Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Abhidhamma Interpretations of “Persons” (puggaldy. with Particular Reference to the Anguttara Nikaya

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search




by Tse-fu Kuan



Abstract General opinion holds that the Abhidhamma treats the Buddha’s teachings in terms of ultimate realities, i.e. dhammas. and that conventional con­structs such as persons (puggala) fall outside the primary concern of the Abhidhamma. The present paper re-examines this ultimate-conventional dichotomy drawn between dhammas and persons and argues that this dichotomy does not hold true for the canonical Abhidhamma in Pali. This study explores how various types of persons are interpreted and approached by the Abhidhamma material, including Abhidhamma texts such as the Puggalapannatti and a number of suttas in the Anguttara Nikaya that are identified in this paper as proto-Abhidhamma.


Keywords AbhidhammaPersonPuggalaPudgalaPannattiAnguttara


The Abhidhamma and the Anguttara Nikaya


For most Buddhist schools, the Buddhist Canon comprises the three Pitakas (Collections), namely the Vinaya-, the Sutra- and the Abhidharma-Pitaka. The Abhidharma (P. Abhidhamma) is generally regarded as later than the Sutra (P. Sutta) material of the Nikciyas and Agamas.' It is widely held that the Abhidharma presents analysis and interpretation of the Buddha’s teachings in such a way that it mostly concerns dharmas (P. dhamma), which are seen as constituents of reality or ultimate constituent elements that really exist; by contrast, persons (P. puggala, Skt.


1 Gethin (1998, p. 204), Reat (1996, p. 25). Williams and Tribe (2000, p. 87). Bhikkhu Bodhi’s introduction to Abhidhamma Studies by Nyanaponika (1998. p. ix). T. Kuan (^)


Yuan Ze University, 135 Yuan-Tung Road, Chung-Li, Taoyuan. Taiwan pudgala) do not really exist since a person is analyzed by Abhidharma into dharmas, which are all there is.“ Owing to this widespread view, which is examined in “Provisional and Definitive Interpretations” and “Can “Persons” (puggala) be Subject Matter Appropriate for the Abhidhamma?” Sections of this paper, scholarly discussions of the Abhidharma have paid much more attention to dharmas than to persons. This study is an attempt to fill the lacuna in our understanding of how the Abhidharma deals with persons.


The Ahguttara Nikaya is included in the Sutta Pitaka of the Pali Canon, but it can be shown to be closely related to the Abhidhamma. Its framework is based on a numerical scheme according to which each successive section (nipata) deals with sets of terms one number more than those dealt with in the preceding section. This feature is also characteristic of some Abhidharma works, such as the Puggala- pahhatti of the Theravadins and the Samgitiparyaya (Jiyimen zu lun, T 1536) of the Sarvastivadins. Besides, the Ahguttara Nikaya’s method of arranging sets of items according to certain principles is similar to that used in constructing the matrkds (P. matika), or comprehensive lists of the fundamental doctrinal items, as found in many Abhidharma texts.


There are different explanations for the historical origin and development of Abhidharma texts. As Cox (1995, p. 8) points out, most Western scholars contend that Abhidharma treatises evolved from the practice of formulating matrices or categorizing lists (mdtrkd/mdtikd) of all topics of the teaching arranged according to both numerical and qualitative criteria. Bronkhorst (1985, p. 307) notes that the development of such lists had run its course well before the final redaction of the Sutra Pitaka. He says that the later tradition which ascribes Abhidharma to Sariputra already finds expression in the SahgTti Sutra and Dasottara Sutra of the DTrgha Agama (equivalent to the SahgTti Sutta

and Dasuttara Sutta of the DTgha Nikaya), and thus we have “another indication that the Abhidharma-Vibhanga existed prior to the completion of the Sutrapitaka” (ibid., p. 316). Frauwallner (1995, pp. 4, 7) also counts these two sutras as pertaining to the earliest Abhidharma. Bronkhorst (1985, p. 316) says: “[T]he early existence of some kind of Abhidharma would explain the peculiar shape of the Sutrapitaka, or rather of two sections of it, the Samyuktagama / P. Samyutta Nikaya and the Ekottaragama / P. Ahguttara Nikaya.” Therefore he asserts the influence of early Abhidharma on the sutras (ibid., p. 317) and states: “Matrkas. and even one or more Abhidharma works, were in existence well before the completion of the Sutrapitaka.” (ibid., p. 318) Accordingly, the peculiar structure and other features of the Ahguttara Nikaya can be explained by the influence of early Abhidhamma on this Nikaya. Even some suttas in the Nikdyas were actually Abhidhamma as Bucknell and Stuart-Fox (1993, pp. 27-28) suggest. This is illustrated in “Four Types of Ascetics”-“Provisional and Definitive Interpretations” Sections of this paper.


Wogihara (1935, front-matter 1—3) takes a different viewpoint on the relation between the Ahguttara Nikaya and Abhidhamma. He suggests that the SahgTti Sutta and Dasuttara Sutta of the Digha Nikaya may have served as precursors of the Ahguttara Nikaya, and that these two suttas, composed of numerical lists, were later expanded and transformed into many suttas of the Ahguttara Nikaya (ibid., front­matter 1-2). Since these two suttas of the Digha Nikaya are attributed to Sariputta (Sariputra), the first person to preach

Abhidhamma according to the tradition, they can be regarded as forerunners of Abhidhamma (ibid., front-matter 2-3). By inference, Wogihara (ibid., front-matter 3) maintains that it is no exaggeration to say that the Ahguttara Nikaya is the source of Abhidhamma. Similarly, Reat (1996, p. 25) thinks that the Sahgiti Sutta and Dasuttara Sutta prefigure the organization of the Ahguttara Nikaya and Samyutta Nikaya, which in turn foreshadow the Abhidhamma literature. Similarly, Cousins (1983, pp. 3^1) suggests that many of the lists in the Sahgiti Sutta “must derive from suttas found only in the Anguttara- nikaya”, and points out that this sutta “is used as the basis for one of the seven canonical abhidharma works of the Sarvastivada”, namely the Samgitiparyaya.b


These two views are not diametrically opposite. Accepting the two possibilities, Cox (1995, pp. 9-10) states: [T]he Ahguttaranikaya adopts a numerical arrangement in which entire sutras are classified according to the number of items represented by their primary topic. ... Even though these modes of organization may indicate antecedents in the sutra of structural procedures that were to fully develop in the Abhidharma literature, ... they may also reflect, in individual cases, the influence of Abhidharma upon the sutra collections themselves. For the final redaction of the sutras certainly does not entirely precede but also overlaps the composition of Abhidharma works.


This paper is mainly concerned with the influence of early Abhidhamma on the Ahguttara Nikaya and early traces of the Abhidhamma material or proto- Abhidhamma found in this Nikaya, but I shall first illustrate a case in which a sutta of the Ahguttara Nikaya provides a list of persons which evolves into items of matika and new doctrines in various Abhidharma works. This case also shows that in the course of such evolution, this sutta’s list of persons was subject to “depersonalization”, which is typical of some Abhidharma texts.


As noted by Bodhi (2012, p. 58), the Ahguttara Nikaya is distinguished among the four Nikayas by its interest in defining and describing types of persons. He says (ibid., p.

25): The Anguttara ... abounds in different ways of classifying people ... and it gives primacy to their qualities, their struggles for happiness and meaning, their aspirations and attainments. The Anguttara thus became the inspiration and a major source for one of the books of the Abhidhamma Pitaka, the Puggalapannatti. Concrete evidence for this has been provided by Moms (1883. p. x), who points out that nearly the whole of the third, fourth and fifth sections (Tayo Puggala, Cattaro Puggala, Panca Puggala) of the Puggalapannatti are found in the corresponding sections (Tika-nipata. etc.) of the, Anguttara Nikaya J Below 1 will demonstrate that the Anguttara Nikaya, besides being a chief source for the Puggalapannatti, provided several points of reference to other Abhidhamma texts as well.


Person with a Mind Like Lightning and Person with a Mind Like a Diamond Sutta 3.25 in the Anguttara Nikaya (hereafter AN 3.25) expounds the following three kinds of persons (translation mostly by Bodhi 2012, pp. 219f.):


(1) What is the person whose mind is like an open sore? Some person is prone to anger and easily exasperated. ...

(2) What is the person whose mind is like lightning (yijjupama-citto puggalop. Some person understands as it really is: “This is suffering” ... “This is the way leading to the cessation of suffering.” Just as, in the dense darkness of night, a man with good sight can see forms by a flash of lightning, so too some person understands as it really is: “This is suffering” ...


(3) What is the person whose mind is like a diamond (yajirupama-citto puggalo)1 With the destruction of the taints, some person ... dwells having attained the taintless liberation of mind, liberation by wisdom. Just as there is nothing that a diamond cannot cut, whether gem or stone, so too, with the destruction of the taints, some person ...


This sutta outlines the spiritual progression from an ordinary state to liberation. These three types of persons are listed in the matika of the Puggalapannatti (p. 4) and this Theravadin Abhidhamma text (p. 30) repeats, almost verbatim, part of AN 3.25 to serve as its exposition of the three items. As Law (1933, p. 48) suggests, that the Puggalapannatti and the I 'ibhahga show close affinity with the sutta material indicates that they are probably the earliest of the seven canonical Abhidhamma treatises in Pali. Rhys Davids (1903, p. 188), Norman (1983, p. 102), Mizuno (1997, p. 262) and Willemen et al. (1998, p. 13) also regard the Puggalapannatti as the earliest Pali Abhidhamma text, while Bronkhorst (1985, pp. 309f.) and Cox (1992, p. 156) indentify the Vibhanga as reflecting the earliest stage. The Puggalapahhatti. faithfully following AN 3.25, does not at all “interpret” the three items in this sutta of the Ahguttara Nikaya. An interpretation is found in another Theravadin Abhidhamma text, the Dhammasangani.

Two of the above three items are alluded to in the Dhammasangani. The second dyad among the 42 dyads in the suttanta-matika of this text (p. 7) is as follows:


(1) lightning-like states (vijjupama dhammd): (2) diamond-like states (vajirupama dhammd).


This pair of “states” (dhamma) instead of “persons” (puggala) is apparently derived from the last two of the three persons in AN 3.25. The Dhammasangani explains “lightning-like states” as “insight into the three lower noble paths” and “diamond­like states” as “insight into the highest path of arahantship”. This interpretation seems to conform to the purport of the above sutta as far as it makes a distinction between the two items in terms of spiritual level with diamond-like states being higher than lightning-like states. While AN 3.25 has no parallel in the extant Chinese Agamas (two of which belong to the Sarvastivada, see below), this sutta apparently has a Sarvastivada counterpart which is interpreted by the Abhidharma of this school. The Samgitip- arydya (T 1536), among the oldest of the seven canonical Sarvastivadin Abhidharma works, refers to the above three persons in AN 3.25 as three minds (^'L')- In its chapter on sets of three dharmas, these three types of mind are expounded in detail. Below are only some main points.


(1) Why is that mind called “like an open sore”? Because when that mind contacts adverse circumstances, it produces a wide variety of defilements. (2) Why is that mind called “like lightning”? Because that mind attains the fruit of non-return (andgdmin) and it can shine for a while but soon goes out. (3) Why is that mind called “like a diamond”? Because that mind attains the fruit of one-beyond-training (asaiksa/asekha, i.e. the arhat/arahant) and there are no fetters (samyojana) and so on that it cannot destroy.


Similar to “diamond-like states” in the Dhammasangani, “the mind like a diamond” in the Samgitiparydya is associated with the arahant, the fully liberated person without any taints or fetters. This corresponds well with the above description of the “person whose mind is like a diamond” in AN 3.25: “with the destruction of the taints, some person ... dwells having attained the taintless liberation of mind, liberation by wisdom”. However, “the mind like lightning" in the Samgltiparyaya does not match the “lightning-like states” of the Dhammasahgani in that the former refers to the fruit of non-return while the latter relates to the three lower noble paths.


It should be noted here that what is described as a “person” in sutta 3.25 is replaced by “dhamma” (state) and “mind” respectively in the two Abhidharma books, the Dhammasahgani and the Samgltiparyaya. This suggests purposeful modification of the sutta/siitra terminology in line with the Abhidharma tendency to “depersonalize”, which however does not necessarily entail the exclusion of persons from the Abhidharma exposition as will be discussed in “Can “Persons” (puggala) be Subject Matter Appropriate for the Abhidhamma?” Section.


There was still further development in the Abhidharma from the foregoing idea in the Anguttara Nikdya. As Frauwallner (1995, pp. 177f.) notes, the “person whose mind is like a diamond” in this Nikdya was developed by the Sarvastivadin Abhidharma in such a way that it led to “felicitous invention” (p. 178) of the term vajropama-samddhi. “diamond-like concentration”, which is used to designate the final “immediate path” (MlWii) IffiiSili, anantarya-marga) to liberation, wherein the last remaining defilements (anusaya) are eliminated and thus all defilements are eradicated. The “diamond-like concentration” in this sense is found in several Abhidharma texts, including the Jhanaprasthana (Fazhi lun, T 1544), one


of the canonical Abhidharma works of the Sarvastivadins, and some post-canonical Abhidharma texts such as the *Abhidharmahrdaya IW 'A3'C'irfnj (Apitan xin lun, T 1550) and the Abhidharmakosabhasya}6


In sum. sutta 3.25 of the Anguttara Nikdya and its Sarvastivada counterpart provided source materials for the architects of the Abhidharma of different schools at different times to construct and elaborate their philosophical systems. Lamotte (1988. p. 184) aptly remarks that “the Abhidhamma abounds in repetitions, rectifications, reclassifications and explanations which give it the character of an unfinished work still in the process of elaboration”.


Four Types of Ascetics


The matika of the Puggalapannatti (p. 8) contains a set of four persons:


(1) the unshaken ascetic (2) the red-lotus ascetic (3) the white-lotus ascetic (4) the delicate ascetic among ascetics


This set of four persons is also listed in the Sahgiti Sulla of the Digha Nikaya (no. 33 at DN III 233) and four suttas of the Anguttara Nikaya (4.87-90 at AN II 86-91). Therefore, this set of four ascetics, which the Anguttara commentary (Mp III 113) refers to as a matika, probably belongs to a very old matika that already existed before the completion of the Nikayas.


The Sangiti Sutta (DN 33) mentions these four ascetics without any explanation. In contrast, a series of four suttas (4.87-90) in the Anguttara Nikaya defines each of them in four different ways, but three of them (4.87, 4.89, 4.90) agree partly on the referents of these four ascetics. In sutta 4.87 the four kinds of persons are defined as follows (abridged):


(1) the unshaken ascetic: a monk is a trainee (sekha) practising the way who dwells aspiring for the unsurpassed security from bondage.

(2) the white-lotus ascetic: with the destruction of the taints, a monk ... dwells having attained the taintless liberation of mind, liberation by wisdom; yet he does not dwell having touched personally the eight emancipations.

(3) the red-lotus ascetic: with the destruction of the taints, a monk ... dwells having attained the taintless liberation of mind, liberation by wisdom; and he dwells having touched personally the eight emancipations.

(4) the delicate ascetic among ascetics: a monk usually uses a robe that has been specifically offered to him ... he usually eats almsfood that has been specifically offered to him ... lodging ... medicines ... His fellow monks ... usually behave toward him in agreeable ways ... With the destruction of the taints, he ... dwells having attained the taintless liberation of mind, liberation by wisdom. If one could rightly say of anyone: “He is a delicate ascetic among ascetics”, it is precisely of me | the Buddha referring to himself] that one might say this.


Let us first look at the definitions of the second and third types of persons. As Bodhi (2012, pp. 57f.) points out, these two definitions introduce a distinction between two kinds of arahants. The white-lotus ascetic refers to the arahantliberated by wisdom” while the red-lotus ascetic refers to the arahantliberated in both respects”. These two kinds of arahants will be examined in the next section of this paper. The first type of ascetic is said to be a trainee (sekha} aspiring for the unsurpassed security from bondage, so this represents a practitioner who is not yet liberated. The fourth type of ascetic refers to the Buddha himself, a perfectly liberated person who enjoys more comfort and respect than other monks. The set of four ascetics as defined in this way shows a sense of hierarchy.


Sutta 4.89 (AN II 89f.) defines the unshaken ascetic as possessing right view, right intention, right speech, right action, right livelihood, right effort, right mindfulness and right concentration, which constitute the Noble Eightfold Path. By contrast, the white-lotus ascetic and the red-lotus ascetic are not only endowed with the Noble Eightfold Path, but also with right knowledge and right liberation. This implies that these two types of ascetics are liberated arahants, while the unshaken ascetic is not yet liberated. Similar to sutta 4.87, sutta 4.89 describes the white-lotus ascetic as one who “does not dwell having touched personally the eight emancipations”, and the red-lotus ascetic as one who “dwells having touched personally the eight emancipations”. Accordingly, the white-lotus ascetic and the red-lotus ascetic as defined in sutta 4.89 also refer respectively to the arahantliberated by wisdom” and the arahantliberated in both respects” as explained in the Pali commentary. For the fourth type of person, the delicate ascetic among ascetics, sutta 4.89 gives the same definition as that in sutta 4.87, i.e. the Buddha.


Sutta 4.90 (AN II 90f.) defines the unshaken ascetic as “a trainee who has not attained his mind’s ideal and dwells aspiring for the unsurpassed security from bondage”, which is almost identical to the definition of the unshaken ascetic in sutta 4.87. The white-lotus ascetic and the red-lotus ascetic are both depicted as a monk who dwells contemplating rise and fall in the five aggregates subject to clinging, but the former “does not dwell having touched personally the eight emancipations” while the latter “dwells having touched personally the eight emancipations”. The definitions of these two ascetics make no mention of their liberation, and the Pali commentary glosses both of them as trainees (sekha) with the distinction that the white-lotus ascetic produces no jhanas whereas the red-lotus ascetic attains the eight emancipations. In this sutta, the delicate ascetic among ascetics is again defined in the same way as in sutta 4.87.


While the above three suttas appear to define the four kinds of persons in a somewhat similar way, sutta 4.88 defines them in a totally different fashion as follows (in brief):


(1) the unshaken ascetic: a stream-enterer tsotdpanna).

(2) the white-lotus ascetic: a once-retumer (sakadagamin).

(3) the red-lotus ascetic: one of spontaneous rebirth, due to attain final Nirvana there without returning from that world (opapatiko hoti tattha-parinibbciyi anavattidhammo tasma loka), i.e. a non-returner (andgdmiri).


(4) the delicate ascetic among ascetics: with the destruction of the taints, a monk ... dwells having attained the taintless liberation of mind, liberation by wisdom; in other words, an arahant.


This sutta corresponds to siltra 7 in chapter 28 of the Ekottarika Agama (hereafter EA 28.7) of probably Mahasamghika origin. This sutra defines four kinds of ascetics in somewhat different terminology and sequence:


(1) the ascetic like a yellow-blue-flower: a stream-enterer.

(2) the white-lotus ascetic: a once-retumer.

(3) the delicate ascetic: a non-returner.


(4) the delicate ascetic among the delicate [sic]: a person has destroyed the taints, attaining the taintless liberation of mind, liberation by wisdom; in other words, an arahant.


Thus, sutta 4.88 of the AN, likewise EA 28.7. expounds this set of four persons in terms of the four fruits by the stock description of these four spiritual types that recurs in the Nikciyas Only the fourth kind, the delicate ascetic among ascetics, represents a liberated arahant. The white-lotus ascetic is not distinguished from the red-lotus ascetic by his lack of the eight emancipations, and neither of the two ascetics refers to an arahant. Such a significant deviation from the definitions in the other three suttas of the Ahguttara Nikdya is surprising since all these four suttas are presented in the form of the Buddha’s discourses delivered to his disciple monks. It is inconceivable that the

Buddha should have defined these four types of persons in such contradictory ways that his disciples would have been confused. Even the three “similar” suttas also diverge considerably in several aspects as discussed above. The only plausible explanation for this anomaly is that these diverse definitions were formulated by different people instead of just one man, the Buddha. Who were they? At least some of them were probably Abhidhamma composers or Abhidharmists as will be elucidated below.


Just as sutta 4.88 of the Ahguttara Nikaya (hereafter AN 4.88), the Puggala- pahhatti (p. 63) also explains this set of four ascetics in terms of the four fruits. Even the four definitions in this Abhidhamma text are almost identical in wording to those in AN 4.88, but curiously the definition of the white-lotus ascetic and the definition of the red-lotus ascetic are exchanged; or put more accurately, the places of the two terms “white-lotus ascetic” and “red-lotus ascetic” are swapped. This divergence should be viewed against the broader background of textual compilation. When the Nikayas and Abhidhamma were compiled, there appeared to be confusions not only in defining the four kinds of ascetics but also in arranging the sequence of these four persons. In the Sahgiti Sutta (DN 33) the sequence is:


1. the unshaken ascetic 2. the red-lotus ascetic 3. the white-lotus ascetic 4. the delicate ascetic In the four suttas of the Ahguttara Nikaya, however, the sequence is: 1. the unshaken ascetic 2. the white-lotus ascetic 3. the red-lotus ascetic 4. the delicate ascetic among ascetics


It should be noted, in addition, that the Ahguttara Nikaya version of the fourth person contains the expression “among ascetics” (samanesu), which is absent from the DN 33 version.

The Puggalapahhatti draws heavily on the Ahguttara Nikaya as pointed out by the scholars mentioned above. Just like the Ahguttara Nikaya, the Puggalapahhatti has the expression “among ascetics” for the fourth type of ascetic in the matika (p. 8) and its exposition (p. 63). However, the sequence of these four types in the Puggalapahhatti follows that in DN 33, i.e. “red-lotus ascetic” before “white-lotus ascetic”. While following the sequence of the terms in DN 33, the Puggalapahhatti seemingly copies the definitions of the four terms from AN 4.88 in exactly the same order as the four definitions appear in this sutta. Consequently, the definition of the white-lotus ascetic (second ascetic) in AN 4.88 is placed under the term “red-lotus ascetic” (second ascetic) in the Puggalapannatti, and the definition of the red-lotus ascetic (third ascetic) in AN 4.88 is placed under the term “white-lotus ascetic” (third ascetic) in the Puggalapannatti. Therefore the definitions of these two kinds of ascetics in one text are reversed in the other. It is difficult to assert which of the two versions is original, but considering the general assumption that Abhidhamma texts are founded on suttas, the Puggalapannatti version may be a secondary development from the above two Nika yas. Alternatively, it is possible that this Puggalapannatti version originated from certain ancient Sutta literature or perhaps more likely Abhidhamma literature, which then evolved in different directions into the Sangiti Sutta (DN 33) and sutta 4.88 of the Anguttara Nikaya as well as EA 28.7. This may also explain why the Puggalapannatti version bears the different characteristics of both suttas extant today.


Let us now return to the point that even the Anguttara Nikaya itself describes diverse ways of defining the four types of ascetics in a series of four suttas. Only the version of sutta 4.88 is adopted by the Puggalapannatti presumably because the author of this shortest canonical Abhidhamma work wanted to give a succinct and standard definition of these four kinds of persons. In contrast, the compilers of the Anguttara Nikaya faithfully preserved four versions of the definitions and allocated them to four suttas in a series, and apparently admitted the existence of disagreement on how to define or interpret the four types of ascetics. In this connection, we may venture to suggest that at least some versions of these definitions in the Anguttara Nikaya were interpolated into this “Sutta literature” as a kind of “Abhidhamma”, even if the possibility cannot be excluded that a certain version/versions might contain the Buddha’s own interpretation. It was not uncommon for Buddhists to disagree about Abhidhamma even during the Buddha’s lifetime according to the Kinti Sutta of the Majjhima Nikaya (no. 103). In this sutta the Buddha is depicted as saying: “While you are training in concord, with mutual appreciation, without disputing, two monks might make different assertions about the Abhidhamma.” These four suttas in the Anguttara Nikaya provide us with such different assertions about the Abhidhamma. It should be noted that “Abhidhamma” in this sense cannot be equated with the Abhidhamma Pitaka, but nevertheless, as Kimura (1968, pp. 31-33) and Willemen et al. (1998, pp. 12—13) suggest, such discussions or debates on the Abhidharma among the Buddha’s disciples can be seen as the inception of the Abhidharma literature. When Watanabe (1983, p. 37) raises the question: “What is then the original (or simple) form of the Abhidhamma Pitaka?”, he supplies an answer by drawing our attention to the following two points regarding “the [[[Buddha’s]]] disciples’ attempts at the elementary philosophical study of dhammas”-. (1) defining dhammas, (2) arranging dhammas in numerical order. Defining the items and arranging them in numerical sequence are exactly the issues involved in the four kinds of ascetics discussed above. “Liberated by Wisdom” and “Liberated in Both Respects”


Let us now move on to the interpretations of “liberated by wisdom” and “liberated in both respects”. First, we should look into the Sutta Pitaka. The Kitagiri Sutta of the Majjhima Nikaya (no. 70) gives a listing of seven spiritual types, among which the highest two are “the person liberated in both respects” and “the person liberated by wisdom”. These are the two kinds of arahants or fully liberated persons found in the Nikayas?1 The Kitagiri Sutta explains these two kinds of persons as follows:


Here some person dwells having touched personally those peaceful emanci­pations that are formless and transcending forms; and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed. This is called “the person liberated in both respects”. ...


Here some person does not dwell having touched personally those peaceful emancipations that are formless and transcending forms; and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed. This is called “the person liberated by wisdom”.


According to the Kitagiri Sutta, the distinction between these two kinds of arahants is this: a person who is “liberated in both respects” experiences the peaceful emancipations that are formless and transcending forms (santa vimokha atikkamma rupe aruppa). but a personliberated by wisdom” does not have such experience of those formless emancipations. Apparently the “formless emancipations” (vimokha aruppa) refer to the four formless attainments, which transcend the four jhan as in the form sphere (atikkamma rape). By implication, a personliberated by wisdom”, although devoid of the formless attainments, may have experience of the jhanas. Disagreeing with the Kitagiri Sutta, the Puggalapahhatti defines these two persons thus:


Here some person dwells having touched personally the eight emancipations; and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed. This is called “the person liberated in both respects”. ... Here some person does not dwell having touched personally the eight emancipations; and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed. This is called “the person liberated by wisdom”. This Abhidhamma definition deviates from that of the Kitagiri Sutta, which also belongs to the Theravada. In this case, surprisingly, the Puggalapannatti, a Theravada Abhidhamma text, does not invoke the Sutta literature of the Theravada, but rather closely parallels the following Sutra literature of the Sarvastivada now extant in Chinese translation. The Sarvastivada counterpart of the Kitagiri Sutta, sutra 195 of the Madhyama Agama (MA 195). states: Some monk dwells having touched personally and attained the eight emancipations; and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed and understood. This is called “the monk liberated in both respects”. ... Some monk does not dwell having touched personally or attained the eight emancipations; and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed and understood. This is called “the monk liberated by wisdom”.


A virtually identical definition is also found in siitra 936 of the Samyukta Agama (SA 936), which is widely ascribed to the Sarvastivada or perhaps more specifically the Mulasarvastivada tradition. Therefore, according to the Sarvas­tivada tradition (MA 195 and SA 936), what distinguishes one type of arahant from the other is that the personliberated in both respects” has experience of the eight emancipations whereas the personliberated by wisdom” does not have such experience of the eight emancipations. The last five of the eight emancipations are the four formless attainments and the “cessation of perception and feeling” (saiiiici- vedayita-nirodha) according to many suttas?9 but the identity of the first three is unclear in the suttas. In the Dhammasahgani the first three emancipations are connected with the four jhanas?0 Bodhi (2007, p. 69 n. 43) explains them thus: “The first three emancipations are equivalent to the four jhanas, but they deal with the state of jhana in terms of its objects rather than in terms of its subjective experience.” In sum, the eight emancipations cover all the nine attainments in concentrative meditation {samadhi). Therefore, an arahantliberated by wisdom” lacks all attainments in concentrative meditation, including even the jhanas. The above passage quoted from the Puggalapannatti conforms to this Sarvastivada Sutra tradition that dissociates “liberated by wisdom” from all the nine meditative attainments, and deviates from its own Theravada Sutta tradition that an arahantliberated by wisdom” lacks only the formless attainments and may possess the jhanas. What should we make of this bizarre fact? The answer may be as follows.


When this Abhidhamma work, the Puggalapahhatti, was not yet completed, the issue of “liberated by wisdom” as against “liberated in both respects” was still under debate. A consensus was probably reached regarding “liberated in both respects”, which was seen to denote the “fully-fledged” arahant with experience of all the nine attainments in concentrative meditation. In contrast with such a “fully-fledged” arahant, the one “liberated by wisdom” was seen as incomplete in concentrative attainments. Disagreement arose about the scale of meditative attainments that was expected of the arahantliberated by wisdom”, and hence the divergent definitions of these two kinds of arahants circulated among the Theravadins and Sarvastivadins. As Kuan (2013a, pp. 64—68) demonstrates, the seven spiritual types, including these two kinds of arahants, were interpolated into many sutras as a result of scholastic debates after the Buddha’s death. The seven spiritual types are found twice in the matika of the Puggalapannatti (pp. 3, 10) and expounded in this Abhidhamma text (pp. 14f., 72). In view of these facts, the diverse definitions of the two types of arahants, often subsumed under the seven spiritual types, could have stemmed from Abhidharma debates or discussions mentioned in the previous section.


It is likely that the Puggalapannatti was composed before the Nikayas had incorporated the Abhidhamma issue of defining the two kinds of arahants. Therefore, without being constrained by a fixed definition in the Theravada Sutta literature, the Puggalapannatti happened to choose the definition in terms of the eight emancipations, and such a definition was also accepted earlier or later by the Sarvastivadins. By contrast, after the Puggalapannatti had been finalized, the compilers of the Majjhima Nikdya decided to incorporate the definition in terms of the formless emancipations while redacting the KTtdgiri Sutta. On the other hand, suttas 4.87 and 4.89 of the Ahguttara Nikdya adopted the definition in terms of the eight emancipations to define the white-lotus ascetic and red-lotus ascetic, which allude respectively to the arahantliberated by wisdom” and the arahantliberated in both respects” as indicated above. This suggests the possibility that the definition of the two types of arahants in the Puggalapahhatti could be modelled on the two kinds of ascetics in Ahguttara Nikdya considering the close relationship between the Puggalapahhatti and the Ahguttara Nikdya as mentioned above. These divergent interpretations of persons as found in the Majjhima and Ahguttara Nikayas represent the outcome of Abhidhamma debates, just as we find in the independent self-avowedly Abhidhamma text, the Puggalapannatti. Provisional and Definitive Interpretations A series of 10 suttas in the Ahguttara Nikdya (AN 9.42-51) explain various terms by using two opposite modes or methods, namely “with pariyaya” (pariyayena) and “without pariyaya” (nippariyayena). The following is relevant information given at PED p. 433, s.v. pariyaya:


in Abhidhamma terminology, specifically: pariyayena, the mode of teaching in the Suttanta, ad hominem, discursively, applied method, illustrated discourse, figurative language as opposed to the abstract, general statements of Abhidhamma = nippariyayena.


As Gombrich (2009, pp. 6) explains, the word pariyaya literally means “way round” and so “indirect route”, but it refers to a “way of putting things”. To sum up. “with pariyaya” (pariyayena) is a way of putting the subject matter indirectly in figurative language, and therefore this term connotes “in a provisional sense” as rendered by Bodhi (2012, pp. 1319ff.). Then “without pariyaya’ (nippariyayena) can be understood as a way of putting the subject matter directly and non-figuratively, and thus it connotes “in a non-provisional sense” as rendered by Bodhi (2012, pp. 1319ff.).


The first sutta (AN 9.42) in the series of ten suttas makes it clear that each of these suttas consists of dialogues between two disciples of the Buddha—Ananda answers questions put by Udayl. As Cox (1995, p. 8) points out, this “catechetical style characterized by an exchange of questions and interpretative answers intended to clarify complex or obscure points of doctrine” is seen as the origin of Abhidharma by many Japanese scholars. As the last member of the ninefold division of the Dharma, vedalla represents the genre of questions and answers. Dhammajoti (2005, p. 112) notes that in the Anguttara Nikaya (III 107), “vedalla- katha occurs juxtaposed with abhidhamma-kathcl which according to the consensus of scholarly opinion was an important fore-runner of Abhidharma in the later technically developed sense.” In the sutta AN 9.44, Udayi asks: “It is said, friend, ‘liberated by wisdom, liberated by wisdom.’ In what way has the Blessed One spoken of one liberated by wisdom?” Ananda answers (abridged):


... a monk ... dwells having attained the first jhdna, and he understands it with wisdom. To this extent the Blessed One has spoken of one liberated by wisdom in a provisional sense. ... a monk ... dwells having attained the second jhdna ... the third jhdna ... the fourth jhdna ... the sphere of infinite space ... the sphere of infinite consciousness ... the sphere of nothingness ... the sphere of neither- perception-nor-non-perception, and he understands it with wisdom. To this extent, too, the Blessed One has spoken of one liberated by wisdom in a provisional sense.


... a monk ... dwells having attained the cessation of perception and feeling, and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed; and he understands it with wisdom. To this extent, friend, the Blessed One has spoken of one liberated by wisdom in a non-provisional sense. In the next sutta, AN 9.45. Udayi asks about “liberated in both respects”. Ananda answers in exactly the same way as in the previous sutta except that the phrase “he dwells having touched that sphere personally in whatever way [it is attained]” is inserted into each of the statements of the nine spheres or meditative attainments. For example, for the first jhdna and the highest attainment, Ananda states:


... a monk ... dwells having attained the first jhdna ... He dwells having touched that sphere personally in whatever way [it is attained], and he understands it with wisdom. To this extent the Blessed One has spoken of one liberated in both respects in a provisional sense. ... a monk ... dwells having attained the cessation of perception and feeling, and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed. He dwells having touched that sphere personally in whatever way [it is attained], and he understands it with wisdom. To this extent, friend, the Blessed One has spoken of one liberated in both respects in a non-provisional sense.


Now we can work out the “non-provisional” or “definitive” interpretation of the two kinds of liberation. According to AN 9.44, if a person attains the highest meditative sphere (the cessation of perception and feeling, which presupposes the eight lower meditative attainments), and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed, then such a person is “one liberated by wisdom” in a definitive sense. According to AN 9.45, if a person attains the highest meditative sphere, and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed, and he dwells having touched that sphere personally, then such a person is “one liberated in both respects” in a definitive sense. In contrast to the “definitive” interpretation, “provisional” interpretations of the two types are distinguished by describing persons as bei ng able to attain some of the eight lower meditative spheres (i.e. the four jhanas and four formless attainments) but not the highest meditative attainment.


Therefore, according to the definitive, non-provisional definitions in these two suttas, both “a person liberated by wisdom” and “a person liberated in both respects” must experience the highest meditative attainment (“dwells having attained the cessation of perception and feeling” as stated in both suttas), not to mention the eight lower attainments. If the texts are taken literally, there is only one difference between the two: “a person liberated in both respects” dwells having touched that sphere (the cessation of perception and feeling) personally in whatever way [it is attained] whereas “a person liberated by wisdom” does not. This distinction is puzzling, however, because “to dwell having attained the cessation of perception and feeling” can hardly be distinguished from “to dwell having touched personally the cessation of perception and feeling”. Therefore, “liberated by wisdom” is hardly different from “liberated in both respects”. Unfortunately, the Pali commentary (Mp IV 206-207) offers no relevant comment regarding this issue. In any case, according to these Anguttara suttas, all the nine meditative attainments are indispensible to both “liberated by wisdom” and “liberated in both respects” in a non­provisional, definitive sense. This interpretation diverges significantly from those in the Majjhima Nikaya, Madhyama Agama, Samyukta Agania and Puggalapannatti. where “liberated by wisdom” is distinct from “liberated in both respects” in lacking either the higher meditative attainments or all nine meditative attainments.


In this connection, it is worth noting the following remark by Hamilton (2000:8): That it was the spirit rather than the letter of them that mattered is further supported by the style in which the central doctrinal teachings have been preserved in the Nikayas\ they are nearly all given cryptically, open to various interpretations but with no one definitive interpretation attached. It is. indeed, this cryptic equivocal style that has allowed there to be confusion and disagreement about what the teachings mean at all... The later Theravada Buddhist Abhidhamma scholars ... pronounced the style of the early material to be just ‘a way of putting things’ (pariydya). And though they then interpreted and explained the teachings in definitively ‘put’ terms (nippariyayena) in their own texts ...


In view of this observation, suttas 9.44 and 9.45 of the Anguttara Nikaya may be seen to verify the fact that “liberated by wisdom” and “liberated in both respects” in the Sutta literature are usually described cryptically, in ways open to various provisional interpretations but with no one definitive interpretation attached. Therefore, we have the various interpretations of these two kinds of liberation in the Nikdyas andAgamas. Most of these interpretations are merely oblique and figurative “ways of putting things”, and thus they should not be taken literally but require further explication for clarity. As Ronkin (2005, p. 26) states: “[T]he Abhidhamma methods of instructing the teaching ... does not need any further explication, because it is couched in non-figurative. definitely put terms (nippariydya-desand)." The two suttas of the Anguttara Nikaya quoted above obviously serve as Abhidhamma, which purports to explain “liberated in both respects” and “liberated by wisdom” in a definitive, non-figurative way (nippariyayena). and hence is entitled to label other definitions as just figurative or provisional (pariydyena). A certain Abhidharmist probably compiled these two suttas in an attempt to provide a final solution to the issue under debate.


Apart from these two suttas, the other suttas in this series of ten suttas on pariydyena and nippariyayena are apparently all meant to serve this purpose. Let us examine a sutta on another type of person. In AN 9.43. while explaining the “witness-in-person” (kaya-sakkhi),'1 Ananda says: ... a monk ... dwells having attained the first jhana ... He dwells having touched that sphere personally in whatever way [it is attained]. To this extent the Blessed One has spoken of a witness-in-person in a provisional sense.


... the secondjhana the sphere of neither-perception-nor-non-perception ... in a provisional sense. ... a monk ... dwells having attained the cessation of perception and feeling, and having seen with wisdom, his taints are destroyed. He dwells having touched that sphere personally in whatever way [it is attained]. To this extent, friend, the Blessed One has spoken of a witness-in-person in a non-provisional 48 sense. Therefore, in definitive terms, a witness-in-person is a taintless liberated person, i.e. an arahant. This “non-provisional” (nippariyaya) interpretation deviates from the usual sutta interpretation of this person as inferior to the arahant. According to another sutta also in the Anguttara Nikaya (AN 3.21 at I 120), a witness-in-person is one who is practising for arahantship, or a once-retumer, or a non-retumer, and is never an arahant. Similarly, according to the Kitagiri Sutta (MN 70), the Buddha defines the “witness-in-person” thus:


Here some person dwells having touched personally those peaceful emanci­pations that are formless and transcending forms; and having seen with wisdom, some o/his taints are destroyed. This is called “the person who is a witness-in-person”. I say that such a monk still has work to do with diligence. Accordingly, a witness-in-person has destroyed only some of his taints, and thus is not a taintless arahant. This is in stark contrast to the definitions of “the person liberated in both respects” and “the person liberated by wisdom”, who are both said to have destroyed taints and have no work to do with diligence (MN I 477^-78); in other words, these two persons are arahants. From the Abhidhamma viewpoint as expressed in the “sM/ta” AN 9.43, the interpretations of witness-in-person in AN 3.21 and MN 70 are just provisional (pariyayena), and hence should not be taken at face value. According to the serial suttas AN 9.43, AN 9.44 and AN 9.45, the three kinds of persons, namely “witness-in-person”, “one liberated by wisdom” and “one liberated in both respects”, are only nominally different; in effect they all refer to the same type of person, i.e. the liberated arahant. The standpoint represented in these three serial suttas seems to be unique, as Buddhist literature usually distinguishes those three kinds of persons into three hierarchically different types.


The position taken by these three suttas is surprisingly similar to the following idea in one Mahayana text, namely the part of the *Mahavaipulya-mahasamnipata Sutra (T 397) translated by Dharmaksema (385—433 CE).


This text identifies the arahant “liberated-by-wisdom” and the arahant “liberated-in-both-respects” respectively with “witness-in-person”


(JtfS). and thereby equates the three types of persons (T Xlll 159a). This Mahayana conception of spiritual types is consonant with the above Abhidhamma hermeneutic approach (nippariyayena) to the three kinds of persons. These types of persons are just conventionally, nominally designated and do not exist in ultimate reality, as Apple (2004, pp. 261-262) observes:


The Prajnaparamita literature repeatedly states that while coursing in the practice ofprajnaparamita - i.e., viewing things through cognizing emptiness, bodhisattvas see the various stages from Stream-enterer up to Buddhahood as being like an illusion. A bodhisattva, if obtaining a result such as Stream-enterer, does not think “I have obtained the result of Stream-enterer.” ... Therefore, all stages are ultimately seen as like illusions, like a fictitious person.


Such a fictitious and non-essentialist perspective of persons could have led to the foregoing interpretations that blur the boundaries between the various spiritual types as found in the Ahguttara Nikdya'’ s Abhidhamma portion and also in the Mahayana sutra quoted above. Since persons, including the spiritual types, do not exist in essence, their definitions are after all just conventionally designated in order to convey significant information concerning the ultimate goal of liberation and how to progress to this goal. The non-essentialist perspective of persons coincides with the “absence of essence (dtman. Self) in persons” (pudgala-nairdtmya) as conceived by the pre­Mahayana traditions. This exegetical approach to the concept of person (pudgala) was already taken up in the Abhidharma and then followed by the Mahayana. It is widely held that the Mahayana, including the Prajnaparamita (Perfection of Wisdom) literature, criticizes the Abhidharma for its inability to understand the “absence of essence (Self) in dharmas” (dharma-nairdtmya)'. instead the Abhi- dharmists considered dharmas to be things that really, ultimately exist. If the


Abhidharmists simply thought of “persons” (pudgala/puggala) as conventional constructs in opposition to dharmas, the ultimately realities, how could there be so many “Abhidharmaexpositions of persons (as discussed above) apart from those of dharmas, which alone were perceived as real and should be the proper subject matter for the Abhidharma? Moreover, as demonstrated above, the three items “person whose mind is like a diamond”, etc. in the Anguttara Nikdya were, as expected, “depersonalized” in the Abhidhamma texts of two different schools, namely the Dhammasahgani and the Samgltiparyaya. But why did the Puggala­pannatti, also an Abhidhamma text, fail to depersonalize those same items in the Anguttara Nikdya?


Can “Persons” (puggala) be Subject Matter Appropriate for the Abhidhamma?

The matika of the Puggalapannatti consists of the following six designations or descriptions (cha pahhattiyo)'.


1. designation of aggregates (khandha-pahhattl) 2. designation of bases (ayatana-pahhatti) 3. designation of elements (dhatu-panhatti) 4. designation of truths (sacca-pahhatti) 5. designation of faculties (indriya-pahhatti) 6. designation of persons (puggala-pahhatti)


According to Kimura (1968, pp. 70, 82), this list represents the southern, or Theravada, classification of the Abhidhamma. While the last designation is expounded in the Puggalapannatti, the first five designations relating to dhammas are treated in the Pibhahga. As mentioned above, the Puggalapannatti and the Vibhahga are probably the earliest of the seven canonical Abhidhamma works in Pali. It is likely that these two texts were meant to be complementary to each other, and therefore persons and dhammas may have enjoyed equal status at the incipient stage of the Abhidhamma. However, Nyanatiloka (1957, p. 57) questions whether the Puggalapannatti qualifies as an Abhidhamma text: This smallest of the seven Abhidhamma books appears to be somewhat out of place in the Abhidhamma Pitaka, as shown even by its title “Description of Individuals”. For it is one of the main characteristics of the Abhidhamma that it does not employ conventional concepts like “individual” (puggala), etc., but deals only with ultimates, or realities in the “highest sense” (paramattha- dhamma). i.e. the mental and material phenomena, and their classifications into groups (khandha). bases, elements, etc. This treatise, however, in accordance with its subject-matter, is written in the conventional language as used in the Sutta-Pitaka.


In a similar vein, Gethin (1998, p. 209) regards the Abhidharma as an attempt to give a systematic and exhaustive account of the world in terms of its constituent physical and mental events, which are known as dharmas, and “ultimately dharmas are all that there is” while “a person is analysed by Abhidharma as consisting of innumerable dharmas”. Nyanaponika (1998, p. 5) also says that in the Abhidharma such sutta terminology as “persons” is replaced by a more precise terminology, which accords with the “impersonalnature of actuality. Therefore, a clear distinction can be drawn between puggala (person) and dhammas. While dhammas are “realities” in accord with the “impersonalnature of actuality, a person (puggala) is just a “conventional concept” or a composite built from innumerable constituent elements or dhammas. The conventional terminologyperson” is used only in the suttas; it is not employed in the Abhidhamma, which is devoted to the exposition of dhammas. Consequently, there appears a dichotomy between persons and dhammas in relation to the way such terminology is used in the Sutta Pitaka and the Abhidhamma Pitaka.


As mentioned above, Nyanatiloka holds that while the Sutta Pitaka employs “conventionalconcepts such as “person” (puggala), the Abhidhamma deals only with “ultimates”, or “realities in the highest sense”, his rendering of paramattha- dhamma. In other words, dhammas (realities) in the highest sense should be distinguished from puggala (person), which exists only in the conventional sense. In this context, we should note that, as Gethin (1998, pp. 207f.) points out, some of the Buddha’s teachings are said to be expressed in conventional terms (samvrti/ sammuti) while others are expressed in ultimate terms (paramdrtha/paramattha), and that according to the later tradition, the sutta/sutra collections contain teachings of both kinds whereas the Abhidharma is “an attempt to give a comprehensive statement of the Buddha’s teachings exclusively in ultimate terms”. Thus the dichotomy between persons and dhammas can be seen as a conventional-ultimate dichotomy.


This dichotomy, however, seems to contradict the aforementioned fact that the Puggalapannatti begins with a matika composed of the six designations, including both dhammas and persons. In addition, Mizuno (1997, p. 262) points out that many types of persons explicated in the Puggalapannatti correspond to those discussed in the Samgitiparyaya (T 15 36), a Sarvastivadin Abhidharma work, and the *Pudgala Varga Ahh (Chapter on Persons) of the *Sariputra-abhidharma


(Shelifu apitan lun, T 1548), probably belonging to the Dharmaguptaka school. Therefore, apart from dhammas, the subject matter of “persons” is indeed among the concerns of the Abhidharma of various schools. If the Puggalapannatti, along with those pudgala-reAaXeA parts of the Samgitiparyaya and of the *Sariputra-abhidh- arma, is regarded as an addition to the “Abhidharma proper”, we can certainly assume that the Abhidharma is concerned solely with dhammas as opposed to persons. But it is not beyond doubt that such person-related portions of the Abhidharma literature can be set aside in this way. Moreover, whether the conception of persons and that of dhammas are categorically different is a crucial question that requires further clarification.


The Dhammasahgani. a canonical Abhidhamma text of the Theravada, does not appear to uphold that dhammas are ultimate realities as against conventional constructs like persons. The title of this text means “compendium of dhammas” The text affirms that “all dhammas are ways of designation”, that “all dhammas are ways of interpretation” and that “all dhammas are ways of expression”. While definingpannatti (designation), nirutti (interpretation) and adhivacana (expression), the Dhammasahgani in each case enumerates a long list of words as follows:


y<7 tesam tesam dhammcmam sahkha (enumeration) samanna (appellation) pannatti (designation) vohdro (parlance) namam (name) namakammam (name giving) namadheyyam (name assigning) nirutti (interpretation) vyahjanam (wording) abhilapo (talk)—ime dhamma adhivacana/nirutti/pahhattiP1


In light of this passage, when the Dhammasahgani describes all dhammas as “ways of designation, ways of interpretation and ways of expression”, the text cannot but mean that all dhammas are just conventional (sammuti) constructs rather than ultimate (paramaiiha) realities. The commentary on the Dhammasahgani explains pannatti in this context (ways of designation) thus: “Making [one and the same idea] known in various ways, such as ‘takka, vitakka, sahkappa', is calledpannatti (designation)”, thereby suggesting that the word pannatti in this context denotes conventional usage of language or concepts. Incidentally, among the above list of words, pannatti, samanna, vohara and nirutti already appear together in the Potthapada Sutta (DN 9),61 where the Buddha uses these words to indicate that the things he just mentions are merely designations in common use in the world Uoka- panhatti, etc.). Kalupahana (1986, p. 340) suggests that by this sutta passage the Buddha intended to take samvrti (P. sammuti, convention) and prajnapti (P. pannatti, designation) as synonyms.


Although the above passage in the Dhammasahgani perhaps suffices to illustrate the point, it is worthwhile to compare this passage with the following passage in the Siksasamuccaya by Santideva (early eighth century CE): amipalabhyamanesu sarvadharmesu katamo ’tra buddhah |... sunyam hi riipam riipena yavad vijhanam || pe || yavad eva vyavaharamatram etat | ndmadheyamatram samketamatram samvrtimatram prajhaptimatram I (Since all dharmas are not to be obtained, what is Buddha? ... For form is empty of form as far as consciousness [is empty of consciousness], and so on [the same is said of the five aggregates]. All this is just parlance, just name assigning, just agreement, just convention, just designation.)


Among this list of five Sanskrit words each combined with mdtra (just), three words also have Pali counterparts in the above long list of words in the Dhammasahgani'. vyavahdra = voharo, namadheya = namadheyyam. prajnapti = pahhatti.


These five words, each combined with mdtra, are apparently enumerated here as synonyms. Consequently, prajnapti (pannatti, designation) is synonymous with samvrti (sammuti, convention) as well as with the other three words in the five- numbered list of synonyms in the Siksasamuccaya. It would not be farfetched to speculate that this Mahayana text and the Dhammasahgani draw on certain Abhidharma material in common, which associates “all dharmas” with “parlance” (vyavahara/vohara), “designation” (prajhapti/pahhatti). etc. to indicate that dharmas are conceptual constructs in conventional terms (samvrti/sammuti) rather than realities in the ultimate sense (paramartha/paramatthci). Kalupahana (1992, p. 145) articulates a similar view on the Abhidhamma:


If the intention of the discourses [i.e. vw/tas] in analyzing the human personality into five aggregates was merely to indicate the absence of a metaphysical agent (anatta) and not to discover a set of irreducible elements called “ultimate realities,” there seems to be no justification for the various psychological and physical items [i.e. dhammas] listed in the canonical Abhidhamma texts (both in Pali and in Sanskrit) to be considered ultimate realities.


He goes on to argue that the Puggalapahhatti, while explaining the conceptions relating to a “person” (puggala), adopts “the contextual analysis of the conceptions of aggregates and so forth”, i.e. dhammas, “in the previous books of the Abhidhamma” (ibid., p. 150). But the matter could be the other way round since the Puggalapahhatti presumably belongs to the earliest stratum of the Pali Abhidhamma as mentioned above. In any case, Kalupahana is probably right in suggesting that the Abhidhamma treats both puggalas and dhammas as context- dependent, thereby dissolving the dichotomy between persons and dhammas which is linked to the distinction between convention and ultimate realities as elaborated in the commentarial tradition. As Ronkin (2010, p. 356) suggests, in the Pali tradition it is the commentaries, including the commentary to the Dhammasahgani, that first draw metaphysical conclusions with regard to the reality of dhammas', the commentaries contend that “there is no being or person apart from dhammas” in order to “refute the rival Puggalavada position of the reality of the person” (Dhs-a 155, etc.), and that “a dhamma arises as a present, ultimate reality, and its sabhava attests to its actual existence as such” (Dhs-a 45, etc.).


As mentioned above, the Mahayana criticizes the Abhidharma for its failure to understand the “absence of essence in dharmas”, which were considered by the Abhidharma to be things that really, ultimately exist. This critique is intended primarily for the Sarvastivadin Abhidharma rather than the Abhidharma in general. The Sarvastivadins maintain that all (sarva) dharmas exist (asti) as real entities (dravyatas). whether past, present, or future, and are defined by a fixed, intrinsic nature (svabhdva)? but this ontological position is not accepted by some other schools, including the Theravada during the canonical period. Cousins (1983— 1984, pp. 106f.) notes:


The Theravada does not reify dhammas to anything like the extent found in the Sarvastivadin abhidharma. ... In North India where the Sarvastivadin abhidharma eventually established a commanding position, the term dharma came to be interpreted as a ‘reality’ and given some kind of ontological status as part of a process of reification of Buddhist terms. ... In the South, at least among the Theravadins, dhamma retains its older meaning of a less reified, more experiential kind.


Ronkin (2005. p. 226) also says: “The Theravadins ... do not subscribe to the Sarvastivada metaphysics: first and foremost they do not hold that a dhamma is a dravyasat [referring back to ‘primary existent’] and do not use the category of sabhava as an ontological determinant of primary existence—at least not until late into the post-canonical period.”


In view of the foregoing discussion, the notion of persons and that of dhammas cannot be categorically differentiated from the perspective of the Abhidharma in general. Just like persons, dhammas exist as experiential events rather than ontological entities according to at least the Theravadin Abhidhamma system of thought as discussed above, although the post-canonical tradition interprets dhammas as ultimate realities and this is followed by many scholars. In this sense there is no big difference between the two categories. Nor is there a wide gap between the Sutta and Abhidhamma literature in terms of how “persons” are treated, despite what the later tradition holds. This has been shown to be corroborated by several facts about the Puggalapahhatti. and the Anguttara Nikaya. The listings and interpretations of “persons” form a significant portion of the Anguttara Nikaya and of the Abhidhamma literature. We have seen above that several suttas on persons (puggala) in the Anguttara Nikaya appear to be proto-Abhidhamma. The Anguttara Nikaya contains a sizable amount of such Abhidhamma material in an eclectic style, embracing a wide variety of divergent Abhidhamma interpretations. By contrast, the self-avowedly Abhidharma literature of the different schools represents the collections of scholastic thoughts which were standardized depending on the schools or the texts themselves.


It is undeniable that the ultimate concern of Buddhism is the welfare of people. The Buddha’s teaching is meant to help or liberate each person as a whole rather than each of the individual dhammas. Even an adequate exposition of Buddhist ethics also entails at least a certain treatment of the person as a whole. The Vijhdnakaya, a canonical Abhidharma text of the Sarvastivadins, presents a debate between the “Personalist” (pudgalavadin) and the “Voidist” (sunyatavadin, follower of the emptiness teaching). The debate is aptly outlined by Cousins (1994, p. 21) thus:


The Personalist asks what is the object of loving-kindness. The Voidist replies that it is the five aggregates given the label of ‘being’. The Personalist, not unreasonably, suggests that this is not in harmony with the suttas which recommend loving-kindness towards living beings rather than aggregates. ... Therefore, although the Abhidharma adopted the methods that attempt to systematize and preserve the Buddha’s teaching (Dharma) by collecting all possible doctrinal concepts or elements, i.e. dharmas, to be found in his sermons, it could not evade the topic of “persons” that is also essential to the Buddha’s teaching. Therefore, in spite of the “depersonalizing” tendencies perceptible in some Abhidharma works, three different schools unanimously devote part of their Abhidharma to the subject of “persons” as discussed above. In his Philosophy and Psychology in the Abhidharma, Guenther (1974, p. 213) comments: “The Path in its four stages is essentially meant to overcome unhealthy attitudes and to produce a certain type of man in whom unhealthy attitudes can no longer operate.” It is therefore appropriate for the Abhidharma to designate and interpret the various spiritual types of persons for the sake of illuminating Buddhism’s aim to transform a person into an arahant and its skilful means in designating spiritual stages which a person can go through to achieve this aim. This is not tantamount to reifying “persons”, which are still treated as conventional constructs no less than dhammas are.


Conclusion


According to a widespread opinion based on the tradition, “person” (puggala/ pudgala) is a “conventional concept” used only in the suttas!Sutras; it is not employed in the Abhidhamma/Abhidharma, which interprets the Buddha’s teaching exclusively in terms of “ultimate realities”, i.e. dhammas!dharmas. This results in a dichotomy between persons and dhammas, which can be seen as a conventional- ultimate dichotomy. The Abhidharma tendency to “depersonalize” is discernible in how two Abhidharma texts interpret a list of persons in a sutta of the Anguttara Nikdya. Although the Abhidharma adopted the methods that attempt to systematize the Buddha’s teaching (Dharma) by collecting all possible doctrinal elements, i.e. dharmas, to be found in his sermons, it could not evade the topic of “persons” that is also essential to the Buddha’s teaching.

There are indications that “persons”, just like dhammas, can be subject matter appropriate for the Abhidhamma. Three different schools devote part of their Abhidharma to the subject of “persons”, notably the Theravadins’ Puggalapannatti, which is closely connected with the Anguttara Nikdya. The mdtika of the Puggalapannatti consists of six designations or descriptions (pahhatti). The last one is the “designation of persons”, which is expounded in the Puggalapannatti. The first five designations, which relate to dhammas, are treated in the Vibhahga. The Puggalapannatti and the Vibhahga are probably the earliest of the seven canonical Theravadin Abhidhamma works, and were apparently meant to be complementary to each other. Therefore persons and dhammas may have enjoyed equal status at the incipient stage of the Abhidhamma. That dhammas are reckoned as conventional constructs rather than ultimate realities is implicit in the Dhammasahgani, a canonical Abhidhamma text of the Theravada. Dhammas are reified by the Sarvastivadin Abhidharma and the Theravadin commentaries, but not by the Abhidharma in general.


Just like persons, dhammas exist as experiential events rather than ontological entities, at least according to the Theravadin Abhidhamma. Thus, there is no big difference between the two categories. Nor is there a wide gap between the Sutta and Abhidhamma literature in terms of how “persons” are dealt with, despite what the later tradition holds. This is corroborated by several facts about the Puggalapannatti and the Anguttara Nikdya. Several suttas on persons (puggala) in the Anguttara Nikdya appear to be proto-Abhidhamma. The Anguttara Nikdya contains a significant amount of such Abhidhamma material in an eclectic style, embracing a wide variety of Abhidhamma interpretations. The divergent definitions of four kinds of ascetics in a series of suttas of the Anguttara Nikdya and the Puggalapannatti represent the outcome of Abhidhamma debates on how to define the items and arrange them in numerical sequence. A series of ten suttas in the Anguttara Nikdya bluntly adopt the Abhidhamma hermeneutic approach, i.e. nippariyayena, whereby three types of persons are rendered just nominally different. Therefore, various kinds of “persons” are seen as conventionally designated rather than really existing in accordance with the non-essentialist perspective of persons in the Abhidhamma. It is no less appropriate for the Abhidhamma to designate and interpret various types of persons than to treat dhammas also as conventional constructs. The Abhidhamma has to accommodate the “conventional” fact that the Buddha’s teaching is meant to help or liberate each person as a whole rather than each of the individual dhammas.


Acknowledgments A preliminary version of this paper entitled “The Ahguttara Nikdya and Abhidharma” was presented at the Conference on “From Abhidhamma to Abhidharma” at Ghent University, Belgium in July 2013. Two participants, Professor Collett Cox and Professor Johannes Bronkhorst, generously gave me advice, for which I am very grateful. My special thanks are due to Dr. Roderick S. Bucknell, who read an earlier draft of this paper, offered valuable suggestions and improved the English. I would like to thank the two reviewers for their helpful comments and Taiwan's Ministry of Science and Technology for the funding (NSC 101-2410-H-155-027-MY3).


Abbreviations


References to Pali texts are to the Pali Text Society editions.


AN Ahguttara Nikaya CBETA CBETA Chinese Electronic Tripitaka Collection Version April 2010. Taipei: Chinese Buddhist Electronic Text Association CSCD Chattha Sangdvana CD-ROM Version 3. Igatpuri: Vipassana Research Institute DA Dirgha Agama Chang ahanjing Dhs Dhammasangani Dhs-a Atthasdlini (Commentary on the Dhammasangani} DN Digha Nikaya EA Ekottarika Agama Zengyi ahanjing FGD Foguang Da Cidian (Foguang Dictionary). ed. Ciyi Kaohsiung: ftjKSji, 1988 MA Madhyama Agama Zhong ahanjing MN Majjhima Nikdya Mp Manorathapiiram (Ahguttara-Nikdyatthakathd. Commentary on the AN) P. Pali PED The Pali Text Society’s Pali-English Dictionary, ed. T.W. Rhys Davids and William Stede. London: Pali Text Society, reprinted 1986. (First published 1921-1925) Pp Puggalapahhatti SA Samyukta Agama Za ahanjing SJD (A Sanskrit-Japanese Dictionary with Equivalents in Chinese Translation), ed. Unrai Wogihara 4C revised edition. Tokyo: 1986 Skt. Sanskrit SN Samyutta Nikdya T Taisho Shinshu Daizokyo Hl AWUzr (Cited from CBETA)


References


English titles in parentheses are my translations. Anacker, S. (2005). Seven works ofVasubandhu: The Buddhist Psychological Doctor (revised ed.). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass (First published 1984k Apple, J. (2004). Twenty varieties of the Samgha: A typology of noble beings (Arya) in Indo-Tibetan scholasticism (Part II). Journal of Indian Philosophy 32(2-3), 211-279. Bendall, C. (Ed.). (1902). (jikshdsamuccaya: A Compendium of Buddhistic Teaching. St. Petersburg: Commissionnaires de l’Academie Imperiale des Sciences. Bendall, C., & Rouse, W. H. D. (Tr.). (1971k Siksd Samuccaya: A compendium of Buddhist Doctrine (2nd ed.). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass (First edition 1922. London). Bodhi, B. (2007). The Susima-sutta and the wisdom-liberated Arahant. Journal of the Pali Text Society, 24, 51-75. Bodhi, B. (Tr.) (2012). The numerical discourses of the Buddha'. A translation of the Ahguttara Nikdya. Boston: Wisdom Publications. Bronkhorst, J. (1985). Dharma and Abhidharma. Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, 48 (2), 305-320. Bronkhorst, J. (2004). Some uses of dharma in classical Indian Philosophy. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 32(5-6), 733-750. Bucknell, R. S., & Stuart-Fox, M. (1993). The Twilight language: Explorations in Buddhist meditation and symbolism. Surrey: Curzon Press. Buswell, Jr., R. E., & Lopez, Jr., D. S. (Eds.). (2014). The Princeton dictionary of Buddhism. Princeton/ Oxford: Princeton University Press. Conze, E. (1962). Buddhist thought in India: Three phases of Buddhist philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. Cousins, L. S. (1983). Pali oral literature. In P. Denwood & A. Piatigorsky (Eds.), Buddhist studies: Ancient and modern (pp. 1-11). London: Curzon Press. Cousins, L. S. (1983-1984). Nibbana and Abhidhamma. Buddhist Studies Review, 7(2), 95-109. Cousins, L. S. (1994). Person and self. Buddhism into the year 2000: International conference proceedings (pp. 15-31). Bangkok/Los Angeles: Dhammakaya Foundation. Cox, C. (1992). The unbroken treatise: Scripture and argument in early Buddhist scholasticism. In M. A. Williams, et al. (Eds.), Innovation in religious traditions: Essays in the interpretation of religious change (pp. 143-189). Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter. Cox, Collett. (1995). Disputed Dharmas: Early Buddhist theories on existence: An annotated translation of the section on factors dissociated from thought from Sahghabhadra’s Nydydnusdra. Tokyo: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies. Cox, C. (2004). From category to ontology: The changing role of Dharma in Sarvastivada Abhidharma. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 32(5-6), 543-597. Crosby, K., & Skilton, A. (Tr.) (1995). Sdntideva: The Bodhicarydvatdra. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dessein, B. (2003). Sautrantika and the Hrdaya treatises. Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies, 26(1), 287-319. Dhammajoti, K. L. (2005). Abhidharma and Upadesa. Journal of the Centre for Buddhist Studies, Sri Lanka, 3, 112-123. Edgerton, F. (1953). Buddhist hybrid Sanskrit grammar and dictionary, Vol II: Dictionary. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass (Reprint 1993). Enomoto, F. (1984a). gft— t —(The Development of the Agamas of the Sarvastivada Lineage: Concerning the Madhyama Agama and the Samyukta Agama). Ep SV Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies, 32(2), 1073-1070. Enomoto, F. (1984b). |5B) VlV. (Formation of the Agama Texts). Journal of the Oriental Studies, 23(1), 93-108. Frauwallner, E. (1995). Studies in Abhidharma literature and the origins of Buddhist philosophical systems (S. F. Kidd, Trans., German). Albany: State University of New York Press. Gethin, R. (1998). The foundations of Buddhism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gethin, R. (2001). The Buddhist path to awakening (2nd cd.). Oxford: Oneworld Publications (First published by E. J. Brill, 1992). Gombrich, R. (2009). What the Buddha thought. London: Equinox. Guenther, H. V. (1974). Philosophy and psychology in the Abhidharma (2nd revised ed.). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. Hallisey, C. (2007). Abhidharma. In D. Keown & C. S. Prebish (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Buddhism (pp. 1- 3). London/New York: Routledge. Hamilton, S. (2000). Early Buddhism: A new approach. Surrey: Curzon Press. Harvey, P. (2013a). An introduction to Buddhism: Teachings, history and practices (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Harvey. P. (2013b). The Sangha of Noble Savakas. with particular reference to their trainee member, the person ‘practising for the realization of the stream-entry-fruit’. Buddhist Studies Review, 30(1), 3-70. Hiraoka, S. (2000). The Sectarian affiliation of two Chinese Samyuktagamas. Ep(g^-®^^y7 jfv. Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies, 49(1), 506 500.Hiraoka. S. (2003). J St J ’RJWhPwWiS (The Samyukta Agama and the Vinaya of the Sarvastivada). Ep S IP WfHff 3c Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies, 51(2). 818-813. Kalupahana, D. J. (1986). Ndgarjuna: The philosophy of the middle way. Albany: State University of New York Press. Kalupahana, D. J. (1992). A history of Buddhist philosophy: Continuities and discontinuities. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. Kato, J. JpSOtfli (1989). ,Uip|0W3l Etude sur les Sautrantika. Tokyo: Shunju-sha. Kimura, T. vfcfcIWJf (1968). TfcfclWJUisIfc MESS W JW tre 01) if 3c (A study of the Ahhidharma Treatises. Vol. 4 of Kimura Taiken Zenshii). Tokyo: lA/SWiiWJ. Kuan, T. (2008). Mindfulness in early Buddhism: New approaches through psychology- and textual Analysis of Pali, Chinese and Sanskrit sources. London/New York: Routledge. Kuan, T. (2013a). The Pavarana Sutta and “liberation in both ways” as against “liberation by wisdom”. Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, 76(1), 49-73. Kuan, T. (2013b). Legends and transcendence: Sectarian affiliations of the Ekottarika Agama in Chinese Translation. Journal of the American Oriental Society, 733(4), 607-634. Kumoi, S. (1963). Agama (2). In G. P. Malalasekera (Ed.), Encyclopaedia of Buddhism (Vol. I. fasc. 2. pp. 244-248). Government of Ceylon. Lamotte, E. (1988). History of Indian buddhism: From the origins to the Saka Era. translated from the French by Sara Webb-Boin. Louvain: Peeters Press. Law, B. C. (1933). A history of Pali literature. Varanasi: Indica Books (this edition 2000). Lii. C. (1963). Agama (1). In G. P. Malalasekera (Ed.), Encyclopaedia of Buddhism (Vol. I. fasc. 2. pp. 241-244). Government of Ceylon. Mating Tin. P. (Tr.). (1976). The expositor: Buddhaghosa’s commentary on the Dhammasahgam the first book of the Abhidhamma Pitaka. edited and revised by Mrs. Rhys Davids. London: Pali Text Society (First published, 1920). Mayeda. E. lijl 11(1964). A history of the formation of original Buddhist texts .feinftSSIfttOEKai. ftMU. Tokyo: Sankibo-Busshorin Publishing Co., Ltd. Mizuno. K. zKJSJIIA.tt: (1966). t&ISifre (A O L > T (On the Sariputra-abhidharma). In f^gESSre(Ed.), (Indian and Buddhist Studies: Festschrift on the Occasion of Dr. Kanakura’s 70th birthday) (pp. 109-134). Kyoto: Mizuno. K. 7KSJPA7E (1996). -fA 3l (A study of Buddhist literature). Tokyo: Shunju-sha. Mizuno. K. 7KSJPA7E (1997). 0 «WW3E (A study of the Pali Abhidhamma treatises). Tokyo: Shunju-sha. Morris. R. (Ed.). (1883). Puggala-pannatti. combined reprint with corrections in 1972. London: Pali Text Society. Nanamoli. B.. & Bodhi. B. (Tr.). (2001). The middle length discourses of the Buddha (revised ed.). Oxford: Pali Text Society. Norman, K. R. (1983). Pali literature: Including the Canonical literature in Prakrit and Sanskrit of All the Hinayana Schools of Buddhism. Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz. Nyanaponika, T. (1998). Abhidhamma Studies, 4th edition, revised and enlarged. Kandy: Buddhist Publication Society (1st edition 1949, Colombo: Frewin & Co. Ltd.). Nyanatiloka, M. (1957). Guide through the Abhidhamma-Pitaka: Being a synopsis of the philosophical collection belonging to the Buddhist Pali canon. Kandy: Buddhist Publication Society. Nyanatiloka, M. (1970). Buddhist dictionary: Manual of Buddhist terms and doctrines Ord revised and enlarged ed.). Singapore: Singapore Buddhist Meditation Centre. Oberlies, T. (2003). Ein bibliographischer Uberblick fiber die kanonischen Texte der Sravakayana- Schulen des Buddhismus. Wiener Zeitschrift fur die Kunde Sudasiens, 47. 37-84. Pradhan, P. (Ed.). (1967). Abhidharma-kosabhdsya. Patna: K. P. Jayaswal Research Institute. Reat, N. R. (1996). The historical Buddha and his teachings. In K. Potter (Ed.). Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. VII: Abhidharma Buddhism to 150 A.D (pp. 3-57). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. Rhys Davids, T. W. (1903). Buddhist India. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass (Indian reprint, 1993). Ronkin, N. (2005). Early Buddhist metaphysics: The making of a philosophical tradition. London/New York: RoutledgeCurzon. Ronkin. N. (2010). From the Buddha’s teaching to the Abhidhamma. Revue internationale dephilosophie, 3(253), 341-365. Thich Minh Chau, B. (1991). The Chinese Madhyama Agama and the Pali Majjhima Nikdya. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. Ui, H. (1965). EpjJ’g^flf^E IS— (A study of Indian philosophy, Vol. II). Tokyo: Walshe. M. (Tr.). (1995). The long discourses of the Buddha. Boston: Wisdom Publications (First published 1987). Watanabe. F. (1983). Philosophy and its development in the Nikdyas and Abhidhamma. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. Willemen, C. (2008). KumarajTva’s ‘explanatory discourse’ about Abhidharmic literature. Journal of the International College for Postgraduate Buddhist Studies, 12, 37-83. Willemen, C., Dessein, B., & Cox, C. (1998). Sarvdstivdda Buddhist Scholasticism. Leiden/New York/ Koln: Brill. Williams, P. (1981). On the Abhidharma ontology. Journal of Indian Philosophy. 9(3). 227-257. Williams, P. (2009). Mahayana Buddhism: The doctrinal foundations (2nd ed.). London/New York: Routledge. Williams, P., & Tribe, A. (2000). Buddhist thought: A complete introduction to the Indian tradition. London/New York: Routledge. Wogihara, U. (Tr.). (1935). (Pb/. 17 of the Southern Tripitaka: Texts of the Ahguttara Nikaya, I). Tokyo: Yinshun E|UII (1968). (A Study of the Sastras and the Sastrakaras principally of the Sarvdstivdda School). Taipei: Yinshun E|UII (1981). (The origins and development of early Mahayana Buddhism). Taipei: Yinshun EIUH (1994). (Compilation of the original Buddhist scriptures) (3rd revised ed.). Taipei: jZWJHjKOi.



Source