmāyaхa’ include set of names and {{Wiki|epithets}} for heroes which are secondary from ‘[[satya]]’ like [[Satyavatī]] (mother of [[Vyāsa]]), satyā ({{Wiki|epithets}} of Durgā and [[Sitā]]), in purāхas (2) [[highest]] sky in the [[world]] {{Wiki|structure}}, [[Brahma loka]], was named [[Satya-loka]] (Sky of [[truth]]) and they told about  
  
Satya-yuga (Golden age of truth and purity). Thanks to Buddhists word ‘satya’ became the philosophical category. They were the first who suggested their concepts of truth. Brahmans had no need in satyacategory, because they had dharma-category. Dharma was universal category and it was signify the universal law, World order, religion, moral prescriptions, status rules, principles of law, various kinds of systematical teachings, Good etc. Dharma-universalia has  
+
[[Satya-yuga]] ([[Golden age]] of [[truth]] and [[purity]]). Thanks to [[Buddhists]] [[word]] ‘[[satya]]’ became the [[philosophical]] category. They were the first who suggested their [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of [[truth]]. [[Brahmans]] had no need in satyacategory, because they had dharma-category. [[Dharma]] was [[universal]] category and it was signify the [[universal law]], [[World]] order, [[religion]], [[moral]] prescriptions, {{Wiki|status}} {{Wiki|rules}}, {{Wiki|principles}} of law, various kinds of systematical teachings, Good etc. Dharma-universalia has  
  
its roots in Vedic religion (3) and for this reason it acquired religious, sacral character. So meanings ‘reality’ and ‘truth’ were attributed to word ‘Dharma’. So it was impossible for Brahmins to ask any questions about validity of Dharma and they had no need in its rational justification. Vedic religion is a belief not only in the pantheon of thousands gods but in the Vedic language, Sanskrit, as in force of World’s creation. Belief in Dharma as  
+
its [[roots]] in {{Wiki|Vedic}} [[religion]] (3) and for this [[reason]] it acquired [[religious]], [[sacral]] [[character]]. So meanings ‘[[reality]]’ and ‘[[truth]]’ were attributed to [[word]] ‘[[Dharma]]’. So it was impossible for [[Brahmins]] to ask any questions about validity of [[Dharma]] and they had no need in its [[rational]] {{Wiki|justification}}. {{Wiki|Vedic}} [[religion]] is a [[belief]] not only in the [[pantheon]] of thousands [[gods]] but in the {{Wiki|Vedic}} [[language]], [[Sanskrit]], as in force of World’s creation. [[Belief]] in [[Dharma]] as  
  
the embodied eternal word of Vedas (śabda) was one of the conditions for using the ‘dharma’ as ‘truth’. It would be tautology for Brahmins to talk about truthfulness of Dharma in their sacred contexts. Brahmanical Dharma was struck by śramaхas and Buddhists were among them. Buddhists brought up the issue of truthfulness of Brahmanical Dharma as well as the issue of the validity of the instruments for its acknowledgment, which were enumerated in Brāhmaхas and  
+
the [[embodied]] eternal [[word]] of [[Vedas]] ([[śabda]]) was one of the [[conditions]] for using the ‘[[dharma]]’ as ‘[[truth]]’. It would be [[Wikipedia:Tautology (logic)|tautology]] for [[Brahmins]] to talk about [[truthfulness]] of [[Dharma]] in their [[sacred]] contexts. [[Brahmanical]] [[Dharma]] was struck by śramaхas and [[Buddhists]] were among them. [[Buddhists]] brought up the issue of [[truthfulness]] of [[Brahmanical]] [[Dharma]] as well as the issue of the validity of the instruments for its [[acknowledgment]], which were enumerated in Brāhmaхas and  
  
Upaniщads. It was historical irony that śramaхas for the disavowal of Brahmanism employed the same theory of dialectics (theory of public debates or — in modern terms — theory of argumentation) which was originally elaborated in Brahmanical schools. In Brāhmaхas and Upaniщads dialectics appeared under the name vākovākya (the art to ask questions) [4. P. 6], and in smзti-literature it was named ānvīkщikī (consideration, clarification, research, analysis) [5. P. 792]. Ānvīkщikī didn’t employ dialectics for the solution of metaphysical problems and justification of those solutions before the birth of the philosophical reflection of World and human life in V AD.  
+
Upaniщads. It was historical irony that śramaхas for the disavowal of [[Brahmanism]] employed the same {{Wiki|theory}} of [[dialectics]] ({{Wiki|theory}} of public [[debates]] or — in {{Wiki|modern}} terms — {{Wiki|theory}} of {{Wiki|argumentation}}) which was originally elaborated in [[Brahmanical]] schools. In Brāhmaхas and Upaniщads [[dialectics]] appeared under the [[name]] vākovākya (the [[art]] to ask questions) [4. P. 6], and in smзti-literature it was named ānvīkщikī ([[consideration]], clarification, research, analysis) [5. P. 792]. Ānvīkщikī didn’t employ [[dialectics]] for the {{Wiki|solution}} of [[metaphysical]] problems and {{Wiki|justification}} of those solutions before the [[birth]] of the [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|reflection}} of [[World]] and [[Wikipedia:Human life|human life]] in V AD.  
  
  
Brahmins applied ānvīkщikī to discussions about special issues of theology, eristic, principles of law and medicine in their professional schools. This Brahmanical tool Śramaхas began to use against them for disestablishment of Brahmanical pre-philosophical ideology and so they demonstrated themselves as match opponents for Brahmins. Why are we talking about Buddhists as the beginners of truth conceptualization? Buddhists were the firsts who identified their own (not Brahmanical) Dharma with satya and proposed two theories of truth at once. The first one we find already in earliest Buddha’s sermons about  
+
[[Brahmins]] applied ānvīkщikī to discussions about special issues of {{Wiki|theology}}, eristic, {{Wiki|principles}} of law and [[medicine]] in their professional schools. This [[Brahmanical]] tool Śramaхas began to use against them for disestablishment of [[Brahmanical]] pre-philosophical ideology and so they demonstrated themselves as match opponents for [[Brahmins]]. Why are we talking about [[Buddhists]] as the beginners of [[truth]] [[conceptualization]]? [[Buddhists]] were the firsts who identified their [[own]] (not [[Brahmanical]]) [[Dharma]] with [[satya]] and proposed two theories of [[truth]] at once. The first one we find already in earliest [[Buddha’s]] [[sermons]] about  
  
Four noble truths, the second one is two truths theory. It was created by early Buddhists schools while later scholars subscribed it to Siddhartha Gautama himself (4). According to L. de la Vallée Poussin in Chinese schools of Buddhism were elaborated theories in which the correlations of two and four truths was set down [6. P. 159—187]. The Doctrine of Four noble truths not only articulates sense of each ‘truths’ but also explains how to reach their realization. The first Buddha’s sermon (according to ‘Dhamma-cakka-ppavatana-sutta’) stated that the first truth (about suffering) must be understood completely, the second one (about thirst) must be helpful for refusing from thirst, the third one (about nirvāхa) must be attained and the fourth one  
+
[[Four noble truths]], the second one is [[two truths]] {{Wiki|theory}}. It was created by early [[Buddhists]] schools while later [[scholars]] subscribed it to [[Siddhartha Gautama]] himself (4). According to L. de la [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Vallée Poussin]] in {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[schools of Buddhism]] were elaborated theories in which the correlations of two and [[four truths]] was set down [6. P. 159—187]. The [[Doctrine]] of [[Four noble truths]] not only articulates [[sense]] of each ‘[[truths]]’ but also explains how to reach their [[realization]]. The first [[Buddha’s]] {{Wiki|sermon}} (according to ‘Dhamma-cakka-ppavatana-sutta’) stated that the [[first truth]] (about [[suffering]]) must be understood completely, the second one (about [[thirst]]) must be helpful for refusing from [[thirst]], the third one (about nirvāхa) must be [[attained]] and [[the fourth]] one  
  
(about way) ought to be put into the practice. In ‘Sa#yuttanikāya’ (LVI. 30) and ‘Visuddhimagga’ (XVI. 84) process of realization of the four truths recieved some different features, but it was described in the first sermon too. Two ways of the Truths’ realization (sacca-$āхa) were told in those texts: understanding (anubodha-$āхa) and penetration (paсivedha-$āхa). Understanding is mundane (lokiya) knowledge and it aids to drop suffering; penetration is super-mundane (lokuttara) knowledge and it refers to cessation of suffering and realization of all four truths at the same moment. The doctrine of Four noble truths have four senses in one: an existential (because they all are serving to human existence), moral (because they are imperatives for a good  
+
(about way) ought to be put into the practice. In ‘Sa#yuttanikāya’ (LVI. 30) and ‘[[Visuddhimagga]]’ (XVI. 84) process of [[realization]] of the [[four truths]] recieved some different features, but it was described in the [[first sermon]] too. Two ways of the [[Truths]]’ [[realization]] (sacca-$āхa) were told in those texts: [[understanding]] (anubodha-$āхa) and [[penetration]] (paсivedha-$āхa). [[Understanding]] is [[mundane]] ([[lokiya]]) [[knowledge]] and it aids to drop [[suffering]]; [[penetration]] is super-mundane ([[lokuttara]]) [[knowledge]] and it refers to [[cessation of suffering]] and [[realization]] of all [[four truths]] at the same [[moment]]. The [[doctrine]] of [[Four noble truths]] have four [[senses]] in one: an [[existential]] (because they all are serving to [[human existence]]), [[moral]] (because they are imperatives for a good  
  
behavior), ontological (because they distinguished levels of being — lower, with suffering, and higher, without suffering) and soteriological one (for they all show the way to the salvation). Those senses were also the points of bifurcation in Buddhists Philosophy: each of them was the beginning for new conceptions of truth which entered in the whole Indian tradition of Philosophical thought. Doctrine of two truths became the logical corollary from the primary stratification of being in the tenet of Four truths. It is also acquired epistemological sense. In epistemological frame term ‘truth’ is equivalent to term ‘knowledge’ (in Pali — $āхa, in Sanskrit — j$āna). In doctrine of two truths Buddhists distinguished ontological and epistemological senses.  
+
{{Wiki|behavior}}), [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] (because they {{Wiki|distinguished}} levels of being — lower, with [[suffering]], and higher, without [[suffering]]) and [[soteriological]] one (for they all show the way to the {{Wiki|salvation}}). Those [[senses]] were also the points of [[bifurcation]] in [[Buddhists]] [[Philosophy]]: each of them was the beginning for new conceptions of [[truth]] which entered in the whole [[Indian tradition]] of [[Philosophical]] [[thought]]. [[Doctrine]] of [[two truths]] became the [[logical]] corollary from the primary stratification of being in the [[tenet]] of [[Four truths]]. It is also acquired [[epistemological]] [[sense]]. In [[epistemological]] frame term ‘[[truth]]’ is {{Wiki|equivalent}} to term ‘[[knowledge]]’ (in [[Pali ]]— $āхa, in [[Sanskrit]] — j$āna). In [[doctrine]] of [[two truths]] [[Buddhists]] {{Wiki|distinguished}} [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]] and [[epistemological]] [[senses]].  
  
Existence of two levels of reality they fixed in special terms: higher being (paramārtha-sat) and lower being (vyavahārika-sat), and they validated them by designation of two correlative kinds of truths: higher truth (paramārtha-satya) and lower one (vyavahārika-satya). Being heavy at odds with validity of supernatural reality Buddhists provoked variety conceptions about the structure and knowability of that reality. Later this Buddhist stratification of reality in two levels was adopted in Vedānta (5). In ‘Abhidharmakośa’ by Vasubandhu quite different conceptions of reality by Sarvāstivādins, Sautrāntikas  
+
[[Existence]] of two levels of [[reality]] they fixed in special terms: higher being (paramārtha-sat) and lower being (vyavahārika-sat), and they validated them by designation of two correlative kinds of [[truths]]: [[higher truth]] ([[paramārtha-satya]]) and lower one (vyavahārika-satya). Being heavy at odds with validity of [[supernatural]] [[reality]] [[Buddhists]] provoked variety conceptions about the {{Wiki|structure}} and knowability of that [[reality]]. Later this [[Buddhist]] stratification of [[reality]] in two levels was adopted in [[Wikipedia:Vedanta|Vedānta]] (5). In ‘[[Abhidharmakośa]]’ by [[Vasubandhu]] quite different conceptions of [[reality]] by [[Sarvāstivādins]], [[Sautrāntikas]]
  
  
and Vaibhāщikās are presented. In realistic Sarvāstivādins ontology higher reality was explained as ultimate truth “consists of irreducible spatial units” (paramāхu), which exist the only moment (kщaхa), and of “irreducible temporal units (e.g., point-instant consciousnesses) of the five basic categories”; lower reality was explained as the conventional truth “consists of reducible spatial wholes or temporal continua” [7]. Sautrāntikas placed in higher  
+
and Vaibhāщikās are presented. In {{Wiki|realistic}} [[Sarvāstivādins]] {{Wiki|ontology}} [[higher reality]] was explained as [[ultimate truth]] “consists of irreducible spatial units” (paramāхu), which [[exist]] the only [[moment]] (kщaхa), and of “irreducible {{Wiki|temporal}} units (e.g., point-instant [[consciousnesses]]) of the five basic categories”; lower [[reality]] was explained as the [[conventional truth]] “consists of reducible spatial wholes or {{Wiki|temporal}} continua” [7]. [[Sautrāntikas]] placed in [[higher reality]] the [[essences]] of some moments ([[dharmas]]) of [[consciousness]] flow ([[dravyasat]]) and other [[dharmas]], which they named unreal (praj$āptisat), they regarded as lower [[reality]] [8. C. 625]. Their {{Wiki|conception}} of two [[realities]] developed by [[Yogacārins]] [[Dignāga]], [[Dharmakīrti]] and [[Dharmottara]] in {{Wiki|conception}} of particularia (svalakщaхa) and universalia (sāmānya-lakщaхa) [9. C. 182]. And when [[Yogacārins]] came in with [[development]] of epistemology and [[logic]] of their [[own]], they introduced in [[Buddhist ontology]] {{Wiki|de facto}} the third, {{Wiki|ideal}} [[reality]]: the [[world]] of [[thought]], “where there is no Matter at all, there are only [[Ideas]]” [10. P.  
reality the essences of some moments (dharmas) of consciousness flow (dravyasat) and other dharmas, which they named unreal (praj$āptisat), they regarded as lower reality [8. C. 625]. Their conception of two realities developed by Yogacārins Dignāga, Dharmakīrti and Dharmottara in conception of particularia (svalakщaхa) and universalia (sāmānya-lakщaхa) [9. C. 182]. And when Yogacārins came in with development of epistemology and logic of their own, they introduced in Buddhist ontology de facto the third, ideal reality: the world of thought, “where there is no Matter at all, there are only Ideas” [10. P.  
 
  
509]. One may read background for Buddhist conception of two truths in such Brahmanical texts like ‘Muхуakopaniщada’ and others in which two kinds of knowledge, higher and lower (parā caivāparā), mentioned. But in ‘Muхуakopaniщada’ (III. 2.4-6) and in other texts the old, Vedic knowledge is opposed to the new post-Vedic knowledge (Atman comprehension, which ascetics-зщi achieve by yoga and saпnyāsa). From this fact another reason and another goal for the conception of two truths follow. World pictures in four Vedas and in Upaniщadas were different, but Brahmins couldn’t say that first of them was a  
+
509]. One may read background for [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|conception}} of [[two truths]] in such [[Brahmanical]] texts like ‘Muхуakopaniщada’ and others in which two kinds of [[knowledge]], higher and lower (parā caivāparā), mentioned. But in ‘Muхуakopaniщada’ (III. 2.4-6) and in other texts the old, {{Wiki|Vedic}} [[knowledge]] is opposed to the new post-Vedic [[knowledge]] ([[Atman]] [[comprehension]], which ascetics-зщi achieve by [[yoga]] and saпnyāsa). From this fact another [[reason]] and another goal for the {{Wiki|conception}} of [[two truths]] follow. [[World]] pictures in four [[Vedas]] and in Upaniщadas were different, but [[Brahmins]] couldn’t say that first of them was a  
  
delusion. Two truths conception let to legitimized the contradictions between them and in this way it preserves the idea of the continuity of sacred tradition. This is why Buddhist theory of two truths cannot be considered just as a result of evolution of Brahmanical ideas. Teaching of epistemological truth as a result of different cognitive practices in Indian philosophical tradition is much elaborated. It also includes a part which tells about logical truth, because Logic didn’t become in India a special science. Epistemological truth was considered in the frame of doctrines of sources or instruments of  
+
[[delusion]]. [[Two truths]] {{Wiki|conception}} let to legitimized the contradictions between them and in this way it preserves the [[idea]] of the continuity of [[sacred]] [[tradition]]. This is why [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[two truths]] cannot be considered just as a result of [[evolution]] of [[Brahmanical]] [[ideas]]. [[Teaching]] of [[epistemological]] [[truth]] as a result of different [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] practices in [[Indian]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]] is much elaborated. It also includes a part which tells about [[logical]] [[truth]], because [[Logic]] didn’t become in [[India]] a special [[science]]. [[Epistemological]] [[truth]] was considered in the frame of [[doctrines]] of sources or instruments of  
  
valid cognition (pramāхavāda). In such theories truth always go as cognition (pramā, j$āna) and it was opposed to not-truth (apramā, aj$āna). Even Buddhists in their pramāхavāda prefer agnominate it j$āna, not satya. This preference seemed to be determined by traditionalism of Indian intellectual life and by the fact that in the beginning of this tradition Brahmins (who were its creators) didn’t employ ‘satya’ as philosophical term. One of the main epistemological problems for Indian paхуitas was the problem of the ability of instruments of knowledge to give valid knowledge (prāmāхya) [11. P. 133]  
+
valid [[cognition]] (pramāхavāda). In such theories [[truth]] always go as [[cognition]] ([[pramā]], j$āna) and it was opposed to not-truth (apramā, aj$āna). Even [[Buddhists]] in their pramāхavāda prefer agnominate it j$āna, not [[satya]]. This preference seemed to be determined by [[traditionalism]] of [[Indian]] [[intellectual]] [[life]] and by the fact that in the beginning of this [[tradition]] [[Brahmins]] (who were its creators) didn’t employ ‘[[satya]]’ as [[philosophical]] term. One of the main [[epistemological]] problems for [[Indian]] paхуitas was the problem of the ability of instruments of [[knowledge]] to give valid [[knowledge]] (prāmāхya) [11. P. 133]  
  
while for a philosopher of Western tradition the meaning of this problem is a question about existence of epistemological truth. Among ten pramāхas which named by different schools, most allowed were perception (pratyakщa), inference (anumāna) and testimony which often was treated as eternal word or sound (śabda) (6). Logical truth was investigated in two relatively independent theories and Indian logicians asked two questions connected with such truth: 1) about the inference of truthful propositions in the frame of theory of inference (anumānavāda), and 2) about meanings of the words in the frame of theory of meanings (apohavāda). Named theories allow  
+
while for a [[philosopher]] of [[Western]] [[tradition]] the meaning of this problem is a question about [[existence]] of [[epistemological]] [[truth]]. Among ten pramāхas which named by different schools, most allowed were [[perception]] (pratyakщa), {{Wiki|inference}} ([[anumāna]]) and testimony which often was treated as eternal [[word]] or [[sound]] ([[śabda]]) (6). [[Logical]] [[truth]] was investigated in two relatively {{Wiki|independent}} theories and [[Indian logicians]] asked two questions connected with such [[truth]]: 1) about the {{Wiki|inference}} of truthful propositions in the frame of [[theory of inference]] (anumānavāda), and 2) about meanings of the words in the frame of {{Wiki|theory}} of meanings (apohavāda). Named theories allow  
  
  
us to talk about the fact that Indians distinguished among inferential truth and truth as semantic concept. The answers for the first question were definitions of invariable concomitance (vyāpti, anyathānupapatti) of Major (sādhya) and Middle (hetu) terms in inference (anumāna). Anumānavāda allowed of resolution the justification problem for inferential knowledge. Apohavāda explained truth-conditions for sentences which are made up of words and phrases. As a result of this division of reality into two levels in Indian tradition, empirical and logical truths, which are produced with the help of reason,  
+
us to talk about the fact that {{Wiki|Indians}} {{Wiki|distinguished}} among inferential [[truth]] and [[truth]] as [[Wikipedia:Semantics|semantic]] {{Wiki|concept}}. The answers for the first question were definitions of [[invariable concomitance]] ([[vyāpti]], anyathānupapatti) of Major ([[sādhya]]) and Middle ([[hetu]]) terms in {{Wiki|inference}} ([[anumāna]]). Anumānavāda allowed of resolution the {{Wiki|justification}} problem for [[inferential knowledge]]. Apohavāda explained truth-conditions for sentences which are made up of [[words and phrases]]. As a result of this [[division]] of [[reality]] into two levels in [[Indian tradition]], [[empirical]] and [[logical]] [[truths]], which are produced with the help of [[reason]],  
  
received lower status of the conventional truth. In Western Philosophy the same kinds of truth have been seen as the higher ones for a much long time. The receiving of perception as valid source of knowledge sets before epistemologists the problem of the criteria of perceptual truth. Indian realists, who admitted the existence of universalia and a soul as subject of cognition, had got the royal road for its resolving. So realists of six orthodox darśanas argued sense organs (indriya) and its objects (viщaya) contacted and just at the precise moment the soul received knowledge of the universalia which was  
+
received lower {{Wiki|status}} of the [[conventional truth]]. In {{Wiki|Western Philosophy}} the same kinds of [[truth]] have been seen as the higher ones for a much long time. The receiving of [[perception]] as valid [[source of knowledge]] sets before [[epistemologists]] the problem of the criteria of {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[truth]]. [[Indian]] [[realists]], who admitted the [[existence]] of universalia and a [[soul]] as [[subject]] of [[cognition]], had got the {{Wiki|royal}} road for its resolving. So [[realists]] of six [[orthodox]] [[darśanas]] argued [[sense organs]] ([[indriya]]) and its [[objects]] (viщaya) contacted and just at the precise [[moment]] the [[soul]] received [[knowledge]] of the universalia which was  
  
verbalized. Buddhists nominalists didn’t recognize reality any objects, any universalia, any soul, that’s why their cognitive situation was more difficult. But it was more convenient to the things in reality. And they have found an exit from the situation when they have seen truth-criteria for perceptual judgments in its empirical effectiveness. “Knowledge is right when it makes us reach the object,” wrote Dharmottara in his “Nyāyabinduсīkā” [12. P. 6]. Judgment “This shell is yellow” will be true only in the case when shell is really yellow but it is not only seemed yellow for the reason of eyes disease.  
+
verbalized. [[Buddhists]] [[Wikipedia:Nominalism|nominalists]] didn’t [[recognize]] [[reality]] any [[objects]], any universalia, any [[soul]], that’s why their [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] situation was more difficult. But it was more convenient to the things in [[reality]]. And they have found an exit from the situation when they have seen truth-criteria for {{Wiki|perceptual}} judgments in its [[empirical]] effectiveness. “[[Knowledge]] is right when it makes us reach the [[object]],” wrote [[Dharmottara]] in his “Nyāyabinduсīkā” [12. P. 6]. [[Judgment]] “This shell is [[yellow]]” will be true only in the case when shell is really [[yellow]] but it is not only seemed [[yellow]] for the [[reason]] of [[eyes]] {{Wiki|disease}}.  
  
Very significant factors influenced deeply on Indian conceptions of epistemological and logical truths were the comprehension of cognition aims not as the truths about first elements of the World (as in Ancient Greece), but as the truths of human entity, and that truths did not considered as fruitless for practical activities. In India epistemology was elaborated as discipline useful for practice, admittedly, practice was understood in a special sense: not  
+
Very significant factors influenced deeply on [[Indian]] conceptions of [[epistemological]] and [[logical]] [[truths]] were the [[comprehension]] of [[cognition]] aims not as the [[truths]] about first [[elements]] of the [[World]] (as in {{Wiki|Ancient Greece}}), but as the [[truths]] of [[human]] [[entity]], and that [[truths]] did not considered as fruitless for {{Wiki|practical}} [[activities]]. In [[India]] epistemology was elaborated as [[discipline]] useful for practice, admittedly, practice was understood in a special [[sense]]: not  
  
as material production of one’s own life but first of all as its spiritual production. And main aim of life they saw in finding the way out of circle of rebirth and death, the way of release (mokщa). Material production of goods was not interesting issue for Indian thinkers. Epistemology was taken in the sense of teaching about most important means (sādhana) for mokщa — knowledge. Such practical (inherently soteriological) orientation of pramāхavāda  
+
as material production of one’s [[own]] [[life]] but first of all as its [[spiritual]] production. And main aim of [[life]] they saw in finding the way out of circle of [[rebirth]] and [[death]], the way of [[release]] (mokщa). Material production of goods was not [[interesting]] issue for [[Indian]] thinkers. {{Wiki|Epistemology}} was taken in the [[sense]] of [[teaching]] about most important means ([[sādhana]]) for mokщa — [[knowledge]]. Such {{Wiki|practical}} (inherently [[soteriological]]) orientation of pramāхavāda  
  
determined requirements for any truths as ideals of knowledge. Those requirements weren’t written but implicitly were in the scholars reasoning and they may be reconstructed and uttered in the words. The reconstructed requirements are: 1) clarity and obviousness (nirхaya, niścaya, adhyavasāya) those propositions which pretend to be truthful; 2) they must have the practical value; 3) they must be verifiable by practice. Seeing higher truth isn’t  
+
determined requirements for any [[truths]] as ideals of [[knowledge]]. Those requirements weren’t written but implicitly were in the [[scholars]] {{Wiki|reasoning}} and they may be reconstructed and uttered in the words. The reconstructed requirements are: 1) clarity and obviousness (nirхaya, niścaya, [[adhyavasāya]]) those propositions which pretend to be truthful; 2) they must have the {{Wiki|practical}} value; 3) they must be verifiable by practice. [[Seeing]] [[higher truth]] isn’t  
  
verifiable by practice in physical World (because it is transcendent) they formulated rule 4) truthful knowledge must be gained in accordance with special rules, which are fixed in authoritative texts. And at last rule 5) truthful knowledge must open the whole picture of reality, not a piece of it. It is clear that perceptual and inferential truths didn’t satisfy last rule. For this reason they never were higher truths in India though they were such ones in  
+
verifiable by practice in [[physical World]] (because it is [[transcendent]]) they formulated {{Wiki|rule}} 4) truthful [[knowledge]] must be gained in accordance with special {{Wiki|rules}}, which are fixed in authoritative texts. And at last {{Wiki|rule}} 5) truthful [[knowledge]] must open the whole picture of [[reality]], not a piece of it. It is clear that {{Wiki|perceptual}} and inferential [[truths]] didn’t satisfy last {{Wiki|rule}}. For this [[reason]] they never were higher [[truths]] in [[India]] though they were such ones in  
  
 
   
 
   
Western philosophy. Higher truth for Indian scholars was unspeakable truth which became a result of insight into transcendent reality by means of super-abilities like numinous perception of yogin (yogīpratyakщa) and meditative practices (for Buddhists), omniscience (kevalaj$āna), telepathy (manaюparyāya), clairvoyance (avadhi) (for Jainas) and mystic love for God (bhakti) (for Vedantists). Aspiration to built theory of World which would explain the existence  
+
{{Wiki|Western philosophy}}. [[Higher truth]] for [[Indian]] [[scholars]] was unspeakable [[truth]] which became a result of [[insight]] into [[transcendent]] [[reality]] by means of super-abilities like numinous [[perception]] of [[yogin]] (yogīpratyakщa) and [[meditative practices]] (for [[Buddhists]]), [[omniscience]] (kevalaj$āna), {{Wiki|telepathy}} (manaюparyāya), {{Wiki|clairvoyance}} ([[avadhi]]) (for [[Jainas]]) and [[mystic]] [[love]] for [[God]] ([[bhakti]]) (for [[Vedantists]]). [[Aspiration]] to built {{Wiki|theory}} of [[World]] which would explain the [[existence]]
of its different levels, natural and supernatural, cognizable by rational and super-rational methods, brought from Western point of view paradoxical, contradictory results, but from the point of view of Indian tradition they were not the paradox. Such example of the contradictory epistemology we find in Jainism. Jainas didn’t accept the two realities conception from Buddhists, but conception of two truths they accepted. They opposed the ontological  
+
of its different levels, natural and [[supernatural]], cognizable by [[rational]] and super-rational [[methods]], brought from [[Western]] point of view {{Wiki|paradoxical}}, [[contradictory]] results, but from the point of view of [[Indian tradition]] they were not the [[paradox]]. Such example of the [[contradictory]] epistemology we find in [[Jainism]]. [[Jainas]] didn’t accept the two [[realities]] {{Wiki|conception}} from [[Buddhists]], but {{Wiki|conception}} of [[two truths]] they accepted. They opposed the [[Wikipedia:Ontology|ontological]]
  
doctrine of plural, manifold reality (anekāntavāda) to Buddhists two realities and also they opposed two theories, “connected with anekāntavāda like wings are connected with bird” [13. P. 177], to epistemological conceptions of other darśanas. They were the doctrine about points of view (nayavāda) and method of conditioned predication (syādvāda) or sevenfold paralogism (saptabhaпgī). Named theories showed their consanguinity with the methods of public debates from which they grow and they agreed in a rude fashion with postdate conception of instruments of cognition (pramāхavāda), which Jainas included in their  
+
[[doctrine]] of plural, manifold [[reality]] ([[anekāntavāda]]) to [[Buddhists]] two [[realities]] and also they opposed two theories, “connected with [[anekāntavāda]] like wings are connected with bird” [13. P. 177], to [[epistemological]] conceptions of other [[darśanas]]. They were the [[doctrine]] about points of view ([[nayavāda]]) and method of [[conditioned]] predication ([[syādvāda]]) or sevenfold paralogism (saptabhaпgī). Named theories showed their consanguinity with the [[methods]] of public [[debates]] from which they grow and they agreed in a rude fashion with postdate {{Wiki|conception}} of instruments of [[cognition]] (pramāхavāda), which [[Jainas]] included in their  
  
philosophy later. According them, diversity of reality doesn’t mean, its stratification and insulation of such level which is materially incommensurable with human cognitive abilities. It doesn’t mean also that various kinds of knowledge are materially incommensurable. But for Jainas it means that it is possible to articulate the propositions about reality which are true in some or other aspect (by form-rūpa or by substance-dravya or by place-kśetra or by time-kāla) that is they are relatively true. Question ‘What to do with relative truths?’ wasn’t a problem for Jainas. They didn’t feel embarrassment about truths’ relativity. For them it is normal because reality is changing permanently and we can’t obtain permanent truth about it. Indeed, their conceptions  
+
[[philosophy]] later. According them, diversity of [[reality]] doesn’t mean, its stratification and insulation of such level which is materially {{Wiki|incommensurable}} with [[human]] [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] {{Wiki|abilities}}. It doesn’t mean also that various kinds of [[knowledge]] are materially {{Wiki|incommensurable}}. But for [[Jainas]] it means that it is possible to articulate the propositions about [[reality]] which are true in some or other aspect (by form-rūpa or by substance-dravya or by place-kśetra or by time-kāla) that is they are relatively true. Question ‘What to do with [[relative truths]]?’ wasn’t a problem for [[Jainas]]. They didn’t [[feel]] {{Wiki|embarrassment}} about [[truths]]’ [[relativity]]. For them it is normal because [[reality]] is changing permanently and we can’t obtain [[permanent]] [[truth]] about it. Indeed, their conceptions  
  
nayavāda and syādvāda prescribe to form a lot of propositions about the same object (7), and all they are relative truths. Why so? Because Jainas had no need in positive knowledge about physical things for material practice but they used their methods for the demonstration of relative character of all theses advanced by their opponents. Nobody intended to formulate 700 or 4900 propositions about one predicate during the debate with opponents. However possible quantity of such propositions shows very well relativity and falsity of opponent doctrines, so epistemological methods must to help non-Jainas to accept Jīna Mahāvīra’s darśana which value is not in its truthfulness but in its effectiveness and this effectiveness is founded upon belief. Even those few observations and generalizations about Indian conceptions of truth which were presented here by the author show as high level theoretical thought in India as grand differences just in foundations of theoretical reasoning of Indian and of Western philosophers. Such dissimilarities convince of the need to go on study of the foundations for authentic comprehension of Indian Philosophy.  
+
[[nayavāda]] and [[syādvāda]] prescribe to [[form]] a lot of propositions about the same [[object]] (7), and all they are [[relative truths]]. Why so? Because [[Jainas]] had no need in positive [[knowledge]] about [[physical]] things for material practice but they used their [[methods]] for the demonstration of [[relative]] [[character]] of all theses advanced by their opponents. Nobody intended to formulate 700 or 4900 propositions about one predicate during the [[debate]] with opponents. However possible {{Wiki|quantity}} of such propositions shows very well [[relativity]] and falsity of opponent [[doctrines]], so [[epistemological]] [[methods]] must to help non-Jainas to accept Jīna Mahāvīra’s [[darśana]] which value is not in its [[truthfulness]] but in its effectiveness and this effectiveness is founded upon [[belief]]. Even those few observations and generalizations about [[Indian]] conceptions of [[truth]] which were presented here by the author show as high level {{Wiki|theoretical}} [[thought]] in [[India]] as grand differences just in foundations of {{Wiki|theoretical}} {{Wiki|reasoning}} of [[Indian]] and of [[Western]] [[philosophers]]. Such dissimilarities convince of the need to go on study of the foundations for [[Wikipedia:Authenticity|authentic]] [[comprehension]] of [[Indian Philosophy]].  
  
  
Line 92: Line 91:
  
  
(1) Specialists in Sanskrit learning.  (2) The beginning of such pseudo-historical texts specialists refer to III—V AD, though they admit information codified in puraхas is more earlier, because they mentioned in Vedas already (for example, in ‘Atharvaveda’, XI. 7. 24).  (3) In иgveda there are as the word ‘Dharma’, as a lot of derivatives from it, for example: Indra was named dharmakзta — ‘creator of universal order’ (see: http://www.sanskritweb.net/rigveda/ rv08.pdf).  (4) According to Nāgārjuna’ s ‘Mūlamadhyamakakārikās’, 24.10. Texts from Buddhist canon teem with such  
+
(1) Specialists in [[Sanskrit]] {{Wiki|learning}}.  (2) The beginning of such pseudo-historical texts specialists refer to III—V AD, though they admit [[information]] codified in puraхas is more earlier, because they mentioned in [[Vedas]] already (for example, in ‘{{Wiki|Atharvaveda}}’, XI. 7. 24).  (3) In иgveda there are as the [[word]] ‘[[Dharma]]’, as a lot of derivatives from it, for example: [[Indra]] was named dharmakзta — ‘creator of [[universal]] order’ (see: http://www.sanskritweb.net/rigveda/ rv08.pdf).  (4) According to [[Nāgārjuna]]’ s ‘[[Mūlamadhyamakakārikās]]’, 24.10. Texts from [[Buddhist canon]] teem with such  
  
citation as L. de la Vallée Poussin found, see: Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā Commentaire de Candrakīrti. Publité par L. de la Vallée Poussin. Fasc. I—VII. SPb., 1903—1913. (Bibliotheca Buddhica. IV).  (5) Vedantists discourse on two kinds of truth one may see in ‘Maхуukyakārikā’ by Gauуapāda and ‘Brahmasūtrabhāщya’ by Śaпkara.  (6) The last one is directly connected with vedic conception of Eternal Word of Veda.  (7) In accordance with syādvāda we must formulate 7 modal propositions about some predicate of an object, then according with nayavāda we must see each of them from 7 points of view; and if we’ll follow “Nayakarхikā” (19) by Vinayavijaya, each of 7 points of view has 100 subspecies, then we may formulate 4900 propositions about one predicate of single object.  
+
citation as L. de la [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Vallée Poussin]] found, see: [[Mūlamadhyamakakārikās]] de [[Nāgārjuna]] avec la [[Prasannapadā]] Commentaire de [[Candrakīrti]]. Publité par L. de la [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Vallée Poussin]]. Fasc. I—VII. SPb., 1903—1913. ([[Bibliotheca Buddhica]]. IV).  (5) [[Vedantists]] [[discourse]] on [[two kinds of truth]] one may see in ‘Maхуukyakārikā’ by Gauуapāda and ‘Brahmasūtrabhāщya’ by Śaпkara.  (6) The last one is directly connected with {{Wiki|vedic}} {{Wiki|conception}} of Eternal [[Word]] of [[Veda]].  (7) In accordance with [[syādvāda]] we must formulate 7 modal propositions about some predicate of an [[object]], then according with [[nayavāda]] we must see each of them from 7 points of view; and if we’ll follow “Nayakarхikā” (19) by Vinayavijaya, each of 7 points of view has 100 subspecies, then we may formulate 4900 propositions about one predicate of single [[object]].  
  
  
Line 102: Line 101:
  
  
[1] Kasavin I.T. Truth // Encylopedia Epistemologii i Philosophii nauki. (Encylopedia of Philosophy and Epistemology of sciences). Moscow. 2009. S. 323—329.  [2] Fedotova V.G. Klassicheskoye i neklassicheskoye v socialnom poznanii // Obschestvennye nauki i sovremennost. (Classic and non-classic in social knowledge // Social sciences and modernity). 1992. N 4.  [3] Monier-Williams M. Sanskзit-English Dictionary. New ed. With collabor. of E. Leumann, C. Cappeller and other. New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers Prvt. Ltd., 1976; 1st ed. 1899.  [4] Solomon E.A. Indian Dialectics: Methods of Philosophical Discussion. 2vols. Vol. I. Ahmedabad. 1976.  [5] Solomon E.A. Indian Dialectics: Methods of Philosophical Discussion. 2 vols. Vol. II. Ahmedabad. 1978.  [6] Vallée Poussin, de la L. Documents d’Abhidharma — les Deux, les Qatre. Les Trois Vérités. Extraits de la Vibhāщa et du Kośa de Sa#ghabhadra // Mélanges chinois et bouddhiques. Bruxel, 1936—1937. T. 5.  [7] Thakchoe S. The Theory of Two Truths in India // The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ sum2011/entries/twotruths-india/>.  [8] Lysenko V.G. Svalakщaхa-sāmānya-lakщaхa // Philosophiya Buddhisma: Encylopedia. (Philosophy of Buddhism: Encyclopedia). Moscow. 2011.  [9] Stcherbatsky F.I. Teoriya poznaniya i logika po ucheniyu pozdneishyh buddistov (Epistemology and Logic in accordance with teaching of latest Buddhists) / Ed. A.V. Paribok. SanktPetersburg. 1995. Pt. 2.  [10] Stcherbatsky Th. Buddhist Logic. In 2 vols. New York, 1984. Vol. I.  [11] Mohanty J. N. Reason and Tradition in Indian Thought: An Essay on the Nature of Indian Philosophical Thinking. N.Y.: Oxford University Press, 1992.  [12] Stcherbatsky Th. Buddhist Logic. In 2 vols. New York, 1984. Vol. II.  [13] Padmarajiah I.J. Anekāntavāda, Nayavāda and Syādvāda // Encyclopaedia of Jainism. In 30 Vols. New Delhi. 2001. Vol. 1.  
+
[1] Kasavin I.T. [[Truth]] // Encylopedia Epistemologii i Philosophii nauki. (Encylopedia of [[Philosophy]] and {{Wiki|Epistemology}} of [[sciences]]). {{Wiki|Moscow}}. 2009. S. 323—329.  [2] Fedotova V.G. Klassicheskoye i neklassicheskoye v socialnom poznanii // Obschestvennye nauki i sovremennost. (Classic and non-classic in {{Wiki|social}} [[knowledge]] // {{Wiki|Social sciences}} and modernity). 1992. N 4.  [3] {{Wiki|Monier-Williams}} M. Sanskзit-English {{Wiki|Dictionary}}. New ed. With collabor. of E. Leumann, C. Cappeller and other. {{Wiki|New Delhi}}: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers Prvt. Ltd., 1976; 1st ed. 1899.  [4] Solomon E.A. [[Indian]] [[Dialectics]]: [[Methods]] of [[Philosophical]] [[Discussion]]. 2vols. Vol. I. Ahmedabad. 1976.  [5] Solomon E.A. [[Indian]] [[Dialectics]]: [[Methods]] of [[Philosophical]] [[Discussion]]. 2 vols. Vol. II. Ahmedabad. 1978.  [6] [[Wikipedia:Louis de La Vallée-Poussin|Vallée Poussin]], de la L. Documents d’Abhidharma — les Deux, les Qatre. Les Trois Vérités. Extraits de la Vibhāщa et du [[Kośa]] de Sa#ghabhadra // Mélanges chinois et bouddhiques. Bruxel, 1936—1937. T. 5.  [7] Thakchoe S. [[The Theory of Two Truths in India]] // {{Wiki|The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}} (Summer 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ sum2011/entries/twotruths-india/>.  [8] Lysenko V.G. Svalakщaхa-sāmānya-lakщaхa // Philosophiya Buddhisma: Encylopedia. ([[Philosophy of Buddhism]]: {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}}). {{Wiki|Moscow}}. 2011.  [9] [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] F.I. Teoriya poznaniya i logika po ucheniyu pozdneishyh buddistov ({{Wiki|Epistemology}} and [[Logic]] in accordance with [[teaching]] of latest [[Buddhists]]) / Ed. A.V. Paribok. SanktPetersburg. 1995. Pt. 2.  [10] [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] Th. [[Buddhist Logic]]. In 2 vols. [[New York]], 1984. Vol. I.  [11] Mohanty J. N. [[Reason]] and [[Tradition]] in [[Indian]] [[Thought]]: An Essay on the [[Nature]] of [[Indian]] [[Philosophical]] [[Thinking]]. N.Y.: [[Oxford University Press]], 1992.  [12] [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]] Th. [[Buddhist Logic]]. In 2 vols. [[New York]], 1984. Vol. II.  [13] Padmarajiah I.J. [[Anekāntavāda]], [[Nayavāda]] and [[Syādvāda]] // Encyclopaedia of [[Jainism]]. In 30 Vols. {{Wiki|New Delhi}}. 2001. Vol. 1.  
  
  

Latest revision as of 09:50, 29 January 2024




N.A. Kanaeva

Cathedra of the History of Philosophy Department of Philosophy National Research University “Higher School of Economics” Maliy Tryehsvyatitelsky Pereulok,



Truth is one of the key values in Western culture, and in the History of Western Philosophy it had different images. The position of truth in the History of Indian Philosophy was similar. But sometimes in India it is very difficult to retrace the way from the wordtruth’ to the philosophical category. In this article are traced main lines of discussions about the truth and principal senses of Indian terms (satya, jñāna, Dharma, prāmāхya). Buddhists were the

firsts who introduced the concept of truth, originally in a form of the Four noble truths doctrine then as Mahayana concept of the two truths (conventional and absolute). In Indian tradition, as well as in Western philosophy, truth was considered differently in existential, moral, ontological, soteriological, epistemological and logical perspectives. Indians also distinguished between inferential and semantic concepts of truth. From Western point of view their aspiration to build a theory of the World, which will explain the existence of its different natural and supernatural levels, which are cognizable by rational and super-rational means, brought Indians to paradoxical, contradictory results. Typical example of such contradictory theory of truth can be

found in Jaina relative truth doctrine about impermanent and pluralistic reality (syādvāda or anekāntavāda). Key words: cognitive practice, epistemological truth, Indian epistemology, logical truth, requirements for truth, satya, stratification of being, truth in Indian philosophy. In Western culture truth is considered to be the ideal of cognition and as one of its basic values. In the History of Western Philosophy truth as well as other cultural values appeared in different images. In Antiquity it was viewed like Good, being (Plato, Aristotle), like ideal of inquiry and the way of

its attainment or proving [1. C. 323] (in modern epistemology), like meanings of propositions (in Logic), the logical ontology (in ‘semantic conception of truth’ of A. Tarski) or even superfluous property of the propositions (in deflationary conception of truth by A. Ayer). Among current theories of truth one can choose between the correspondence theory, conventional and coherence theories of truth. Historically philosophers discussed the ideas of absolute truth and relative one, an empirical and theoretical truth, and now more frequently we are even hearing that notion ‘truth’ is not really a productive concept

and so there is no need in this notion at all. This list of the truth’s images transformations in the history of Western Philosophy is a vindication of its innate pluralism in comprehension and it compels us to perceive the truth pluralism as philosophical norm [2. C. 50]. Truth in India was also very significant category, but along of original character of Indian thought the wordtruth’ had its own way for transforming to the philosophical category. Sometimes it is very difficult to retrace this transformation for the reason that truth in Paхуitas (1) discussions had divers names and sometimes wasn’t named explicitly at all. But it is necessary to identify the meaning of the Indian philosophers’ discussions as the discussions about truth, because this meaning provides understand


ing of the level Indian theoretical thought as very high and it helps to see the peculiarity of Indian philosophy. Such reasons became the foundations for the choice of our topic of study. I am planning to show the beginnings of truth question in Indian philosophy and how Indian thinkers began to use term ‘truth’ as the philosophical category. I’ll try to fetch out main lines of discussions about truth and principal senses of the term which are comparable with Western ones. Basic method of my research will be semantic analysis of the pre-philosophical and philosophical texts in Sanskrit where are present

different conceptions associated with the terms indicating truth. Most correlative with term for ‘truth’ in Sanskrit is wordsatya’. It was derived from ‘sat’ — ‘being’, ‘existing’. ‘good’, ‘right’, ‘venerable’, ‘reality’, ‘a sage’ and so on [3. P. 1134] and inherited from ‘sat’ some meanings: ‘truth’, ‘reality’, ‘entity’. They use ‘satya’ also as adjectival words: ‘true’, ‘real’, ‘actual’, ‘genuine’, ‘truthful’, ‘successful’, ‘pure’, ‘virtuous’, ‘good’,

‘valid’ an so on [3. P. 1135]. Word satya was employed in vedic literature from the Ancient time. иgveda teems with derivatives from satya, Upanisads and epic poemsMahābhārata’ and ‘Rāmāyaхa’ include set of names and epithets for heroes which are secondary from ‘satya’ like Satyavatī (mother of Vyāsa), satyā (epithets of Durgā and Sitā), in purāхas (2) highest sky in the world structure, Brahma loka, was named Satya-loka (Sky of truth) and they told about

Satya-yuga (Golden age of truth and purity). Thanks to Buddhists wordsatya’ became the philosophical category. They were the first who suggested their concepts of truth. Brahmans had no need in satyacategory, because they had dharma-category. Dharma was universal category and it was signify the universal law, World order, religion, moral prescriptions, status rules, principles of law, various kinds of systematical teachings, Good etc. Dharma-universalia has

its roots in Vedic religion (3) and for this reason it acquired religious, sacral character. So meanings ‘reality’ and ‘truth’ were attributed to wordDharma’. So it was impossible for Brahmins to ask any questions about validity of Dharma and they had no need in its rational justification. Vedic religion is a belief not only in the pantheon of thousands gods but in the Vedic language, Sanskrit, as in force of World’s creation. Belief in Dharma as

the embodied eternal word of Vedas (śabda) was one of the conditions for using the ‘dharma’ as ‘truth’. It would be tautology for Brahmins to talk about truthfulness of Dharma in their sacred contexts. Brahmanical Dharma was struck by śramaхas and Buddhists were among them. Buddhists brought up the issue of truthfulness of Brahmanical Dharma as well as the issue of the validity of the instruments for its acknowledgment, which were enumerated in Brāhmaхas and

Upaniщads. It was historical irony that śramaхas for the disavowal of Brahmanism employed the same theory of dialectics (theory of public debates or — in modern terms — theory of argumentation) which was originally elaborated in Brahmanical schools. In Brāhmaхas and Upaniщads dialectics appeared under the name vākovākya (the art to ask questions) [4. P. 6], and in smзti-literature it was named ānvīkщikī (consideration, clarification, research, analysis) [5. P. 792]. Ānvīkщikī didn’t employ dialectics for the solution of metaphysical problems and justification of those solutions before the birth of the philosophical reflection of World and human life in V AD.


Brahmins applied ānvīkщikī to discussions about special issues of theology, eristic, principles of law and medicine in their professional schools. This Brahmanical tool Śramaхas began to use against them for disestablishment of Brahmanical pre-philosophical ideology and so they demonstrated themselves as match opponents for Brahmins. Why are we talking about Buddhists as the beginners of truth conceptualization? Buddhists were the firsts who identified their own (not Brahmanical) Dharma with satya and proposed two theories of truth at once. The first one we find already in earliest Buddha’s sermons about

Four noble truths, the second one is two truths theory. It was created by early Buddhists schools while later scholars subscribed it to Siddhartha Gautama himself (4). According to L. de la Vallée Poussin in Chinese schools of Buddhism were elaborated theories in which the correlations of two and four truths was set down [6. P. 159—187]. The Doctrine of Four noble truths not only articulates sense of each ‘truths’ but also explains how to reach their realization. The first Buddha’s sermon (according to ‘Dhamma-cakka-ppavatana-sutta’) stated that the first truth (about suffering) must be understood completely, the second one (about thirst) must be helpful for refusing from thirst, the third one (about nirvāхa) must be attained and the fourth one

(about way) ought to be put into the practice. In ‘Sa#yuttanikāya’ (LVI. 30) and ‘Visuddhimagga’ (XVI. 84) process of realization of the four truths recieved some different features, but it was described in the first sermon too. Two ways of the Truthsrealization (sacca-$āхa) were told in those texts: understanding (anubodha-$āхa) and penetration (paсivedha-$āхa). Understanding is mundane (lokiya) knowledge and it aids to drop suffering; penetration is super-mundane (lokuttara) knowledge and it refers to cessation of suffering and realization of all four truths at the same moment. The doctrine of Four noble truths have four senses in one: an existential (because they all are serving to human existence), moral (because they are imperatives for a good

behavior), ontological (because they distinguished levels of being — lower, with suffering, and higher, without suffering) and soteriological one (for they all show the way to the salvation). Those senses were also the points of bifurcation in Buddhists Philosophy: each of them was the beginning for new conceptions of truth which entered in the whole Indian tradition of Philosophical thought. Doctrine of two truths became the logical corollary from the primary stratification of being in the tenet of Four truths. It is also acquired epistemological sense. In epistemological frame term ‘truth’ is equivalent to term ‘knowledge’ (in Pali — $āхa, in Sanskrit — j$āna). In doctrine of two truths Buddhists distinguished ontological and epistemological senses.

Existence of two levels of reality they fixed in special terms: higher being (paramārtha-sat) and lower being (vyavahārika-sat), and they validated them by designation of two correlative kinds of truths: higher truth (paramārtha-satya) and lower one (vyavahārika-satya). Being heavy at odds with validity of supernatural reality Buddhists provoked variety conceptions about the structure and knowability of that reality. Later this Buddhist stratification of reality in two levels was adopted in Vedānta (5). In ‘Abhidharmakośa’ by Vasubandhu quite different conceptions of reality by Sarvāstivādins, Sautrāntikas


and Vaibhāщikās are presented. In realistic Sarvāstivādins ontology higher reality was explained as ultimate truth “consists of irreducible spatial units” (paramāхu), which exist the only moment (kщaхa), and of “irreducible temporal units (e.g., point-instant consciousnesses) of the five basic categories”; lower reality was explained as the conventional truth “consists of reducible spatial wholes or temporal continua” [7]. Sautrāntikas placed in higher reality the essences of some moments (dharmas) of consciousness flow (dravyasat) and other dharmas, which they named unreal (praj$āptisat), they regarded as lower reality [8. C. 625]. Their conception of two realities developed by Yogacārins Dignāga, Dharmakīrti and Dharmottara in conception of particularia (svalakщaхa) and universalia (sāmānya-lakщaхa) [9. C. 182]. And when Yogacārins came in with development of epistemology and logic of their own, they introduced in Buddhist ontology de facto the third, ideal reality: the world of thought, “where there is no Matter at all, there are only Ideas” [10. P.

509]. One may read background for Buddhist conception of two truths in such Brahmanical texts like ‘Muхуakopaniщada’ and others in which two kinds of knowledge, higher and lower (parā caivāparā), mentioned. But in ‘Muхуakopaniщada’ (III. 2.4-6) and in other texts the old, Vedic knowledge is opposed to the new post-Vedic knowledge (Atman comprehension, which ascetics-зщi achieve by yoga and saпnyāsa). From this fact another reason and another goal for the conception of two truths follow. World pictures in four Vedas and in Upaniщadas were different, but Brahmins couldn’t say that first of them was a

delusion. Two truths conception let to legitimized the contradictions between them and in this way it preserves the idea of the continuity of sacred tradition. This is why Buddhist theory of two truths cannot be considered just as a result of evolution of Brahmanical ideas. Teaching of epistemological truth as a result of different cognitive practices in Indian philosophical tradition is much elaborated. It also includes a part which tells about logical truth, because Logic didn’t become in India a special science. Epistemological truth was considered in the frame of doctrines of sources or instruments of

valid cognition (pramāхavāda). In such theories truth always go as cognition (pramā, j$āna) and it was opposed to not-truth (apramā, aj$āna). Even Buddhists in their pramāхavāda prefer agnominate it j$āna, not satya. This preference seemed to be determined by traditionalism of Indian intellectual life and by the fact that in the beginning of this tradition Brahmins (who were its creators) didn’t employ ‘satya’ as philosophical term. One of the main epistemological problems for Indian paхуitas was the problem of the ability of instruments of knowledge to give valid knowledge (prāmāхya) [11. P. 133]

while for a philosopher of Western tradition the meaning of this problem is a question about existence of epistemological truth. Among ten pramāхas which named by different schools, most allowed were perception (pratyakщa), inference (anumāna) and testimony which often was treated as eternal word or sound (śabda) (6). Logical truth was investigated in two relatively independent theories and Indian logicians asked two questions connected with such truth: 1) about the inference of truthful propositions in the frame of theory of inference (anumānavāda), and 2) about meanings of the words in the frame of theory of meanings (apohavāda). Named theories allow


us to talk about the fact that Indians distinguished among inferential truth and truth as semantic concept. The answers for the first question were definitions of invariable concomitance (vyāpti, anyathānupapatti) of Major (sādhya) and Middle (hetu) terms in inference (anumāna). Anumānavāda allowed of resolution the justification problem for inferential knowledge. Apohavāda explained truth-conditions for sentences which are made up of words and phrases. As a result of this division of reality into two levels in Indian tradition, empirical and logical truths, which are produced with the help of reason,

received lower status of the conventional truth. In Western Philosophy the same kinds of truth have been seen as the higher ones for a much long time. The receiving of perception as valid source of knowledge sets before epistemologists the problem of the criteria of perceptual truth. Indian realists, who admitted the existence of universalia and a soul as subject of cognition, had got the royal road for its resolving. So realists of six orthodox darśanas argued sense organs (indriya) and its objects (viщaya) contacted and just at the precise moment the soul received knowledge of the universalia which was

verbalized. Buddhists nominalists didn’t recognize reality any objects, any universalia, any soul, that’s why their cognitive situation was more difficult. But it was more convenient to the things in reality. And they have found an exit from the situation when they have seen truth-criteria for perceptual judgments in its empirical effectiveness. “Knowledge is right when it makes us reach the object,” wrote Dharmottara in his “Nyāyabinduсīkā” [12. P. 6]. Judgment “This shell is yellow” will be true only in the case when shell is really yellow but it is not only seemed yellow for the reason of eyes disease.

Very significant factors influenced deeply on Indian conceptions of epistemological and logical truths were the comprehension of cognition aims not as the truths about first elements of the World (as in Ancient Greece), but as the truths of human entity, and that truths did not considered as fruitless for practical activities. In India epistemology was elaborated as discipline useful for practice, admittedly, practice was understood in a special sense: not

as material production of one’s own life but first of all as its spiritual production. And main aim of life they saw in finding the way out of circle of rebirth and death, the way of release (mokщa). Material production of goods was not interesting issue for Indian thinkers. Epistemology was taken in the sense of teaching about most important means (sādhana) for mokщa — knowledge. Such practical (inherently soteriological) orientation of pramāхavāda

determined requirements for any truths as ideals of knowledge. Those requirements weren’t written but implicitly were in the scholars reasoning and they may be reconstructed and uttered in the words. The reconstructed requirements are: 1) clarity and obviousness (nirхaya, niścaya, adhyavasāya) those propositions which pretend to be truthful; 2) they must have the practical value; 3) they must be verifiable by practice. Seeing higher truth isn’t

verifiable by practice in physical World (because it is transcendent) they formulated rule 4) truthful knowledge must be gained in accordance with special rules, which are fixed in authoritative texts. And at last rule 5) truthful knowledge must open the whole picture of reality, not a piece of it. It is clear that perceptual and inferential truths didn’t satisfy last rule. For this reason they never were higher truths in India though they were such ones in


Western philosophy. Higher truth for Indian scholars was unspeakable truth which became a result of insight into transcendent reality by means of super-abilities like numinous perception of yogin (yogīpratyakщa) and meditative practices (for Buddhists), omniscience (kevalaj$āna), telepathy (manaюparyāya), clairvoyance (avadhi) (for Jainas) and mystic love for God (bhakti) (for Vedantists). Aspiration to built theory of World which would explain the existence of its different levels, natural and supernatural, cognizable by rational and super-rational methods, brought from Western point of view paradoxical, contradictory results, but from the point of view of Indian tradition they were not the paradox. Such example of the contradictory epistemology we find in Jainism. Jainas didn’t accept the two realities conception from Buddhists, but conception of two truths they accepted. They opposed the ontological

doctrine of plural, manifold reality (anekāntavāda) to Buddhists two realities and also they opposed two theories, “connected with anekāntavāda like wings are connected with bird” [13. P. 177], to epistemological conceptions of other darśanas. They were the doctrine about points of view (nayavāda) and method of conditioned predication (syādvāda) or sevenfold paralogism (saptabhaпgī). Named theories showed their consanguinity with the methods of public debates from which they grow and they agreed in a rude fashion with postdate conception of instruments of cognition (pramāхavāda), which Jainas included in their

philosophy later. According them, diversity of reality doesn’t mean, its stratification and insulation of such level which is materially incommensurable with human cognitive abilities. It doesn’t mean also that various kinds of knowledge are materially incommensurable. But for Jainas it means that it is possible to articulate the propositions about reality which are true in some or other aspect (by form-rūpa or by substance-dravya or by place-kśetra or by time-kāla) that is they are relatively true. Question ‘What to do with relative truths?’ wasn’t a problem for Jainas. They didn’t feel embarrassment about truthsrelativity. For them it is normal because reality is changing permanently and we can’t obtain permanent truth about it. Indeed, their conceptions

nayavāda and syādvāda prescribe to form a lot of propositions about the same object (7), and all they are relative truths. Why so? Because Jainas had no need in positive knowledge about physical things for material practice but they used their methods for the demonstration of relative character of all theses advanced by their opponents. Nobody intended to formulate 700 or 4900 propositions about one predicate during the debate with opponents. However possible quantity of such propositions shows very well relativity and falsity of opponent doctrines, so epistemological methods must to help non-Jainas to accept Jīna Mahāvīra’s darśana which value is not in its truthfulness but in its effectiveness and this effectiveness is founded upon belief. Even those few observations and generalizations about Indian conceptions of truth which were presented here by the author show as high level theoretical thought in India as grand differences just in foundations of theoretical reasoning of Indian and of Western philosophers. Such dissimilarities convince of the need to go on study of the foundations for authentic comprehension of Indian Philosophy.



FOOTNOTES


(1) Specialists in Sanskrit learning. (2) The beginning of such pseudo-historical texts specialists refer to III—V AD, though they admit information codified in puraхas is more earlier, because they mentioned in Vedas already (for example, in ‘Atharvaveda’, XI. 7. 24). (3) In иgveda there are as the wordDharma’, as a lot of derivatives from it, for example: Indra was named dharmakзta — ‘creator of universal order’ (see: http://www.sanskritweb.net/rigveda/ rv08.pdf). (4) According to Nāgārjuna’ s ‘Mūlamadhyamakakārikās’, 24.10. Texts from Buddhist canon teem with such

citation as L. de la Vallée Poussin found, see: Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā Commentaire de Candrakīrti. Publité par L. de la Vallée Poussin. Fasc. I—VII. SPb., 1903—1913. (Bibliotheca Buddhica. IV). (5) Vedantists discourse on two kinds of truth one may see in ‘Maхуukyakārikā’ by Gauуapāda and ‘Brahmasūtrabhāщya’ by Śaпkara. (6) The last one is directly connected with vedic conception of Eternal Word of Veda. (7) In accordance with syādvāda we must formulate 7 modal propositions about some predicate of an object, then according with nayavāda we must see each of them from 7 points of view; and if we’ll follow “Nayakarхikā” (19) by Vinayavijaya, each of 7 points of view has 100 subspecies, then we may formulate 4900 propositions about one predicate of single object.


BIBLIOGRAPHY


[1] Kasavin I.T. Truth // Encylopedia Epistemologii i Philosophii nauki. (Encylopedia of Philosophy and Epistemology of sciences). Moscow. 2009. S. 323—329. [2] Fedotova V.G. Klassicheskoye i neklassicheskoye v socialnom poznanii // Obschestvennye nauki i sovremennost. (Classic and non-classic in social knowledge // Social sciences and modernity). 1992. N 4. [3] Monier-Williams M. Sanskзit-English Dictionary. New ed. With collabor. of E. Leumann, C. Cappeller and other. New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers Prvt. Ltd., 1976; 1st ed. 1899. [4] Solomon E.A. Indian Dialectics: Methods of Philosophical Discussion. 2vols. Vol. I. Ahmedabad. 1976. [5] Solomon E.A. Indian Dialectics: Methods of Philosophical Discussion. 2 vols. Vol. II. Ahmedabad. 1978. [6] Vallée Poussin, de la L. Documents d’Abhidharma — les Deux, les Qatre. Les Trois Vérités. Extraits de la Vibhāщa et du Kośa de Sa#ghabhadra // Mélanges chinois et bouddhiques. Bruxel, 1936—1937. T. 5. [7] Thakchoe S. The Theory of Two Truths in India // The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ sum2011/entries/twotruths-india/>. [8] Lysenko V.G. Svalakщaхa-sāmānya-lakщaхa // Philosophiya Buddhisma: Encylopedia. (Philosophy of Buddhism: Encyclopedia). Moscow. 2011. [9] Stcherbatsky F.I. Teoriya poznaniya i logika po ucheniyu pozdneishyh buddistov (Epistemology and Logic in accordance with teaching of latest Buddhists) / Ed. A.V. Paribok. SanktPetersburg. 1995. Pt. 2. [10] Stcherbatsky Th. Buddhist Logic. In 2 vols. New York, 1984. Vol. I. [11] Mohanty J. N. Reason and Tradition in Indian Thought: An Essay on the Nature of Indian Philosophical Thinking. N.Y.: Oxford University Press, 1992. [12] Stcherbatsky Th. Buddhist Logic. In 2 vols. New York, 1984. Vol. II. [13] Padmarajiah I.J. Anekāntavāda, Nayavāda and Syādvāda // Encyclopaedia of Jainism. In 30 Vols. New Delhi. 2001. Vol. 1.



Source