Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Philosophical nonegocentrism in Wittgenstein and Candrakirti in their treatment of the private language problem"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " <poem> Philosophical nonegocentrism in {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} and Candrakirti in their treatment of the private language problem By R. A. F. Thurman Philo...")
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
+
{{DisplayImages|2429|321|1740|3830|2073|3057|294|1978|128|1192|2275|598|2174|2367|2048|736|1395|256|2336|53|478|3963|1875|2323|3111|1693|4062|1995|1388|1746|2173|848|3769|2277|4114|3647|446|2185|4174|2003}}
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
 
     [[Philosophical]] nonegocentrism in {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} and [[Candrakirti]]  
 
     [[Philosophical]] nonegocentrism in {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} and [[Candrakirti]]  
 
in their treatment of the private [[language]] problem  
 
in their treatment of the private [[language]] problem  
By R. A. F. Thurman  
+
By [[R. A. F. Thurman]]
 
[[Philosophy]] [[East]] and [[West]]  
 
[[Philosophy]] [[East]] and [[West]]  
 
30:3, 1980.07  
 
30:3, 1980.07  
Line 14: Line 14:
 
Foreword
 
Foreword
 
 
The [[reason]] behind choosing this article for recension, out of the many that I’ve read on Wittgenstein’s [[philosophy]] in the last few years, is that it follows a new trend among [[western]] [[philosophers]], which I find feasible in treating philosophycal problems. The basic [[attitude]] behind this trend is clearly marked in Thurman’s introduction to his [[writing]]:  
+
The [[reason]] behind choosing this article for recension, out of the many that I’ve read on Wittgenstein’s [[philosophy]] in the last few years, is that it follows a new trend among [[western]] [[philosophers]], which I find feasible in treating philosophical problems.  
 +
 
 +
The basic [[attitude]] behind this trend is clearly marked in [[Thurman’s]] introduction to his [[writing]]:  
  
 
“In their [[book]] The Private [[Language]]  Problem, Saunders and  Henze  [[state]]  that  ‘it  is  primarily  in  the twentieth century that questions regarding the [[nature]] and possibility  of a private [[language]]  have received specific formulation and specific [[attention]].’   
 
“In their [[book]] The Private [[Language]]  Problem, Saunders and  Henze  [[state]]  that  ‘it  is  primarily  in  the twentieth century that questions regarding the [[nature]] and possibility  of a private [[language]]  have received specific formulation and specific [[attention]].’   
Line 22: Line 24:
 
[[Philosophers]] should no longer allow themselves to remain [[ignorant]] of the {{Wiki|planetary}} [[nature]] of  [[philosophy]],  in  spite    of  the  ingrained presuppositions of the {{Wiki|superiority}} of the [[West]] and of modernity which make the contribution  of the [[East]] so startling.” (p.1)
 
[[Philosophers]] should no longer allow themselves to remain [[ignorant]] of the {{Wiki|planetary}} [[nature]] of  [[philosophy]],  in  spite    of  the  ingrained presuppositions of the {{Wiki|superiority}} of the [[West]] and of modernity which make the contribution  of the [[East]] so startling.” (p.1)
  
Treating [[philosophical]] problems in this manner, clearly has the advantage of presenting ‘the problem’ itself, rather than the way it has appeared in some kind of philosophycal text.
+
Treating [[philosophical]] problems in this manner, clearly has the advantage of presenting ‘the problem’ itself, rather than the way it has appeared in some kind of [[philosophical]] text.
  
 
Besides this, it enables us to throw some {{Wiki|light}} on our preconceptions that we all have, when we come in [[contact]] with ‘the eastern’ [[thought]]. Looking back on my personal [[attitude]] towards the [[east]], I have to say that I have fully lost all of my negative [[feelings]] towards the ‘eastern’ way of [[thinking]].  
 
Besides this, it enables us to throw some {{Wiki|light}} on our preconceptions that we all have, when we come in [[contact]] with ‘the eastern’ [[thought]]. Looking back on my personal [[attitude]] towards the [[east]], I have to say that I have fully lost all of my negative [[feelings]] towards the ‘eastern’ way of [[thinking]].  
  
I also have lost my over-optimistic positive [[feelings]] about it. I have to say that by having studied [[western]] and eastern [[philosophy]] for several years by now, I have become [[neutral]] in treating both, and share Thurman’s point of view by saying that [[philosophy]] has a plantary [[nature]] and [[philosophers]] (not [[religious]] thinkers) think in the same way on all sides of the {{Wiki|globe}}.  
+
I also have lost my over-optimistic positive [[feelings]] about it. I have to say that by having studied [[western]] and eastern [[philosophy]] for several years by now, I have become [[neutral]] in treating both, and share [[Thurman’s]] point of view by saying that [[philosophy]] has a plantary [[nature]] and [[philosophers]] (not [[religious]] thinkers) think in the same way on all sides of the {{Wiki|globe}}.  
  
 
What I mean by this is that ‘[[thinking]]’ has the same qualities in every {{Wiki|culture}}, and it follows [[universal]] [[logical]] {{Wiki|rules}} that provide a cultural-free basis for all {{Wiki|reasoning}}.  
 
What I mean by this is that ‘[[thinking]]’ has the same qualities in every {{Wiki|culture}}, and it follows [[universal]] [[logical]] {{Wiki|rules}} that provide a cultural-free basis for all {{Wiki|reasoning}}.  
Line 33: Line 35:
  
  
I can’t say that Thurman’s article has amused me; I seem to lack the {{Wiki|abilities}} to [[grasp]] what his lines of [[thought]] are at some points.  
+
I can’t say that [[Thurman’s]] article has amused me; I seem to lack the {{Wiki|abilities}} to [[grasp]] what his lines of [[thought]] are at some points.  
  
 
Despite this I have found the article [[interesting]] because of it’s way of dealing with the problem of private [[language]] in the first place, rather than {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} only.
 
Despite this I have found the article [[interesting]] because of it’s way of dealing with the problem of private [[language]] in the first place, rather than {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} only.
Line 42: Line 44:
 
(And it gives me a chance to practice my English more than trying to teach {{Wiki|present}} {{Wiki|perfect}} almost thirty hours a week.)
 
(And it gives me a chance to practice my English more than trying to teach {{Wiki|present}} {{Wiki|perfect}} almost thirty hours a week.)
  
In his essay, Thurman intends  to establish  the  nearly  total  similarity  between {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  as mature critical [[philosopher]] and the Prasangika-madhyamika [[philosophers]] ranging from [[Candrakirti]]  ([[India]], sixth to seventh  centuries) to Tson Khapa ([[Tibet]], 1357-1420) in their treatment  of  the [[philosophical]]  questions  related to the ‘private [[language]] problem’.  
+
In his essay, [[Thurman]] intends  to establish  the  nearly  total  similarity  between {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  as mature critical [[philosopher]] and the [[Prasangika-madhyamika]] [[philosophers]] ranging from [[Candrakirti]]  ([[India]], sixth to seventh  centuries) to [[Tson Khapa]] ([[Tibet]], 1357-1420) in their treatment  of  the [[philosophical]]  questions  related to the ‘private [[language]] problem’.  
  
 
He starts to introduce the topic by quoting Saunders    and  Henze, who convey  the general [[philosophical]] relevance of  the question  in  the following passage:  
 
He starts to introduce the topic by quoting Saunders    and  Henze, who convey  the general [[philosophical]] relevance of  the question  in  the following passage:  
Line 54: Line 56:
 
If  on the  other  hand, the  [[egocentric]] predicament  be viewed as an illegitimate  problem, a pseudo  problem, then the response  to this "problem" will be to repudiate the [[egocentric]]  viewpoint.   
 
If  on the  other  hand, the  [[egocentric]] predicament  be viewed as an illegitimate  problem, a pseudo  problem, then the response  to this "problem" will be to repudiate the [[egocentric]]  viewpoint.   
  
This is  the  response  of one  who  "begins  abroad," who begins  in the  public  rather  than  in the  private domain,  and  attempts  in  one  way  or  another  to understand both of these domains. ”  Thurman believes that the terms used frequently by Saunders  and  Henze, “[[philosophical]]  egocentrist” and “[[philosophical]] nonegocentrist” are precisely adequate to translate the [[Sanskrit]] átmavádin (literally, “self-advocate”) and anátmavádin (literally, “[[selflessness]]  advocate”), and this most central [[Indian]] [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|dichotomy}} persists onto the subtlest levels in a long [[debate]] over presence or absence of svabháva (“intrinsic  [[reality]]”), [[svalaksana]] (“intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]”) and finally svátantrya (“[[logical]] privacy”) .   
+
This is  the  response  of one  who  "begins  abroad," who begins  in the  public  rather  than  in the  private domain,  and  attempts  in  one  way  or  another  to understand both of these domains. ”  Thurman believes that the terms used frequently by Saunders  and  Henze, “[[philosophical]]  [[egocentrist]]” and “[[philosophical]] [[nonegocentrist]]” are precisely adequate to translate the [[Sanskrit]] átmavádin (literally, “self-advocate”) and [[anátmavádin]] (literally, “[[selflessness]]  advocate”), and this most central [[Indian]] [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|dichotomy}} persists onto the subtlest levels in a long [[debate]] over presence or absence of [[svabháva]] (“intrinsic  [[reality]]”), [[svalaksana]] (“intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]”) and finally [[svátantrya]] (“[[logical privacy]]) .   
  
 
He also believes that once we notice this obvious parallel, we naturally  become [[interested]]  in the arguments  used  by both  sides, considering  the longevity  of the issue  in [[India]]  and [[Tibet]], and its [[relative]] newness in the [[West]].
 
He also believes that once we notice this obvious parallel, we naturally  become [[interested]]  in the arguments  used  by both  sides, considering  the longevity  of the issue  in [[India]]  and [[Tibet]], and its [[relative]] newness in the [[West]].
  
One  major  [[obstacle]]  to  [[appreciation]]  of  the richness of the [[Buddhist]] nonegocentrist  [[tradition]] by {{Wiki|modern}}  [[philosophers]], who would therein  find so much of [[interest]]  and  use, is the unwarranted  prejudice that  [[Buddhist]]  [[thought]]  is  “[[mysticism]]”, that  is, antiphilosophical or aphilosophical.   
+
One  major  [[obstacle]]  to  [[appreciation]]  of  the richness of the [[Buddhist]] nonegocentrist  [[tradition]] by {{Wiki|modern}}  [[philosophers]], who would therein  find so much of [[interest]]  and  use, is the unwarranted  prejudice that  [[Buddhist]]  [[thought]]  is  “[[mysticism]]”, that  is, anti-philosophical or a-philosophical.   
  
  
Line 64: Line 66:
 
This prejudice has  only  been  intensified  by  those  contemporary ‘[[mystics]]’ who have pointed  to the young Wittgenstein's famous statement about [[silence]] in the Tractatus [[as evidence]] of his similarity to the [[imagined]] ‘[[silent]] [[sages]] of the [[East]].’   
 
This prejudice has  only  been  intensified  by  those  contemporary ‘[[mystics]]’ who have pointed  to the young Wittgenstein's famous statement about [[silence]] in the Tractatus [[as evidence]] of his similarity to the [[imagined]] ‘[[silent]] [[sages]] of the [[East]].’   
  
Thurman also warnes us about this and also argues that in [[actuality]], the vast  majority of ‘[[mystics]]’, or nonrationalists, both Eastern  and [[Western]], have usually  belonged  to the egocentrist camp, at  least  tacitly  if  not formally.  “Recourse to [[mysticism]]  is a typical aspect of being  stuck in the [[egocentric]]  predicament.   
+
Thurman also warnes us about this and also argues that in [[actuality]], the vast  majority of ‘[[mystics]]’, or nonrationalists, both Eastern  and [[Western]], have usually  belonged  to the egocentrist camp, at  least  tacitly  if  not formally.   
 +
 
 +
“Recourse to [[mysticism]]  is a typical aspect of being  stuck in the [[egocentric]]  predicament.   
  
 
The mature {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  clearly  exposes  the tremendous amount of [[mysticism]] involved in the uncritical use of ordinary  [[language]],  especially  by  the  egocentrist [[philosophers]].     
 
The mature {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  clearly  exposes  the tremendous amount of [[mysticism]] involved in the uncritical use of ordinary  [[language]],  especially  by  the  egocentrist [[philosophers]].     
Line 72: Line 76:
 
And here  we may fancy  naming  to be some remarkable act  of [[mind]], as it were  a baptism  of an [[object]]..." (PI  143).(4) An  egocentrist  [[philosopher]], when  yet unwilling  to surrender  the notion  as a mere [[mental]] construction, quite typically resorts to 'ineffability',  'inexpressibility', and so forth, making  a [[virtue]] of his  inability  to  find  either  a nonentity  or its absence.” (p.2)
 
And here  we may fancy  naming  to be some remarkable act  of [[mind]], as it were  a baptism  of an [[object]]..." (PI  143).(4) An  egocentrist  [[philosopher]], when  yet unwilling  to surrender  the notion  as a mere [[mental]] construction, quite typically resorts to 'ineffability',  'inexpressibility', and so forth, making  a [[virtue]] of his  inability  to  find  either  a nonentity  or its absence.” (p.2)
  
On the other  hand,  the  {{Wiki|mainstream}} [[Buddhist philosophers]] were typically nonegocentrist and critical,  not  [[mystical]], in approach. The  famous [[doctrine]]  of  ‘two  [[realities]]’  ([[satyadvaya]]) ,  the [[absolute]] (paramártha) and the contingent ([[samvrti]]) or [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]  ([[vyavahara]]), is not at all [[mystical]] but  is  rather  an effective  technical  device  for analyzing  apart the “queer”, “[[occult]]”, “mysterious”,  hence absolutistic  [[element]], to clear up the [[realm]] of [[experience]],  [[causality]],  and  [[action]].   
+
On the other  hand,  the  {{Wiki|mainstream}} [[Buddhist philosophers]] were typically nonegocentrist and critical,  not  [[mystical]], in approach. The  famous [[doctrine]]  of  ‘two  [[realities]]’  ([[satyadvaya]]) ,  the [[absolute]] ([[paramártha]]) and the contingent ([[samvrti]]) or [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]  ([[vyavahara]]), is not at all [[mystical]] but  is  rather  an effective  technical  device  for analyzing  apart the “queer”, “[[occult]]”, “mysterious”,  hence absolutistic  [[element]], to clear up the [[realm]] of [[experience]],  [[causality]],  and  [[action]].   
  
 
The  [[doctrine]] properly  puts  the  ‘[[absolute]]’  in its  place  as  a {{Wiki|conceptual}}    limiting  case, which frees the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[world]],  the  [[space]] of  living from [[absolutism]] and its problems.   
 
The  [[doctrine]] properly  puts  the  ‘[[absolute]]’  in its  place  as  a {{Wiki|conceptual}}    limiting  case, which frees the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[world]],  the  [[space]] of  living from [[absolutism]] and its problems.   
Line 80: Line 84:
 
Thus,  in  the  [[Buddhist tradition]],  [[philosophical]] analysis  was seen as the way to treat  the prevalent [[forms]] of 'misknowledge'  by applying [[criticism]] to the {{Wiki|conceptual}}  knots  of  the  day.” (p.2)   
 
Thus,  in  the  [[Buddhist tradition]],  [[philosophical]] analysis  was seen as the way to treat  the prevalent [[forms]] of 'misknowledge'  by applying [[criticism]] to the {{Wiki|conceptual}}  knots  of  the  day.” (p.2)   
  
The  level  of {{Wiki|sophistication}} of the application varied according to the  {{Wiki|sophistication}} of  the  ‘[[philosophical]] knots’, resulting in a critical [[metaphysics]] ([[Vaibhasika]]) as treatment of native [[realism]] ([[Vaisesika]]), a critical  {{Wiki|nominalism}} ([[Sautrantika]]), a  critical {{Wiki|idealism}} (Vijnánaváda), and  finally  the critical {{Wiki|relativism}} of the Mádhyamikas.  
+
The  level  of {{Wiki|sophistication}} of the application varied according to the  {{Wiki|sophistication}} of  the  ‘[[philosophical]] knots’, resulting in a critical [[metaphysics]] ([[Vaibhasika]]) as treatment of native [[realism]] ([[Vaisesika]]), a critical  {{Wiki|nominalism}} ([[Sautrantika]]), a  critical {{Wiki|idealism}} (Vijnánaváda), and  finally  the critical {{Wiki|relativism}} of the [[Mádhyamikas]].  
  
 
The high point in this [[philosophical]] refinement process was reached in the sixth century  by [[Candrakirti]], who entered  into the refutation of [[logical]] privacy.  
 
The high point in this [[philosophical]] refinement process was reached in the sixth century  by [[Candrakirti]], who entered  into the refutation of [[logical]] privacy.  
  
This  refutation,  as  preserved  in [[Candrakirti’s]]  Prasannapáda,  [[Chapter]]  I, served  as  the basis of a [[philosophical]]  [[discussion]] that went on for three more centuries in [[India]].   
+
This  refutation,  as  preserved  in [[Candrakirti’s]]  [[Prasannapáda]],  [[Chapter]]  I, served  as  the basis of a [[philosophical]]  [[discussion]] that went on for three more centuries in [[India]].   
  
It then came down to the {{Wiki|present}} day preserved in lively [[traditions]] of the [[Tibetan]] [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|training}} {{Wiki|colleges}}. Perhaps the greatest  [[master]]  of this [[subject]]  in [[Tibet]] was Tson Khapa  Blo Bzan Grags-pa  (1357-1420), whose {{Wiki|texture}} of [[thought]] and analysis can probably be treated best to that of {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} and his followers.
+
It then came down to the {{Wiki|present}} day preserved in lively [[traditions]] of the [[Tibetan]] [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|training}} {{Wiki|colleges}}. Perhaps the greatest  [[master]]  of this [[subject]]  in [[Tibet]] was [[Tson Khapa]] [[Blo Bzan Grags-pa]] (1357-1420), whose {{Wiki|texture}} of [[thought]] and analysis can probably be treated best to that of {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}} and his followers.
  
  
Line 99: Line 103:
  
  
Thurman draws a parallel with Tson  Khapa: “Thson Khapa also  describes the 'habitual  mode of [[intellectual]]  presumption'  ('sgro'dogs  [[kun btags]] kyi '[[dzin]] tshul) in parallel  terms, calling  that '[[essence]]'  in things that anchors their names "intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]" ([[svalaksana]]),  indispensable for the egocentrist, impossible for the nonegocentrist” (p.3.), quoting one of his works:  
+
Thurman draws a parallel with [[Tson  Khapa]]: “[[Thson Khapa]] also  describes the 'habitual  mode of [[intellectual]]  presumption'  ('[[sgro'dogs  kun btags kyi 'dzin tshul) in parallel  terms, calling  that '[[essence]]'  in things that anchors their names "intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]" ([[svalaksana]]),  indispensable for the egocentrist, impossible for the nonegocentrist” (p.3.), quoting one of his works:  
  
  
Line 109: Line 113:
  
  
Thurman believes that Tson Khapa was able to return to the surface of the question with the nonegocentrists view by appreciating  the conventionality  of the expression, content  with  that.   
+
Thurman believes that [[Tson Khapa]] was able to return to the surface of the question with the nonegocentrists view by appreciating  the conventionality  of the expression, content  with  that.   
  
 
Further, he was able to isolate the  [[mental]]  [[Wikipedia:Habit (psychology)|habit]] that  had [[caused]]  him  the  whole problem, revealing  the egocentrist's  [[dependence]]  on the ‘private [[object]]’, internally  designated  via the ‘private [[language]]’.  
 
Further, he was able to isolate the  [[mental]]  [[Wikipedia:Habit (psychology)|habit]] that  had [[caused]]  him  the  whole problem, revealing  the egocentrist's  [[dependence]]  on the ‘private [[object]]’, internally  designated  via the ‘private [[language]]’.  
  
Tson Khapa mentions the ‘private [[language]]’ explicitly  in a [[language]] in which a [[person]] could write down or give {{Wiki|vocal}}  expression  to  his  inner  [[experiences]] - his [[feelings]],  moods,  and  the  rest - for  his  private use. The {{Wiki|individual}}  words of this [[language]]  are to refer  to what  can only  be known  to  the  [[person]]  {{Wiki|speaking}};  to  his  immediate private  [[sensations]].  So  another  [[person]]  cannot understand the [[language]].
+
[[Tson Khapa]] mentions the ‘private [[language]]’ explicitly  in a [[language]] in which a [[person]] could write down or give {{Wiki|vocal}}  expression  to  his  inner  [[experiences]] - his [[feelings]],  moods,  and  the  rest - for  his  private use. The {{Wiki|individual}}  words of this [[language]]  are to refer  to what  can only  be known  to  the  [[person]]  {{Wiki|speaking}};  to  his  immediate private  [[sensations]].  So  another  [[person]]  cannot understand the [[language]].
  
  
Line 167: Line 171:
 
It  will readily be granted  that the mature {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  was primarily  critical  in approach, and  the  [[Buddhists]] were well known for their  critical  [[attitude]]  toward the  ‘given’ as naively  accepted  in  their  host cultures.   
 
It  will readily be granted  that the mature {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  was primarily  critical  in approach, and  the  [[Buddhists]] were well known for their  critical  [[attitude]]  toward the  ‘given’ as naively  accepted  in  their  host cultures.   
  
[[Vipasyana]], or ‘[[transcendental]] analysis’ is the main type of Maháyána [[meditation]].  Prajná, the  [[highest wisdom]], is glossed  as dharmapravicaya, literally,  the  ‘analysis  of  things’, and  it  is [[symbolized]]  as a sword that cuts through the [[knot]] of [[perplexity]].   
+
[[Vipasyana]], or ‘[[transcendental]] analysis’ is the main type of [[Maháyána]] [[meditation]].  [[Prajná]], the  [[highest wisdom]], is glossed  as [[dharmapravicaya]], literally,  the  ‘analysis  of  things’, and  it  is [[symbolized]]  as a sword that cuts through the [[knot]] of [[perplexity]].   
  
  
Line 193: Line 197:
  
  
Examples    from  the  [[Buddhist]]  [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|literature}} could be plenty, but Thurman finds Tson Khapa's description of the critical techniques of his predecessors particularly striking, from EE , p. 161: “..  the [[absolute]]  {{Wiki|status}}  of anything  is refuted  by showing  first of all, in the face of no {{Wiki|matter}}  what [[assertion]]  of [[Buddhist]]  or [[non-Buddhist]]  [[scholar]], the impossibility  of an indivisible, a thing  without  a plurality  of parts such as periods of time, parts of [[physical objects]], or aspects  of [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]]  [[objects]],  and then by demonstrating  that, whereas [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[objects]] may [[exist]] as unitary things while established as composed  of parts, as far as [[absolute]]  {{Wiki|status}}  is concerned, there are inevitable inconsistencies; for example, if part and whole are absolutely  different, there can be no connection  between them, and if part and  whole  are absolutely  the same, then  the whole becomes  a plurality....   
+
Examples    from  the  [[Buddhist]]  [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|literature}} could be plenty, but Thurman finds [[Tson Khapa's]] description of the critical techniques of his predecessors particularly striking, from EE , p. 161: “..  the [[absolute]]  {{Wiki|status}}  of anything  is refuted  by showing  first of all, in the face of no {{Wiki|matter}}  what [[assertion]]  of [[Buddhist]]  or [[non-Buddhist]]  [[scholar]], the impossibility  of an indivisible, a thing  without  a plurality  of parts such as periods of time, parts of [[physical objects]], or aspects  of [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]]  [[objects]],  and then by demonstrating  that, whereas [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[objects]] may [[exist]] as unitary things while established as composed  of parts, as far as [[absolute]]  {{Wiki|status}}  is concerned, there are inevitable inconsistencies; for example, if part and whole are absolutely  different, there can be no connection  between them, and if part and  whole  are absolutely  the same, then  the whole becomes  a plurality....   
  
  
Line 205: Line 209:
 
Then  production  from  a  previously undestroyed  [[cause]]  is  restricted  to  being  either obstructed  or unobstructed, and production  from  an obstructed  [[cause]] is rejected."   
 
Then  production  from  a  previously undestroyed  [[cause]]  is  restricted  to  being  either obstructed  or unobstructed, and production  from  an obstructed  [[cause]] is rejected."   
  
The refutation  thus far  is  rather  easy.  "Then,  production  from  an unobstructed  [[cause]]  is  restricted  to being  either wholly unobstructed or partiaily unobstructed;  then,  in the  former  case, an {{Wiki|atom}}  and  (its  aggregative effects  such  as) a molecule  must be confused  as a single  [[object]],  (the  causal  [[atoms]])  being  wholly unobstructed;  or else, in the  [[latter]]  case, as (the [[cause]],  the  indivisible,  etc.)  would  have  parts, production  would  be [[relative]]  (sa.mv.rti) (and  not [[absolute]]).”
+
The refutation  thus far  is  rather  easy.  "Then,  production  from  an unobstructed  [[cause]]  is  restricted  to being  either wholly unobstructed or partiaily unobstructed;  then,  in the  former  case, an {{Wiki|atom}}  and  (its  aggregative effects  such  as) a molecule  must be confused  as a single  [[object]],  (the  causal  [[atoms]])  being  wholly unobstructed;  or else, in the  [[latter]]  case, as (the [[cause]],  the  indivisible,  etc.)  would  have  parts, production  would  be [[relative]]  ([[sa.mv.rti]]) (and  not [[absolute]]).”
  
  
  
Here the opponent, as the interlocutor  in the PI passage,  is    a  [[philosophical]]    [[absolutist]],  a substantivist, who  is “bewitched  by [[language]]”  into perceiving  things  to  be  absolutely  true, “really real”  before  him,  and  the  Wittgensteinian and [[Madhyamika]] nonegocentrist critical analyses intend to force him to look deeper  into things  and {{Wiki|processes}}  by examining  his account  of them to actually  try to find the [[essence]] assumed to correspond  to the [[name]], the ‘[[metaphysical]] [[entity]]’,  the  ‘simple’,  the  ‘indivisible’.   
+
Here the opponent, as the interlocutor  in the PI passage,  is    a  [[philosophical]]    [[absolutist]],  a substantivist, who  is “bewitched  by [[language]]”  into perceiving  things  to  be  absolutely  true, “really real”  before  him,  and  the  [[Wittgensteinian]] and [[Madhyamika]] nonegocentrist critical analyses intend to force him to look deeper  into things  and {{Wiki|processes}}  by examining  his account  of them to actually  try to find the [[essence]] assumed to correspond  to the [[name]], the ‘[[metaphysical]] [[entity]]’,  the  ‘simple’,  the  ‘indivisible’.   
  
 
The absolutist’s failure to find  any  such analysis-resistant  [[essence]] is the first step on the road to [[liberation]] of his [[intelligence]] from the spell of  [[language]].
 
The absolutist’s failure to find  any  such analysis-resistant  [[essence]] is the first step on the road to [[liberation]] of his [[intelligence]] from the spell of  [[language]].
Line 260: Line 264:
 
[[Essence]]  is expressed  by {{Wiki|grammar}}  (PI 371).  {{Wiki|Grammar}}  tells  what  kind  of  [[object]]  anything  is. ({{Wiki|Theology}} as {{Wiki|grammar}}) (PI 373).”
 
[[Essence]]  is expressed  by {{Wiki|grammar}}  (PI 371).  {{Wiki|Grammar}}  tells  what  kind  of  [[object]]  anything  is. ({{Wiki|Theology}} as {{Wiki|grammar}}) (PI 373).”
  
Thurman believes that the [[buddhist]] Prásangika counterpart of  this conventionalism can be most clearly seen in [[Candrakirti’s]] critique  of  Bhavya’s (a contemporary thinker) use of the “head  of [[Ráhu]]” example as {{Wiki|justification}} for employing the expression “{{Wiki|hardness}}  is the intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]  of [[earth]]” as a {{Wiki|conventionally}}  acceptable  expression.   
+
[[Thurman]] believes that the [[buddhist]] [[Prásangika]] counterpart of  this conventionalism can be most clearly seen in [[Candrakirti’s]] critique  of  [[Bhavya’s]] (a contemporary thinker) use of the “head  of [[Ráhu]]” example as {{Wiki|justification}} for employing the expression “{{Wiki|hardness}}  is the intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]  of [[earth]]” as a {{Wiki|conventionally}}  acceptable  expression.   
  
 
([[Ráhu]]  is a [[mythological]]  {{Wiki|demon}}  who is all head  and no [[body]], so “head”  and “[[Ráhu]]”  refer  to the same  thing, as do “{{Wiki|hardness}}” and “[[earth]]”.) “[[Candra]] states: “  
 
([[Ráhu]]  is a [[mythological]]  {{Wiki|demon}}  who is all head  and no [[body]], so “head”  and “[[Ráhu]]”  refer  to the same  thing, as do “{{Wiki|hardness}}” and “[[earth]]”.) “[[Candra]] states: “  
Line 267: Line 271:
 
Moreover,  this  example  is  incorrect  because  the expression...  "Raahu"  does  [[exist]]  among  [[mundane]], established  without  analysis, and does apply  to  its  referent...  "head,"  just  like  the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] designation "[[person]]," (EE, p. 171).”  
 
Moreover,  this  example  is  incorrect  because  the expression...  "Raahu"  does  [[exist]]  among  [[mundane]], established  without  analysis, and does apply  to  its  referent...  "head,"  just  like  the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] designation "[[person]]," (EE, p. 171).”  
  
Thurman also quotes Tson Khapa, who here comments: “... it is correct, according to conventions of {{Wiki|social}} [[communication]], for a speaker to dispel the [[doubt]] of a listener  with the expression...  '[[Ráhu]]'  since  the [[latter]]  has  formed  the  notion  of a...  head  from hearing that [[word]] and is wondering "whose head? "  
+
Thurman also quotes [[Tson Khapa]], who here comments: “... it is correct, according to conventions of {{Wiki|social}} [[communication]], for a speaker to dispel the [[doubt]] of a listener  with the expression...  '[[Ráhu]]'  since  the [[latter]]  has  formed  the  notion  of a...  head  from hearing that [[word]] and is wondering "whose head? "  
  
The speaker thus wishes to eliminate  the possibility  of reference...  to any head other  than that  of [[Ráhu]].  However, this example does not correspond to the case of the expression "{{Wiki|hardness}} is the intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] of [[earth]]," there  being  no [[earth]] which  is not hard,  and hence no need to dispel any such [[doubt]] (EE, 172).
+
The speaker thus wishes to eliminate  the possibility  of reference...  to any head other  than that  of [[Ráhu]].   
 +
 
 +
However, this example does not correspond to the case of the expression "{{Wiki|hardness}} is the intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] of [[earth]]," there  being  no [[earth]] which  is not hard,  and hence no need to dispel any such [[doubt]] (EE, 172).
 
   
 
   
  
  
Thurman [[thinks]] that the main target of the critique  is the notion of  ‘intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’  which  would not occur  to the ordinary hearer.  “{{Wiki|Hardness}}  of [[earth]]” might fit with the  example, but there  is no room  for  notions  of ‘intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’ - the  hearer  would  not [[wonder]] ‘whose  intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’?  but  only  ‘whose {{Wiki|hardness}}’?
+
[[Thurman]] [[thinks]] that the main target of the critique  is the notion of  ‘intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’  which  would not occur  to the ordinary hearer.  “{{Wiki|Hardness}}  of [[earth]]” might fit with the  example, but there  is no room  for  notions  of ‘intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’ - the  hearer  would  not [[wonder]] ‘whose  intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’?  but  only  ‘whose {{Wiki|hardness}}’?
  
  
Line 282: Line 288:
 
I say that is not so;  for, in the usage of [[mundane]]  conventions, such a sort of analysis  (as that  seeking  [[essential]]  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]],  etc.)  is  not employed, and further, the  things  of the [[world]]  are [[existent]] (only insofar) as unexamined critically (EE, p. 173)”.  
 
I say that is not so;  for, in the usage of [[mundane]]  conventions, such a sort of analysis  (as that  seeking  [[essential]]  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]],  etc.)  is  not employed, and further, the  things  of the [[world]]  are [[existent]] (only insofar) as unexamined critically (EE, p. 173)”.  
  
[[Candra]]  states  that once one looks analytically  for ‘head’, ‘[[Ráhu]]’, or  anything  else, nothing  can  be found to withstand  analysis, but still  those things are there  when unanalytically  accepted.  He pursues this [[idea]] then with a key {{Wiki|concept}}:
+
[[Candra]]  states  that once one looks analytically  for ‘head’, ‘[[Ráhu]]’, or  anything  else, nothing  can  be found to withstand  analysis, but still  those things are there  when unanalytically  accepted.   
“Although  analytically  there  is [[no self]] apart  from [[form]]    etc.,  from    the    [[mundane]]    [[superficial]] (lokasamvrtya) point  of view such (a [[self]]) has its [[existence]]  dependent  on  the  [[aggregates]]...  (EE, p. 174).”
 
  
 +
He pursues this [[idea]] then with a key {{Wiki|concept}}:
  
 +
“Although  analytically  there  is [[no self]] apart  from [[form]]    etc.,  from    the    [[mundane]]    [[superficial]] ([[lokasamvrtya]]) point  of view such (a [[self]]) has its [[existence]]  dependent  on  the  [[aggregates]]...  (EE, p. 174).”
  
Let’s show Thurman’s comment on this line of [[thought]]: “Conventionally,  even  the  abhorrent    (to  the nonegocentrist) '[[self]]' is reinstated, as 'part of the {{Wiki|grammar}}'  of  [[mundane]]  [[communication]].  And  thus  the feared [[nihilism]], which the [[absolutist]]  imagines lurks at the  end of the analysis  that  seeks  a [[self]]  and cannot  find  anything,  is  avoided  through  the reaffirmation  of  the  mutually  dependent, [[mundane]], [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], nonanalytic [[existence]] of '[[self]]'.  
+
 
 +
 
 +
Let’s show Thurman’s comment on this line of [[thought]]:  
 +
 
 +
“Conventionally,  even  the  abhorrent    (to  the nonegocentrist) '[[self]]' is reinstated, as 'part of the {{Wiki|grammar}}'  of  [[mundane]]  [[communication]].   
 +
 
 +
And  thus  the feared [[nihilism]], which the [[absolutist]]  imagines lurks at the  end of the analysis  that  seeks  a [[self]]  and cannot  find  anything,  is  avoided  through  the reaffirmation  of  the  mutually  dependent, [[mundane]], [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], nonanalytic [[existence]] of '[[self]]'.  
  
 
[[Candra]] finally  shows  his [[awareness]]  of how  such  [[nihilism]] cannot  be  avoided  by any  means  other  than  such thoroughgoing  conventionalism, saying: "otherwise, the  [[superficial]]  ([[reality]]) would  no  longer  be the [[superficial]]  and would either lack validity  entirely or would become ([[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]]) [[reality]]..." (EE, p.175).   
 
[[Candra]] finally  shows  his [[awareness]]  of how  such  [[nihilism]] cannot  be  avoided  by any  means  other  than  such thoroughgoing  conventionalism, saying: "otherwise, the  [[superficial]]  ([[reality]]) would  no  longer  be the [[superficial]]  and would either lack validity  entirely or would become ([[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]]) [[reality]]..." (EE, p.175).   
Line 297: Line 310:
 
Here it should  be noted  that [[Candrakirti’s]]  opponent in this  is by no means  a {{Wiki|naive}}  [[absolutist]], but  is only  trying  to  uphold  the  ‘intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’ ([[svalaksana]])  of  things  {{Wiki|conventionally}},  having already, as  he [[thinks]], ruled  them  out  absolutely.   
 
Here it should  be noted  that [[Candrakirti’s]]  opponent in this  is by no means  a {{Wiki|naive}}  [[absolutist]], but  is only  trying  to  uphold  the  ‘intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’ ([[svalaksana]])  of  things  {{Wiki|conventionally}},  having already, as  he [[thinks]], ruled  them  out  absolutely.   
  
[[Candrakirti’s]]  thrust  is thus to show the incompatibility of the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of conventionality and intrinsicality.  Finally, to forestall any {{Wiki|misunderstanding}}  about the sort of analysis that can be involved  in calling the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] ‘nonanalytic’, Tson Khapa comments (with intriguing implications for Wittgenstein’s ‘everyday’ use of [[language]], even [[philosophically]]): “  
+
[[Candrakirti’s]]  thrust  is thus to show the incompatibility of the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of conventionality and intrinsicality.  Finally, to forestall any {{Wiki|misunderstanding}}  about the sort of analysis that can be involved  in calling the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] ‘nonanalytic’, [[Tson Khapa]] comments (with intriguing implications for Wittgenstein’s ‘everyday’ use of [[language]], even [[philosophically]]): “  
  
 
We might suppose here, as the [[mundane]]  [[person]] engages in  a great  deal  of analysis--"Is  it happening  or not?" or "Is it produced  or not?"--that  it must  be improper  to reply to such inquiries  "It happens" or "it  is  produced.”     
 
We might suppose here, as the [[mundane]]  [[person]] engages in  a great  deal  of analysis--"Is  it happening  or not?" or "Is it produced  or not?"--that  it must  be improper  to reply to such inquiries  "It happens" or "it  is  produced.”     
Line 325: Line 338:
  
  
Tson Khapa  introduces the refutation as follows: “ In  general,  the  two  [[masters]]  ([[Buddhapalita]]  and [[Candrakirti]]) took  as the  [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]]  in  {{Wiki|subtle}}  and profound  [[philosophical]]  reasonings  those reasonings proving the {{Wiki|perfect}} viability  of all systems such as [[causality]]  in the  absence  of any intrinsic  [[reality]] such  as  that  (already)  rejected  as  intrinsic identifiability even {{Wiki|conventionally}}, as well as those reasonings  negating  the  negandum  of  intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]  by the very [[reason]]  of [[relativity]], asserted clearly  as  the  [[relativity]]    of  all  things,   
+
[[Tson Khapa]] introduces the refutation as follows: “ In  general,  the  two  [[masters]]  ([[Buddhapalita]]  and [[Candrakirti]]) took  as the  [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]]  in  {{Wiki|subtle}}  and profound  [[philosophical]]  reasonings  those reasonings proving the {{Wiki|perfect}} viability  of all systems such as [[causality]]  in the  absence  of any intrinsic  [[reality]] such  as  that  (already)  rejected  as  intrinsic identifiability even {{Wiki|conventionally}}, as well as those reasonings  negating  the  negandum  of  intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]  by the very [[reason]]  of [[relativity]], asserted clearly  as  the  [[relativity]]    of  all  things,
 +
 
 +
[[transcendental]]  as  well  as  non-transcendental.  
  
[[transcendental]]  as  well  as  non-transcendental.  Moreover,  they  took  this  refutation  of  [[logical]] privacy as the most {{Wiki|subtle}} among them (EE, p. 218).”
+
Moreover,  they  took  this  refutation  of  [[logical]] privacy as the most {{Wiki|subtle}} among them (EE, p. 218).”
 
   
 
   
Thus, the refutation of [[logical]] privacy is stated to be a [[form]] of the refutation  of intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]  ([[svalaksana]]),  at  the  final  level  of  subtlety. ‘Intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’, as  we  have  seen  is  the egocentrist’s  designative  base,  the  essentialist private [[object]], necessary  for private or {{Wiki|independent}} reference  and  [[language]].  
+
Thus, the refutation of [[logical]] privacy is stated to be a [[form]] of the refutation  of intrinsic [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]  ([[svalaksana]]),  at  the  final  level  of  subtlety.  
 +
 
 +
‘Intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]’, as  we  have  seen  is  the egocentrist’s  designative  base,  the  essentialist private [[object]], necessary  for private or {{Wiki|independent}} reference  and  [[language]].  
  
  
Thurman goes on like this for the rest of the article, making his line of [[thought]] more and more difficult to follow. I simply don’t have the [[desire]] to give a further account of his [[reasons]] of why he comes to the following conclusion. (His method of treating the problem and what he is aiming at can be clearly seen from what I have already reasembled.)
+
Thurman goes on like this for the rest of the article, making his line of [[thought]] more and more difficult to follow.  
 +
 
 +
I simply don’t have the [[desire]] to give a further account of his [[reasons]] of why he comes to the following conclusion.  
 +
 
 +
(His method of treating the problem and what he is aiming at can be clearly seen from what I have already reasembled.)
  
 
Conclusion:
 
Conclusion:
  
Although I [[feel]] quite at home among [[sanskrit]] [[philosophical]] terms, I had found Thurman’s way of {{Wiki|reasoning}} quite difficult to follow. Despite of this, his [[attitude]] towards [[philosophy]] had a great impact on me, and his final conclusion could be heeded by many {{Wiki|modern}} [[philosophers]]. That’s why I’ll quote it in whole:
+
Although I [[feel]] quite at home among [[sanskrit]] [[philosophical]] terms, I had found Thurman’s way of {{Wiki|reasoning}} quite difficult to follow. Despite of this, his [[attitude]] towards [[philosophy]] had a great impact on me, and his final conclusion could be heeded by many {{Wiki|modern}} [[philosophers]].  
 +
 
 +
That’s why I’ll quote it in whole:
  
  
Line 351: Line 374:
 
If the type of critical [[vision]] he achieved and  cultivated  on  his  [[own]]  was  highly  developed systematically  already  in  a great  [[tradition]]  with thousands  of members in the most populous nations of [[earth]], (not that very many perhaps  ever reached  the greatest  heights  or depths), then  there  must have been a rather  bountiful  crop of unsung, unpublished Wittgensteins  over the twenty centuries during which [[Indian]],   
 
If the type of critical [[vision]] he achieved and  cultivated  on  his  [[own]]  was  highly  developed systematically  already  in  a great  [[tradition]]  with thousands  of members in the most populous nations of [[earth]], (not that very many perhaps  ever reached  the greatest  heights  or depths), then  there  must have been a rather  bountiful  crop of unsung, unpublished Wittgensteins  over the twenty centuries during which [[Indian]],   
  
[[Tibetan]],  {{Wiki|Chinese}}, [[Japanese]],  and  {{Wiki|Mongolian}} [[scholars]]  pursued  the [[goddess of wisdom]], (the [[Sophia]] of  [[philosophy]]  as  Prajnápáramitá,  "[[Transcendent Wisdom]]") whose [[attainment]] was defined as the [[ultimate liberation]] from the "fly-bottle" of [[perplexity]].   
+
[[Tibetan]],  {{Wiki|Chinese}}, [[Japanese]],  and  {{Wiki|Mongolian}} [[scholars]]  pursued  the [[goddess of wisdom]], (the [[Sophia]] of  [[philosophy]]  as  [[Prajnápáramitá]],  "[[Transcendent Wisdom]]") whose [[attainment]] was defined as the [[ultimate liberation]] from the "fly-bottle" of [[perplexity]].   
  
 
Such being  the case, or even the possibility, it behooves us not to rest content  with our one [[river]] of [[Western]] [[tradition]], but to explore and reveal to our young the great  ocean of [[world]] [[philosophy]].   
 
Such being  the case, or even the possibility, it behooves us not to rest content  with our one [[river]] of [[Western]] [[tradition]], but to explore and reveal to our young the great  ocean of [[world]] [[philosophy]].   
  
It is all ours, we are all [[human beings]], and  the  [[Indian]]  or {{Wiki|Chinese}}  heritage belongs  as  much  to  us as to the  {{Wiki|Chinese}}  or  the {{Wiki|Indians}}. Especially the [[philosophical]] heritage of the nonegocentrist, critical  [[tradition]]  which  was  born  from  [[liberation]]  from {{Wiki|cultural}}  {{Wiki|conditioning}}  at the deepest  levels, {{Wiki|perceptual}}  and  {{Wiki|ideological}},   
+
It is all ours, we are all [[human beings]], and  the  [[Indian]]  or {{Wiki|Chinese}}  heritage belongs  as  much  to  us as to the  {{Wiki|Chinese}}  or  the {{Wiki|Indians}}.  
 +
 
 +
Especially the [[philosophical]] heritage of the nonegocentrist, critical  [[tradition]]  which  was  born  from  [[liberation]]  from {{Wiki|cultural}}  {{Wiki|conditioning}}  at the deepest  levels, {{Wiki|perceptual}}  and  {{Wiki|ideological}},   
  
 
never belonged  to  any  race, {{Wiki|culture}}, or even  {{Wiki|linguistic}} [[tradition]], but always  to those  members  of whatever such  [[tradition]]  who  dare  to  question  what  seems [[self-evident]]    right    before    them,  what    is authoritatively  told to them, what  seems  safe  and natural  to them--those whose sensibilities  demand the surpassing  [[peace]] that comes with the eradication of [[perplexity]].”
 
never belonged  to  any  race, {{Wiki|culture}}, or even  {{Wiki|linguistic}} [[tradition]], but always  to those  members  of whatever such  [[tradition]]  who  dare  to  question  what  seems [[self-evident]]    right    before    them,  what    is authoritatively  told to them, what  seems  safe  and natural  to them--those whose sensibilities  demand the surpassing  [[peace]] that comes with the eradication of [[perplexity]].”
Line 362: Line 387:
  
  
The [[word]] I have rendered in the preceding passage as "[[logical]] privacy" is the [[Tibetan]] ran rgyud, which renders the [[Sanskrit]] svaatantrya, previously rendered in this  context  by Stcherbatski  as "{{Wiki|independence}}."   
+
The [[word]] I have rendered in the preceding passage as "[[logical privacy]]" is the [[Tibetan]] [[ran rgyud]], which renders the [[Sanskrit]] [[svaatantrya]], previously rendered in this  context  by [[Stcherbatski]] as "{{Wiki|independence}}."   
  
  
Mention  of the [[Tibetan]] as well as the [[Sanskrit]]  here is  important, since  it was  mainly  in  [[Tibet]]  that followers  of  Candra's  [[thought]]  elaborated  this question  in  great  detail.   
+
Mention  of the [[Tibetan]] as well as the [[Sanskrit]]  here is  important, since  it was  mainly  in  [[Tibet]]  that followers  of  [[Candra's]]   [[thought]]  elaborated  this question  in  great  detail.   
  
The  usual  [[Tibetan]] translation  for [[Sanskrit]] svaatantrya  (adjectivally,  [[svatantra]]) is ran  dban, which  is also  the normal [[Tibetan]]  expression  for  '{{Wiki|independent}}',  meaning literally  'self-powered', opposed to '[[other-powered]]'  (gzan dban, [[paratantra]]) .  
+
The  usual  [[Tibetan]] translation  for [[Sanskrit]] [[svaatantrya]] (adjectivally,  [[svatantra]]) is [[ran  dban]], which  is also  the normal [[Tibetan]]  expression  for  '{{Wiki|independent}}',  meaning literally  'self-powered', opposed to '[[other-powered]]'  ([[gzan dban]], [[paratantra]]) .  
  
In this crucial [[philosophical]] context,  a  context  which  generated  centuries  of [[discussion]]  and  volumes  of commentary  and rigorous analysis,  why  did  the  [[Tibetan]]  [[translators]]  and [[scholars]]  use  ran  rgyud,  which  literally  means "own-continuum," translating  back  into [[Sanskrit]]  in most  contexts    as  svasa.mtaana,  often    "[[own]] [[personality]]"  or even  "[[own]]  [[mind]]"?  
+
In this crucial [[philosophical]] context,  a  context  which  generated  centuries  of [[discussion]]  and  volumes  of commentary  and rigorous analysis,  why  did  the  [[Tibetan]]  [[translators]]  and [[scholars]]  use  [[ran  rgyud]],  which  literally  means "own-continuum," translating  back  into [[Sanskrit]]  in most  contexts    as  [[svasa.mtaana]],  often    "[[own]] [[personality]]"  or even  "[[own]]  [[mind]]"?  
  
To be  sure, Tson Khapa himself  glosses ran rgyud with ran dban, (just as Saunders  and Henze gloss 'private [[language]]'  as a [[language]] whose words are "conceptually {{Wiki|independent}} of publicly  observable  [[phenomena]]"), but that does  not alter  the fact that he and his [[colleagues]]  persisted in using ran rgyud, talking of the ran rgyud problem,   
+
To be  sure, [[Tson Khapa]] himself  glosses [[ran rgyud]] with [[ran dban]], (just as Saunders  and Henze gloss 'private [[language]]'  as a [[language]] whose words are "conceptually {{Wiki|independent}} of publicly  observable  [[phenomena]]"), but that does  not alter  the fact that he and his [[colleagues]]  persisted in using [[ran rgyud]], talking of the [[ran rgyud]] problem,   
  
(which would not have been necessary if ran rgyud was [[identical]]  with  ran  dban), in all  of its contexts.  Looking  at these, we note  that  ran  rgyud  is used nominally, as direct  [[object]]  of [['gog pa]], to refute, [[sgrub pa]], to establish.   
+
(which would not have been necessary if [[ran rgyud]] was [[identical]]  with  [[ran  dban]]), in all  of its contexts.  Looking  at these, we note  that  [[ran  rgyud]] is used nominally, as direct  [[object]]  of [['gog pa]], to refute, [[sgrub pa]], to establish.   
  
  
"{{Wiki|Independence}}"  here, while not  wrong, is too vague, and  does  not specifically connect  to the [[philosophical]]  issues  involved.  ran rgyud is also used adjectivally  with "[[reason]]" ([[hetu]],  li^nga),  "{{Wiki|thesis}}"  (pratij~naa), position  ([[pak.sa]]),  "[[probandum]]"  (saadhya),  "[[syllogism]]"  ([[anumaana]]), and "validating  [[cognition]]" ([[pramaa.na]]), all of which are [[essentially]]  {{Wiki|linguistic}}  [[phenomena]],  although  to  my [[knowledge]]  it  is  never  used  with  "[[language]]" (bhaa.sya).   
+
"{{Wiki|Independence}}"  here, while not  wrong, is too vague, and  does  not specifically connect  to the [[philosophical]]  issues  involved.   
  
In all of these cases, it is contrasted, not with "dependent"  ([[paratantra]]), but with "public" (paraprasiddha,   literally,   "other-acknowledged") [[reason]], {{Wiki|thesis}}, and so forth.  
+
[[ran rgyud]] is also used adjectivally  with "[[reason]]" ([[hetu]], ]]li^nga\\), "{{Wiki|thesis}}" (pratij~naa), position ([[pak.sa]]), "[[probandum]]" (]]saadhya\\), "[[syllogism]]"  ([[anumaana]]), and "validating  [[cognition]]" ([[pramaa.na]]), all of which are [[essentially]] {{Wiki|linguistic}} [[phenomena]], although  to  my [[knowledge]]  it  is  never  used  with  "[[language]]" (]]bhaa.sya\\).
  
Finally, it crops up in the  [[name]]  of [[Bhaavaviveka's]]  [[Maadhyamika]]  subschool,  [[Svaatantrika]], the "school  of those  who use  private arguments," as opposed to Candra's  Praasa^ngika, the "school of those who use {{Wiki|consequences}}" (prasa^nga) of their opponent's absolutisms, the most public [[form]] of [[philosophical]] approach.  
+
In all of these cases, it is contrasted, not with "dependent"  ([[paratantra]]), but with "public" (]]paraprasiddha\\,    literally,  "other-acknowledged") [[reason]], {{Wiki|thesis}}, and so forth.
 +
 
 +
Finally, it crops up in the  [[name]]  of [[Bhaavaviveka's]]  [[Maadhyamika]]  subschool,  [[Svaatantrika]], the "school  of those  who use  private arguments," as opposed to [[Candra's]] [[Praasa^ngika]], the "school of those who use {{Wiki|consequences}}" ([[prasa^nga]]) of their opponent's absolutisms, the most public [[form]] of [[philosophical]] approach.  
  
 
By derivation, the former can be  aptly  called  the  "[[Dogmatic]]  [[Maadhyamikas]]"  in contrast  to the "[[Dialectical]]  [[Maadhyamikas]]," as long as  it  is  understood  that  the  [[reason]]  for  their {{Wiki|dogmatism}}, albeit  only [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], is their  tacit {{Wiki|resurrection}} of intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] in the [[form]] of [[logical]] privacy as the  basis  of  [[language]]  used  rigorously    in [[philosophical]] arguments.(8)
 
By derivation, the former can be  aptly  called  the  "[[Dogmatic]]  [[Maadhyamikas]]"  in contrast  to the "[[Dialectical]]  [[Maadhyamikas]]," as long as  it  is  understood  that  the  [[reason]]  for  their {{Wiki|dogmatism}}, albeit  only [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], is their  tacit {{Wiki|resurrection}} of intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] in the [[form]] of [[logical]] privacy as the  basis  of  [[language]]  used  rigorously    in [[philosophical]] arguments.(8)
  
Tson  Khapa,  in  typical  [[Tibetan]]  [[philosophic]] style, first cites the [[Indian]] Jayaananda's  attack on the private  [[reason]]  and then goes on to reject it as the wrong approach.  
+
[[Tson  Khapa]],  in  typical  [[Tibetan]]  [[philosophic]] style, first cites the [[Indian]] [[Jayaananda's]] attack on the private  [[reason]]  and then goes on to reject it as the wrong approach.  
  
  
Line 399: Line 426:
 
This false start on the refutation  of privacy is strikingly  reminiscent  of  Saunders  and  Henze's formulation  of the opening "prong" of the assault on the  private  [[language]], where  the  possibility  of a private  [[language]]  is challenged  on  grounds  of the unreliability  of [[subjective]] [[memory]] [[impressions]] which are not {{Wiki|independently}}  checkable or substantiated.(9)   
 
This false start on the refutation  of privacy is strikingly  reminiscent  of  Saunders  and  Henze's formulation  of the opening "prong" of the assault on the  private  [[language]], where  the  possibility  of a private  [[language]]  is challenged  on  grounds  of the unreliability  of [[subjective]] [[memory]] [[impressions]] which are not {{Wiki|independently}}  checkable or substantiated.(9)   
  
But,  just  like  Jayaananda's, this  attack  is  not conclusive, since the criterial  demand itself is too stringent, and the antagonist  is able  to throw  the same [[doubt]] back at public  discourse--"you  think you can  check  public  [[impressions]]  based  on  other's testimony,  etc.,  but  couldn't  you  hear  them wrong?"--and  so  forth.(10)  
+
But,  just  like  [[Jayaananda's]], this  attack  is  not conclusive, since the criterial  demand itself is too stringent, and the antagonist  is able  to throw  the same [[doubt]] back at public  discourse--"you  think you can  check  public  [[impressions]]  based  on  other's testimony,  etc.,  but  couldn't  you  hear  them wrong?"--and  so  forth.(10)  
 +
 
 +
The  [[Wittgensteinian]]  is then required to come back stressing the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] acceptability  of public  substantiation  and  so on, which anticipates  Tson Khapa's progression, to which we now return.
  
The  Wittgensteinian  is then required to come back stressing the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] acceptability  of public  substantiation  and  so on, which anticipates  Tson Khapa's progression, to which we now return.
 
  
  
 +
[[Tson  Khapa]]  elucidates  [[Candra's]]  assault  on a customary  private  [[syllogism]]  of [[Bhaavaviveka]]. 
  
Tson  Khapa  elucidates  Candra's  assault  on a customary  private  [[syllogism]]  of [[Bhaavaviveka]].  This passage  in the  [[Prasannapadaa]]  I, is considered  the locus classicus of the refutation of [[logical]] privacy. [[Bhaavaviveka]] is arguing against a /.../?  
+
This passage  in the  [[Prasannapadaa]]  I, is considered  the locus classicus of the refutation of [[logical]] privacy. [[Bhaavaviveka]] is arguing against a /.../?  
  
respective private  [[objects]], encountered  by each  in  a private [[perception]]  of  the  [[subject]]  of  the  [[syllogism]] ([[eye-consciousness,]] and so on), the  [[reason]]  employed  (its  [[existence]]), and the concomitance  [[perceived]]  in the  example, which  are named  in the  argument  and understood  by each  via each  object's  [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] (vyavahaarikasvalak.sa.na), which [[Bhaavaviveka]]    maintains    consistently    to    be indispensable  for  [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]  functionality.   
+
respective private  [[objects]], encountered  by each  in  a private [[perception]]  of  the  [[subject]]  of  the  [[syllogism]] ([[eye-consciousness,]] and so on), the  [[reason]]  employed  (its  [[existence]]), and the concomitance  [[perceived]]  in the  example, which  are named  in the  argument  and understood  by each  via each  object's  [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] ([[vyavahaarikasvalak.sa.na]]), which [[Bhaavaviveka]]    maintains    consistently    to    be indispensable  for  [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]  functionality.   
  
 
The Saa.mkhya himself  is much more grossly absolutistic, believing that inner  [[phenomena]]  such as [[eye-consciousness]]  are absolutely  [[existent]], self-produced, and  so on.   
 
The Saa.mkhya himself  is much more grossly absolutistic, believing that inner  [[phenomena]]  such as [[eye-consciousness]]  are absolutely  [[existent]], self-produced, and  so on.   
  
And this  is  why  [[Bhaavaviveka]]  [[feels]]  it  necessary  to qualify    his    argument,    adding    "absolutely" (paramaarthata.h) ,  which  [[Candra]]  seizes  upon  [[as evidence]]  of  his  {{Wiki|subtle}}  absolutization  of  the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]. [[Candra]] attacks as follows:   
+
And this  is  why  [[Bhaavaviveka]]  [[feels]]  it  necessary  to qualify    his    argument,    adding    "absolutely" ([[paramaarthata.h]]) ,  which  [[Candra]]  seizes  upon  [[as evidence]]  of  his  {{Wiki|subtle}}  absolutization  of  the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]. [[Candra]] attacks as follows:   
  
  
Line 428: Line 457:
 
Sensing  these difficulties, [[Bhavya]] sidesteps  the necessity  of the qualification "absolutely," and instead tries to show his argument's  [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]  viability, arguing  for the  accessibility  of  a  general  [[subject]]  of  the [[syllogism]],  mere  [[eye-consciousness,]]  and  so  on,  disregarding  all  qualifications.   
 
Sensing  these difficulties, [[Bhavya]] sidesteps  the necessity  of the qualification "absolutely," and instead tries to show his argument's  [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]]  viability, arguing  for the  accessibility  of  a  general  [[subject]]  of  the [[syllogism]],  mere  [[eye-consciousness,]]  and  so  on,  disregarding  all  qualifications.   
  
He  gives  the plausible  example  of  the  argument  between  the [[Buddhist]] [[Vaibhaa.sika]] and the [[Brahmanical]] Vai'se.sika about  the  {{Wiki|status}}  of [[sound]], which  proceeds  on the basis  of  the  general  [[subject]]  "mere  [[sound]]"  not qualified as either "etheric [[sound]]" (unacceptable  to [[Vaibhaa.sika]]) or "material  [[sound]]"  (unacceptable  to Vai'se.sika) .   
+
He  gives  the plausible  example  of  the  argument  between  the [[Buddhist]] [[Vaibhaa.sika]] and the [[Brahmanical]] [[Vai'se.sika]] about  the  {{Wiki|status}}  of [[sound]], which  proceeds  on the basis  of  the  general  [[subject]]  "mere  [[sound]]"  not qualified as either "etheric [[sound]]" (unacceptable  to [[Vaibhaa.sika]]) or "material  [[sound]]"  (unacceptable  to [[Vai'se.sika]]) .   
  
 
This,  [[Bhavya]]  argues,  evades  the thesis-fault  of  groundlessness,  restores  a  "bare datum" as the private [[object]], in [[principle]] accessible to both parties as basis of private [[syllogism]].
 
This,  [[Bhavya]]  argues,  evades  the thesis-fault  of  groundlessness,  restores  a  "bare datum" as the private [[object]], in [[principle]] accessible to both parties as basis of private [[syllogism]].
Line 436: Line 465:
 
This apparently reasonable tack proves calamitous for [[Bhavya]], as it enables [[Candra]] to expose his {{Wiki|subtle}} [[absolutism]], his commitment to a private [[object]] as the objectively  real  basis  of  [[perception]],  hence  of {{Wiki|justification}}, [[language]], even [[causality]].   
 
This apparently reasonable tack proves calamitous for [[Bhavya]], as it enables [[Candra]] to expose his {{Wiki|subtle}} [[absolutism]], his commitment to a private [[object]] as the objectively  real  basis  of  [[perception]],  hence  of {{Wiki|justification}}, [[language]], even [[causality]].   
  
Tson Khapa [[Wikipedia:paraphrase|paraphrases]] Candra's argument here: “It  is wrong  to posit  mere  [[eye]], etc., disregarding qualifications  in  {{Wiki|light}}  of two  [[realities]], as  the [[subject]] of the [[syllogism]]  proving the absence  of the self-production of [[eye]], etc.;  because, (according to your  [[own]] system), the validating  [[cognition]]  must be unmistaken  about the intrinsic [[reality]] of [[eye]], etc.; and because, as unmistaken [[cognition]] does not mistake intrinsic [[reality]], the [[object]] it encounters cannot be an erroneous  [[object]]  which falsely  appears  to have intrinsic  identifiability  when in fact it does  not (EE, p. 231 following P, pp. 8 ff).
+
[[Tson Khapa]] [[Wikipedia:paraphrase|paraphrases]] [[Candra's]] argument here: “It  is wrong  to posit  mere  [[eye]], etc., disregarding qualifications  in  {{Wiki|light}}  of two  [[realities]], as  the [[subject]] of the [[syllogism]]  proving the absence  of the self-production of [[eye]], etc.;   
 +
 
 +
because, (according to your  [[own]] system), the validating  [[cognition]]  must be unmistaken  about the intrinsic [[reality]] of [[eye]], etc.;  
 +
 
 +
and because, as unmistaken [[cognition]] does not mistake intrinsic [[reality]], the [[object]] it encounters cannot be an erroneous  [[object]]  which falsely  appears  to have intrinsic  identifiability  when in fact it does  not (EE, p. 231 following P, pp. 8 ff).
 +
 
  
  
 +
[[Candra]]  argues  that [[Bhavya]]  cannot  have a 'mere [[object]]', general  and unqualified, and  still  uphold his 'private system', since according  to that even a 'bare  datum'  can  only  [[exist]]  if encountered  by a validating [[cognition]] which must not mistake the object's intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]. 
  
[[Candra]]  argues  that [[Bhavya]]  cannot  have a 'mere [[object]]', general  and unqualified, and  still  uphold his 'private system', since according  to that even a 'bare  datum'  can  only  [[exist]]  if encountered  by a validating [[cognition]] which must not mistake the object's intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]].  Such a bare datum  thus must be absolutely  real, even to be there  for  an  [[absolutist]]    who  requires  its certification  by  a  private, unmistaken, validating [[cognition]].  
+
Such a bare datum  thus must be absolutely  real, even to be there  for  an  [[absolutist]]    who  requires  its certification  by  a  private, unmistaken, validating [[cognition]].  
  
Tson Khapa clarifies this point: “...  in  a  [[philosophical]]  system  that  claims  that whatever [[exists]], [[exists]] in its [[own]] right objectively,  a  ([[cognition]])  that  errs  in  its [[perception]]  of intrinsic  identifiability  cannot be established  as discovering its proper [[object]]. Any sort of validating [[cognition]], either  {{Wiki|conceptual}}  or [[nonconceptual]], must be unmistaken  about  the intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]  of its validated  [[object]]....   
+
[[Tson Khapa]] clarifies this point: “...  in  a  [[philosophical]]  system  that  claims  that whatever [[exists]], [[exists]] in its [[own]] right objectively,  a  ([[cognition]])  that  errs  in  its [[perception]]  of intrinsic  identifiability  cannot be established  as discovering its proper [[object]].  
 +
 
 +
Any sort of validating [[cognition]], either  {{Wiki|conceptual}}  or [[nonconceptual]], must be unmistaken  about  the intrinsic  [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]  of its validated  [[object]]....   
  
 
Thus, a  validating  [[cognition]] must derive  its validity  from an [[object]]  which, not being merely a conventiozal, nominal designation, has an  objectivity  or  intrinsic  [[reality]]  as its  [[own]] actual  [[condition]].  And this is just  what (Bhavya's)  [[own]] system claims (EE, p. 231, italics mine).
 
Thus, a  validating  [[cognition]] must derive  its validity  from an [[object]]  which, not being merely a conventiozal, nominal designation, has an  objectivity  or  intrinsic  [[reality]]  as its  [[own]] actual  [[condition]].  And this is just  what (Bhavya's)  [[own]] system claims (EE, p. 231, italics mine).
Line 448: Line 485:
 
The refutation  here comes down to the hyperbolic private  [[object]], just  as it does in the {{Wiki|modern}}  one.  How uncanny is the resonance of Saunder's and Henze's description  of  the  private  "experiential-datum" needed to anchor the term in private [[language]].
 
The refutation  here comes down to the hyperbolic private  [[object]], just  as it does in the {{Wiki|modern}}  one.  How uncanny is the resonance of Saunder's and Henze's description  of  the  private  "experiential-datum" needed to anchor the term in private [[language]].
  
  (A  private  [[language]]  is) A [[language]], each  [[word]]  of which refers to experiential  {{Wiki|data}}, although  each of these words is conceptually  {{Wiki|independent}}  of publicly observable  [[phenomena]].  (When  we  say  that  an experiential-datum  term,  "E,"  is  conceptually {{Wiki|independent}} of publicly observable [[phenomena]], we mean this: the [[existence]]  of an E neither  entails  nor is entailed by the [[existence]]  of any publicly observable [[phenomena]];  nor is it part of the meaning of "E" that publicly  observable  [[phenomena]]  provide {{Wiki|evidence}} for the [[existence]] of an E) (PLP, pp. 6-7).
+
  (A  private  [[language]]  is) A [[language]], each  [[word]]  of which refers to experiential  {{Wiki|data}}, although  each of these words is conceptually  {{Wiki|independent}}  of publicly observable  [[phenomena]].   
 +
 
 +
(When  we  say  that  an experiential-datum  term,  "E,"  is  conceptually {{Wiki|independent}} of publicly observable [[phenomena]], we mean this: the [[existence]]  of an E neither  entails  nor is entailed by the [[existence]]  of any publicly observable [[phenomena]];  nor is it part of the meaning of "E" that publicly  observable  [[phenomena]]  provide {{Wiki|evidence}} for the [[existence]] of an E) (PLP, pp. 6-7).
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
To recapitulate, [[Bhavya]] tries to reestablish  his private [[syllogism]]  by employing a mere, general (that is, publicly  observable  and ostensible) [[object]] as a basis of [[discussion]], thus tacitly  [[acknowledging]]  the publicness    of  [[objects]],  [[subjects]],  [[syllogisms]],  [[language]], and so forth, which he cannot rightly do in the framework  of his system, which posits intrinsic, not  [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], objectivity  to genuine  [[phenomena]] and hence cannot tolerate  their mere [[relativity]]  and superficiality.
 +
 
 +
And [[Candra]] holds him to his [[own]] basic outlook  without  letting  him  pay  lip  service  to conventionality,  saying,  as  it  were,  your  "bare datum" must be [[absolute]], intrinsically  identifiable, and hence privately cognizable  and substantiable, if only  for  you to {{Wiki|perceive}}  it at all, since  for you nothing can even [[exist]] unless it is thus established.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Candra]] then follows  this point with a refutation of  Bhavya's  example  itself,  pointing  out  its inapplicability.  [[Candra]] agrees that the [[Vaibhaa.sika]] and the [[Vai'se.sika]]  each can point  out a mere [[sound]] to argue about, since both tacitly  share  a [[sense]] of the {{Wiki|perceptual}}  objectivity, the private  "givenness" of the [[object]], its "thereness," as it were. 
  
 +
However, as [[Tson Khapa]] [[Wikipedia:paraphrase|paraphrases]]: “... the case is different  when  the advocate  of the [[emptiness]] of intrinsic [[reality]] proves to the advocate of nonemptiness  of intrinsic  [[reality]] that [[eye]], etc.  are  not self-produced.  For not only  can  they  not discover  any  [[objective]]  [[existence]]  or  even  any [[objective]]  [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]], but also they  can not point out to each  other  "such  a thing  a 'this'  we both encounter  as the [[actual thing]] to use as [[subject]]  of our argument (EE, p. 236).
  
  
To recapitulate, [[Bhavya]] tries to reestablish  his private [[syllogism]]  by employing a mere, general (that is, publicly  observable  and ostensible) [[object]] as a basis of [[discussion]], thus tacitly  [[acknowledging]]  the publicness    of  [[objects]],  [[subjects]],  [[syllogisms]],  [[language]], and so forth, which he cannot rightly do in the framework  of his system, which posits intrinsic, not  [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]], objectivity  to genuine  [[phenomena]] and hence cannot tolerate  their mere [[relativity]]  and superficiality. And [[Candra]] holds him to his [[own]] basic outlook  without  letting  him  pay  lip  service  to conventionality,  saying,  as  it  were,  your  "bare datum" must be [[absolute]], intrinsically  identifiable, and hence privately cognizable  and substantiable, if only  for  you to {{Wiki|perceive}}  it at all, since  for you nothing can even [[exist]] unless it is thus established.
 
  
 +
This is perhaps  the most {{Wiki|subtle}}  point to [[grasp]], either in the Wittgensteinian  or in the [[Praasa^ngika]] context, because of our innate {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[absolutism]], reinforced  by  {{Wiki|culture}}  through  [[language]],  but  the [[attainment]]  of  the  accomplished  nonegocentrist [[philosopher]]  comes down even to this. 
  
 +
In looking for an [[object]]  to use as the [[subject]]  of a [[syllogism]], the nonegocentrist  (that  is,  advocate  of  [[emptiness]]) cannot find anything whatsoever, when he looks with a  truthdeterminant analysis at [[objects]] supposed to have a  cognitively  [[objective]]  {{Wiki|status}}  according  to  the egocentrist  (nonemptiness  advocate) . 
  
[[Candra]] then follows this point with a refutation of Bhavya's   example   itself, pointing  out its inapplicability. [[Candra]] agrees that the [[Vaibhaa.sika]] and the Vai'se.sika each can point  out a mere [[sound]] to argue about, since both tacitly share a [[sense]] of the {{Wiki|perceptual}} objectivity, the private "givenness" of the [[object]], its "thereness," as it were.
+
Of  course, {{Wiki|conventionally}}  all sorts of unanalyzed  [[objects]]  are right  there without   having   to  be looked for, [[relative]],    designatively    dependent,    publicly observable  and  so forth, easily accessible to the nonanalytic  [[attitude]]   of  everyday [[consciousness]].  
  
However, as Tson Khapa [[Wikipedia:paraphrase|paraphrases]]: “... the case is different when  the advocate  of the [[emptiness]] of intrinsic [[reality]] proves to the advocate of nonemptiness  of intrinsic [[reality]] that [[eye]], etc. are not self-produced. For not only  can  they  not discover  any [[objective]]   [[existence]]   or  even any [[objective]] [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]], but also they can not point out to each other "such a thing a 'this' we both encounter as the [[actual thing]] to use as [[subject]] of our argument (EE, p. 236).
+
However,  when   he adopts  the   [[attitude]]   called "[[philosophical]]  [[cognition]] analytic of ultimacy" ([[don dam  dpyod  pai  rigs  'ses]]) which he does when advocating [[emptiness]] to the [[absolutist]] in the attempt to cure his absolutistic {{Wiki|illness}}, he cannot find any single thing that is intrinsically identifiable, privately cognizable, or ostensively definable or even accessible.  
  
 +
Under this analysis, both public and private  disappear, as they can only [[exist]]  in mutual [[dependence]]. 
  
 +
Only  such  an  [[appreciation]]  of  the transformative power of analytic [[vision]] can ever make clear  the  otherwise    cryptic    statement    of {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}, the remarkable PI 398:
  
This is perhaps  the most {{Wiki|subtle}}  point to [[grasp]], either in the Wittgensteinian  or in the Praasa^ngika context, because of our innate {{Wiki|perceptual}} [[absolutism]], reinforced  by  {{Wiki|culture}}  through [[language]],  but the [[attainment]]  of  the  accomplished  nonegocentrist [[philosopher]] comes down even to this.   
+
"But when I [[imagine]] something, or even actually see [[objects]], I have got something which my neighbor has not!"--l understand you.   
  
In looking for an [[object]]  to use as the [[subject]] of a [[syllogism]], the nonegocentrist  (that is,  advocate  of  [[emptiness]]) cannot find anything whatsoever, when he looks with a  truthdeterminant analysis at [[objects]] supposed to have a  cognitively  [[objective]]  {{Wiki|status}}  according  to  the egocentrist  (nonemptiness  advocate) .  Of  course, {{Wiki|conventionally}}  all sorts of unanalyzed  [[objects]] are right  there  without  having  to  be  looked  for,  [[relative]],    designatively    dependent,    publicly observable  and  so forth, easily  accessible  to the nonanalytic  [[attitude]]  of  everyday  [[consciousness]].
+
You want to look about you and say: "at any rate, only I have  got THIS!" What are these words for?
  
However, when  he  adopts  the  [[attitude]]  called "[[philosophical]]  [[cognition]]  analytic of ultimacy" ([[don dam]]  dpyod  pai  [[rigs]]  'ses) , which  he  does  when advocating [[emptiness]] to the [[absolutist]] in the attempt to cure his absolutistic  {{Wiki|illness}}, he cannot find any single  thing  that  is  intrinsically  identifiable, privately  cognizable, or  ostensively  definable  or even accessible. Under this analysis, both public and private  disappear, as they can only [[exist]]  in mutual [[dependence]].  Only  such  an [[appreciation]]  of  the transformative power of analytic [[vision]] can ever make clear  the  otherwise    cryptic    statement    of {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}, the remarkable PI 398: "But when I [[imagine]]  something, or even actually  see [[objects]], I have got something which my neighbor has not!"--l understand you.  
+
They serve no purpose.--Can one not add: "there is here no question of a '[[seeing]]' and therefore none of a 'having'--nor of a [[subject]], nor therefore of 'I' either?" Might  I not ask: in what [[sense]]  have you got what you are talking about and saying that only you have got it? Do you possess  it?  
  
You want to look about you and  say: "at any rate, only  I have  got THIS!" What are these words for? They serve no purpose.--Can  one not add: "there is here no question of a '[[seeing]]' and therefore  none of a 'having'--nor  of a [[subject]], nor therefore  of 'I'  either?" Might  I not ask: in what [[sense]]  have you got what  you are talking  about  and saying that only you have got it? Do you possess  it?  You DO NOT EVEN  SEE IT! And this too is clear: If as a {{Wiki|matter}} of [[logic]] you exclude  other people's  having something, it loses  its [[sense]]  to say that  you have it. (Double underscore added.)
+
You DO NOT EVEN  SEE IT! And this too is clear: If as a {{Wiki|matter}} of [[logic]] you exclude  other people's  having something, it loses  its [[sense]]  to say that  you have it. (Double underscore added.)
  
Here  again  we find {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  levelling  the clincher at his opponent, preceding what Saunders and Henze call the "ascription argument" and attribute to Strawson,  namely,  that  no  "private"  [[object]], [[perception]], or [[language]]  can [[exist]] without the public notion  of "[[person]]," which thus vitiates  the [[logical]] privacy  of them; as they put it, "the  traditionist  (just like [[Svaatantrika]]) cannot treat the notions  of  'I'  and 'my [[experience]]'  as [[logically]]  primitive  to with  [[respect]]  to  the  notions  of  'he'  and  'his [[experience]]'  because  one who  does  not possess  the [[latter]] notions  lacks the former notions as well"(11) (parentheses  added).  
+
Here  again  we find {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  levelling  the clincher at his opponent, preceding what Saunders and Henze call the "ascription argument" and attribute to Strawson,  namely,  that  no  "private"  [[object]], [[perception]], or [[language]]  can [[exist]] without the public notion  of "[[person]]," which thus vitiates  the [[logical]] privacy  of them;   
  
 +
as they put it, "the  traditionist  (just like [[Svaatantrika]]) cannot treat the notions  of  'I'  and 'my [[experience]]'  as [[logically]]  primitive  to with  [[respect]]  to  the  notions  of  'he'  and  'his [[experience]]'  because  one who  does  not possess  the [[latter]] notions  lacks the former notions as well"(11) (parentheses  added). 
  
This  argument  topples  the traditionist's  adherence  to the  private  [[language]],  enables  {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  to exclaim  to his  [[absolutist]] interlocutor  "You do not even see it!" (PI 398), and enables  [[Candra]]  to demolish  Bhavya's  [[sense]]  of the plausibility  even of his example, as the two parties in the supposed  private argument  cannot find either any    [[objective]]    [[existence]]    or  any  [[objective]] [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]]! Thus  all  three  end  up on  the  same point, from  which  proceeds  the [[Wikipedia:scientific method|methodology]]  of the nonegocentrist.   
+
 
 +
This  argument  topples  the traditionist's  adherence  to the  private  [[language]],  enables  {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  to exclaim  to his  [[absolutist]] interlocutor  "You do not even see it!" (PI 398), and enables  [[Candra]]  to demolish  [[Bhavya's]] [[sense]]  of the plausibility  even of his example, as the two parties in the supposed  private argument  cannot find either any    [[objective]]    [[existence]]    or  any  [[objective]] [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]]!  
 +
 
 +
Thus  all  three  end  up on  the  same point, from  which  proceeds  the [[Wikipedia:scientific method|methodology]]  of the nonegocentrist.   
  
 
He does  not try  to employ  private [[syllogisms]], [[reasons]], and so forth, since antagonist and {{Wiki|protagonist}} are so far apart there is no ground of [[discussion]] established in any  satistactory  manner, but rather  makes  his [[own]] analytic,  critical  [[attitude]]  available  to  his antagonist dialectically, leading him through [[logical]] ramifications of his position that end up with absurd {{Wiki|consequences}}.  The antagonist thus is able to see the awkwardness  of his original position  and gracefully abandon it.
 
He does  not try  to employ  private [[syllogisms]], [[reasons]], and so forth, since antagonist and {{Wiki|protagonist}} are so far apart there is no ground of [[discussion]] established in any  satistactory  manner, but rather  makes  his [[own]] analytic,  critical  [[attitude]]  available  to  his antagonist dialectically, leading him through [[logical]] ramifications of his position that end up with absurd {{Wiki|consequences}}.  The antagonist thus is able to see the awkwardness  of his original position  and gracefully abandon it.
Line 485: Line 542:
 
It  means  that  [[philosophy]]  today  is  {{Wiki|crippled}}  by prejudices  of a very nonphilosophical  sort--racial,  {{Wiki|cultural}}, and historical. It means that our ingrained [[sense]]  of  the  "progress"  of  [[knowledge]]  is  highly suspect, not because  of some {{Wiki|sentimental}}  appeal  to some [[imagined]] primitive  stage of [[nature]], but because even rigorous technical matters were as well and even better  explored  in  [[ancient]]  times  by  [[people]]  in supposed  "non-technological''  cultures  and  times.   
 
It  means  that  [[philosophy]]  today  is  {{Wiki|crippled}}  by prejudices  of a very nonphilosophical  sort--racial,  {{Wiki|cultural}}, and historical. It means that our ingrained [[sense]]  of  the  "progress"  of  [[knowledge]]  is  highly suspect, not because  of some {{Wiki|sentimental}}  appeal  to some [[imagined]] primitive  stage of [[nature]], but because even rigorous technical matters were as well and even better  explored  in  [[ancient]]  times  by  [[people]]  in supposed  "non-technological''  cultures  and  times.   
  
After  all, we  greatly  [[respect]]  {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  as  a shining [[star]] in the {{Wiki|firmament}}  of [[philosophy]], even if some  of his  twinklings  elude  us, and many  of the finest  [[philosophical]]  [[minds]]  today  follow  him indirectly  if not directly  in many aspects of their [[thinking]].  If the type of critical [[vision]] he achieved and  cultivated  on  his  [[own]]  was  highly  developed systematically  already  in  a great  [[tradition]]  with thousands  of members in the most populous nations of [[earth]], (not that very many perhaps  ever reached  the greatest  heights  or depths), then  there  must have been a rather  bountiful  crop of unsung, unpublished [[Wittgensteins]]  over the twenty centuries during which [[Indian]],  [[Tibetan]],  {{Wiki|Chinese}}, [[Japanese]],  and  {{Wiki|Mongolian}} [[scholars]]  pursued  the [[goddess of wisdom]], (the [[Sophia]] of  [[philosophy]]  as  [[Prajnaparamita]],  "[[Transcendent Wisdom]]") whose [[attainment]] was defined as the [[ultimate liberation]] from the "fly-bottle" of [[perplexity]].  Such being  the case, or even the possibility, it behooves us not to rest content  with our one [[river]] of [[Western]] [[tradition]], but to explore and reveal to our young the great  ocean of [[world]] [[philosophy]].   
+
After  all, we  greatly  [[respect]]  {{Wiki|Wittgenstein}}  as  a shining [[star]] in the {{Wiki|firmament}}  of [[philosophy]], even if some  of his  twinklings  elude  us, and many  of the finest  [[philosophical]]  [[minds]]  today  follow  him indirectly  if not directly  in many aspects of their [[thinking]].   
 +
 
 +
If the type of critical [[vision]] he achieved and  cultivated  on  his  [[own]]  was  highly  developed systematically  already  in  a great  [[tradition]]  with thousands  of members in the most populous nations of [[earth]], (not that very many perhaps  ever reached  the greatest  heights  or depths), then  there  must have been a rather  bountiful  crop of unsung, unpublished [[Wittgensteins]]  over the twenty centuries during which [[Indian]],   
 +
 
 +
[[Tibetan]],  {{Wiki|Chinese}}, [[Japanese]],  and  {{Wiki|Mongolian}} [[scholars]]  pursued  the [[goddess of wisdom]], (the [[Sophia]] of  [[philosophy]]  as  [[Prajnaparamita]],   
 +
 
 +
"[[Transcendent Wisdom]]") whose [[attainment]] was defined as the [[ultimate liberation]] from the "fly-bottle" of [[perplexity]].   
 +
 
 +
Such being  the case, or even the possibility, it behooves us not to rest content  with our one [[river]] of [[Western]] [[tradition]], but to explore and reveal to our young the great  ocean of [[world]] [[philosophy]].   
  
 
It is all ours, we are all [[human beings]], and  the  [[Indian]]  or {{Wiki|Chinese}}  heritage belongs  as  much  to  us as to the  {{Wiki|Chinese}}  or  the {{Wiki|Indians}}. Especially the [[philosophical]] heritage of the nonegocentrist, critical  [[tradition]]  which  was  born  from  [[liberation]]  from {{Wiki|cultural}}  {{Wiki|conditioning}}  at the deepest  levels, {{Wiki|perceptual}}  and  {{Wiki|ideological}},  never belonged  to  any  race, {{Wiki|culture}}, or even  {{Wiki|linguistic}} [[tradition]], but always  to those  members  of whatever such  [[tradition]]  who  dare  to  question  what  seems [[self-evident]]    right    before    them,  what    is authoritatively  told to them, what  seems  safe  and natural  to them--those whose sensibilities  demand the surpassing  [[peace]] that comes with the eradication of [[perplexity]].
 
It is all ours, we are all [[human beings]], and  the  [[Indian]]  or {{Wiki|Chinese}}  heritage belongs  as  much  to  us as to the  {{Wiki|Chinese}}  or  the {{Wiki|Indians}}. Especially the [[philosophical]] heritage of the nonegocentrist, critical  [[tradition]]  which  was  born  from  [[liberation]]  from {{Wiki|cultural}}  {{Wiki|conditioning}}  at the deepest  levels, {{Wiki|perceptual}}  and  {{Wiki|ideological}},  never belonged  to  any  race, {{Wiki|culture}}, or even  {{Wiki|linguistic}} [[tradition]], but always  to those  members  of whatever such  [[tradition]]  who  dare  to  question  what  seems [[self-evident]]    right    before    them,  what    is authoritatively  told to them, what  seems  safe  and natural  to them--those whose sensibilities  demand the surpassing  [[peace]] that comes with the eradication of [[perplexity]].
Line 498: Line 563:
 
11. PLP, p. 139. 6
 
11. PLP, p. 139. 6
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
 +
{{E}}
 +
[[Category:Buddhist Philosophy]]

Revision as of 09:24, 21 February 2015

Nguoi-tu-Phat.jpg
Imacjfgjges.jpg
07Buddha-3D.jpg
BfguOWf.jpg
Bhhge.jpg
Guru rinpoche zangdokpelri.jpg
22a59f.jpg
127gjh3.jpg
0-12-2-18-352.jpg
Kuh0187.JPG
Edu4.jpg
Db67d z.jpg
4qOL6E1qi.jpg
Kri0021.JPG
Bbbbnkd.jpg
Linefha 250.jpg
Japvbdha.jpg
Guru-Detailid.jpg
Japan-monk.jpg
Mindewtyy.jpg
Sherabch.jpg
Uy086 n.jpg
2709589.jpg
Incustoms.jpg
Rainbow guru.jpg
Gur7ad.JPG
1447mj.jpg
26bn0.jpg
Olmo Ling.jpg
Mahakala1.jpg
4mh.jpg
Tantra pose.jpg
Amida Nyorai.jpg
Ekesamonks.jpg
1bnmhj3 n.jpg
11cv13 n.jpg
Supe 6gsx3c.jpg
64a8bf8.jpg
5633tyutu.jpg
327 edium.jpg

    Philosophical nonegocentrism in Wittgenstein and Candrakirti
in their treatment of the private language problem
By R. A. F. Thurman
Philosophy East and West
30:3, 1980.07
p. 321-337

recension by Bence Tarr

R. A. F. Thurman is Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy and Religion, Amherst College, Amherst, Massachusetts.

Foreword

The reason behind choosing this article for recension, out of the many that I’ve read on Wittgenstein’s philosophy in the last few years, is that it follows a new trend among western philosophers, which I find feasible in treating philosophical problems.

The basic attitude behind this trend is clearly marked in Thurman’s introduction to his writing:

“In their book The Private Language Problem, Saunders and Henze state that ‘it is primarily in the twentieth century that questions regarding the nature and possibility of a private language have received specific formulation and specific attention.’

This statement is only true if the qualification "in the West" is added, since the Buddhist tradition of critical philosophy was implicity concerned with this question in a central way for over two thousand years, and explicitly since the time of Candrakirti (sixth century).

Philosophers should no longer allow themselves to remain ignorant of the planetary nature of philosophy, in spite of the ingrained presuppositions of the superiority of the West and of modernity which make the contribution of the East so startling.” (p.1)

Treating philosophical problems in this manner, clearly has the advantage of presenting ‘the problem’ itself, rather than the way it has appeared in some kind of philosophical text.

Besides this, it enables us to throw some light on our preconceptions that we all have, when we come in contact with ‘the eastern’ thought. Looking back on my personal attitude towards the east, I have to say that I have fully lost all of my negative feelings towards the ‘eastern’ way of thinking.

I also have lost my over-optimistic positive feelings about it. I have to say that by having studied western and eastern philosophy for several years by now, I have become neutral in treating both, and share Thurman’s point of view by saying that philosophy has a plantary nature and philosophers (not religious thinkers) think in the same way on all sides of the globe.

What I mean by this is that ‘thinking’ has the same qualities in every culture, and it follows universal logical rules that provide a cultural-free basis for all reasoning.

Therefore no philosophical investigation is ‘eastern’ or ‘western’ unless we use these terms to clarify the geographical origin of the treated problem.


I can’t say that Thurman’s article has amused me; I seem to lack the abilities to grasp what his lines of thought are at some points.

Despite this I have found the article interesting because of it’s way of dealing with the problem of private language in the first place, rather than Wittgenstein only.


I have chosen to write this recension in English, since the original text is in English, and the quotations are given in English too.

(And it gives me a chance to practice my English more than trying to teach present perfect almost thirty hours a week.)

In his essay, Thurman intends to establish the nearly total similarity between Wittgenstein as mature critical philosopher and the Prasangika-madhyamika philosophers ranging from Candrakirti (India, sixth to seventh centuries) to Tson Khapa (Tibet, 1357-1420) in their treatment of the philosophical questions related to the ‘private language problem’.

He starts to introduce the topic by quoting Saunders and Henze, who convey the general philosophical relevance of the question in the following passage:

“The series of problems (i.e. physical world, perception, self, etc. relating to PL question)... may be said to constitute the egocentric predicament: the predicament of one who begins "from his own case" and attempts to analyze and justify his system of beliefs and attitudes.... This is the predicament of "how to get out," how to move justifiably from one's own experiential data to the existence of an external world....

If the egocentric predicament be taken as a legitimate problem, then the response to this problem will constitute one or another of the strands composing what we have called the egocentric outlook. This is the outlook of one who begins at home, with the private object (with his own private experiential data), and attempts, in one way or another, to "go abroad."...



If on the other hand, the egocentric predicament be viewed as an illegitimate problem, a pseudo problem, then the response to this "problem" will be to repudiate the egocentric viewpoint.

This is the response of one who "begins abroad," who begins in the public rather than in the private domain, and attempts in one way or another to understand both of these domains. ” Thurman believes that the terms used frequently by Saunders and Henze, “philosophical egocentrist” and “philosophical nonegocentrist” are precisely adequate to translate the Sanskrit átmavádin (literally, “self-advocate”) and anátmavádin (literally, “selflessness advocate”), and this most central Indian philosophical dichotomy persists onto the subtlest levels in a long debate over presence or absence of svabháva (“intrinsic reality”), svalaksana (“intrinsic identity”) and finally svátantrya (“logical privacy”) .

He also believes that once we notice this obvious parallel, we naturally become interested in the arguments used by both sides, considering the longevity of the issue in India and Tibet, and its relative newness in the West.

One major obstacle to appreciation of the richness of the Buddhist nonegocentrist tradition by modern philosophers, who would therein find so much of interest and use, is the unwarranted prejudice that Buddhist thought is “mysticism”, that is, anti-philosophical or a-philosophical.



This prejudice has only been intensified by those contemporary ‘mystics’ who have pointed to the young Wittgenstein's famous statement about silence in the Tractatus as evidence of his similarity to the imaginedsilent sages of the East.’

Thurman also warnes us about this and also argues that in actuality, the vast majority of ‘mystics’, or nonrationalists, both Eastern and Western, have usually belonged to the egocentrist camp, at least tacitly if not formally.

“Recourse to mysticism is a typical aspect of being stuck in the egocentric predicament.

The mature Wittgenstein clearly exposes the tremendous amount of mysticism involved in the uncritical use of ordinary language, especially by the egocentrist philosophers.

He humorously points to our predilection to reify things by constructing realities out of concepts, substances out of substantives, revealing the common notion of "naming as, so to speak, an occult process... and... when the philosopher tries to bring out the relation between name and thing by staring at an object in front of him and repeating a name or even the word 'this'....

And here we may fancy naming to be some remarkable act of mind, as it were a baptism of an object..." (PI 143).(4) An egocentrist philosopher, when yet unwilling to surrender the notion as a mere mental construction, quite typically resorts to 'ineffability', 'inexpressibility', and so forth, making a virtue of his inability to find either a nonentity or its absence.” (p.2)

On the other hand, the mainstream Buddhist philosophers were typically nonegocentrist and critical, not mystical, in approach. The famous doctrine of ‘two realities’ (satyadvaya) , the absolute (paramártha) and the contingent (samvrti) or conventional (vyavahara), is not at all mystical but is rather an effective technical device for analyzing apart the “queer”, “occult”, “mysterious”, hence absolutistic element, to clear up the realm of experience, causality, and action.

The doctrine properly puts the ‘absolute’ in its place as a conceptual limiting case, which frees the conventional world, the space of living from absolutism and its problems.

The fundamental insight that Thurman also quotes is that: “egocentrist absolutisms, ranging from the unconscious and perceptual to the theoretical and ideological, all categorized under the rubric "mis-knowledge" (avidya) , cause all evils and problems.

Thus, in the Buddhist tradition, philosophical analysis was seen as the way to treat the prevalent forms of 'misknowledge' by applying criticism to the conceptual knots of the day.” (p.2)

The level of sophistication of the application varied according to the sophistication of the ‘philosophical knots’, resulting in a critical metaphysics (Vaibhasika) as treatment of native realism (Vaisesika), a critical nominalism (Sautrantika), a critical idealism (Vijnánaváda), and finally the critical relativism of the Mádhyamikas.

The high point in this philosophical refinement process was reached in the sixth century by Candrakirti, who entered into the refutation of logical privacy.

This refutation, as preserved in Candrakirti’s Prasannapáda, Chapter I, served as the basis of a philosophical discussion that went on for three more centuries in India.

It then came down to the present day preserved in lively traditions of the Tibetan philosophical training colleges. Perhaps the greatest master of this subject in Tibet was Tson Khapa Blo Bzan Grags-pa (1357-1420), whose texture of thought and analysis can probably be treated best to that of Wittgenstein and his followers.



Thurman’s major opinion about Wittgenstein, is that one of the most remarkable things about him is that he had great courage, and ability to make a radical change in his thinking and publicly repudiate his earlier statements.

Thurman quotes Wittgenstein: “In PI 46-47 , he mentions his earlier attempt to find an absolutistic peg in reality on which to hang language through meaning, and he then repudiates it:

"What lies behind the idea that names really signify simples?--... (then quoting Plato) "what exists in its own right has to be... named without any other determination... its name is all it has."...

Both Russell's 'individuals' and my 'objects' (Tractatus...) were such primary elements.... (However).... it makes no sense at all to speak absolutely of the simple parts of a chair'.” (p.3)


Thurman draws a parallel with Tson Khapa: “Thson Khapa also describes the 'habitual mode of intellectual presumption' ('[[sgro'dogs kun btags kyi 'dzin tshul) in parallel terms, calling that 'essence' in things that anchors their names "intrinsic identity" (svalaksana), indispensable for the egocentrist, impossible for the nonegocentrist” (p.3.), quoting one of his works:


“What sort of mental habit holds things to be intrinsically identifiable?.... the Philosophers... investigate the meaning of the conventional expression "person" in such cases as this "this person performed this action and experienced this result," by such analysis as "is the 'person' the very same thing as 'his' aggregates?

Or is 'he' something different from them?" When they discover whichever possibility, sameness or difference, to be the case, it gives them a basis for establishing that 'person', and they are then able to establish his accumulation of action, etc.

If they do not find any such basis, they are unable to establish anything at all, and hence they cannot rest content with the simple use of the expression 'person'.”


Thurman believes that Tson Khapa was able to return to the surface of the question with the nonegocentrists view by appreciating the conventionality of the expression, content with that.

Further, he was able to isolate the mental habit that had caused him the whole problem, revealing the egocentrist's dependence on the ‘private object’, internally designated via the ‘private language’.

Tson Khapa mentions the ‘private language’ explicitly in a language in which a person could write down or give vocal expression to his inner experiences - his feelings, moods, and the rest - for his private use. The individual words of this language are to refer to what can only be known to the person speaking; to his immediate private sensations. So another person cannot understand the language.



It is clear he does not mean simply the private use of language, the internal enunciation of the usual public means of communication. Rather he means to imagine a logically private language, a language in principle unique to the individual who invents and employs it, in Buddhist terms, an absolutely private not relatively private language.



Thurman thinks that Wittgenstein has also arrived at the thought of an absolute private language: “But why does Wittgenstein bother to imagine such a thing? He does so as that is the best way to make explicit the unconscious assumptions of 'reality', 'massiveness', 'ab soluteness', 'facticity', 'objectivity', and so forth, that we habitually impose upon our perceptions.

Thus, logical privacy is the natural absurd consequence forced upon the philosophical egocentrist, as he tries to give an account of his absolute 'given', 'simple', 'first', 'individual', 'essence', 'self', and so on, that is, element constitutive of reality, self-evident, irreducible, and indispensable to the coherence of his world.

The egocentrist is indeed so strongly attached to his groundedness on this supposed solid basis, he perceives any challenge as mere nihilistic skepticism.

Thus he is best approached by the nonegocentrist, (for whom the very nonsolidity of things itself is their actual workability) , critically, by demonstration of the absurdity of his absolutism via either such as Wittgenstein's hyperbolic imaginings of private language...” (p.3)



Since the question is now seen to lie at the core of a fundamental polarity in philosophy, before tackling the actual refutations of privacy, ancient and modern, Thurman gives a partial typology of philosophical egocentrism and nonegocentrism.

This typology is the following: The outlook of philosophical egocentrism is characterized by an avid grasp of the ‘given’, a sort of ‘private object’, self-evident and indubitable, the substance of all order, whether it be used to justify materialism, skeptical nihilism, phenomenalism, positivism, idealism, or any other form of ancient or modern absolutism.

The egocentrist does employ critical methods in dealing with predecessors and adversaries, but once he feels he has found the ‘essence’, he proceeds constructively, systematizing reality dogmatically according to discovered ‘laws’, ‘principles’, and so forth.



This essence then becomes the foundation of practical life in social reality, and any relativistic account of language, meaning, morals, and so on, is dismissed as anarchistic and nihilistic. He is absolutistic even in empirical matters.

Finally, he considers philosophy a constructive activity, an elaboration of formal structures of truth, beauty, and goodness.

Hence his contribution is always dated, useful in the period as a temple and perhaps later as a museum, an edifice that stands quite apart from the person himself.
 


In contrast, the nonegocentrist outlook is essentially critical of all givens, not by taking as given the essential unreliability of everything as does the absolutistic skeptic, but by never being satisfied with any supposedly analysisproof element, and by sustaining the critical process itself as a valid mode of thought, tolerant of less than absolute security.

“The nonegocentrist's attitude toward the empirical is thoroughly relativistic and conventionalistic.

Having found that life goes on even without any irreducible element, he works flexibly with what there is consensually established and yet does not abdicate the task of refining the consensus.

He considers philosophy itself a therapeutic process rather than a constructive metascience.



Instead of building up grand solutions, he dissolves problems critically, finding the inconsistencies in the terms of the question. He perceives perplexity, 'misknowledge', a disease, and the clarity and insight afforded by critical analysis a cure.

His philosophy tends to be less dated, less systematic, and more informal than the egocentrist's, since his refinement of thought, intensity of insight, and attention to self-transformation render philosophizing more accessible to perplexed thinkers of later eras.” (p.4)
 


How do Wittgenstein and the Buddhist nonegocentrists fit into this typology?

It will readily be granted that the mature Wittgenstein was primarily critical in approach, and the Buddhists were well known for their critical attitude toward the ‘given’ as naively accepted in their host cultures.

Vipasyana, or ‘transcendental analysis’ is the main type of Maháyána meditation. Prajná, the highest wisdom, is glossed as dharmapravicaya, literally, the ‘analysis of things’, and it is symbolized as a sword that cuts through the knot of perplexity.



Thurman thinks that the most striking of all is the similarity of the actual texture of critical analysis of the two nonegocentrists.

First he quotes Wittgenstein’s famous passage from the Philosophical Investigations:
“Again, does my visual image of this tree, of this chair, consist of parts? And what are its simple component parts?



Multi-colouredness is one kind of complexity; another is, for example, that of a broken outline composed of straight bits. And a curve can be said to be composed of an ascending and a descending segment....

But isn't a chessboard for instance, obviously and absolutely composite?--You are probably thinking of the composition out of thirty-two White and thirty-two black squares.

But could we not say, for instance, that it was composed of the colours black and white and the schema of the squares?

And if there are quite different ways of looking at it, do you still want to say that the chessboard is absolutely composite?.... (Is the colour of a square on a chessboard simple, or does it consist of pure white and pure yellow?

And is white simple, or does it consist of the colours of the rainbow?--)”


Then he states that Wittgenstein applies the same type of analysis to his feelings as to objects, as in PI 642, which proves that the wordself’ (so far as it means something like ‘person’, ‘human being’, ‘he himself’, ‘I myself’), is not an analysis of any such thing, but the state of a philosopher's attention when he says the wordself’ to himself and tries to analyze its meaning.
 


Examples from the Buddhist philosophical literature could be plenty, but Thurman finds Tson Khapa's description of the critical techniques of his predecessors particularly striking, from EE , p. 161: “.. the absolute status of anything is refuted by showing first of all, in the face of no matter what assertion of Buddhist or non-Buddhist scholar, the impossibility of an indivisible, a thing without a plurality of parts such as periods of time, parts of physical objects, or aspects of cognitive objects, and then by demonstrating that, whereas conventional objects may exist as unitary things while established as composed of parts, as far as absolute status is concerned, there are inevitable inconsistencies; for example, if part and whole are absolutely different, there can be no connection between them, and if part and whole are absolutely the same, then the whole becomes a plurality....



To give the actual line of argument... "to refute absolute production of one thing from another, the cause is first restricted to being permanent or impermanent, and production from a permanent thing is rejected. Then, production from an impermanent thing is restricted to being either sequential or simultaneous, and production from a simultaneous cause is rejected.



Then, a sequential cause is restricted to being either destroyed or undestroyed, and production from a destroyed cause is rejected.

Then production from a previously undestroyed cause is restricted to being either obstructed or unobstructed, and production from an obstructed cause is rejected."

The refutation thus far is rather easy. "Then, production from an unobstructed cause is restricted to being either wholly unobstructed or partiaily unobstructed; then, in the former case, an atom and (its aggregative effects such as) a molecule must be confused as a single object, (the causal atoms) being wholly unobstructed; or else, in the latter case, as (the cause, the indivisible, etc.) would have parts, production would be relative (sa.mv.rti) (and not absolute).”



Here the opponent, as the interlocutor in the PI passage, is a philosophical absolutist, a substantivist, who is “bewitched by language” into perceiving things to be absolutely true, “really real” before him, and the Wittgensteinian and Madhyamika nonegocentrist critical analyses intend to force him to look deeper into things and processes by examining his account of them to actually try to find the essence assumed to correspond to the name, the ‘metaphysical entity’, the ‘simple’, the ‘indivisible’.

The absolutist’s failure to find any such analysis-resistant essence is the first step on the road to liberation of his intelligence from the spell of language.
 
Thurman picks up the line of thought from here: “Relativism or conventionalism about the empirical, which includes language primarily, is a central component of the nonegocentrist outlook, the key to the nonegocentrist's avoidance of nihilistic skepticism and mysticism.



The egocentrist tends to engage in one or the other of these alternatives when his critical analysis goes further than usual, and he sees through his previously accepted 'givens', such as 'self', 'matter', 'object', or 'sense-contents', and so on, and he feels his universe crumble.

And even if he never reaches such a frontier, he perceives the nonegocentrist as courting chaos and typically accuses him of nihilism.

Wittgenstein responds to the charge, in PI 304: “ Not at all. It is not a something, but not a nothing either! The conclusion was only that a nothing would serve just as well as a something about which nothing could be said. We have only rejected the grammar which tries to force itself on us here.

The paradox disappears only if we make a radical break with the idea that language always functions in one way....

He goes still further in response to another challenge, in PI 118: “Where does our investigation get its importance from, since it seems only to destroy everything interesting, that is, all that is great and important? (As it were all the buildings, leaving behind only bits of stone and rubble.) What we are destroying is nothing but houses of cards and we are clearing up the ground of language on which they stand.” (p.4)


 
Thus it is precisely the reaffirmation of language, free of any supposed absolute substratum, as a practical, conventional process, an ordinary activity of human beings, a "form of life, " (Lebensform) that sets the nonegocentrist analytic philosopher apart from the skeptic and the mystic, who makes the classic absolutist mistake of thinking that lack of an absolute basis is no basis at all, lack of an absolute process is no process at all, lack of an absolutistic, privately grounded language is no language at all,

lack of a mathematically absolute, perfect logic is no logic at all, and so on. Wittgenstein is most explicit about the sheer conventionality of language, as in the following group of statements: “


(About) the 'language of our perceptions',... this language, like any other, is founded on convention. (PI 355)...

One objects: "So you are saying that human agreement decides what is true and what is false?"--lt is what human beings say that is true and false; and they agree in the language they use.

That is not agreement in opinions but in form of life (PI 241)...Here we strike rock bottom, that is, we have come down to conventions. (BBB , p.24) ...When philosophers use a word--'knowledge', 'being', 'object', 'I', 'proposition', 'name'--and try to grasp the essence of the thing, one must always ask oneself: is the word ever actually used in this way in the language-game which is its original home.



What we do is to bring words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use. (PI 116)...

The meaning of a word is its use in the language (PI 43)...


When I talk about language (words, sentences, etc.) I must speak the language of everyday. Is this language somehow too coarse and material for what we want to say? Then how is another one to be constructed? (PI 120)...

And main source of our failure to understand is that we do not command a clear view of the use of our words (PI 122)...


Philosophy may in no way interfere with the actual use of language; it can in the end only describe it.


For it cannot give it any foundation either. It leaves everything as it is (PI 124)...


Essence is expressed by grammar (PI 371). Grammar tells what kind of object anything is. (Theology as grammar) (PI 373).”

Thurman believes that the buddhist Prásangika counterpart of this conventionalism can be most clearly seen in Candrakirti’s critique of Bhavya’s (a contemporary thinker) use of the “head of Ráhu” example as justification for employing the expression “hardness is the intrinsic identity of earth” as a conventionally acceptable expression.

(Ráhu is a mythological demon who is all head and no body, so “head” and “Ráhu” refer to the same thing, as do “hardness” and “earth”.) “Candra states: “


Moreover, this example is incorrect because the expression... "Raahu" does exist among mundane, established without analysis, and does apply to its referent... "head," just like the conventional designation "person," (EE, p. 171).”

Thurman also quotes Tson Khapa, who here comments: “... it is correct, according to conventions of social communication, for a speaker to dispel the doubt of a listener with the expression... 'Ráhu' since the latter has formed the notion of a... head from hearing that word and is wondering "whose head? "

The speaker thus wishes to eliminate the possibility of reference... to any head other than that of Ráhu.

However, this example does not correspond to the case of the expression "hardness is the intrinsic identity of earth," there being no earth which is not hard, and hence no need to dispel any such doubt (EE, 172).
 


Thurman thinks that the main target of the critique is the notion of ‘intrinsic identity’ which would not occur to the ordinary hearer. “Hardness of earth” might fit with the example, but there is no room for notions of ‘intrinsic identity’ - the hearer would not wonder ‘whose intrinsic identity’? but only ‘whose hardness’?


Thurman says Candrakirti returns the attack, by saying that conventionally ‘head’ and ‘Ráhu’ are different, hence the example cannot illustrate a supposed case of essential nondifference. But then, rejoins the essentialist (Bhavya), when one investigates the referents of the expressions, they prove to be the same thing.

Candra then succinctly states his conventionalism about language: “If you propose that the example is indeed applicable since (... Raahu) is proved to be nothing other than ... 'head', since only the latter can finally be apprehended,

I say that is not so; for, in the usage of mundane conventions, such a sort of analysis (as that seeking essential identity, etc.) is not employed, and further, the things of the world are existent (only insofar) as unexamined critically (EE, p. 173)”.

Candra states that once one looks analytically for ‘head’, ‘Ráhu’, or anything else, nothing can be found to withstand analysis, but still those things are there when unanalytically accepted.

He pursues this idea then with a key concept:

“Although analytically there is no self apart from form etc., from the mundane superficial (lokasamvrtya) point of view such (a self) has its existence dependent on the aggregates... (EE, p. 174).”



Let’s show Thurman’s comment on this line of thought:

“Conventionally, even the abhorrent (to the nonegocentrist) 'self' is reinstated, as 'part of the grammar' of mundane communication.

And thus the feared nihilism, which the absolutist imagines lurks at the end of the analysis that seeks a self and cannot find anything, is avoided through the reaffirmation of the mutually dependent, mundane, conventional, nonanalytic existence of 'self'.

Candra finally shows his awareness of how such nihilism cannot be avoided by any means other than such thoroughgoing conventionalism, saying: "otherwise, the superficial (reality) would no longer be the superficial and would either lack validity entirely or would become (ultimate) reality..." (EE, p.175).

Thus, no 'simple' analysis-resistant referential base can be found to anchor the conventional, which is precisely why it works as sheer conventionality, free of the extremisms of absolutism and nihilism.”



Here it should be noted that Candrakirti’s opponent in this is by no means a naive absolutist, but is only trying to uphold the ‘intrinsic identity’ (svalaksana) of things conventionally, having already, as he thinks, ruled them out absolutely.

Candrakirti’s thrust is thus to show the incompatibility of the concepts of conventionality and intrinsicality. Finally, to forestall any misunderstanding about the sort of analysis that can be involved in calling the conventional ‘nonanalytic’, Tson Khapa comments (with intriguing implications for Wittgenstein’s ‘everyday’ use of language, even philosophically): “

We might suppose here, as the mundane person engages in a great deal of analysis--"Is it happening or not?" or "Is it produced or not?"--that it must be improper to reply to such inquiries "It happens" or "it is produced.”

However, this type of (conventional) inquiry and the above analytic method (seeking absolute referential bases) are utterly different.

As Thurman states: “The mundane person is not inquiring into coming and going through analysis into the meaning of the use of the conventional expressions 'comer', 'goer' 'coming', 'going', out of dissatisfaction with (the fact that they are) merely conventional usages.

He is rather making spontaneous inquiry into the spontaneous usage of the expressions 'coming' and 'going' (EE, p. 178).”

The mature Wittgenstein's refusal to pretend to a system, his insistence on ordinary language (which so frustrated logical absolutists such as Russell), gains support when juxtaposed to Candrakirti’s view of language, conceptual analysis, and philosophical investigation as conventional procedures, ‘programs’ (Thurman’s expresion) that function on the surface, the superficial level (samvrti).

The question asked at this point is: “Indeed, how could language, logic, and understanding exclude themselves from the universal relativity that permeates all causal processes?” (p.7)
 
The philosophical nonegocentrist’s attitude toward philosophy as therapy is attested to in Wittgenstein’s writings, as in the following famous passages: “ For the clarity we are aiming at is indeed complete clarity. But this simply means that the philosophical problems should completely disappear.



The real discovery is the one that makes me capable of stopping doing philosophy when I want to.--The one that gives philosophy peace, so that it is no longer tormented by questions that bring itself into question.--

Instead, we now demonstrate a method, by examples and the series of examples can be broken off.-- problems are solved (difficulties eliminated), not a single problem. There is not a philosophical method, though there are indeed methods, like different therapies (PI, p.133) ....

The philosopher's treatment of a question is like the treatment of an illness (PI, p.255)....What is your aim in philosophy? --To shew the fly the way out of the fly-bottle (PI, p.309).”

After the general establishment of a nonegocentrists’ ‘family resemblance’, Thurman forces us to reflect deeply upon the many historical and cultural notions we have that make the whole idea “seem so outlandish a priori”. Thurman: “



Tson Khapa introduces the refutation as follows: “ In general, the two masters (Buddhapalita and Candrakirti) took as the ultimate in subtle and profound philosophical reasonings those reasonings proving the perfect viability of all systems such as causality in the absence of any intrinsic reality such as that (already) rejected as intrinsic identifiability even conventionally, as well as those reasonings negating the negandum of intrinsic identity by the very reason of relativity, asserted clearly as the relativity of all things,

transcendental as well as non-transcendental.

Moreover, they took this refutation of logical privacy as the most subtle among them (EE, p. 218).”
 
Thus, the refutation of logical privacy is stated to be a form of the refutation of intrinsic identity (svalaksana), at the final level of subtlety.

‘Intrinsic identity’, as we have seen is the egocentrist’s designative base, the essentialist private object, necessary for private or independent reference and language.


Thurman goes on like this for the rest of the article, making his line of thought more and more difficult to follow.

I simply don’t have the desire to give a further account of his reasons of why he comes to the following conclusion.

(His method of treating the problem and what he is aiming at can be clearly seen from what I have already reasembled.)

Conclusion:

Although I feel quite at home among sanskrit philosophical terms, I had found Thurman’s way of reasoning quite difficult to follow. Despite of this, his attitude towards philosophy had a great impact on me, and his final conclusion could be heeded by many modern philosophers.

That’s why I’ll quote it in whole:


“In closing, I cannot resist a brief comment on the implications for philosophy of the remarkable fact that Wittgenstein and his successors are very close to the Prasangika tradition in many ways, without ever knowing anything about them directly, simply from pursuing the deepest questions of philosophy in a rigorously critical way, and in spite of the enormous temporal and cultural differences involved.

It means that philosophy today is crippled by prejudices of a very nonphilosophical sort--racial, cultural, and historical.

It means that our ingrained sense of the "progress" of knowledge is highly suspect, not because of some sentimental appeal to some imagined primitive stage of nature, but because even rigorous technical matters were as well and even better explored in ancient times by people in supposed "non-technological cultures and times.



After all, we greatly respect Wittgenstein as a shining star in the firmament of philosophy, even if some of his twinklings elude us, and many of the finest philosophical minds today follow him indirectly if not directly in many aspects of their thinking.

If the type of critical vision he achieved and cultivated on his own was highly developed systematically already in a great tradition with thousands of members in the most populous nations of earth, (not that very many perhaps ever reached the greatest heights or depths), then there must have been a rather bountiful crop of unsung, unpublished Wittgensteins over the twenty centuries during which Indian,

Tibetan, Chinese, Japanese, and Mongolian scholars pursued the goddess of wisdom, (the Sophia of philosophy as Prajnápáramitá, "Transcendent Wisdom") whose attainment was defined as the ultimate liberation from the "fly-bottle" of perplexity.

Such being the case, or even the possibility, it behooves us not to rest content with our one river of Western tradition, but to explore and reveal to our young the great ocean of world philosophy.

It is all ours, we are all human beings, and the Indian or Chinese heritage belongs as much to us as to the Chinese or the Indians.

Especially the philosophical heritage of the nonegocentrist, critical tradition which was born from liberation from cultural conditioning at the deepest levels, perceptual and ideological,

never belonged to any race, culture, or even linguistic tradition, but always to those members of whatever such tradition who dare to question what seems self-evident right before them, what is authoritatively told to them, what seems safe and natural to them--those whose sensibilities demand the surpassing peace that comes with the eradication of perplexity.”




The word I have rendered in the preceding passage as "logical privacy" is the Tibetan ran rgyud, which renders the Sanskrit svaatantrya, previously rendered in this context by Stcherbatski as "independence."


Mention of the Tibetan as well as the Sanskrit here is important, since it was mainly in Tibet that followers of Candra's thought elaborated this question in great detail.

The usual Tibetan translation for Sanskrit svaatantrya (adjectivally, svatantra) is ran dban, which is also the normal Tibetan expression for 'independent', meaning literally 'self-powered', opposed to 'other-powered' (gzan dban, paratantra) .

In this crucial philosophical context, a context which generated centuries of discussion and volumes of commentary and rigorous analysis, why did the Tibetan translators and scholars use ran rgyud, which literally means "own-continuum," translating back into Sanskrit in most contexts as svasa.mtaana, often "own personality" or even "own mind"?

To be sure, Tson Khapa himself glosses ran rgyud with ran dban, (just as Saunders and Henze gloss 'private language' as a language whose words are "conceptually independent of publicly observable phenomena"), but that does not alter the fact that he and his colleagues persisted in using ran rgyud, talking of the ran rgyud problem,

(which would not have been necessary if ran rgyud was identical with ran dban), in all of its contexts. Looking at these, we note that ran rgyud is used nominally, as direct object of 'gog pa, to refute, sgrub pa, to establish.


"Independence" here, while not wrong, is too vague, and does not specifically connect to the philosophical issues involved.

ran rgyud is also used adjectivally with "reason" (hetu, ]]li^nga\\), "thesis" (pratij~naa), position (pak.sa), "probandum" (]]saadhya\\), "syllogism" (anumaana), and "validating cognition" (pramaa.na), all of which are essentially linguistic phenomena, although to my knowledge it is never used with "language" (]]bhaa.sya\\).

In all of these cases, it is contrasted, not with "dependent" (paratantra), but with "public" (]]paraprasiddha\\, literally, "other-acknowledged") reason, thesis, and so forth.

Finally, it crops up in the name of Bhaavaviveka's Maadhyamika subschool, Svaatantrika, the "school of those who use private arguments," as opposed to Candra's Praasa^ngika, the "school of those who use consequences" (prasa^nga) of their opponent's absolutisms, the most public form of philosophical approach.

By derivation, the former can be aptly called the "Dogmatic Maadhyamikas" in contrast to the "Dialectical Maadhyamikas," as long as it is understood that the reason for their dogmatism, albeit only conventional, is their tacit resurrection of intrinsic identity in the form of logical privacy as the basis of language used rigorously in philosophical arguments.(8)

Tson Khapa, in typical Tibetan philosophic style, first cites the Indian Jayaananda's attack on the private reason and then goes on to reject it as the wrong approach.


In this regard, a certain pandit argues "the private reason would be appropriate if there were substantiation by validating cognition of both reason and the invariable concomitance proving the probandum; but it is not appropriate, such not being the case.

For it is wrong to assert that a reason can be authoritatively substantiated for both protagonist and antagonist, since the protagonist does not know what is established by validating cognition for the antagonist, not able to know the other's thoughts either by perception or inference, nor does he know what is established by right knowledge for himself, as it is always possible his judgment is in error."



(But we respond that) this (approach) is utterly wrong; for, if such were the case, it would also be inappropriate to refute (an antagonist with a public) syllogism) based on his own assertions; for one could not know that antagonist's position, not knowing his thoughts, and one's own refutation by advancing his fallacies could be wrong, as it would always be possible that one's judgment about those fallacies could be mistaken (EE, p. 218).



This false start on the refutation of privacy is strikingly reminiscent of Saunders and Henze's formulation of the opening "prong" of the assault on the private language, where the possibility of a private language is challenged on grounds of the unreliability of subjective memory impressions which are not independently checkable or substantiated.(9)

But, just like Jayaananda's, this attack is not conclusive, since the criterial demand itself is too stringent, and the antagonist is able to throw the same doubt back at public discourse--"you think you can check public impressions based on other's testimony, etc., but couldn't you hear them wrong?"--and so forth.(10)

The Wittgensteinian is then required to come back stressing the conventional acceptability of public substantiation and so on, which anticipates Tson Khapa's progression, to which we now return.



Tson Khapa elucidates Candra's assault on a customary private syllogism of Bhaavaviveka.

This passage in the Prasannapadaa I, is considered the locus classicus of the refutation of logical privacy. Bhaavaviveka is arguing against a /.../?

respective private objects, encountered by each in a private perception of the subject of the syllogism (eye-consciousness, and so on), the reason employed (its existence), and the concomitance perceived in the example, which are named in the argument and understood by each via each object's conventional intrinsic identity (vyavahaarikasvalak.sa.na), which Bhaavaviveka maintains consistently to be indispensable for conventional functionality.

The Saa.mkhya himself is much more grossly absolutistic, believing that inner phenomena such as eye-consciousness are absolutely existent, self-produced, and so on.

And this is why Bhaavaviveka feels it necessary to qualify his argument, adding "absolutely" (paramaarthata.h) , which Candra seizes upon as evidence of his subtle absolutization of the conventional. Candra attacks as follows:




“Your use of the thesis-qualification "absolutely" is unnecessary from your own standpoint, since you do not accept self-production even superficially... and as it relates to others' standpoints, it is better to refute outsiders without any such qualifications, since outsiders muddle the two realities and should be refuted in terms of both.

Further, as it is inappropriate to refute the claim of self-production in conventional terms, it is also inappropriate to employ such qualifications in that context; for the mundane person assents to mere arisal of effect without any analytic inquiry as to whether it is produced from self or other, etc.

Again, if it is the case that you wish to refute even the superficial production of the eye, etc., which your antagonist believes to be absolute, this then entails with respect to yourself the thesis-fault of groundlessness, since you yourself do not accept eye, etc., as absolutely existent (EE, pp. 228-229).



Candra here is basically challenging Bhavya to give an account of his supposed privately based discourse, asking him how can he find any common ground of discussion with his antagonist, since each exists in a private, logically inaccessible world of private objects, and so forth.

Sensing these difficulties, Bhavya sidesteps the necessity of the qualification "absolutely," and instead tries to show his argument's conventional viability, arguing for the accessibility of a general subject of the syllogism, mere eye-consciousness, and so on, disregarding all qualifications.

He gives the plausible example of the argument between the Buddhist Vaibhaa.sika and the Brahmanical Vai'se.sika about the status of sound, which proceeds on the basis of the general subject "mere sound" not qualified as either "etheric sound" (unacceptable to Vaibhaa.sika) or "material sound" (unacceptable to Vai'se.sika) .

This, Bhavya argues, evades the thesis-fault of groundlessness, restores a "bare datum" as the private object, in principle accessible to both parties as basis of private syllogism.



This apparently reasonable tack proves calamitous for Bhavya, as it enables Candra to expose his subtle absolutism, his commitment to a private object as the objectively real basis of perception, hence of justification, language, even causality.

Tson Khapa paraphrases Candra's argument here: “It is wrong to posit mere eye, etc., disregarding qualifications in light of two realities, as the subject of the syllogism proving the absence of the self-production of eye, etc.;

because, (according to your own system), the validating cognition must be unmistaken about the intrinsic reality of eye, etc.;

and because, as unmistaken cognition does not mistake intrinsic reality, the object it encounters cannot be an erroneous object which falsely appears to have intrinsic identifiability when in fact it does not (EE, p. 231 following P, pp. 8 ff).



Candra argues that Bhavya cannot have a 'mere object', general and unqualified, and still uphold his 'private system', since according to that even a 'bare datum' can only exist if encountered by a validating cognition which must not mistake the object's intrinsic identity.

Such a bare datum thus must be absolutely real, even to be there for an absolutist who requires its certification by a private, unmistaken, validating cognition.

Tson Khapa clarifies this point: “... in a philosophical system that claims that whatever exists, exists in its own right objectively, a (cognition) that errs in its perception of intrinsic identifiability cannot be established as discovering its proper object.

Any sort of validating cognition, either conceptual or nonconceptual, must be unmistaken about the intrinsic identity of its validated object....

Thus, a validating cognition must derive its validity from an object which, not being merely a conventiozal, nominal designation, has an objectivity or intrinsic reality as its own actual condition. And this is just what (Bhavya's) own system claims (EE, p. 231, italics mine).

The refutation here comes down to the hyperbolic private object, just as it does in the modern one. How uncanny is the resonance of Saunder's and Henze's description of the private "experiential-datum" needed to anchor the term in private language.

 (A private language is) A language, each word of which refers to experiential data, although each of these words is conceptually independent of publicly observable phenomena.

(When we say that an experiential-datum term, "E," is conceptually independent of publicly observable phenomena, we mean this: the existence of an E neither entails nor is entailed by the existence of any publicly observable phenomena; nor is it part of the meaning of "E" that publicly observable phenomena provide evidence for the existence of an E) (PLP, pp. 6-7).



To recapitulate, Bhavya tries to reestablish his private syllogism by employing a mere, general (that is, publicly observable and ostensible) object as a basis of discussion, thus tacitly acknowledging the publicness of objects, subjects, syllogisms, language, and so forth, which he cannot rightly do in the framework of his system, which posits intrinsic, not conventional, objectivity to genuine phenomena and hence cannot tolerate their mere relativity and superficiality.

And Candra holds him to his own basic outlook without letting him pay lip service to conventionality, saying, as it were, your "bare datum" must be absolute, intrinsically identifiable, and hence privately cognizable and substantiable, if only for you to perceive it at all, since for you nothing can even exist unless it is thus established.



Candra then follows this point with a refutation of Bhavya's example itself, pointing out its inapplicability. Candra agrees that the Vaibhaa.sika and the Vai'se.sika each can point out a mere sound to argue about, since both tacitly share a sense of the perceptual objectivity, the private "givenness" of the object, its "thereness," as it were.

However, as Tson Khapa paraphrases: “... the case is different when the advocate of the emptiness of intrinsic reality proves to the advocate of nonemptiness of intrinsic reality that eye, etc. are not self-produced. For not only can they not discover any objective existence or even any objective nonexistence, but also they can not point out to each other "such a thing a 'this' we both encounter as the actual thing to use as subject of our argument (EE, p. 236).



This is perhaps the most subtle point to grasp, either in the Wittgensteinian or in the Praasa^ngika context, because of our innate perceptual absolutism, reinforced by culture through language, but the attainment of the accomplished nonegocentrist philosopher comes down even to this.

In looking for an object to use as the subject of a syllogism, the nonegocentrist (that is, advocate of emptiness) cannot find anything whatsoever, when he looks with a truthdeterminant analysis at objects supposed to have a cognitively objective status according to the egocentrist (nonemptiness advocate) .

Of course, conventionally all sorts of unanalyzed objects are right there without having to be looked for, relative, designatively dependent, publicly observable and so forth, easily accessible to the nonanalytic attitude of everyday consciousness.

However, when he adopts the attitude called "philosophical cognition analytic of ultimacy" (don dam dpyod pai rigs 'ses) , which he does when advocating emptiness to the absolutist in the attempt to cure his absolutistic illness, he cannot find any single thing that is intrinsically identifiable, privately cognizable, or ostensively definable or even accessible.

Under this analysis, both public and private disappear, as they can only exist in mutual dependence.

Only such an appreciation of the transformative power of analytic vision can ever make clear the otherwise cryptic statement of Wittgenstein, the remarkable PI 398:

"But when I imagine something, or even actually see objects, I have got something which my neighbor has not!"--l understand you.

You want to look about you and say: "at any rate, only I have got THIS!" What are these words for?

They serve no purpose.--Can one not add: "there is here no question of a 'seeing' and therefore none of a 'having'--nor of a subject, nor therefore of 'I' either?" Might I not ask: in what sense have you got what you are talking about and saying that only you have got it? Do you possess it?

You DO NOT EVEN SEE IT! And this too is clear: If as a matter of logic you exclude other people's having something, it loses its sense to say that you have it. (Double underscore added.)

Here again we find Wittgenstein levelling the clincher at his opponent, preceding what Saunders and Henze call the "ascription argument" and attribute to Strawson, namely, that no "private" object, perception, or language can exist without the public notion of "person," which thus vitiates the logical privacy of them;

as they put it, "the traditionist (just like Svaatantrika) cannot treat the notions of 'I' and 'my experience' as logically primitive to with respect to the notions of 'he' and 'his experience' because one who does not possess the latter notions lacks the former notions as well"(11) (parentheses added).


This argument topples the traditionist's adherence to the private language, enables Wittgenstein to exclaim to his absolutist interlocutor "You do not even see it!" (PI 398), and enables Candra to demolish Bhavya's sense of the plausibility even of his example, as the two parties in the supposed private argument cannot find either any objective existence or any objective nonexistence!

Thus all three end up on the same point, from which proceeds the methodology of the nonegocentrist.

He does not try to employ private syllogisms, reasons, and so forth, since antagonist and protagonist are so far apart there is no ground of discussion established in any satistactory manner, but rather makes his own analytic, critical attitude available to his antagonist dialectically, leading him through logical ramifications of his position that end up with absurd consequences. The antagonist thus is able to see the awkwardness of his original position and gracefully abandon it.

As Wittgenstein proposed, the nonegocentrist should "yield to the temptation to use this (absolutist's) picture (of the world) but then investigate how the application of the picture goes" (PI 374) (parentheses added).

And, thus confirmed by the more systematized Praasangika methodology, it is now obvious why Wittgenstein refused to appear too systematic or formal in his mature investigations, why he adopted an inner dialogue form, and why many of his points are made through asking obviously unanswerable questions. Indeed, it is amazing how well he managed, all alone as he was, not knowing that he was in fact a luminary of the "anti-traditionist's tradition," and was applying to European absolutism the same critique earlier applied to Indian absolutism by the proponents of the Middle Way!

In closing, I cannot resist a brief comment on the implications for philosophy of the remarkable fact that Wittgenstein and his successors are very close to the Praasa^ngika tradition in many ways, without ever knowing anything about them directly, simply from pursuing the deepest questions of philosophy in a rigorously critical way, and in spite of the enormous temporal and cultural differences involved.

It means that philosophy today is crippled by prejudices of a very nonphilosophical sort--racial, cultural, and historical. It means that our ingrained sense of the "progress" of knowledge is highly suspect, not because of some sentimental appeal to some imagined primitive stage of nature, but because even rigorous technical matters were as well and even better explored in ancient times by people in supposed "non-technological cultures and times.

After all, we greatly respect Wittgenstein as a shining star in the firmament of philosophy, even if some of his twinklings elude us, and many of the finest philosophical minds today follow him indirectly if not directly in many aspects of their thinking.

If the type of critical vision he achieved and cultivated on his own was highly developed systematically already in a great tradition with thousands of members in the most populous nations of earth, (not that very many perhaps ever reached the greatest heights or depths), then there must have been a rather bountiful crop of unsung, unpublished Wittgensteins over the twenty centuries during which Indian,

Tibetan, Chinese, Japanese, and Mongolian scholars pursued the goddess of wisdom, (the Sophia of philosophy as Prajnaparamita,

"Transcendent Wisdom") whose attainment was defined as the ultimate liberation from the "fly-bottle" of perplexity.

Such being the case, or even the possibility, it behooves us not to rest content with our one river of Western tradition, but to explore and reveal to our young the great ocean of world philosophy.

It is all ours, we are all human beings, and the Indian or Chinese heritage belongs as much to us as to the Chinese or the Indians. Especially the philosophical heritage of the nonegocentrist, critical tradition which was born from liberation from cultural conditioning at the deepest levels, perceptual and ideological, never belonged to any race, culture, or even linguistic tradition, but always to those members of whatever such tradition who dare to question what seems self-evident right before them, what is authoritatively told to them, what seems safe and natural to them--those whose sensibilities demand the surpassing peace that comes with the eradication of perplexity.

NOTES

7. Candrakirti, Prasannapada, Vaidya ed. (Darbhanga,
1962), p. 1.
8. Confer EE, Chapter V,n. 98.
9. PLP, pp. 28ff
10. PLP, p. 62ff.
11. PLP, p. 139. 6