Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Nyāya - The School of Logicians"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " <poem> Nyāya - The School of Logicians The Nyāya is the science of logic, and provides the only sound [[Wikipedia:scientific method|methodology]...")
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
+
<nomobile>{{DisplayImages|2106|662|3094|410|1809|1372|3129|1658|4452|1012|164|49|77|3362|147|2560|3807|309|3988|3641|348|331|3953|3337|2797|2383|2564|3823|1132|1153|3366|4355|2314|2160|3633|2410|889|4212|1023|591|3502|2801|934|124|1979|3832|601|2803|2197|3077|2773|1707|3928|1161|2808|425|4429|4157|1596|10|68|1201|1093|2189|3841|2771|4064|174|1432|3274|2587|3393|2641|2180|2191|953|2804|3970|1622|3982|3|1926|2640|2877|149|2428|2364|1814|778|134|2178|633|445|2085|3591|480|2013|108|1016|2188}}</nomobile>
  
  
Line 14: Line 14:
 
The term [[Nyāya]] in [[Sanskrit]] {{Wiki|signifies}} "going into a [[subject]]," —an analytical [[investigation]] of the [[subject]] through the process of [[logical]] {{Wiki|reasoning}}.
 
The term [[Nyāya]] in [[Sanskrit]] {{Wiki|signifies}} "going into a [[subject]]," —an analytical [[investigation]] of the [[subject]] through the process of [[logical]] {{Wiki|reasoning}}.
  
[[Vātsyāyana]], the classic commentator on the Nyāya-Sūtra, defines it as:
+
[[Vātsyāyana]], the classic commentator on the [[Nyāya-Sūtra]], defines it as:
  
 
"a critical {{Wiki|examination}} of the [[objects of knowledge]] by means of the canons of [[logical]] [[proof]]."
 
"a critical {{Wiki|examination}} of the [[objects of knowledge]] by means of the canons of [[logical]] [[proof]]."
Line 20: Line 20:
 
The [[Nyāya]] is also called [[Tarka-vidyā]], "[[science]] of {{Wiki|reasoning}}," or [[Vāda-vidyā]] "[[science of discussion]]."'
 
The [[Nyāya]] is also called [[Tarka-vidyā]], "[[science]] of {{Wiki|reasoning}}," or [[Vāda-vidyā]] "[[science of discussion]]."'
  
The founder of the [[Nyāya]] was [[Gautama]] ([[Gotama]]) who is frequently-referred to in the {{Wiki|literature}} as Akṣa-pāda, “Eye-footed," and Dīrgha-tapas, "Long-penance."
+
The founder of the [[Nyāya]] was [[Gautama]] ([[Gotama]]) who is frequently-referred to in the {{Wiki|literature}} as [[Akṣa-pāda]], “Eye-footed," and [[Dīrgha-tapas]], "Long-penance."
  
 
In {{Wiki|ancient India}} it was customary to give [[people]] nicknames which gave a descriptive characterisation of the {{Wiki|individual}}.
 
In {{Wiki|ancient India}} it was customary to give [[people]] nicknames which gave a descriptive characterisation of the {{Wiki|individual}}.
Line 28: Line 28:
 
There is considerable argument about the exact date of [[Gautama]] but authorities place him about 550 BC., making him almost a contemporary of [[Buddha]].
 
There is considerable argument about the exact date of [[Gautama]] but authorities place him about 550 BC., making him almost a contemporary of [[Buddha]].
  
According to [[tradition]], [[Gautama]], the founder of the [[Nyāya]], was born in the village of Gautama-sthāna, and each year a fair is held in this village in his honour on the 9th day of the [[lunar month]] of [[Wikipedia:Chaitra|Caitra]] (March-April). The village is located 28 {{Wiki|miles}} [[north east]] of Darbhaṅga.
+
According to [[tradition]], [[Gautama]], the founder of the [[Nyāya]], was born in the village of [[Gautama-sthāna]], and each year a fair is held in this village in his honour on the 9th day of the [[lunar month]] of [[Wikipedia:Chaitra|Caitra]] (March-April). The village is located 28 {{Wiki|miles}} [[north east]] of [[Darbhaṅga]].
  
 
Before [[Gautama]], the {{Wiki|principles}} of the [[Nyāya]] existed as an unsorted [[body]] of [[philosophical]] [[thought]], concerning things that can be known and on the means of acquiring such [[knowledge]].
 
Before [[Gautama]], the {{Wiki|principles}} of the [[Nyāya]] existed as an unsorted [[body]] of [[philosophical]] [[thought]], concerning things that can be known and on the means of acquiring such [[knowledge]].
Line 41: Line 41:
 
According to nyāyikas the [[world]] presents itself us as a chain of {{Wiki|consequences}} which needs to be broken in [[order]] to attain [[Liberation]] from [[suffering]].
 
According to nyāyikas the [[world]] presents itself us as a chain of {{Wiki|consequences}} which needs to be broken in [[order]] to attain [[Liberation]] from [[suffering]].
  
Misapprehension [[[ajñāna]]]
+
Misapprehension [[ajñāna]]
=> imbalance[[[doṣa]]]
+
 
=> [[activity]] [[[karma]]]
+
=> imbalance [[doṣa]]]
  => [[rebirth]] [[[janma]]]
+
=> [[activity]] [[karma]]
  => [[suffering]] [[[duḥkha]]]
+
  => [[rebirth]] [[janma]]
 +
  => [[suffering]] [[duḥkha]]
  
 
Misapprehension — the inability to see things as they really are; the superimposition of false [[ideas]] and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] upon [[reality]] — identification of the [[Self]] with the mind/body complex.
 
Misapprehension — the inability to see things as they really are; the superimposition of false [[ideas]] and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] upon [[reality]] — identification of the [[Self]] with the mind/body complex.
Line 116: Line 117:
 
6. Demonstrated [[Truth]] [[siddhānta]]
 
6. Demonstrated [[Truth]] [[siddhānta]]
 
7. Factors of {{Wiki|Reasoning}} —[[syllogism]] [[avayava]]
 
7. Factors of {{Wiki|Reasoning}} —[[syllogism]] [[avayava]]
8. {{Wiki|Reasoning}} and confutation tarka
+
8. {{Wiki|Reasoning}} and confutation [[tarka]]
 
9. Ascertainment [[nirṇaya]]
 
9. Ascertainment [[nirṇaya]]
 
10. [[Discussion]] [[vāda]]
 
10. [[Discussion]] [[vāda]]
Line 124: Line 125:
 
14. Casuistry (unfair {{Wiki|reasoning}}) [[chala]]
 
14. Casuistry (unfair {{Wiki|reasoning}}) [[chala]]
 
15. Futile Rejoinder [[jāti]]
 
15. Futile Rejoinder [[jāti]]
16. Clinchers nigraha-sthāna
+
16. Clinchers [[nigraha-sthāna]]
  
 
The first two are the most important. The first nine deal more strictly with [[logic]], while the last seven have the [[function]] of preventing and mitigating error.
 
The first two are the most important. The first nine deal more strictly with [[logic]], while the last seven have the [[function]] of preventing and mitigating error.
Line 133: Line 134:
 
=> [[definition]]
 
=> [[definition]]
 
=>{{Wiki|examination}}
 
=>{{Wiki|examination}}
[[1]]. THE MEANS OF RIGHT [[KNOWLEDGE]]
+
 
[[[Pramāṇa]]]
+
 
 +
1. THE MEANS OF RIGHT [[KNOWLEDGE]]
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Pramāṇa]]
  
 
[[Definition]] of [[Right Knowledge]] ([[pramā]])
 
[[Definition]] of [[Right Knowledge]] ([[pramā]])
  
Yathāvasthita vyavahārāṇuguṇa jñānam [[pramā]]
+
[[Yathāvasthita vyavahārāṇuguṇa jñānam pramā]]
 +
 
 +
 
 
[[Right knowledge]] is that which reveals a thing as it actually is and is {{Wiki|pragmatic}}.
 
[[Right knowledge]] is that which reveals a thing as it actually is and is {{Wiki|pragmatic}}.
  
 
[[Knowledge]] is said to be true when there is –
 
[[Knowledge]] is said to be true when there is –
  
[[1]]. Coherence
+
1. Coherence
 
2. [[Correspondence]]
 
2. [[Correspondence]]
 
3. Consequence or Utility
 
3. Consequence or Utility
 +
  
 
Coherence —The statement must be [[logical]] and consistent.
 
Coherence —The statement must be [[logical]] and consistent.
  
[[Correspondence]] —the [[knowledge]] must correspond to the actual [[nature]] of [[the object]] as it is. (tadvati-tat-prakāraka)
+
[[Correspondence]] —the [[knowledge]] must correspond to the actual [[nature]] of [[the object]] as it is. ([[tadvati-tat-prakāraka]])
  
Consequence — Utility —our {{Wiki|practical}} [[activities]] in [[relation]] to [[the object]] are successful. (pravṛtti-samārthya).In other words we can do something with it.
+
Consequence — Utility —our {{Wiki|practical}} [[activities]] in [[relation]] to [[the object]] are successful. ([[pravṛtti-samārthya]]).In other words we can do something with it.
  
 
[[Right knowledge]] ([[pramā]]) reveals a thing as it really is and leads to successful utilisation thereof.
 
[[Right knowledge]] ([[pramā]]) reveals a thing as it really is and leads to successful utilisation thereof.
Line 205: Line 213:
  
 
They are not considered as {{Wiki|independent}} means of [[right knowledge]] because they do not [[form]] a separate category, and there is no need to consider them separately.
 
They are not considered as {{Wiki|independent}} means of [[right knowledge]] because they do not [[form]] a separate category, and there is no need to consider them separately.
 +
 +
 
1:1 [[Perception]] ([[pratyakṣa]])
 
1:1 [[Perception]] ([[pratyakṣa]])
  
Line 211: Line 221:
 
[[Sense perception]] is of two kinds:-
 
[[Sense perception]] is of two kinds:-
  
[[1]]. {{Wiki|Indeterminate}} (nirvikalpaka) or abstract —general, non-specific.
+
1. {{Wiki|Indeterminate}} ([[nirvikalpaka]]) or abstract —general, non-specific.
2. {{Wiki|Determinate}} (savikalpaka) or concrete —specific.
+
2. {{Wiki|Determinate}} ([[savikalpaka]]) or concrete —specific.
  
 
"{{Wiki|Indeterminate}}" [[knowledge]] is vague and non-specific —
 
"{{Wiki|Indeterminate}}" [[knowledge]] is vague and non-specific —
Line 243: Line 253:
 
e.g., on [[seeing]] a [[river]] swollen, one infers that there has been [[rain]] fall.
 
e.g., on [[seeing]] a [[river]] swollen, one infers that there has been [[rain]] fall.
  
3. It may also be what is termed 'commonly seen,'(samānyatodṛṣṭa) which is [[knowledge]] of [[one thing]] derived from the [[perception]] of another thing with which it is commonly seen;
+
3. It may also be what is termed 'commonly seen,'([[samānyatodṛṣṭa]]) which is [[knowledge]] of [[one thing]] derived from the [[perception]] of another thing with which it is commonly seen;
  
 
e.g., on [[seeing]] [[rain]], one infers that there are clouds.
 
e.g., on [[seeing]] [[rain]], one infers that there are clouds.
Line 257: Line 267:
  
 
Analogy has been regarded in [[Nyāya]] as an {{Wiki|independent}} means of [[Right Knowledge]] because it brings about a [[right cognition]] that cannot be achieved through either [[sense-perception]] or {{Wiki|inference}}.
 
Analogy has been regarded in [[Nyāya]] as an {{Wiki|independent}} means of [[Right Knowledge]] because it brings about a [[right cognition]] that cannot be achieved through either [[sense-perception]] or {{Wiki|inference}}.
1:4 [[Verbal]] Testimony ([[śabda]]/ āgama/āpta-vākya)
+
 
 +
 
 +
1:4 [[Verbal]] Testimony ([[śabda]]/ [[āgama]]/[[āpta-vākya]])
  
 
The instructive [[assertion]] of a reliable [[person]] (āpta), that is, one who is possessed of true [[knowledge]] and is truthful.
 
The instructive [[assertion]] of a reliable [[person]] (āpta), that is, one who is possessed of true [[knowledge]] and is truthful.
Line 285: Line 297:
 
[[[Prameya]]]
 
[[[Prameya]]]
  
The [[body]] [[[śarīra]]] | [[Self]] [[[ātman]]] | [[Senses]] [[[indriya]]] | [[Experiences]] [[[artha]]]| [[Intelligence]] [[[buddhi]]] | {{Wiki|Intellect}} [[[manas]]]| [[Activity]] [[[pravṛtti]]] | Imbalances [[[doṣa]]]| Consequence [[[phala]]] | [[Suffering]] [[[duḥkha]]]| [[Re-birth]] [pratyabhāva] | [[Liberation]] [[[apavarga]]]
+
The [[body]] [[[śarīra]]] | [[Self]] [[[ātman]]] | [[Senses]] [[[indriya]]] | [[Experiences]] [[[artha]]]| [[Intelligence]] [[[buddhi]]] | {{Wiki|Intellect}} [[[manas]]]| [[Activity]] [[[pravṛtti]]] | Imbalances [[[doṣa]]]| Consequence [[[phala]]] | [[Suffering]] [[[duḥkha]]]| [[Re-birth]] [[pratyabhāva]] | [[Liberation]] [[[apavarga]]]
  
 
There are many things that might be regarded as topics of [[right knowledge]], but these 12 are especially significant:
 
There are many things that might be regarded as topics of [[right knowledge]], but these 12 are especially significant:
Line 301: Line 313:
 
[[pleasure]] ([[sukha]]) | [[pain]] ([[duḥkha]])
 
[[pleasure]] ([[sukha]]) | [[pain]] ([[duḥkha]])
  
[[knowledge]] ([[jñāna]]) | striving(prayatna)
+
[[knowledge]] ([[jñāna]]) | striving([[prayatna]])
  
 
=> These are [[experiences]] which are common to all [[sentient beings]].
 
=> These are [[experiences]] which are common to all [[sentient beings]].
Line 317: Line 329:
 
The [[body]] is that which is the locus of {{Wiki|motion}} (ceṣṭa), of the [[senses]] (iṅdriyas) and of their effects/experiences (arthas) of [[pleasure]] and [[pain]].
 
The [[body]] is that which is the locus of {{Wiki|motion}} (ceṣṭa), of the [[senses]] (iṅdriyas) and of their effects/experiences (arthas) of [[pleasure]] and [[pain]].
  
=> The [[body]] is the field of the Ātman’s [[experiences]] as it strives to attain what is [[pleasurable]] and avoid what is un-pleasurable.
+
=> The [[body]] is the field of the [[Ātman’s]] [[experiences]] as it strives to attain what is [[pleasurable]] and avoid what is un-pleasurable.
  
 
=> All these [[activities]] are actualised through the 10 [[senses]], the instruments through which the [[ātman]] receives {{Wiki|stimuli}} from the [[external world]] and through which it reacts to those {{Wiki|stimuli}}.
 
=> All these [[activities]] are actualised through the 10 [[senses]], the instruments through which the [[ātman]] receives {{Wiki|stimuli}} from the [[external world]] and through which it reacts to those {{Wiki|stimuli}}.
Line 403: Line 415:
 
Here it must be remembered that the [[hatred]] of [[pain]] is none the less [[hatred]]; and until all such reactions are removed by true [[knowledge]], one will remain [[attached]] to the [[illusory]] [[world]] of [[name]] [[[nāma]] —[[mind]]] and [[form]] [[[rūpa]] —[[body]]].
 
Here it must be remembered that the [[hatred]] of [[pain]] is none the less [[hatred]]; and until all such reactions are removed by true [[knowledge]], one will remain [[attached]] to the [[illusory]] [[world]] of [[name]] [[[nāma]] —[[mind]]] and [[form]] [[[rūpa]] —[[body]]].
  
[[Self-realisation]] [ātma-bodha] is acquired by [[constant]] study and {{Wiki|reflection}} on the [[Dharma]].
+
[[Self-realisation]] [[ātma-bodha]] is acquired by [[constant]] study and {{Wiki|reflection}} on the [[Dharma]].
  
 
In this way [[wisdom]] can be matured until all [[doubt]] has been removed, and the [[mind]] will then [[awaken]] to the latent potential {{Wiki|lying}} within.
 
In this way [[wisdom]] can be matured until all [[doubt]] has been removed, and the [[mind]] will then [[awaken]] to the latent potential {{Wiki|lying}} within.
Line 427: Line 439:
 
An impediment that hinders the progress of the [[Self]].
 
An impediment that hinders the progress of the [[Self]].
  
=> The [[body]] is said to be the abode of [[suffering]] [duḥkha-ālaya];
+
=> The [[body]] is said to be the abode of [[suffering]] [[duḥkha-ālaya]];
  
 
=> The [[senses]] are the instruments whereby we [[experience]] [[suffering]],
 
=> The [[senses]] are the instruments whereby we [[experience]] [[suffering]],
Line 441: Line 453:
 
It can, therefore, be said that one who is addicted to the pursuit of [[pleasure]] is in [[reality]] given to the pursuit of [[pain]], for there is no [[pleasure]], in the [[attainment]] and [[enjoyment]] of which, [[pain]] in some [[form]] or other is not {{Wiki|present}}.
 
It can, therefore, be said that one who is addicted to the pursuit of [[pleasure]] is in [[reality]] given to the pursuit of [[pain]], for there is no [[pleasure]], in the [[attainment]] and [[enjoyment]] of which, [[pain]] in some [[form]] or other is not {{Wiki|present}}.
  
2:11. [[Rebirth]] (pratyabhāva)
+
2:11. [[Rebirth]] ([[pratyabhāva]])
  
 
The re-embodiment of the animating [[principle]] [jīva] in [[physical form]] after [[death]].
 
The re-embodiment of the animating [[principle]] [jīva] in [[physical form]] after [[death]].
Line 463: Line 475:
 
The [[śāstras]] teach that the following 4 things must be investigated and known by the discerning aspirant:—
 
The [[śāstras]] teach that the following 4 things must be investigated and known by the discerning aspirant:—
  
([[1]]) that [[rebirth]], {{Wiki|consequences}}, and [[pain]] are the things to be known;
+
(1) that [[rebirth]], {{Wiki|consequences}}, and [[pain]] are the things to be known;
 
(2) that [[action]] and the faults are to be avoided;
 
(2) that [[action]] and the faults are to be avoided;
 
(3) that [[Liberation]] is the goal to be pursued; and
 
(3) that [[Liberation]] is the goal to be pursued; and
Line 474: Line 486:
 
[[Right Knowledge]] is developed by;
 
[[Right Knowledge]] is developed by;
  
[[1]]. Self-restraint. (dama)
+
[[1]]. Self-restraint. ([[dama]])
  
 
2. Holding the [[mind]] steadfast and focused upon the [[ātman]] by sustained [[effort]], maintaining a [[state of tranquillity]] ([[sama]]).
 
2. Holding the [[mind]] steadfast and focused upon the [[ātman]] by sustained [[effort]], maintaining a [[state of tranquillity]] ([[sama]]).
Line 480: Line 492:
 
The motivating force to develop [[right knowledge]] is a strong [[desire]] to know the [[Truth]].
 
The motivating force to develop [[right knowledge]] is a strong [[desire]] to know the [[Truth]].
 
By habitual [[cultivation]] of this [[state]], one learns to rest within the [[Self]], and [[enlightenment]] dawns.
 
By habitual [[cultivation]] of this [[state]], one learns to rest within the [[Self]], and [[enlightenment]] dawns.
 +
 +
 +
 
3. DOUBT [[[saṁśaya]]]
 
3. DOUBT [[[saṁśaya]]]
 +
  
 
A conflicting [[judgment]] about the precise [[character]] of an [[object]], [[arising]] from the {{Wiki|recognition}} of properties common to many [[objects]], or of properties not common to any of the [[objects]], from conflicting testimony, and from irregularity of [[perception]] and [[non-perception]].
 
A conflicting [[judgment]] about the precise [[character]] of an [[object]], [[arising]] from the {{Wiki|recognition}} of properties common to many [[objects]], or of properties not common to any of the [[objects]], from conflicting testimony, and from irregularity of [[perception]] and [[non-perception]].
Line 490: Line 506:
 
Error is defined as that [[knowledge]] which does not lead to successful [[action]].
 
Error is defined as that [[knowledge]] which does not lead to successful [[action]].
  
For example, it is impossible to fulfil the expectations created by [[hallucinations]]. In other words, the {{Wiki|ideal}} [[world]] of [[thought]] must correspond to the outer [[reality]] in [[order]] to be considered true.
+
For example, it is impossible to fulfill the expectations created by [[hallucinations]]. In other words, the {{Wiki|ideal}} [[world]] of [[thought]] must correspond to the outer [[reality]] in [[order]] to be considered true.
  
 
The {{Wiki|rules}} of [[Nyāya]] are to be applied when [[doubt]] has arisen, and it becomes necessary, therefore, to examine [[reality]] for confirmation.
 
The {{Wiki|rules}} of [[Nyāya]] are to be applied when [[doubt]] has arisen, and it becomes necessary, therefore, to examine [[reality]] for confirmation.
Line 511: Line 527:
  
 
e.g. [[being]] unable to believe that something [[exists]] based on never having [[perceived]] a thing with qualities as described. Or inability to believe that such a thing [[exists]].
 
e.g. [[being]] unable to believe that something [[exists]] based on never having [[perceived]] a thing with qualities as described. Or inability to believe that such a thing [[exists]].
 +
 +
  
 
4. MOTIVE [[[prayojana]]]
 
4. MOTIVE [[[prayojana]]]
Line 523: Line 541:
  
 
No act is of itself either good or bad, there as {{Wiki|sincere}} [[spiritual]] aspirants we should always be examining and {{Wiki|reflecting}} upon our motives.
 
No act is of itself either good or bad, there as {{Wiki|sincere}} [[spiritual]] aspirants we should always be examining and {{Wiki|reflecting}} upon our motives.
 +
  
 
5. CORROBORATIVE INSTANCE (familiar example) [[[dṛṣṭānta]]]
 
5. CORROBORATIVE INSTANCE (familiar example) [[[dṛṣṭānta]]]
Line 529: Line 548:
  
 
Both [[scientists]] and [[laymen]] accept the general proposition that whenever there is [[rain]] there must be clouds; therefore, such an example can be used as an example in the process of {{Wiki|reasoning}} from the known to the unknown.
 
Both [[scientists]] and [[laymen]] accept the general proposition that whenever there is [[rain]] there must be clouds; therefore, such an example can be used as an example in the process of {{Wiki|reasoning}} from the known to the unknown.
 +
 +
  
 
6. DEMONSTRATED [[TRUTH]] [[[siddhānta]]]
 
6. DEMONSTRATED [[TRUTH]] [[[siddhānta]]]
Line 535: Line 556:
  
 
[[Siddhānta]] is a conclusion that is recognised as proven by a certain school of [[philosophy]].
 
[[Siddhānta]] is a conclusion that is recognised as proven by a certain school of [[philosophy]].
 +
 +
  
 
These are of 4 kinds of [[Siddhānta]]:—
 
These are of 4 kinds of [[Siddhānta]]:—
Line 701: Line 724:
 
There are, therefore, 2 kinds of concomitance: {{Wiki|equivalent}} and non-equivalent.
 
There are, therefore, 2 kinds of concomitance: {{Wiki|equivalent}} and non-equivalent.
  
a. Non-equivalent concomitance (asama-vyāpti) is an [[invariable concomitance]] between 2 unequal entities (such as smoke and [[fire]]).
+
a. Non-equivalent concomitance ([[asama-vyāpti]]) is an [[invariable concomitance]] between 2 unequal entities (such as smoke and [[fire]]).
  
 
It has already been shown that in this type of concomitance, one [[entity]] may be inferred from the other, but not [[vice versa]].
 
It has already been shown that in this type of concomitance, one [[entity]] may be inferred from the other, but not [[vice versa]].
  
b. {{Wiki|Equivalent}} concomitance (sama-vyāpti) is an [[invariable concomitance]] between two coexistent terms, either of which can be inferred from the other.
+
b. {{Wiki|Equivalent}} concomitance ([[sama-vyāpti]]) is an [[invariable concomitance]] between two coexistent terms, either of which can be inferred from the other.
  
 
For example, a chair is a nameable thing because a chair is knowable, and whatever is knowable, is nameable.
 
For example, a chair is a nameable thing because a chair is knowable, and whatever is knowable, is nameable.
Line 711: Line 734:
 
Here nameable and knowable can both be inferred from each other.
 
Here nameable and knowable can both be inferred from each other.
  
Concomitance thus denotes a relationship of coexistence (sahacarya). But not every instance of coexistence is an example of concomitance. [[Fire]], for example, often coexists with smoke, yet it may [[exist]] without smoke.
+
Concomitance thus denotes a relationship of coexistence ([[sahacarya]]). But not every instance of coexistence is an example of concomitance. [[Fire]], for example, often coexists with smoke, yet it may [[exist]] without smoke.
  
 
The coexistent relationship of [[fire]] and smoke depends on certain [[conditions]] – temperature and {{Wiki|wetness}}, for instance:
 
The coexistent relationship of [[fire]] and smoke depends on certain [[conditions]] – temperature and {{Wiki|wetness}}, for instance:
Line 717: Line 740:
 
The limiting [[condition]] on which the [[relation]] of coexistence depends is called [[upādhi]], and for an {{Wiki|inference}} to be valid, the [[relation]] between the middle and major terms of a [[syllogism]] must be {{Wiki|independent}} of any and all [[conditions]].
 
The limiting [[condition]] on which the [[relation]] of coexistence depends is called [[upādhi]], and for an {{Wiki|inference}} to be valid, the [[relation]] between the middle and major terms of a [[syllogism]] must be {{Wiki|independent}} of any and all [[conditions]].
  
In other words, a valid concomitance represents an invariable and unconditional [[concomitant]] [[relation]] ([[nitya]] anaupādika saṁbandha) between the middle and major terms of a [[syllogism]].
+
In other words, a valid concomitance represents an invariable and unconditional [[concomitant]] [[relation]] ([[nitya anaupādika saṁbandha]]) between the middle and major terms of a [[syllogism]].
  
 
But how does one know that a [[relation]] is invariable and unconditional?
 
But how does one know that a [[relation]] is invariable and unconditional?
Line 723: Line 746:
 
The [[Wikipedia:Vedanta|Vedānta]] [[philosophers]] reply that concomitance is established by the uncontradicted [[experiences]] of the relationships between two things.
 
The [[Wikipedia:Vedanta|Vedānta]] [[philosophers]] reply that concomitance is established by the uncontradicted [[experiences]] of the relationships between two things.
  
But according to [[Nyāya]], concomitance is established through the [[perception]] of classes (samānya [[lakṣaṇa]] [[perception]]).
+
But according to [[Nyāya]], concomitance is established through the [[perception]] of classes ([[samānya lakṣaṇa perception]]).
  
 
Actually, the [[Nyāya]] method of {{Wiki|inference}} uses [[inductive reasoning]]; that is, it draws a particular conclusion on the grounds of a general and universally known [[truth]].
 
Actually, the [[Nyāya]] method of {{Wiki|inference}} uses [[inductive reasoning]]; that is, it draws a particular conclusion on the grounds of a general and universally known [[truth]].
Line 745: Line 768:
 
=> The third kind of inductive process is a combination of the first and second methods:
 
=> The third kind of inductive process is a combination of the first and second methods:
  
In this method, known as {{Wiki|uniform}} agreement in both presence and absence ([[anvaya-vyatireka]] or vyabhicāra-graha), both constituents of a relationship are always found together; neither is ever {{Wiki|present}} without the other. From this, it is induced that there must [[exist]] a natural relationship of [[invariable concomitance]] between them.
+
In this method, known as {{Wiki|uniform}} agreement in both presence and absence ([[anvaya-vyatireka]] or [[vyabhicāra-graha]]), both constituents of a relationship are always found together; neither is ever {{Wiki|present}} without the other. From this, it is induced that there must [[exist]] a natural relationship of [[invariable concomitance]] between them.
  
 
These three methods of generalization demonstrate a systematic technique for [[inductive reasoning]].
 
These three methods of generalization demonstrate a systematic technique for [[inductive reasoning]].
Line 751: Line 774:
 
The most crucial [[concern]], however, in any systematic {{Wiki|inference}} is how to make certain that concomitance, the [[logical]] basis for the {{Wiki|inference}}, is valid – that is, free from limiting [[conditions]] (upādhis).
 
The most crucial [[concern]], however, in any systematic {{Wiki|inference}} is how to make certain that concomitance, the [[logical]] basis for the {{Wiki|inference}}, is valid – that is, free from limiting [[conditions]] (upādhis).
  
  This process of insuring that vyāptis are free from all vitiating [[conditions]] is called upādhi-nirasa.
+
  This process of insuring that [[vyāptis]] are free from all vitiating [[conditions]] is called upādhi-nirasa.
  
 
One way of insuring this is by the repeated observation of both constituents of a relationship under all possible circumstances to make certain that the relationship is in fact invariable.
 
One way of insuring this is by the repeated observation of both constituents of a relationship under all possible circumstances to make certain that the relationship is in fact invariable.
Line 757: Line 780:
 
Another way is to employ {{Wiki|hypothetical}} critical {{Wiki|argumentation}} or tarka.
 
Another way is to employ {{Wiki|hypothetical}} critical {{Wiki|argumentation}} or tarka.
  
But [[Nyāya]] places the greatest {{Wiki|emphasis}} on samānya [[lakṣaṇa]] – the [[perception]] of general classes – as the major means for insuring the validity of vyāptis.
+
But [[Nyāya]] places the greatest {{Wiki|emphasis}} on [[samānya lakṣaṇa]] – the [[perception]] of general classes – as the major means for insuring the validity of [[vyāptis]].
 +
 
 +
 
  
 
13. FALLACIOUS REASONING [[[hetvābhāsa]] ]
 
13. FALLACIOUS REASONING [[[hetvābhāsa]] ]
  
These are: [[1]]. the irregular middle (sabyabhicāra), 2. the [[contradictory]] ([[viruddha]]), 3. the inconclusive (satpratipakṣa), 4. the unproved ([[asiddha]]), and 5. the Anachronism (bādhita).
+
These are: [[1]]. the irregular middle ([[sabyabhicāra]]), 2. the [[contradictory]] ([[viruddha]]), 3. the inconclusive (satpratipakṣa), 4. the unproved ([[asiddha]]), and 5. the Anachronism (bādhita).
  
 
These are the five [[forms]] of erroneous {{Wiki|reasoning}}. To understand the {{Wiki|reasoning}} we need to bear
 
These are the five [[forms]] of erroneous {{Wiki|reasoning}}. To understand the {{Wiki|reasoning}} we need to bear
Line 834: Line 859:
 
3. the impossible
 
3. the impossible
  
8. HYPOTHETICAL REASONING [tarka],
+
8. HYPOTHETICAL REASONING [[tarka]],
  
 
- A process for ascertaining the real [[nature]] of a thing of which the [[character]] is not known. A method of arriving at the [[truth]] by showing the absurdity of all contrary [[ideas]].
 
- A process for ascertaining the real [[nature]] of a thing of which the [[character]] is not known. A method of arriving at the [[truth]] by showing the absurdity of all contrary [[ideas]].
  
Tarka is a method of [[attaining]] [[knowledge]] of the [[truth]] about an unknown thing by comparing and then gradually eliminating all the competing suppositions;
+
[[Tarka]] is a method of [[attaining]] [[knowledge]] of the [[truth]] about an unknown thing by comparing and then gradually eliminating all the competing suppositions;
  
 
Example - Is the [[Self]] a product or a non-Product?
 
Example - Is the [[Self]] a product or a non-Product?
Line 851: Line 876:
  
 
It simply eliminates all other contesting theories to the supposition it supports; after which [[Truth]] is established through the [[application]] of other means of [[Right Knowledge]]. For this [[reason]] Confutation is considered to be a supporting technique and is, therefore mentioned separately.
 
It simply eliminates all other contesting theories to the supposition it supports; after which [[Truth]] is established through the [[application]] of other means of [[Right Knowledge]]. For this [[reason]] Confutation is considered to be a supporting technique and is, therefore mentioned separately.
 +
 +
  
 
9. DIALECTIC [[[nirṇaya]]]
 
9. DIALECTIC [[[nirṇaya]]]
 +
 +
  
 
- The removal of [[doubts]], and the resolution of a dispute, by examining two opposite [[views]].
 
- The removal of [[doubts]], and the resolution of a dispute, by examining two opposite [[views]].
Line 872: Line 901:
  
 
Ascertainment is unnecessary in the case of direct [[perception]] or [[verbal]] testimony.
 
Ascertainment is unnecessary in the case of direct [[perception]] or [[verbal]] testimony.
 +
 +
  
 
10. DISCUSSION [[[vāda]]]
 
10. DISCUSSION [[[vāda]]]
 +
 +
  
 
- A {{Wiki|dialogue}} in which one adopts one of two opposing positions.
 
- A {{Wiki|dialogue}} in which one adopts one of two opposing positions.
Line 884: Line 917:
  
 
The usual procedure is to maintain the {{Wiki|thesis}} by means of [[Right Knowledge]] and to attack the counter-thesis by means of tarka.
 
The usual procedure is to maintain the {{Wiki|thesis}} by means of [[Right Knowledge]] and to attack the counter-thesis by means of tarka.
 +
 +
  
 
11. POLEMIC [[[jalpa]]]
 
11. POLEMIC [[[jalpa]]]
 +
 +
  
 
A [[verbal]] disputation directed at gaining victory.
 
A [[verbal]] disputation directed at gaining victory.
Line 894: Line 931:
  
 
These devices are usually of a negative [[character]], such as attacking the opponent’s [[character]], (argumentum ad hominem) [[quibbling]], advancing futile arguments, reducing to absurdity, evading the issue etc.
 
These devices are usually of a negative [[character]], such as attacking the opponent’s [[character]], (argumentum ad hominem) [[quibbling]], advancing futile arguments, reducing to absurdity, evading the issue etc.
 +
 +
  
 
12. CAVIL [[[vitaṇḍā]]]
 
12. CAVIL [[[vitaṇḍā]]]
 +
  
 
- A kind of [[wrangling]], which consists in mere attacks on the opposite side.
 
- A kind of [[wrangling]], which consists in mere attacks on the opposite side.
Line 909: Line 949:
 
Under such circumstances the [[student]] is urged to make use of these argumentative devices in [[order]] to safeguard the [[development]] of [[knowledge]] in the same way that [[nature]] uses thorns on some [[plants]] to safeguard the growth of its [[fruit]].
 
Under such circumstances the [[student]] is urged to make use of these argumentative devices in [[order]] to safeguard the [[development]] of [[knowledge]] in the same way that [[nature]] uses thorns on some [[plants]] to safeguard the growth of its [[fruit]].
  
14 CASUISTRY [cala]
+
 
 +
 
 +
14 CASUISTRY [[cala]]
 +
 
  
 
- The [[opposition]] [[offered]] to a proposition by the assumption of an alternative meaning.
 
- The [[opposition]] [[offered]] to a proposition by the assumption of an alternative meaning.
Line 948: Line 991:
 
23. Balancing the eternality. 24. Balancing the effect.
 
23. Balancing the eternality. 24. Balancing the effect.
  
16. CLINCHERS [nigraha-sthāna]
+
16. CLINCHERS [[nigraha-sthāna]]
  
 
- A situation in which one misunderstands, or does not understand at all.
 
- A situation in which one misunderstands, or does not understand at all.

Revision as of 10:41, 26 October 2015

132j1813.jpg
57la-alus.jpg
P1060190.jpg
1.125891.jpg
Ma66pg.jpg
84972 top.jpg
33139398.png
12122..jpg
BAMdf.jpg
Manjushri 00.jpg
One-300.jpg
6991 g.jpg
Guru-Rinpoche-104.jpg
Shaman921.jpg
Akshobya-detail-0011.jpg
Encxv959-4.jpg
BeoGh46CIAEdf.jpg
500 det.jpg
10156bnmmv.jpg
0vx 2.jpg
87250-84352.jpg
Who-r.jpg
Raha1.jpg
Tehjnks.jpg
12ncontal.jpg
LS13 large.jpg
Hafeme1.jpeg
Bfgit NCdf.jpg
415 small.jpg
E486ab78 z.jpg
Shamanism35212.png
10cvbb13 n.jpg
Images576.jpg
4146378.jpg
Shitennoj honbo garden06s3200.jpg
MonksPoisid.jpg
Kuh0103.JPG
8v17ghh n.jpg
Mby-sea.jpg
Gu aal-00.jpg
Watkung 01.jpg
16787828-lg.jpg
Brain-Powe.jpg
4-ilma-Guru.jpg
12ukkphics.jpg
BfhCN5df.jpg
6a0.jpg
201212zc008.jpg
9629384 n.jpg
Mbhava1.jpg
Daishonin.psd.jpg
Tain.jpg
Jowo statue.jpg
BUDDHA hot.jpg
20czHAILAND.jpg
Yamantaka2.45jpg.jpg
6ff.JPG
3bn.png
Kurukulla15132.jpg
Guru-rves-Lootosel.jpg
Kuh0064.JPG
Sitapatra-0000.JPG
Amido-body.jpg
7-26-1.jpg
BgyuaY.jpg
6fhG8a.jpg
14638zxc.jpg
Schubring 001.jpg
1jetsuntara.jpg
Ima4ge15.jpg
Chipmunk.jpg
Awaking.jpg
Abha inet.jpg
5c7a54887.jpg
72a235 z.jpg
3d l 114.jpg
201cxNUNS.jpg
Msdnfluiu.jpg
Sakjamuni-Troonil-00.jpg
100xc.jpg
435.jpg
Img 9868.jpg
泰山 南天门.jpg
Imagcxes.jpg
2018.jpg
Ngagpa-35.jpg
Kri0018.JPG
03246901X300.jpg
Herab th.jpg
008.jpg73.jpg
55828 n.jpg
Mental 01.jpg
Dharmachakra.jpg
Kidgsses.jpg
Tushita 11.jpg
Transcendental-Medit1.jpg
3dfrs.jpg
Milarepa-line-gurus.jpg
Athāgata.jpg
6Oq2RZVl.jpg


Nyāya - The School of Logicians

The Nyāya is the science of logic, and provides the only sound methodology of philosophical inquiry into the nature of knowledge and the objects of knowledge.

It is the means to obtain Right Knowledge(pramā)about the Self and to discover the purpose of life.

The only way to impart our experience to others and to elucidate their implications for the rest of our life and defend their validity against hostile criticism is by means of logic.

The term Nyāya in Sanskrit signifies "going into a subject," —an analytical investigation of the subject through the process of logical reasoning.

Vātsyāyana, the classic commentator on the Nyāya-Sūtra, defines it as:

"a critical examination of the objects of knowledge by means of the canons of logical proof."

The Nyāya is also called Tarka-vidyā, "science of reasoning," or Vāda-vidyā "science of discussion."'

The founder of the Nyāya was Gautama (Gotama) who is frequently-referred to in the literature as Akṣa-pāda, “Eye-footed," and Dīrgha-tapas, "Long-penance."

In ancient India it was customary to give people nicknames which gave a descriptive characterisation of the individual.

Gautama probably received these names from his habit of performing long penances during his periods of study and from the fact that he was customarily seen with his eyes directed toward his feet when walking, (probably due to his deep reflection while strolling)

There is considerable argument about the exact date of Gautama but authorities place him about 550 BC., making him almost a contemporary of Buddha.

According to tradition, Gautama, the founder of the Nyāya, was born in the village of Gautama-sthāna, and each year a fair is held in this village in his honour on the 9th day of the lunar month of Caitra (March-April). The village is located 28 miles north east of Darbhaṅga.

Before Gautama, the principles of the Nyāya existed as an unsorted body of philosophical thought, concerning things that can be known and on the means of acquiring such knowledge.

Gautama merely formulated the generally accepted principles of the time.
The Problem

All systems of Indian philosophy begin with the problem of sufferingduḥkha.

The goal of the Nyāya is to enable us to attain the highest goal of life which is Liberation from duḥkha and the attendant cycle of births and deathsmokṣa, variously known as ‘release’, ‘freedom’, ‘emancipation’ or nirvāṇa –the state of non-return to birth/death.

According to nyāyikas the world presents itself us as a chain of consequences which needs to be broken in order to attain Liberation from suffering.

Misapprehension ajñāna

=> imbalance doṣa]
=> activity karma
 => rebirth janma
 => suffering duḥkha

Misapprehension — the inability to see things as they really are; the superimposition of false ideas and concepts upon reality — identification of the Self with the mind/body complex.

Imbalance —ego-centrism, and the creation of a vast network of false identities and ideologies in order to bolster and maintain the ego —activated by the three dynamic forces of attraction, aversion and delusion.

Karmaactivity in accordance with this false view of ourselves and the world; designed to perpetuate our transient selves and to give some meaning to our lives.

All actions involving other beings have 3 possible outcomes: negative (cause suffering), positive (cause joy), or neutral.

Negative and positive acts result in consequences which are experienced either now or later.

Rebirth —in order to actualise the karma that we have created for good or bad.

Sufferingdisease, dissatisfaction, unhappiness, stress, depression etc.
The Solution

1. The way to break this chain is to obtain insight and wisdom (jñāna).

2. Wisdom dissolves the delusive identification of the Self with the mind-body complex.

3. The doṣas causing us to like and dislike a thing will no longer exist. When this disappears, there will no longer be any desire which is the stimulus for all goal orientated activity.

4. Cessation from action will break the eternal bond of karma which will then free us from rebirth; the cause of all sorrow and suffering, and enable us to achieve the supreme end of life [[[mokṣa]]].

5. This goal can be attained by thoroughly studying and understanding the 4 topics presented in the Nyāya sūtras, namely:

(1) The thing to be avoided (i.e., duḥkha)
(2) Its cause (i.e., desire, attachment and ignorance)
(3) Its solution i.e. absolute avoidance
(4) The means of such avoidance (i.e., true knowledge of things as they really are)

The Nyāya examines the logic and coherence of philosophical or religious statements, and by comparing such statements with other widely-held beliefs about life, assess the appropriateness of accepting them as true.
What is rational?

— The rational process is one in which conclusion are drawn from premises by a sequel of mental steps which can be followed, verified, and which others (provided they understand the meaning of the words used) would accept as being true —true for everyone, not just for that particular individual).

The study of Nyāya enables us to discern the true from the false, and ensures the avoidance of false teachings and beliefs while knowledge matures into the dawning of enlightenment.

Today, as was the case centuries ago we are confronted by many gurus with many teachings. The conflicting doctrines of each new sect and teacher raises doubts as to which is the right path. The spiritual aspirant is confronted with the same problem of trying to discern the true from the false.

The teachings of the Nyāya System are intended to give us a rational basis for knowing the Truth.

The Nyāya deals with critical inquiry. It explores all traditional beliefs and argues vigorously against all superstition, prejudiced and irrational beliefs.

Wherever there is constructive thinking directed at acquiring real understanding there is a need for Logic.

This desire for seeking truth is innate in human nature and logic enables us to accomplish constructive rational thinking.

The purpose of logic is the realisation of the Self by providing the means of studying, listening, reflecting and judging. This culminates in the removal of doubt and leads to mature wisdom, or to confirm that which has been passed down through tradition.

It is only by thorough examination of the sources and expressions can Truth be ascertained. Therefore all knowledge and traditional teaching offered to us, as well as our experiences must be submitted to critical inquiry.

The chief concern of the Nyāya methodology is the means of knowing and not the nature of knowledge.

1. It investigates the objects of our present perception, not their origination.

2. It lays down the rules of syllogistic reasoning for the purpose of examining the objects of perceptions.

3. It is the operative cause of Right knowledge and classifies the different ways in which knowledge is acquired.
Methodology

The logical method of ascertaining the Truth is through the application of the 16 categories of Logic, called Padārthas or topics these are:

1. Means of right knowledge pramāṇa
2. Object of right knowledge prameya
3. Doubt Saṁśaya
4. Motive prayojana
5. Illustrations dṛṣṭānta
6. Demonstrated Truth siddhānta
7. Factors of Reasoningsyllogism avayava
8. Reasoning and confutation tarka
9. Ascertainment nirṇaya
10. Discussion vāda
11. Disputation jalpa
12. Cavil or objecting vitaṇḍā
13. Fallacious Reasoning hetvābhāsa
14. Casuistry (unfair reasoning) chala
15. Futile Rejoinder jāti
16. Clinchers nigraha-sthāna

The first two are the most important. The first nine deal more strictly with logic, while the last seven have the function of preventing and mitigating error.

The process of Nyāya consists of three stages:—

=> Statement
=> definition
=>examination


1. THE MEANS OF RIGHT KNOWLEDGE


Pramāṇa

Definition of Right Knowledge (pramā)

Yathāvasthita vyavahārāṇuguṇa jñānam pramā


Right knowledge is that which reveals a thing as it actually is and is pragmatic.

Knowledge is said to be true when there is –

1. Coherence
2. Correspondence
3. Consequence or Utility


Coherence —The statement must be logical and consistent.

Correspondence —the knowledge must correspond to the actual nature of the object as it is. (tadvati-tat-prakāraka)

Consequence — Utility —our practical activities in relation to the object are successful. (pravṛtti-samārthya).In other words we can do something with it.

Right knowledge (pramā) reveals a thing as it really is and leads to successful utilisation thereof.

False knowledge does not correspond to reality and any activity directed thereby results in failure and disappointment.

N.B. ‘Right’ or ‘valid’ knowledge in the Indian context is somewhat individualized —

for example; knowledge of quantum particles is useful for a scientist engaged in that type of research but not useful for the common person, as nothing can be done with this knowledge —it may certainly be true but it is not valid in terms of practical outcomes of daily life.

It may be possible to count the number of grains of sand on a beach and this may have some scientific application, but the knowledge, albeit true is unusable for all practical purposes and therefore said to be “invalid” or more properly “irrelevant”.

According to Nyāya, there are 4 means whereby we obtain information:

1. Empirical knowledge, Sense perception/experience [[[pratyakṣa]]]
2. Discursive reasoning, inference [[[anumāna]]]
3. Analogy [[[upamāna]]]
4. Verbal testimony of a trustworthy source. [[[śabda]]]

Each school of Indian thought has its own theory of the Means to obtain Right knowledge:

Cārvākas: Perception [[[pratyakṣa]]]

Mīmāṁsakas: Verbal Testimony [[[śabda]]]

Vaiśeṣika & Buddhists: perception [[[pratyakṣa]]] & inference [[[anumāna]]]

Sānkhyas: perception [[[pratyakṣa]]], inference [[[anumāna]]] & verbal testimony [[[śabda]]]

Naiyāyikas: perception [[[pratyakṣa]]], inference [[[anumāna]]] comparison [[[upamāna]]] verbal testimony [[[śabda]]]

Prabhākaras: perception [[[pratyakṣa]]], inference [[[anumāna]]] comparison [[[upamāna]]] verbal testimony [[[śabda]]] presumption [[[arthāpatti]]],

Bhāṭṭas & Vedāṅtins perception [[[pratyakṣa]]], inference [[[anumāna]]] comparison [[[upamāna]]] verbal testimony [[[śabda]]] presumption [[[arthāpatti]]], non-existence [[[abhāva]]]

Paurāṇikas: perception [[[pratyakṣa]]], inference [[[anumāna]]] comparison [[[upamāna]]] verbal testimony [[[śabda]]] presumption [[[arthāpatti]]], non-existence [[[abhāva]]] probability [saṁbhava] and tradition [[[aitihya]]]

Presumption [[[arthāpatti]]] —is the deduction of one thing from the assertion of another thing,

e.g., from the assertion that —'unless there is a cloud, there is no rain,' we presume that -'there is rain, if there is cloud.'

Non-existence [[[abhāva]]] —is the deduction of the existence of one of two contradictory things from the non-existence of the other;

e.g., the absence of the sun establishes the presence of the stars.

Probability [[[sambhava]]] —consists in cognising the existence of a thing from that of another thing in which it is included.

Tradition [[[aitihya]]] —received wisdom without any verification of the source from which it first originated.

According to Nyāya these four additional means:

presumption, non-existence and probability are included in inference, and tradition is included in Verbal Testimony.

They are not considered as independent means of right knowledge because they do not form a separate category, and there is no need to consider them separately.


1:1 Perception (pratyakṣa)

The knowledge which arises from the contact of a sense with its object, and which is determinate, unnameable and consistent.

Sense perception is of two kinds:-

1. Indeterminate (nirvikalpaka) or abstract —general, non-specific.
2. Determinate (savikalpaka) or concrete —specific.

"Indeterminate" knowledge is vague and non-specific —

i.e. not being able to tell the difference between smoke or dust seen at a distance. Or not being able to distinguish between a snake and a rope in dim light.

Determinateknowledge is that which is clear and differentiated from other things.

The "unnameable" brings to our attention the fact that the name of an object has no connection with the knowledge of it derived through our direct perception. We know the object but may not know the name of the object.

The "consistent" means that we can actualise the knowledge, i.e. the perception of water in a mirage which is an illusion is inconsistent with what we know and can use.

Perceptual knowledge must be real, actual, suitable, specific, particular and not vague, visionary or general.
1:2 Inference (Anumāna)

That knowledge which is deduced from prior perception.

Anumāna is based upon a well-known or observed connection (concomitance) between 2 things (cause and effect).

E.g. clouds + rain, rain + harvest, smoke + fire, insult + anger, love + attachment, etc.

There are 3 types of anumāna or inference;–

1. It may be a priori, —from cause to effect; (pūrvavat)

e.g., on seeing clouds, one infers that it is going to rain;

2. or it may be a posteriori, —from effect to cause; (śeṣavat)

e.g., on seeing a river swollen, one infers that there has been rain fall.

3. It may also be what is termed 'commonly seen,'(samānyatodṛṣṭa) which is knowledge of one thing derived from the perception of another thing with which it is commonly seen;

e.g., on seeing rain, one infers that there are clouds.

Another example of this sort is the movement of the moon which is inferred on the basis of its changing position in the sky, although the movement of the moon is not perceived directly by the senses.
1:3 Analogy (Upamāna)

Knowledge of a thing derived from its similarity to another thing already well known.

For example, one is told that a water buffalo resembles a big black cow;

One then travels to a place where the water buffalo lives, and on seeing an animal resembling a big black cow, one concludes that it must be a water-buffalo.

Analogy has been regarded in Nyāya as an independent means of Right Knowledge because it brings about a right cognition that cannot be achieved through either sense-perception or inference.


1:4 Verbal Testimony (śabda/ āgama/āpta-vākya)

The instructive assertion of a reliable person (āpta), that is, one who is possessed of true knowledge and is truthful.

This instruction may be about perceptible things or about intangible realities.

The first can be verified, but one must depend upon inference (anumāna) to ascertain the truth of the latter.

The “reliable” person (āpta) must be someone who is:—

1. Free from prejudices or bias
2. Has no self-interest in the outcomes of instruction.
3. Is recognised by other authorities as trustworthy

For example, the ‘scientists’ who provide a tobacco company with ‘evidence’ that tobacco is not injurious to health are not reliable persons, because they are being funded by the tobacco company and their results are favourable to a product which has been proven beyond reasonable doubt to be harmful to human health and the majority of their colleagues denounce them.

=> Perception is concerned chiefly with the present;

=> Inference deals with the past, present, and future;

=> Comparison is an instrument of perception, enabling us to know a named object.

=> Verbal testimony reveals knowledge about things which we cannot know by ourselves.

=> It is by means of these four sources of right knowledge that the goals of humankind are accomplished.
2. 1 THE TOPICS OF RIGHT KNOWLEDGE
[[[Prameya]]]

The body [[[śarīra]]] | Self [[[ātman]]] | Senses [[[indriya]]] | Experiences [[[artha]]]| Intelligence [[[buddhi]]] | Intellect [[[manas]]]| Activity [[[pravṛtti]]] | Imbalances [[[doṣa]]]| Consequence [[[phala]]] | Suffering [[[duḥkha]]]| Re-birth pratyabhāva | Liberation [[[apavarga]]]

There are many things that might be regarded as topics of right knowledge, but these 12 are especially significant:

because the true knowledge about them will dispel all delusions and lead to freedom from suffering; while false knowledge concerning these topics perpetuates rebirth and suffering.

Nyāya only establishes these principles on a rational basis but does not attempt to dilate upon them.

Nyāya does not attempt to explain all that is known about these several topics that is left for the more speculative systems of philosophy.

The indications of the existence of the Self (ātman):

attraction (rāga) | aversion (dveṣa)

pleasure (sukha) | pain (duḥkha)

knowledge (jñāna) | striving(prayatna)

=> These are experiences which are common to all sentient beings.

=> There is obviously a subject that experiences them and that subject is called a Self or ātman.

=> Since the ātman is one of the intangible realities it cannot be apprehended through the senses; the Self is self-evident to all of us, none of us doubt our own existence.

=> The ātman is the subject of these phenomena and is something distinct from the body and the mind. But it cannot be demonstrated by sense-perception as it is the Subject.

=> It’s existence is established through anumāna or inference and from śabdascriptural testimony.

2:2. The body (śarīra)

The body is that which is the locus of motion (ceṣṭa), of the senses (iṅdriyas) and of their effects/experiences (arthas) of pleasure and pain.

=> The body is the field of the Ātman’s experiences as it strives to attain what is pleasurable and avoid what is un-pleasurable.

=> All these activities are actualised through the 10 senses, the instruments through which the ātman receives stimuli from the external world and through which it reacts to those stimuli.

=> The receptors of pleasure and pain lie within the brain which mediates the experiences thereof. The śarīra includes both the physical body and the brain and hence is usually referred to as the mind/body complex.

2:3. The Senses & 2:4. Their Experiences

Senses (Iṅdriyas) -> Elements (Bhūtas) -> Experiences (Arthas)

smell — (ghrāṇa) | Earth —(pṛthivī) | odour — (gaṅdha)
taste — (rasana) | water — (apas), | flavour — (rasa)
vision — (cakṣus) | fire — (tejas) | colour — (rūpa)
touch — (tvak) | air — (vāyu) | sensation — (sparśa)
hearing — (śrotra) | ether — (ākāśa ) | sound — (śabda)

The senses and their objects provide five varieties of perception yielding special kinds of knowledge according to the objects which they reveal.

There are six categories which constitute “the field” of the senses these are:—

1. Substance —is defined as that which is the material cause or constituent cause of a thing, or that which is the substratum of “qualities”.

According to Nyāya, there are 9 substances: —

earth (pṛthivī), water (ap), light (tejas), air (vāyu), gravity (dig), space (ākāśa), time (kāla), Self (ātman) and Mind (manas).

2. Quality —that which has general characteristics, or, the general attributes of a substance.

All the afore mentioned substances have qualities. These are 24 in number and are:

colour, taste, odour, touch, number, dimension, separateness, conjunction & disjunction, nearness & remoteness (both space and time), heaviness, fluidity, viscosity (smoothness of water), sound, knowledge, pleasure (gratification), suffering, desire (attachment), aversion, effort, merit & demerit and faculty (velocity, impression and elasticity).

3. Actions —upwards, downwards, horizontal movement, contracting and expanding.

4. Generality — all the known objects although different from one another are still substance. Their being substance is the higher generalization.

But these objects can be further divided into different classes, each class differing from the others but having an individual or lower generality.

5. Individuality — all matter is composed of atoms and each atom is an individual, therefore there are an infinite number of individuals.

6. Inherence.— this category refers to the intimate relationship that exists between a substance and its attributes or qualities, between atoms and their compounds, between the whole and its parts, between substance and its modifications.

=> Non-existence —this is a category which is included by some teachers of Nyāya

2:5. Intelligence; [[[Buddhi]]]

The ability of forming ideas and general notions, retaining conceptions and the faculty of the mind to discern, judge, comprehend, apprehend, and understand the meaning of right knowledge.

It is that mental power which enables one to reflect upon the teachings and to contemplate the Self.

2:6. Mind [[[Manas]]]

The capacity for reflection, inference, testimony, doubt, humour, dream, cognition, conjecture, memory, desire, and feeling of pleasure and pain.

In contrast with the faculty of intelligence; the intellect (buddhi) seeks factual knowledge which is worldly, while the Mind (manas) aims at wisdom which is divine.

2:7. Extrovert Activity (Pravṛtti)

That which sets the mind, body, and voice in motion, for good or bad.

It is the effect of these extroverted actions, stimulated by craving arising from false knowledge, which holds one in bondage to the cycle of suffering and saṃsāra

2:8. Imbalances (Doṣa) —The initiating causes of all action.

Fault => Manifestation

Attraction [[[rāga]]] => lust, greed, craving, selfishness, longing, and covetousness;

Aversion [[[dveṣa]]] => anger, envy, jealousy, and implacability

Delusion [abhiniveṣa] => Clutching, clinging, grasping, attachment

=> The mark of attraction is attachment;

=> The mark of aversion, is the lack of forbearance;

=> The mark of delusion, is misapprehension.

The worst of these is delusion because it gives rise to further attraction and aversion, which make one forget that there is nothing in actual fact which is agreeable or disagreeable to the ātman; therefore, there is no reason to like or dislike objects.

The reason for the appearance of the doṣas is due to the incapacity to distinguish the part from the whole, that is, the real from the unreal.

e.g., the beautiful body provokes lust, while the sight of blood repels. And so it is with everything throughout nature; there is the twofold aspect, the real and the unreal. Because of this false conception of the true nature of things, desires arise which in turn, stimulate us to action.

Here it must be remembered that the hatred of pain is none the less hatred; and until all such reactions are removed by true knowledge, one will remain attached to the illusory world of name [[[nāma]] —mind] and form [[[rūpa]] —body].

Self-realisation ātma-bodha is acquired by constant study and reflection on the Dharma.

In this way wisdom can be matured until all doubt has been removed, and the mind will then awaken to the latent potential lying within.

We are all in essence enlightened beings —we only don’t know it yet!

2:9. Consequence (phala)

Consequence is the outcome of activity.

Every activity has an outcome which may take the form of either pleasure (sukha) or pain (duḥkha), depending upon the nature of its cause.

It is also twofold in that it gives pleasure or pain to another being or gives pleasure of pain to the actor.

The effect is also of two kinds; that which appears immediately as seen in practical projects, or that which appears after a lapse of time as seen in the planting of seed by a farmer.

The same principles operate in the ethical realm.

The fruit of right conduct in this world may appear as companionship (sahatva), progeny (prajā) and wealth (vittam), which are the three sources of worldly joy.

2:10. Suffering (duḥkha)

An impediment that hinders the progress of the Self.

=> The body is said to be the abode of suffering duḥkha-ālaya;

=> The senses are the instruments whereby we experience suffering,

=> The intellect is the agent of suffering;

=> Birth, then, is association with suffering; therefore, life is a passing experience of sorrow and suffering.

Pleasure is but an interval in this process, a mere distraction, for all pleasures are attended with non-fulfilment or non-perpetuation which produces constant low-level anxiety.

In other words - the default human condition is dissatisfaction.

It can, therefore, be said that one who is addicted to the pursuit of pleasure is in reality given to the pursuit of pain, for there is no pleasure, in the attainment and enjoyment of which, pain in some form or other is not present.

2:11. Rebirth (pratyabhāva)

The re-embodiment of the animating principle [jīva] in physical form after death.

Birth consists of the connection of the ātman with a new body and mind complex.

Therefore, birth is not the production of a new circumstance, but only re-association; while death is not the destruction of anything, but only separation.

To deny this principle would be to negate the moral law of the universe and promote antinomianism. It would also render meaningless all moral instruction of enlightened beings.

2:12. Liberation (apavarga).

The absolute freedom from suffering.

Only the ātman which is liberated from the body, sense-organs and intellect is freed from duḥkha.

When the mind is awakened to the true nature of things by means of the cultivation of Right Knowledge, duḥkha will fade away as the darkness of the night before the rising sun:

The faults will dissipate, and there will be no longer any incentive to action, which, in turn, will free the Self from future rebirths.

The śāstras teach that the following 4 things must be investigated and known by the discerning aspirant:—

(1) that rebirth, consequences, and pain are the things to be known;
(2) that action and the faults are to be avoided;
(3) that Liberation is the goal to be pursued; and
(4) that knowledge of Truth is the means of its attainment.

It is by constantly reflecting on these teachings that true knowledge arises.

Development of Right Knowledge

Right Knowledge is developed by;

1. Self-restraint. (dama)

2. Holding the mind steadfast and focused upon the ātman by sustained effort, maintaining a state of tranquillity (sama).

The motivating force to develop right knowledge is a strong desire to know the Truth.
By habitual cultivation of this state, one learns to rest within the Self, and enlightenment dawns.



3. DOUBT [[[saṁśaya]]]


A conflicting judgment about the precise character of an object, arising from the recognition of properties common to many objects, or of properties not common to any of the objects, from conflicting testimony, and from irregularity of perception and non-perception.

Doubt must not be confused with error, which is false knowledge. Doubt is incomplete knowledge which serves as the incentive for further investigation —it is therefore a very positive and desirable quality to have.

False knowledge/error may produce an erroneous conviction which sedates the mind by removing all desire for further knowledge.

Error is defined as that knowledge which does not lead to successful action.

For example, it is impossible to fulfill the expectations created by hallucinations. In other words, the ideal world of thought must correspond to the outer reality in order to be considered true.

The rules of Nyāya are to be applied when doubt has arisen, and it becomes necessary, therefore, to examine reality for confirmation.

There are 4 kinds of doubt:-

(1) Perception of common properties or failure to perceive the difference

e.g. in the dark a post may be mistaken for a person, or a coiled rope mistaken for a snake.

(2) Conflicting testimony or differing opinions.

(3) Irregularity of perception;

e.g. being unable to determine whether water is perceived when it is seen in a pond where it actually exists, or when it is seen in a mirage where it really does not exist.

e.g. Hearing the rustle of leaves in the bush and having some doubt that it could be an animal or a human.

(4) Irregularity of non-perception;

e.g. being unable to believe that something exists based on never having perceived a thing with qualities as described. Or inability to believe that such a thing exists.



4. MOTIVE [[[prayojana]]]

A desire which impels one to act.

Purpose serves as the motive behind all action which may be to attain something pleasurable or to avoid something undesirable.

Until there is purpose, there can be no successful action; therefore a wise person never engages in purposeless action.

It is also the purpose or motive which determines if an act is morally right or wrong:

No act is of itself either good or bad, there as sincere spiritual aspirants we should always be examining and reflecting upon our motives.


5. CORROBORATIVE INSTANCE (familiar example) [[[dṛṣṭānta]]]

The thing about which a layman and an expert entertain the same opinion.

Both scientists and laymen accept the general proposition that whenever there is rain there must be clouds; therefore, such an example can be used as an example in the process of reasoning from the known to the unknown.



6. DEMONSTRATED TRUTH [[[siddhānta]]]

A conclusion on a hypothesis reached and agreed upon by a school of philosophy.

Siddhānta is a conclusion that is recognised as proven by a certain school of philosophy.



These are of 4 kinds of Siddhānta:—

(1) A commonly accepted truth — is a tenet which is not opposed by any school of philosophy and which is claimed by at least one school;

e.g. All schools of Hindu Philosophy accept earth, water, light, air, and ether as the basic five elements, and smell, taste, colour, touch, and sound as the objects of the five senses.

(2) A peculiar truth —is a tenet which is accepted by similar schools, but rejected by opposite schools.

e.g., the 3 Abrahamic schools all accept that God creates the world from nothing. All schools of Indian philosophy reject this conclusion as a thing cannot come into existence out of nothing. (ex nihilo nihilo fit).

(3) A consequential truth —is a tenet which if accepted, leads to the acceptance of another tenet;

e.g., the acceptance of the doctrine that there is a self separate from the senses, because it can recognise one and the same object by seeing and touch, implies:—

(a) that the senses are more than one,
(b) that each of the senses has its particular object;
(c) that the self derives its knowledge through the channels of the senses; and
(d) that a substance which is distinct from its qualities is the locus of them.

(4) An implied truth —is a tenet which is not explicitly declared as such, but which follows from the examination of particulars concerning it.

e.g., the discussion whether certain people should be allowed to vote implies that those people are capable of understanding and making political decisions.

7. THE FACTORS OF REASONING (Syllogism) [[[avayava]]]

1. proposition [[[pratijñā]]],
2. reason [[[hetu]]],
3. example [[[udāharaṇa]]],
4. application [[[upanaya]]],
5. conclusion [[[nigamana]]]

Inference is the process of knowing something not by means of contact between the senses and the objects of the world and not by observation but rather through the medium of a sign, or linga, that is invariably related to it.

Inference involves the process of analysing memories, correlations, propositions, theories and arguments.

There is a systematic method for arriving at, and testing the validity of inferential knowledge this is through the paradigm known as the syllogism.

There are always some inseparable constituents to a syllogism, and if any of these parts are missing or if there is any defect in the parts, then the knowledge inferred is invalid.

The process of reasoning has two applications:

1. svārthareasoning for oneself to gain correct knowledge.
2. parārthareasoning to convince another of correct knowledge.

There are 5 logical steps used to establish the Right Knowledge.

(1) Proposition is the statement of the thing to be proved.
(2) Reason is the argument used to prove the proposition.
(3) Example is an accepted instance of a similar thing.
(4) Application consists of drawing the comparison.
(5) Conclusion shows the convergence of the four means of right knowledge toward the same object.

The application of the syllogism can best be illustrated by 2 examples:

Example I

1. Proposition There is fire burning on the mountain.
2. Reason Because there are billows of smoke arising in the distance.
3. Example Wherever there is smoke there is also fire, as in a camp-fire or bonfire.
4. Application So, on this mountain there is smoke.
5. Conclusion Therefore, this mountain is alight.

Example II

1. Proposition John is mortal
2. Reason Because he is a man
3. Example All men are mortal such as Socrates, Napoleon, King Henry etc.
4. Application John is also a man
5. Conclusion Therefore he is mortal

Three parts of inference.

Thus, a syllogism contains 3 parts:

1. The major term (sādhya),
2. The minor term (pakṣa),
3. and the middle term (hetu or liṅga).

In the example with proposition:

There is fire burning on the mountain.

1. the first step is the sight of smoke (hetu) on the hill (pakṣa);

2. the second step is the recollection of the universal relationship between smoke and fire (hetu and sādhya);

3. and the third step is the cognition of fire (sādhya).

When used for reasoning for one’s self (svārtha) then only these 3 factors are necessary but when used as a formal statement or verbal expression designed to convince others (parārtha), however, all five factors come into play.

In making a statement to convince others we proceed thus:–

1. The first step will be the predication of the major term in relation to the minor term:

‘There is fire on the hill’.

2. The second step will be the formation of the middle term in relation to the minor term:

‘There is visible smoke on the hill’.

3. The third step will be the formation of the middle term in its universal or invariable relationship with the major term:

‘Where there’s smoke, there’s fire’.

4. In the fourth step it is sometimes helpful to use a specific example to confirm the relationship between the middle term and major term. For instance,

‘Where there’s smoke there’s fire, as in the kitchen’.

5. The fifth step is to affirm the conclusion.

Here is another example:

(1) John is mortal (fact); => The first premise states a positive fact.

(2) Because he is a man (reason); =>The second premise states the reason for this assertion.

(3) All men are mortal – for example, Napoleon, Lincoln, Socrates, and so on (example); =>

The third premise then confirms the relationship between the reason for the assertion and the asserted fact itself as supported by a well-known example.

(4) John is also a man (application); => The fourth constituent of the syllogism represents the application of the universal proposition to the present case.

(5) Therefore John is mortal (conclusion). => The fifth part, or conclusion, is drawn from the preceding four parts.

To gain a proper understanding of the workings of logic, let’s examine more closely how a systematic syllogism functions.

To do this, the previous example may be reanalysed:

‘There is fire on the hill because there is smoke, and where there is smoke, there is fire’.

As was previously discussed, fire is the major term, hill is the minor term, and smoke is the middle term.

The middle term (smoke) is so-called because, on the one hand, it is connected to the minor term (hill), and, on the other hand, it is universally related to the major term (fire).

This middle term is also called reason or grounds since it is because of its perception that the major term is inferred.

Thus, an inference has two conditions:

1. the knowledge of the middle term must exist in the minor term;
2. and a relationship must exist between the middle and the major terms.

It is not possible to realize the existence of fire on the hill as a conclusion based on inferential reasoning if the invariable concomitance between the middle and major terms is not established.

This invariable concomitance between these two terms of an inference is called vyāpti, the logical ground for inference.

Concomitance guarantees the validity of the conclusion; the validity or invalidity of an inference depends on the validity or invalidity of vyāpti.

Therefore, Nyāya philosophy goes into great detail concerning the nature of concomitance and the fallacies related to it.

Logical ground for inference.

Vyāpti, meaning ‘the state of pervasiveness’, implies both that which pervades and that which is pervaded.

For example, in the inference of fire and smoke, smoke is the pervaded and fire is the pervader.

Here smoke is always accompanied by fire – wherever there is smoke, there will also be fire.

The reverse, however, is not necessarily true:—

it is possible to have fire without smoke – for example, a Bunsen burner.

But there are examples in which both the pervader and the pervaded coexist permanently – for example, fire and heat.

There are, therefore, 2 kinds of concomitance: equivalent and non-equivalent.

a. Non-equivalent concomitance (asama-vyāpti) is an invariable concomitance between 2 unequal entities (such as smoke and fire).

It has already been shown that in this type of concomitance, one entity may be inferred from the other, but not vice versa.

b. Equivalent concomitance (sama-vyāpti) is an invariable concomitance between two coexistent terms, either of which can be inferred from the other.

For example, a chair is a nameable thing because a chair is knowable, and whatever is knowable, is nameable.

Here nameable and knowable can both be inferred from each other.

Concomitance thus denotes a relationship of coexistence (sahacarya). But not every instance of coexistence is an example of concomitance. Fire, for example, often coexists with smoke, yet it may exist without smoke.

The coexistent relationship of fire and smoke depends on certain conditions – temperature and wetness, for instance:

The limiting condition on which the relation of coexistence depends is called upādhi, and for an inference to be valid, the relation between the middle and major terms of a syllogism must be independent of any and all conditions.

In other words, a valid concomitance represents an invariable and unconditional concomitant relation (nitya anaupādika saṁbandha) between the middle and major terms of a syllogism.

But how does one know that a relation is invariable and unconditional?

The Vedānta philosophers reply that concomitance is established by the uncontradicted experiences of the relationships between two things.

But according to Nyāya, concomitance is established through the perception of classes (samānya lakṣaṇa perception).

Actually, the Nyāya method of inference uses inductive reasoning; that is, it draws a particular conclusion on the grounds of a general and universally known truth.

The universal truth is considered to fall within the range of vyāpti.

In Nyāya, there are 3 types of inductive analysis, or generalization.

=> The first is anvaya, or uniform agreement present.

This type of inductive process arises from observing a relationship in which if one constituent is present, then in every instance the other constituent is also present

for example, wherever there is smoke there is fire.

=> The second type of inductive analysis is the obverse of the first, and is called uniform agreement in absence (vyatireka).

In this method, a negative universal relationship or invariable concomitance is observed –

for example, wherever there is no fire, there is no smoke.

=> The third kind of inductive process is a combination of the first and second methods:

In this method, known as uniform agreement in both presence and absence (anvaya-vyatireka or vyabhicāra-graha), both constituents of a relationship are always found together; neither is ever present without the other. From this, it is induced that there must exist a natural relationship of invariable concomitance between them.

These three methods of generalization demonstrate a systematic technique for inductive reasoning.

The most crucial concern, however, in any systematic inference is how to make certain that concomitance, the logical basis for the inference, is valid – that is, free from limiting conditions (upādhis).

 This process of insuring that vyāptis are free from all vitiating conditions is called upādhi-nirasa.

One way of insuring this is by the repeated observation of both constituents of a relationship under all possible circumstances to make certain that the relationship is in fact invariable.

Another way is to employ hypothetical critical argumentation or tarka.

But Nyāya places the greatest emphasis on samānya lakṣaṇa – the perception of general classes – as the major means for insuring the validity of vyāptis.



13. FALLACIOUS REASONING [[[hetvābhāsa]] ]

These are: 1. the irregular middle (sabyabhicāra), 2. the contradictory (viruddha), 3. the inconclusive (satpratipakṣa), 4. the unproved (asiddha), and 5. the Anachronism (bādhita).

These are the five forms of erroneous reasoning. To understand the reasoning we need to bear

in mind the 3 parts of a syllogism:

1. The major term (sādhya) —that which we are seeking to prove
2. The minor term (pakṣa) —the subject
3. and the middle term (hetu) —the reason given for the conclusion.

1. The Irregular middle or the ambiguous —the reason given leads to more than one conclusion.

Proposition => All beings that live in the Himalayas are saints; tigers live in the Himalayas and therefore tigers are saints.

Major term: => Saints
Middle term => Himalayan beings
Minor term => tigers
Conclusion => Wrong or ambiguous

As we learnt earlier the middle and the major terms must be in a concomitant relationship.

Because tigers and saints as well as many other varieties of beings live in the Himalayas the conclusion of this inference cannot be said to be correct, because the middle term, Himalayan beings, is not invariably related to the major term, saints.

2. The self-Contradictory — the reason dismisses what is sought to be established.

Proposition => Sound is eternal because it is produced, everything produced is impermanent.

Major term => Eternality
Middle term => Produced things are impermanent
Minor term => Sound
Conclusion => Contradiction

Here the reason contradicts that which is to be proved, because that which is eternal is never produced. Eternal and produced are contradictory attributes and mutually exclusive.

3. The Inconclusive (i.e. Petitio Principii) —the reason which provokes the very question for the solution of which it was employed. (Begging the question)

Proposition => The body is non-eternal, because it does not possess the attribute of eternality.

Major term => Non-eternality
Middle term => The attribute of eternality
Minor term => The body
Conclusion =>Non-eternality is the same as ‘not possessing the attribute of eternality’

Here nothing new is contributed to the thesis. The reason merely begs the question, for "non-eternal" is the same as "not possessing the attribute of eternality."

In other words, the subject matter of the topic is advanced as the reason for the desired inference.

This stops the argument and makes the investigation of Truth impossible.

4. Illogical –unproven —the reason which needs proof, in the same way as the proposition does.

Proposition => All Hindus are vegetarians because they all believe in the doctrine of Ahimsā.

Major term => vegetarians
Middle term => believe [in ahimsa]
Minor term => Hindus
Conclusion => unproven

Here it is necessary to prove the middle term i.e. that all those who believe in ahimsa are necessarily vegetarians (Buddhists, Jains, Quakers etc.); therefore, proposition remains unproved

5. The Annulled or Contradicted—the reason given contradicts the premise:

Proposition => Fire is cool
Annulled reason => Because it is a product like water

Here the thing to be proven is the coolness of fire, but in this syllogism the fact of being a product has been advanced as the proof for the absence of heat, but heat, the negation of coolness is known from tactile perception and so therefore the reason contradicts the premise.

Added to these five fallacies also those which suffer from the three defects which are:–

1. too narrow definition
2. too broad definition
3. the impossible

8. HYPOTHETICAL REASONING tarka,

- A process for ascertaining the real nature of a thing of which the character is not known. A method of arriving at the truth by showing the absurdity of all contrary ideas.

Tarka is a method of attaining knowledge of the truth about an unknown thing by comparing and then gradually eliminating all the competing suppositions;

Example - Is the Self a product or a non-Product?

If the Self is a non-product, it will experience the result of its action and will, on the eradication of the causes of re-birth, attain release; therefore, re-birth and release are indeed possible.

If it is a product, these will not be possible, because the Self's connection with the body, mind, and senses will not be the result of its own action, nor will it experience the fruit of its own actions. The phenomenon of re-birth and release is well known and established; therefore, the Self must be a non-product.

This form of reasoning is also called Confutation:

This is not a method which ascertains, determines and verifies that the Self is a particular thing and nothing else.

It simply eliminates all other contesting theories to the supposition it supports; after which Truth is established through the application of other means of Right Knowledge. For this reason Confutation is considered to be a supporting technique and is, therefore mentioned separately.



9. DIALECTIC [[[nirṇaya]]]



- The removal of doubts, and the resolution of a dispute, by examining two opposite views.

Dialectic is in the form of a dialogue between two people who may hold differing views, yet wish to establish the truth by seeking agreement with one another.

This is in contrast to debate in which two or more people hold differing views and wish to persuade or prove one another wrong (and thus a jury or judge is needed to decide the matter),

The sequence of investigation is as follows:—

=> First impression
=> doubt arises
=> examining the opposite view
=> application of logic
=> determination of the controversy
=> ascertainment of Truth.

Doubt is the result of first impression and gives impetus to investigation in order to ascertain the truth.

Ascertainment is unnecessary in the case of direct perception or verbal testimony.



10. DISCUSSION [[[vāda]]]



- A dialogue in which one adopts one of two opposing positions.

The purpose of Discussion is to arrive at the truth of the proposition under consideration. This may be achieved by talking about the topic with anyone who is a sincere seeker of Truth.

In vāda it is not necessary to establish one's own thesis; it is enough to submit one's views for examination in order to ascertain the Truth.

The discussion does not necessarily have to take into consideration the opposite opinion; it is enough to put any proposition to the test of logic.

The usual procedure is to maintain the thesis by means of Right Knowledge and to attack the counter-thesis by means of tarka.



11. POLEMIC [[[jalpa]]]



A verbal disputation directed at gaining victory.

The sole purpose of engaging in a polemic is simply to gain victory over the other party.

There’s no desire to either gain further knowledge of Truth or to establish one’s own position, and therefore, one can employ any device of debate in order to win.

These devices are usually of a negative character, such as attacking the opponent’s character, (argumentum ad hominem) quibbling, advancing futile arguments, reducing to absurdity, evading the issue etc.



12. CAVIL [[[vitaṇḍā]]]


- A kind of wrangling, which consists in mere attacks on the opposite side.

In cavil there is no desire to establish any proposition. The only interest is to heckle the speaker by carping and offering frivolous objections.

Polemics and Cavilling, which are considered as forms of Discussion, may be used by an aspirant of Truth only as means of protecting one's young and fragile knowledge which has not yet matured into a full blossomed conviction.

One may occasionally encounter objectionable people who, devoid of true knowledge, are puffed up with their academic achievements or are deluded by their own erroneous convictions.

These people may try to impose their views and beliefs on others.

Under such circumstances the student is urged to make use of these argumentative devices in order to safeguard the development of knowledge in the same way that nature uses thorns on some plants to safeguard the growth of its fruit.



14 CASUISTRY cala


- The opposition offered to a proposition by the assumption of an alternative meaning.

Casuistry is of three sorts: -

(1) Playing upon words (vacas). This consists of wilfully taking a term to mean something different from that intended by the speaker;

e.g., taking the word 'quadruped' to mean four-legged table instead of an animal.

(2) Generalisations (sāmānyas). This consists of asserting the impossibility of a particular part because of the impossibility of the whole;

e.g., to deny that a particular cow is black because all cows are not black.

(3) Metaphors (upacārās). This consists of invalidating a word used in a particular context by taking it literally when it was used metaphorically;

e.g., the ‘House cheered’ means that the people in the house cheered and not the physical structure.

15. FUTILE REJOINDER [[[jāti]]]

- Offering objections founded on mere similarity or dissimilarity.

The reply is said to be futile if it does not take into consideration the universal connection between the middle term and the major term. Mere similarity or dissimilarity is not sufficient.

There are 24 kinds of futility which aim at showing an equality of the arguments of two sides. They are as follows:

1. Balancing the homogeneity. 2. Balancing the heterogeneity.
3. Balancing the addition. 4. Balancing the subtraction.
5. Balancing the questionable. 6. Balancing the unquestionable.
7. Balancing the alternative 8. Balancing the reciprocity
9. Balancing the co-presence. 10. Balancing the mutual absence.
11. Balancing the infinite regression. 12. Balancing the counter-example
13. Balancing the non-produced. 14. Balancing the doubt.
15. Balancing the controversy. 16. Balancing the non-reason.
17. Balancing the presumption. 18. Balancing the non-difference
19. Balancing the non-demonstration. 20. Balancing the perception.
21. Balancing the non-perception. 22. Balancing the non-eternality.
23. Balancing the eternality. 24. Balancing the effect.

16. CLINCHERS nigraha-sthāna

- A situation in which one misunderstands, or does not understand at all.

There is no purpose in entering into a debate with one who demonstrates an utter lack of understanding of the subject being investigated; therefore, one is advised to stop the discussion.

22 occasions of “disagreement in principle” are listed and discussed in the Nyāya Texts, these all result in the loss of the debate, but it is beyond the scope of this course to examine them in full detail.

They are:-

1. Non sequitur —the conclusion does not follow from the premise.
2. Shifting or adjusting the original proposition in response to the arguments.
3. Contradicting one’s own original proposition
4. Renouncing the original proposition.
5. Changing or altering the original reason.
6. Changing the topic in the middle of the debate.
7. Offering meaningless reasoning.
8. The unintelligible reasoning.
9. The incoherent reasoning.
10. Advancing a line of reasoning which is inappropriate to the occasion.
11. Saying too little or refusing to elaborate.
12. Saying too much or over stating the case
13. Repetition of the argument.
14. Silence.
15. Demonstrating an Ignorance of the subject matter under discussion, or lacking pertinent details
16. Non-ingenuity.
17. Evasion of the question.
18. Admission of the opponents view.
19. Overlooking the censurable aspects of one’s logic
20. Censuring the non-censurable.
21. Deviating from the original tenet.
22. Giving only a semblance of a reason.

Source

[1]