Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Gradual Enlightenment, Sudden Enlightenment and Empiricism"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
Line 1: Line 1:
[[File:Zh 9665.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
+
[[File:Zh 9665.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
 
  By [[Ivan Strenski]]
 
  By [[Ivan Strenski]]
 
[[Ivan Strenski]] is an associate {{Wiki|professor}} in the [[Department of Religious Studies, Connecticut|College]], [[New London]], {{Wiki|Connecticut}}.
 
[[Ivan Strenski]] is an associate {{Wiki|professor}} in the [[Department of Religious Studies, Connecticut|College]], [[New London]], {{Wiki|Connecticut}}.
  
Note. This article was first read in another version at the [[International History of Religious Congress]], August. 1975 at the {{Wiki|University of Lancaster}}, Lancaster, {{Wiki|England}}. All references to the [[life]] [[Pali Canon]] are given in standard [[form]] and are quoted from the {{Wiki|translations}} of I. B. Horner, [[Middle Length Sayings]], 3 volumes ({{Wiki|London}}: Luzuc, 1959. 1957, 1954).
+
Note. This article was first read in another version at the [[International History of Religious Congress]], August. 1975 at the {{Wiki|University of Lancaster}}, [[Lancaster]], {{Wiki|England}}. All references to the [[life]] [[Pali Canon]] are given in standard [[form]] and are quoted from the {{Wiki|translations}} of I. B. Horner, [[Middle Length Sayings]], 3 volumes ({{Wiki|London}}: Luzuc, 1959. 1957, 1954).
  
 
[[Philosophy]] {{Wiki|East}} and {{Wiki|West}}
 
[[Philosophy]] {{Wiki|East}} and {{Wiki|West}}
Line 13: Line 21:
 
[[File:Zenart3 4 94.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Zenart3 4 94.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    By way of innovation, I want to see how {{Wiki|epistemological}} perspectives might [[illuminate]] the shape of [[Buddhist]] attitudes toward the [[gradual]] or sudden [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]]. Using a modified and rather informal structuralism, I want to compare the structures of institutionalized theories of [[knowledge]] with the structures of [[meditational]] practices and [[beliefs]] to see whether one might understand the {{Wiki|characteristics}} of these practices and [[beliefs]] in terms of their underlying {{Wiki|epistemological}} {{Wiki|structure}}. I want to argue that one can plot the salient {{Wiki|characteristics}} of [[meditational]] practices—here, whether [[enlightenment]] occurs gradually or suddenly—as symptoms of the presupposed {{Wiki|structure}} of their institutionalized {{Wiki|theory}} of [[knowledge]].
+
By way of innovation, I want to see how {{Wiki|epistemological}} perspectives might [[illuminate]] the shape of [[Buddhist]] attitudes toward the [[gradual]] or sudden [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]]. Using a modified and rather informal structuralism, I want to compare the structures of institutionalized theories of [[knowledge]] with the structures of [[meditational]] practices and [[beliefs]] to see whether one might understand the {{Wiki|characteristics}} of these practices and [[beliefs]] in terms of their underlying {{Wiki|epistemological}} {{Wiki|structure}}. I want to argue that one can plot the salient {{Wiki|characteristics}} of [[meditational]] practices—here, whether [[enlightenment]] occurs gradually or suddenly—as symptoms of the presupposed {{Wiki|structure}} of their institutionalized {{Wiki|theory}} of [[knowledge]].
 
But before embarking on the critical study of [[meditational]] practices we ought to first clarify just what the [[Buddhists]] themselves [[thought]] about [[gradual]] and [[sudden enlightenment]], and how they [[conceived]] the [[relation]] of these aspects of [[meditational]] practice to their [[beliefs]] about the acquisition of [[knowledge]].
 
But before embarking on the critical study of [[meditational]] practices we ought to first clarify just what the [[Buddhists]] themselves [[thought]] about [[gradual]] and [[sudden enlightenment]], and how they [[conceived]] the [[relation]] of these aspects of [[meditational]] practice to their [[beliefs]] about the acquisition of [[knowledge]].
 
[[File:Zen478l.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Zen478l.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
I. APPROACHES TO THE PROBLEM OF GRADUAL AND [[SUDDEN ENLIGHTENMENT]]: [[NATURALISM]] AND [[PHENOMENOLOGY]]
+
 
 +
 
 +
==I. Approaches To The Problem Of [[Gradual Enlightenment]] And [[Sudden Enlightenment]]: [[Naturalism]] And [[Phenomenology]]==
 +
 
 +
 
  
 
[[File:Zen-Bu4hism.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Zen-Bu4hism.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
    It is commonplace to read that [[Theravāda Buddhism]] teaches that [[nirvāna]] is [[attained]] gradually and that [[Chan]] or [[Zen Buddhism]] teaches 'sudden' [[enlightenment]]. Little is said about the bases for studying what such [[meditational]] claims mean, and less is said about the [[logical]] [[grammar]] of words as peculiar as '[[gradual]]'. Typically, it is facilely assumed that this problem is merely a {{Wiki|factual}} [[matter]] about {{Wiki|temporal}} duration. On this [[view]], to say [[enlightenment is gradual]]' usually means that it takes a long [[time]] for this [[quasi-mental state]] to occur.  
+
It is commonplace to read that [[Theravāda Buddhism]] teaches that [[nirvāna]] is [[attained]] gradually and that [[Chan]] or [[Zen Buddhism]] teaches 'sudden' [[enlightenment]]. Little is said about the bases for studying what such [[meditational]] claims mean, and less is said about the [[logical]] [[grammar]] of words as peculiar as '[[gradual]]'. Typically, it is facilely assumed that this problem is merely a {{Wiki|factual}} [[matter]] about {{Wiki|temporal}} duration. On this [[view]], to say [[enlightenment is gradual]]' usually means that it takes a long [[time]] for this [[quasi-mental state]] to occur.  
  
Such a claim does not seem [[logically]] different than saying that it took a [[person]] a long [[time]] to get 'dizzy' or 'drunk,' and so on. Now, to put a {{Wiki|factual}} [[stress]] on this [[matter]] should immediately strike anyone familiar with the {{Wiki|pragmatic}} [[attitude]] of (early) [[Buddhism]] as odd. Surely, it must have been unedifying for an early [[Buddhist]] to be concerned with rather speculative matters of fact. Is this just an example of 'corruption' in [[early Buddhism]], analogous to the storied {{Wiki|medieval}} {{Wiki|Christian}} {{Wiki|scholastic}} problem of {{Wiki|angels}} on the head of a pin? What could be the {{Wiki|practical}} salvific value of talk of gradualism in various [[Buddhist]] contexts? What could have been the possible [[interest]] for an early [[Buddhist]] in saying that [[enlightenment]] was to be [[attained]] gradually?
+
Such a claim does not seem [[logically]] different than saying that it took a [[person]] a long [[time]] to get 'dizzy' or 'drunk,' and so on. Now, to put a {{Wiki|factual}} [[stress]] on this [[matter]] should immediately strike anyone familiar with the {{Wiki|pragmatic}} [[attitude]] of (early) [[Buddhism]] as odd. Surely, it must have been unedifying for an early [[Buddhist]] to be concerned with rather speculative matters of fact. Is this just an example of 'corruption' in [[early Buddhism]], analogous to the storied {{Wiki|medieval}} {{Wiki|Christian}} {{Wiki|scholastic}} problem of {{Wiki|angels}} on the head of a pin? What could be the {{Wiki|practical}} salvific value of talk of [[gradualism]] in various [[Buddhist]] contexts? What could have been the possible [[interest]] for an early [[Buddhist]] in saying that [[enlightenment]] was to be [[attained]] gradually?
 
[[File:Xin 9194.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Xin 9194.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    Despite such considerations, [[scholars]] of [[meditation]] have persisted in treating [[meditational]] [[discourses]] as mere descriptive matters of fact. This is true, even though these [[scholars]] disagree implicitly about what counts as a 'fact', or, perhaps more accurately, [[stress]] different [[views]] about what counts as a fact. Basically, two such emphases seem current. As applied to my earlier example of dizziness, one may take the fact of dizziness to be an [[experience]] in which case one might term such an approach '{{Wiki|phenomenological}}.' However, one might [[feel]] required to seek facts in some supposedly underlying [[neurophysiological]] process, in which case one might term such an approach 'naturalist.' Although both naturalist and [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologist]] would agree that {{Wiki|temporal}} duration was crucial to the meaning of '[[gradual]]', they would not agree about the {{Wiki|nature}} of what endured in [[time]].
+
Despite such considerations, [[scholars]] of [[meditation]] have persisted in treating [[meditational]] [[discourses]] as mere descriptive matters of fact. This is true, even though these [[scholars]] disagree implicitly about what counts as a 'fact', or, perhaps more accurately, [[stress]] different [[views]] about what counts as a fact. Basically, two such emphases seem current. As applied to my earlier example of dizziness, one may take the fact of dizziness to be an [[experience]] in which case one might term such an approach '{{Wiki|phenomenological}}.' However, one might [[feel]] required to seek facts in some supposedly underlying [[neurophysiological]] process, in which case one might term such an approach 'naturalist.' Although both naturalist and [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologist]] would agree that {{Wiki|temporal}} duration was crucial to the meaning of '[[gradual]]', they would not agree about the {{Wiki|nature}} of what endured in [[time]].
 
[[File:X145.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:X145.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    I am convinced both these approaches {{Wiki|emphasize}} the wrong things about [[Buddhist]] [[gradualism]]—for whatever different [[reasons]]. Not only does the [[Pali Canon]] tell a more complete story, but another [[order]] of {{Wiki|analysis}} of the texts is required. Basically, I believe those tempted by either of these two approaches mistake a norm for a [[matter]] of fact, and that where a fact may be indicated, it tends more often to be a spatial fact, rather than a {{Wiki|temporal}} one. Although the {{Wiki|temporal}} and the {{Wiki|factual}} question may not be without [[interest]], it does not seem to be the chief [[concern]] of the [[Pali]] [[Suttas]]. Here, the [[Buddha]] recommends a particular mode of life—an issue which reads far [[beyond]] any such unedifying {{Wiki|factual}} [[matter]] of the {{Wiki|speed}} of the [[attainment]] of [[nirvāna]].
+
I am convinced both these approaches {{Wiki|emphasize}} the wrong things about [[Buddhist]] [[gradualism]]—for whatever different [[reasons]]. Not only does the [[Pali Canon]] tell a more complete story, but another [[order]] of {{Wiki|analysis}} of the texts is required. Basically, I believe those tempted by either of these two approaches mistake a norm for a [[matter]] of fact, and that where a fact may be indicated, it tends more often to be a spatial fact, rather than a {{Wiki|temporal}} one. Although the {{Wiki|temporal}} and the {{Wiki|factual}} question may not be without [[interest]], it does not seem to be the chief [[concern]] of the [[Pali]] [[Suttas]]. Here, the [[Buddha]] recommends a particular mode of life—an issue which reads far [[beyond]] any such unedifying {{Wiki|factual}} [[matter]] of the {{Wiki|speed}} of the [[attainment]] of [[nirvāna]].
 
[[File:Tr-high-go chonb.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Tr-high-go chonb.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    Taking the {{Wiki|temporal}} point first, it would seem important to note that the term '[[gradual]]' is ordinarily used in two quite different ways: Insofar as '[[gradual]]' is used factually, it may indeed mean something {{Wiki|temporal}}, like 'slow.' But, it may also mean 'graded.' It may be a {{Wiki|temporal}} [[word]] just as easily as it may be a spatial one. The same is true of the [[Pali]] term [[anupubba]], as I shall show in the [[discussion]] of the [[Pali Canon's]] [[view]] of "[[gradual enlightenment]]. Thus, "[[gradual]]' is like other words that play across the {{Wiki|temporal}} and spatial [[conditions]] of [[experience]]. Does a 'dashing' man need to be fleet of foot? Does a 'snappy' dresser need to be quick with buttons and zippers?  
+
Taking the {{Wiki|temporal}} point first, it would seem important to note that the term '[[gradual]]' is ordinarily used in two quite different ways: Insofar as '[[gradual]]' is used factually, it may indeed mean something {{Wiki|temporal}}, like 'slow.' But, it may also mean 'graded.' It may be a {{Wiki|temporal}} [[word]] just as easily as it may be a spatial one. The same is true of the [[Pali]] term [[anupubba]], as I shall show in the [[discussion]] of the [[Pali Canon's]] [[view]] of "[[gradual enlightenment]]. Thus, "[[gradual]]' is like other words that play across the {{Wiki|temporal}} and spatial [[conditions]] of [[experience]]. Does a 'dashing' man need to be fleet of foot? Does a 'snappy' dresser need to be quick with buttons and zippers?  
  
Although spatial and {{Wiki|temporal}} uses of '[[gradual]]' often coincide, they need not do so. Doing something gradually—by degrees, in stages—may take less [[time]] than trying to do the same task at one go. [[Gradual]] methods are, indeed, often devised to save time—say, in building a house, taming a [[horse]], [[writing]] a [[book]], or [[attaining]] [[nirvāna]]—especially when contrasted to available alternatives in achieving the same sophisticated result. Perhaps, part of the [[reason]] this spatial [[sense]] of '[[gradual]]' escapes our [[attention]] may have something to do with the fact that the ordinary {{Wiki|English}} contrast [[word]], 'sudden,' does not seem to have a spatial [[sense]] at all. It only seems to have {{Wiki|temporal}} uses, and thus by {{Wiki|analogy}}, we think of '[[gradual]]' in the same way. [[Attention]] to the contexts of the [[discourses]] on gradualism tells another story.
+
Although spatial and {{Wiki|temporal}} uses of '[[gradual]]' often coincide, they need not do so. Doing something gradually—by degrees, in stages—may take less [[time]] than trying to do the same task at one go. [[Gradual]] methods are, indeed, often devised to save time—say, in building a house, taming a [[horse]], [[writing]] a [[book]], or [[attaining]] [[nirvāna]]—especially when contrasted to available alternatives in achieving the same sophisticated result. Perhaps, part of the [[reason]] this spatial [[sense]] of '[[gradual]]' escapes our [[attention]] may have something to do with the fact that the ordinary {{Wiki|English}} contrast [[word]], 'sudden,' does not seem to have a spatial [[sense]] at all. It only seems to have {{Wiki|temporal}} uses, and thus by {{Wiki|analogy}}, we think of '[[gradual]]' in the same way. [[Attention]] to the contexts of the [[discourses]] on [[gradualism]] tells another story.
  
 
[[File:Tea-And-Zen.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Tea-And-Zen.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
    As one might {{Wiki|emphasize}} either {{Wiki|temporal}} or spatial aspects of gradualism so also have [[scholars]] of [[meditation]] emphasized different [[senses]] in which [[meditational]] forces are facts. Through their reliance on {{Wiki|neurological}} research, the {{Wiki|psychologists}} of [[consciousness]] exemplify a {{Wiki|naturalistic}} approach. The question of [[gradual attainment of enlightenment]] would become a question to be settled by [[measuring]] the duration of 'extent' of certain {{Wiki|neurological}} {{Wiki|processes}}. Now, the {{Wiki|psychologists}} of [[consciousness]] have not, to my [[knowledge]], dealt with our particular problem. Yet, it would seem important—at least in passing—to represent their increasingly popular work in this context— even if I am forced to extrapolate from their more {{Wiki|general}} work on [[meditation]]. They seem to exemplify an extreme contrast to the kind of {{Wiki|epistemological}} approach I advocate, since they seem to avoid the whole issue of the theory-ladenness of [[meditational]] "facts."
+
As one might {{Wiki|emphasize}} either {{Wiki|temporal}} or spatial aspects of [[gradualism]] so also have [[scholars]] of [[meditation]] emphasized different [[senses]] in which [[meditational]] forces are facts. Through their reliance on {{Wiki|neurological}} research, the {{Wiki|psychologists}} of [[consciousness]] exemplify a {{Wiki|naturalistic}} approach. The question of [[gradual attainment of enlightenment]] would become a question to be settled by [[measuring]] the duration of 'extent' of certain {{Wiki|neurological}} {{Wiki|processes}}. Now, the {{Wiki|psychologists}} of [[consciousness]] have not, to my [[knowledge]], dealt with our particular problem. Yet, it would seem important—at least in passing—to represent their increasingly popular work in this context— even if I am forced to extrapolate from their more {{Wiki|general}} work on [[meditation]]. They seem to exemplify an extreme contrast to the kind of {{Wiki|epistemological}} approach I advocate, since they seem to avoid the whole issue of the theory-ladenness of [[meditational]] "facts."
  
 
[[File:Shuixin Zen CF8739.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Shuixin Zen CF8739.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
    A [[characteristic]] of this loosely related group of writers is their reliance on quantitative {{Wiki|neurological}} [[investigation]] of [[meditation]]. Typical of this [[view]] is the work of [[Dan Goleman]]. Here, EEGs supposedly get the investigator behind "abstract concept"—'the [[realm]] of {{Wiki|discourse}}' (the [[beliefs]] and reports of [[meditators]]) to the "raw {{Wiki|data}}." [1] Conveniently, this move (if possible) {{Wiki|liberates}} the investigator from the need to deal with troublesome {{Wiki|institutions}}, [[beliefs]], theories, and critics! Thanks to the {{Wiki|EEG}} one reaches the promised land-of-value-free inquiry. Consistent with this supralinguistic approach, no arguments will be found supporting such claims that a conceptually [[neutral]] [[realm]] has been reached. In their stead one finds pronouncements and decrees—poor surrogates for solutions to our awkward {{Wiki|epistemological}} position. But, instead of evading {{Wiki|epistemological}} issues, I believe we ought to face them squarely: What presuppositions, theories, [[beliefs]], and {{Wiki|institutions}} [[condition]] [[mystical]] or [[meditative]] [[experience]]? What [[sense]] can one make of [[truth]] claims made under such [[conditions]]?
+
A [[characteristic]] of this loosely related group of writers is their reliance on quantitative {{Wiki|neurological}} [[investigation]] of [[meditation]]. Typical of this [[view]] is the work of [[Dan Goleman]]. Here, EEGs supposedly get the investigator behind "abstract concept"—'the [[realm]] of {{Wiki|discourse}}' (the [[beliefs]] and reports of [[meditators]]) to the "raw {{Wiki|data}}." [1] Conveniently, this move (if possible) {{Wiki|liberates}} the investigator from the need to deal with troublesome {{Wiki|institutions}}, [[beliefs]], theories, and critics! Thanks to the {{Wiki|EEG}} one reaches the promised land-of-value-free inquiry. Consistent with this supralinguistic approach, no arguments will be found supporting such claims that a conceptually [[neutral]] [[realm]] has been reached. In their stead one finds pronouncements and decrees—poor surrogates for solutions to our awkward {{Wiki|epistemological}} position. But, instead of evading {{Wiki|epistemological}} issues, I believe we ought to face them squarely: What presuppositions, theories, [[beliefs]], and {{Wiki|institutions}} [[condition]] [[mystical]] or [[meditative]] [[experience]]? What [[sense]] can one make of [[truth]] claims made under such [[conditions]]?
 
[[File:Sha ung-fu.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Sha ung-fu.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    It is to the [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologists]] of [[religion]], like Winston [[King]], however, that one must look for the most direct [[discussion]] of our problem. In a comparison of [[Theravāda]] and [[Zen]] [[meditation]], [[King]] concludes that there is really no difference between sudden and [[gradual attainments of enlightenment]]. As one might expect from a [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologist]], [[King]] believes that there is in fact no difference, because there is no experiential difference between sudden and [[gradual attainment of enlightenment]].
+
It is to the [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologists]] of [[religion]], like Winston [[King]], however, that one must look for the most direct [[discussion]] of our problem. In a comparison of [[Theravāda]] and [[Zen]] [[meditation]], [[King]] concludes that there is really no difference between sudden and [[gradual attainments of enlightenment]]. As one might expect from a [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologist]], [[King]] believes that there is in fact no difference, because there is no experiential difference between sudden and [[gradual attainment of enlightenment]].
 
[[File:Sha 53924658.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Sha 53924658.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
+
"suddenness" or "gradualness" of [[enlightenment]] ... appears to depend primarily upon {{Wiki|emphasis}} and/or point of specification. One may choose to {{Wiki|emphasize}} the prior preparation .. . and call it "[[gradual]]"; or one may [[stress]] the experiential [[breakthrough]] and call it "sudden." But in both [[Theravada]] and [[Zen]], there are [[development]] and pinpointed [[breakthrough]].  
    "suddenness" or "gradualness" of [[enlightenment]] ... appears to depend primarily upon {{Wiki|emphasis}} and/or point of specification. One may choose to {{Wiki|emphasize}} the prior preparation .. . and call it "[[gradual]]"; or one may [[stress]] the experiential breakthrough and call it "sudden." But in both [[Theravada]] and [[Zen]], there are [[development]] and pinpointed breakthrough.[2]
 
  
 
[[File:Samgak-san-07.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Samgak-san-07.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
    For [[King]], this virtually closes the case. If, however, one takes seriously the theory-ladenness of [[meditational]] [[experiences]], the hard questions just begin. Why, indeed, the differences in "[[stress]]," as [[King]] himself is compelled to ask? Why the {{Wiki|canonical}}, {{Wiki|commentarial}}, and {{Wiki|modern}} norm among [[Theravādins]] that [[nirvāna]] comes gradually? King's reply to his own question is couched in terms of "the [[Indian]] penchant for {{Wiki|classification}} and {{Wiki|analysis}}" versus the "Sino-Japanese impatience with [[metaphysical]] speculation and a fundamental reliance upon intuitional apprehension of existential [[truth]]."[3] One wonders what the [[Buddha]] would say to the implication that he was not impatient with [[metaphysical]] speculation. Or what the [[Hua-Yen]] [[philosophers]] would say to the implication that they were not among the most [[supreme]] speculative {{Wiki|metaphysicians}} of all [[time]].  
+
For [[King]], this virtually closes the case. If, however, one takes seriously the theory-ladenness of [[meditational]] [[experiences]], the hard questions just begin. Why, indeed, the differences in "[[stress]]," as [[King]] himself is compelled to ask? Why the {{Wiki|canonical}}, {{Wiki|commentarial}}, and {{Wiki|modern}} norm among [[Theravādins]] that [[nirvāna]] comes gradually? King's reply to his [[own]] question is couched in terms of "the [[Indian]] penchant for {{Wiki|classification}} and {{Wiki|analysis}}" versus the "[[Sino-Japanese]] impatience with [[metaphysical]] speculation and a fundamental reliance upon intuitional apprehension of [[existential]] [[truth]]." One wonders what the [[Buddha]] would say to the implication that he was not impatient with [[metaphysical]] speculation. Or what the [[Hua-Yen]] [[philosophers]] would say to the implication that they were not among the most [[supreme]] speculative {{Wiki|metaphysicians}} of all [[time]].  
  
 
[[File:Samgak-san-06.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Samgak-san-06.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
But, like many {{Wiki|cultural}} generalizations, King's also contains an unexpected germ of [[truth]]. Surprisingly, [[King]] drops the [[matter]] at this point. Yet, one should not be altogether puzzled, since King's approach will not let him push [[beyond]] the reports of [[experiences]] to levels of structuring which may give rise to these [[experiences]]. I want to suggest that an [[appreciation]] of fundamental attitudes toward [[knowledge]] may help stimulate [[understanding]] of these divergent [[views]] of what may or may not be [[identical]] {{Wiki|processes}} or [[experiences]]- In part, I [[aim]] to reinforce Jayatilleke's [[views]] about early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}} by arguing that its underlying structural pervasiveness accounts for much of the [[character]] of early [[Buddhist]] [[belief]] in the [[gradual attainment of nirvāna]].[4] Contrary to what [[Buddhist]] empiricists themselves might believe, I believe that their [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|epistemology}} is symptomatic of a deep yet compromised [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|structure}}.
+
But, like many {{Wiki|cultural}} generalizations, King's also contains an unexpected germ of [[truth]].  
 +
 
 +
Surprisingly, [[King]] drops the [[matter]] at this point. Yet, one should not be altogether puzzled, since King's approach will not let him push [[beyond]] the reports of [[experiences]] to levels of structuring which may give rise to these [[experiences]].  
 +
 
 +
I want to suggest that an [[appreciation]] of fundamental attitudes toward [[knowledge]] may help stimulate [[understanding]] of these divergent [[views]] of what may or may not be [[identical]] {{Wiki|processes}} or [[experiences]]- In part, I [[aim]] to reinforce [[Jayatilleke's]] [[views]] about early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}} by arguing that its underlying structural pervasiveness accounts for much of the [[character]] of early [[Buddhist]] [[belief]] in the [[gradual attainment of nirvāna]].
 +
 
 +
Contrary to what [[Buddhist]] [[empiricists]] themselves might believe, I believe that their [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|epistemology}} is symptomatic of a deep yet compromised [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|structure}}.
 +
 
 +
 
  
 
[[File:S5onk.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:S5onk.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
II. THE PALI [[CANON]] ON [[GRADUALISM]]
+
Ii. The [[Pali Canon]] On [[Gradualism]]
 +
 
 +
 
  
 
[[File:Pr1ctice3.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Pr1ctice3.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
The classical and [[principal]] discussions of gradualism occur in four places in the [[Majjhima Nikāya]] (MN). In two condensed analogies, the [[Buddha]] teaches what has become known crudely as "[[gradual enlightenment]]." Both these analogies—taming a thoroughbred colt (MN 1.445-446; MN III.1-6) and mastering complex skills (calculating and [[archery]]: MN III.1-6)—indicate much of the [[character]] of gradualism, which I shall explain shortly. In MN 1 (480-481), the [[Buddha]] deals directly with [[gradual]] [[attainment]] of [[paññā]]. Contrary to popular {{Wiki|misconception}}, this shows that the {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[gradual]] and [[sudden enlightenment]] differs from the {{Wiki|distinction}} between those who attain [[nirvāna]] by [[paññā]]. and the [[jhānas]], respectively. As the [[Buddha]] implies in MN I(478ff), the [[paññāvimutta]] seems to achieve [[nirvana]] immediately (in both spatial and {{Wiki|temporal}} [[senses]]), because he has previously achieved those stages of sanctity which others may only now be set to achieve.
+
The classical and [[principal]] discussions of [[gradualism]] occur in four places in the [[Majjhima Nikāya]] (MN). In two condensed analogies, the [[Buddha]] teaches what has become known crudely as "[[gradual enlightenment]]." Both these analogies—taming a thoroughbred colt (MN 1.445-446; MN III.1-6) and mastering complex skills (calculating and [[archery]]: MN III.1-6)—indicate much of the [[character]] of [[gradualism]], which I shall explain shortly. In MN 1 (480-481), the [[Buddha]] deals directly with [[gradual]] [[attainment]] of [[paññā]]. Contrary to popular {{Wiki|misconception}}, this shows that the {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[gradual]] and [[sudden enlightenment]] differs from the {{Wiki|distinction}} between those who attain [[nirvāna]] by [[paññā]]. and the [[jhānas]], respectively. As the [[Buddha]] implies in MN I(478ff), the [[paññāvimutta]] seems to achieve [[nirvana]] immediately (in both spatial and {{Wiki|temporal}} [[senses]]), because he has previously achieved those stages of sanctity which others may only now be set to achieve.
  
 
[[File:Pjnner1.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Pjnner1.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
Line 66: Line 87:
 
[[File:Mas5ter16.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Mas5ter16.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    Some of these notions need explaining. The early [[Buddhists]] held definite [[beliefs]] about the details and [[reality]] of the [[mental]] landscape. The [[meditator]] was [[thought]] to ascend a graded trail of {{Wiki|real}}, though [[impermanent]], [[mental]] steps ([[jhānas]]), one after another, until the summit of [[nirvāna]] was won. It is true that [[nirvāna]] is not itself another [[jhāna]] and, that, strictly {{Wiki|speaking}}, is not necessarily 'won' by [[meditation]]: it is not the [[Wikipedia:Causality|causal]] product of the process of [[meditation]]. Yet, there is some [[relation]] between [[meditation]] and [[nirvāna]], although the precise {{Wiki|nature}} of it is often difficult to make out. More on this [[matter]] shortly. Moreover, the progress of the [[meditator]] through the [[jhānas]] was also [[thought]] to be open to precise location in terms of a [[psychological]] map of the {{Wiki|real}}, though [[impermanent]], [[mind]].  
+
Some of these notions need explaining. The early [[Buddhists]] held definite [[beliefs]] about the details and [[reality]] of the [[mental]] landscape. The [[meditator]] was [[thought]] to ascend a graded trail of {{Wiki|real}}, though [[impermanent]], [[mental]] steps ([[jhānas]]), one after another, until the summit of [[nirvāna]] was won. It is true that [[nirvāna]] is not itself another [[jhāna]] and, that, strictly {{Wiki|speaking}}, is not necessarily 'won' by [[meditation]]: it is not the [[Wikipedia:Causality|causal]] product of the process of [[meditation]]. Yet, there is some [[relation]] between [[meditation]] and [[nirvāna]], although the precise {{Wiki|nature}} of it is often difficult to make out. More on this [[matter]] shortly. Moreover, the progress of the [[meditator]] through the [[jhānas]] was also [[thought]] to be open to precise location in terms of a [[psychological]] map of the {{Wiki|real}}, though [[impermanent]], [[mind]].  
 
[[File:Majgyen.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Majgyen.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
 
To follow the [[Buddha]] meant, in part, to accept his map of the mind—at least provisionally for the {{Wiki|purpose}} of testing its accuracy and its utility for [[attaining]] [[release]]. In [[meditation]], these [[directions]] were, in turn, tested for their truth—although, of course, the question of vicious circularity is conveniently passed over by the [[Buddhists]]. One might also add that as the route to [[nirvāna]] by [[meditation]] was graded, so was the goal itself, in some [[sense]], graded. Early [[Buddhist]] notions of levels of [[accomplishment]], like "[[Streamwinner]]," "[[Once-returner]]," and so on, seem to point in the same [[direction]] of gradual-graded-attainment.
 
To follow the [[Buddha]] meant, in part, to accept his map of the mind—at least provisionally for the {{Wiki|purpose}} of testing its accuracy and its utility for [[attaining]] [[release]]. In [[meditation]], these [[directions]] were, in turn, tested for their truth—although, of course, the question of vicious circularity is conveniently passed over by the [[Buddhists]]. One might also add that as the route to [[nirvāna]] by [[meditation]] was graded, so was the goal itself, in some [[sense]], graded. Early [[Buddhist]] notions of levels of [[accomplishment]], like "[[Streamwinner]]," "[[Once-returner]]," and so on, seem to point in the same [[direction]] of gradual-graded-attainment.
 
[[File:Ko5ino.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Ko5ino.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
+
Apart from these descriptive uses of the grades of [[attainment]], two aspects of the early [[Buddhist]] [[attitude]] to saving [[knowledge]] are also termed "[[gradual]]" although in a different [[sense]] than we have seen thus far. The context of this new [[sense]] of "[[gradual]]" is the classical [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|milieu}} of {{Wiki|learning}} and [[teaching]]. [[Gradual teaching or instruction]] ([[anupubba-kathā]]) refers to the [[Buddha's]] normative analytical and graded {{Wiki|pedagogy}}.[7] This method of instruction exemplifies the [[Buddha's]] use of skill-in-means ([[upāya-kosalla]]0) [8] which, as [[Jayatilleke]] has argued, encompasses a kind of [[openness]] to [[falsification]] and [[corresponding]] {{Wiki|obligation}} for verification.[9]  
    Apart from these descriptive uses of the grades of [[attainment]], two aspects of the early [[Buddhist]] [[attitude]] to saving [[knowledge]] are also termed "[[gradual]]" although in a different [[sense]] than we have seen thus far. The context of this new [[sense]] of "[[gradual]]" is the classical [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|milieu}} of {{Wiki|learning}} and [[teaching]]. [[Gradual teaching or instruction]] ([[anupubba-kathā]]) refers to the [[Buddha's]] normative analytical and graded {{Wiki|pedagogy}}.[7] This method of instruction exemplifies the [[Buddha's]] use of skill-in-means ([[upāya-kosalla]]0) [8] which, as [[Jayatilleke]] has argued, encompasses a kind of [[openness]] to [[falsification]] and corresponding {{Wiki|obligation}} for verification.[9]  
 
 
[[File:Ink45wing.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Ink45wing.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
Because of his [[compassionate]] care and [[sympathy]] for [[humanity]] and its [[physical]] and [[intellectual]] [[suffering]], the [[Buddha]] prescribed [[teaching]] the [[dhamma]] in orderly and [[logical]] ways, tailored to the needs and capacities of his [[listeners]], and open, in large [[measure]], to dispute and verification.[10] Although, at times he speaks in the {{Wiki|didactic}} mode, the [[Buddha]] eschewed an abrupt, {{Wiki|paradoxical}}, or [[esoteric]] mode, typical of the thwacks and slaps of some [[Zen]] [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|pedagogy}} and the later [[Mahāyāna]] uses of [[upāya]], respectively.
+
Because of his [[compassionate]] care and [[sympathy]] for [[humanity]] and its [[physical]] and [[intellectual]] [[suffering]], the [[Buddha]] prescribed [[teaching]] the [[dhamma]] in orderly and [[logical]] ways, tailored to the needs and capacities of his [[listeners]], and open, in large [[measure]], to dispute and verification. Although, at times he speaks in the {{Wiki|didactic}} mode, the [[Buddha]] eschewed an abrupt, {{Wiki|paradoxical}}, or [[esoteric]] mode, typical of the thwacks and slaps of some [[Zen]] [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|pedagogy}} and the later [[Mahāyāna]] uses of [[upāya]], respectively.
 
[[File:Im;lages.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Im;lages.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    From the {{Wiki|perspective}} of the [[student]], gradualism requires a correspondingly earnest methodical and analytic study of the [[dhamma]]. A [[student]] is responsible for testing and verifying the [[dhamma]] experientially. If one follows [[Jayatilleke]] here, {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[gradualism]]—this [[attitude]] of experiential scrutiny—applies to all aspects of the [[dhamma]]—both to preliminary matters as well as to those which arise at rarified [[meditational]] levels.[11]
+
From the {{Wiki|perspective}} of the [[student]], [[gradualism]] requires a correspondingly earnest methodical and analytic study of the [[dhamma]]. A [[student]] is responsible for testing and verifying the [[dhamma]] experientially. If one follows [[Jayatilleke]] here, {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[gradualism]]—this [[attitude]] of experiential scrutiny—applies to all aspects of the [[dhamma]]—both to preliminary matters as well as to those which arise at rarified [[meditational]] levels.
  
    One cannot then conclude that the [[gradual attainment of enlightenment]] primarily meant that [[nirvāna]] came slowly, or that it was the norm of the slow-witted. This, at any rate, is not the [[view]] of the [[Pali Canon]]. For the early [[Buddhists]], [[gradualism]] was a complex notion, involving both the description of a graded model of the [[meditational]] and [[cognitive]] landscape, along with certain values or prescriptions about the proper {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[attitude]] of [[scrutiny]] and experiential testing needed at all levels of the [[teaching]] and {{Wiki|learning}} process of [[attaining]] [[release]].
+
One cannot then conclude that the [[gradual attainment of enlightenment]] primarily meant that [[nirvāna]] came slowly, or that it was the norm of the slow-witted. This, at any rate, is not the [[view]] of the [[Pali Canon]]. For the early [[Buddhists]], [[gradualism]] was a complex notion, involving both the description of a graded model of the [[meditational]] and [[cognitive]] landscape, along with certain values or prescriptions about the proper {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[attitude]] of [[scrutiny]] and experiential testing needed at all levels of the [[teaching]] and {{Wiki|learning}} process of [[attaining]] [[release]].
 
[[File:Hgmages.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Hgmages.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    In another [[discussion]] on [[Theravāda]] [[meditation]], [[Winston King]] underscores this [[opposition]] of description and prescription by repeating it in terms of the contrast between [[jhānic]] and [[vipāssanic]] aspects of [[meditation]].[12] Although these two aspects are "set in tension with each other,"[13] they also complement each other.[14] [[Vipāssana]] ([[insight]]) supplies "critical [[awareness]]"[15] of the [[jhānic]] [[attainments]], a "reviewing of the [[path]]."[16] The [[jhānic]] route thus describes a journey through a series of gradually ascending stages, while [[vipāssana]] censors and scrutinizes the quality of those achievements.
+
In another [[discussion]] on [[Theravāda]] [[meditation]], [[Winston King]] underscores this [[opposition]] of description and prescription by repeating it in terms of the contrast between [[jhānic]] and [[vipāssanic]] aspects of [[meditation]]. Although these two aspects are "set in tension with each other," they also complement each other. [[Vipāssana]] ([[insight]]) supplies "critical [[awareness]]" of the [[jhānic]] [[attainments]], a "reviewing of the [[path]]." The [[jhānic]] route thus describes a journey through a series of gradually ascending stages, while [[vipāssana]] censors and scrutinizes the [[quality]] of those achievements.
 
[[File:Ha4ddha.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Ha4ddha.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    For [[King]], the {{Wiki|central}} question still {{Wiki|remains}} why these two [[disciplines]] are combined at all. What is achieved by their combination in the [[trance]] of [[cessation]] ([[nirodha-sampātti]]), or in the [[Theravāda]] [[tradition]] as a whole? Once again [[King]] couches his explanation in experiential or {{Wiki|phenomenological}} terms:
+
For [[King]], the {{Wiki|central}} question still {{Wiki|remains}} why these two [[disciplines]] are combined at all. What is achieved by their combination in the [[trance]] of [[cessation]] ([[nirodha-sampātti]]), or in the [[Theravāda]] [[tradition]] as a whole? Once again [[King]] couches his explanation in experiential or {{Wiki|phenomenological}} terms:
 
[[File:Gon4gfu13.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Gon4gfu13.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
        The [[jhānic]] [[discipline]] contributes [[meditational]] expertise, which may strengthen the [[concentration]] of the [[vipassanic]] [[meditator]] ... and very importantly gives a quality of depth and lastingness of experiential [[attainment]]... . On the reverse sides, [[vipāssana]] keeps the whole [[jhānic]] progression within [[Buddhist]] bounds so that none of its utterly [[peaceful]] states will be construed as the final goal of [[meditation]].[17]
+
The [[jhānic]] [[discipline]] contributes [[meditational]] expertise, which may strengthen the [[concentration]] of the [[vipassanic]] [[meditator]] ... and very importantly gives a [[quality]] of depth and lastingness of experiential [[attainment]]... . On the reverse sides, [[vipāssana]] keeps the whole [[jhānic]] progression within [[Buddhist]] bounds so that none of its utterly [[peaceful]] states will be construed as the final goal of [[meditation]].
 
[[File:Flo 009.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Flo 009.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
    Now,I do not wish to quibble with these admirable {{Wiki|conclusions}}. They strike me as [[sensitive]] and germane. Indeed. I should like to confirm them and also take them a step further [[beyond]] the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} level which they occupy. I am urging the reader to consider that there are deeper [[reasons]] behind this felicitous {{Wiki|conjunction}} of [[meditational]] modes, which I, first of all, identify as {{Wiki|epistemological}} in {{Wiki|nature}}. My 'hunch' is that the {{Wiki|connection}} between the [[jhānic]] description of [[cognitive]] growth with the [[vipassanic]] {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[scrutiny]] suggests a fundamental {{Wiki|connection}} with a comprised [[empiricist]] syndrome recently spelled out by Ernest Gellner.[18] There are parallels to the specific {{Wiki|conjunction}} of the [[jhānic]] and [[vipāssanic]] modes of [[meditation]] in similar conjunctions in the {{Wiki|general}} [[development]] of [[empiricist]] approaches to the growth of [[knowledge]]. [[Jhānic]] and [[vipāssanic]] modes of [[meditation]] are joined for the same [[reason]] similar aspects of the {{Wiki|general}} [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[knowledge]] are joined.
+
Now,I do not wish to quibble with these admirable {{Wiki|conclusions}}. They strike me as [[sensitive]] and germane. Indeed. I should like to confirm them and also take them a step further [[beyond]] the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} level which they occupy. I am urging the reader to consider that there are deeper [[reasons]] behind this felicitous {{Wiki|conjunction}} of [[meditational]] modes, which I, first of all, identify as {{Wiki|epistemological}} in {{Wiki|nature}}. My 'hunch' is that the {{Wiki|connection}} between the [[jhānic]] description of [[cognitive]] growth with the [[vipassanic]] {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[scrutiny]] suggests a fundamental {{Wiki|connection}} with a comprised [[empiricist]] syndrome recently spelled out by [[Ernest Gellner]]. There are parallels to the specific {{Wiki|conjunction}} of the [[jhānic]] and [[vipāssanic]] modes of [[meditation]] in similar conjunctions in the {{Wiki|general}} [[development]] of [[empiricist]] approaches to the growth of [[knowledge]]. [[Jhānic]] and [[vipāssanic]] modes of [[meditation]] are joined for the same [[reason]] similar aspects of the {{Wiki|general}} [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[knowledge]] are joined.
 
[[File:Ea ilFP.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Ea ilFP.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
III. THE "[[GHOST]]" MEETS THE "MACHINE"
+
 
 +
 
 +
==Iii. The "[[Ghost]]" Meets The "Machine"==
 +
 
 +
 
  
 
[[File:Dayi Daoxin.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Dayi Daoxin.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
    One can speak of an '[[empiricist]] syndrome' today largely because it has been the [[subject]] of intense [[debate]] by {{Wiki|modern}} [[epistemologists]]. This is perhaps especially true of {{Wiki|north}} Atlantic {{Wiki|analytic philosophy}}, although the ferment on the continent in {{Wiki|Marxist}} and structuralist circles seems to focus on similar issues from the {{Wiki|opposite}} [[philosophical]] shore. Among [[philosophers]] of [[science]], [[Ernest Gellner]] has been particularly active in recent years in this area.  
+
One can speak of an '[[empiricist]] syndrome' today largely because it has been the [[subject]] of intense [[debate]] by {{Wiki|modern}} [[epistemologists]]. This is perhaps especially true of {{Wiki|north}} Atlantic {{Wiki|analytic philosophy}}, although the ferment on the continent in {{Wiki|Marxist}} and structuralist circles seems to focus on similar issues from the {{Wiki|opposite}} [[philosophical]] shore. Among [[philosophers]] of [[science]], [[Ernest Gellner]] has been particularly active in recent years in this area.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Gellner]] believes one ought to distinguish two moments in the [[life]] of {{Wiki|empiricism}} as it has developed in certain favored contexts: {{Wiki|empiricism}} is both a description of how [[knowledge]] works and a prescription about what ought to count as [[knowledge]]. As a description, {{Wiki|empiricism}} offers a mere "toddler's toy" model, far too crude and simple to reflect the complexity of [[cognition]]; but, as a prescription, it provides a useful "touchstone," admirably stating a clear normative [[attitude]] toward the limits of [[cognition]]. In this [[latter]] [[sense]], {{Wiki|empiricism}} actsas a "censor" or "selector," laying downtwo {{Wiki|imperatives}}: "Be [[sensitive]] to whether or not assertions are testable (in the specified approved [[manner]])! Spurn those which are not".  [[Gellner]] realizes that an [[empiricist]] would not typically [[recognize]] that {{Wiki|empiricism}} itself rests of prescriptions. Indeed, part of what {{Wiki|being}} an [[empiricist]] has meant in the {{Wiki|past}}, has been [[bound]] up with the conviction that our [[cognitive]] situation is grounded in unbiased observations.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
But, for [[Gellner]] and any one of the numerous critics of {{Wiki|empiricism}} today, this is just not so.
 +
 
 +
As for the [[empiricist]] "toddler's toy" model, it can be summarized along the lines of an acquisitive enterprise. Beginning with an active {{Wiki|external}} [[world]] and a passive {{Wiki|internal}} one, the [[inner world]] of '[[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]' or '[[knowledge]]' is built up by accumulating sense-data. But, since all one '[[knows]]' consists of sense-data, the [[existence]] of a [[world]] behind sense-data becomes theoretically problematic, and unless something intervenes, one is led down the primrose [[path]] to {{Wiki|phenomenalism}} and {{Wiki|nominalism}}. In this [[condition]] one can still 'generalize,' by assembling sense-data into complex '[[beliefs]]' or '[[ideas]]' by 'induction.'
 +
 
 +
The [[truth]] of these [[beliefs]] is tested or verified by '[[correspondence]]' with the facts of [[sense]] [[experience]]. This comparison of simple and complex is achieved through the process of 'analyzing' complex '[[beliefs]]' into their constituent sense-data. Normative statements analyzed in this fashion reveal no [[world]] of 'good' or [['bad]],' but mere [[pleasures]], [[pains]], or [[emotions]]. [[Science]], especially in its reductionist and impersonalist [[moods]], represents the kind of model explanation of the [[world]] of [[experience]] to which all other [[cognitive]] enterprises should aspire.
 +
 
 +
For [[Gellner]], {{Wiki|empiricism}} tends toward {{Wiki|solipsism}} and eventually idealism—as long as it {{Wiki|remains}} [[pure]]. After all, [[experience]] is just my [[experience]]. My [[experience]] is composed of private sense-data, and the [[existence]] of the {{Wiki|external}} [[world]] is necessarily left in [[doubt]]. Yet, historically and, in [[Gellner's]] [[view]], happily, {{Wiki|empiricism}} did not in every case actually retain its [[purity]] and develop into {{Wiki|idealism}} and {{Wiki|solipsism}}; {{Wiki|Bishop}} {{Wiki|Berkeley}} was not the sole heir to the [[empiricist]] [[tradition]].
 +
 
 +
The Utilitarians, Locke, Russell, and others, claim this birthright as well. Their [[thought]] [[embodies]] a salutary convergence of {{Wiki|empiricism}} and materialism—the "[[ghost]]" and the "machine," in [[Gellner's]] words. These thinkers sought a "{{Wiki|stable}}, recognisable {{Wiki|structure}} that could somehow be reached through the qualitative sense-data available to the [[ghost]]." Because of their [[confidence]] in [[knowing]] the [[world]], they also believed that the [[world]] was improvable, and that {{Wiki|analysis}} and [[scrutiny]] were both worthwhile and [[appropriate]] [[activities]] for [[human beings]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
==Iv. Early [[Buddhist Empiricism]] And [[Meditation]]==
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
[[Gellner's]] [[myth]] about this compromised {{Wiki|empiricism}} fits remarkably well with [[K.. N. Jayatilleke's]] account of early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of knowledge—especially in the way it resists {{Wiki|idealism}} (as later [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] does not) and allies itself with {{Wiki|materialism}}. [[Early Buddhism]] populates the {{Wiki|vacuum}} between [[experience]] and the otherwise [[noumenal]] [[world]] with {{Wiki|real}}, though [[impermanent]] and [[causally]] [[conditioned]], [[causally]] agent, {{Wiki|material}} sense-data. These sense-data, in turn, activate the [[causally]] passive (initially, at any rate) and {{Wiki|material}} [[mind]], producing '[[knowledge]]' of the [[world]]. For both [[Gellner]] and [[early Buddhism]] this convergence of "[[ghost]]" and "machine" reinforces the [[characteristic]] [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[attitude]] of {{Wiki|analysis}}. This analytic spirit—like perhaps the "[[spirit]]" of {{Wiki|Protestantism}} or [[capitalism]] in Weber—fits with the [[spirit]] of the [[development]] of [[traditional]] {{Wiki|empiricism}} and [[early Buddhism]].
 +
 
 +
Both take the [[world]] seriously, because it is not [[illusory]]; both exhibit a "salutary censoriousness" which "seems only to come when [[cognitive]] {{Wiki|hope}} and [[confidence]] have already been raised high." This is why both [[Gellner's]] compromised {{Wiki|empiricism}} and [[early Buddhism]] (surprisingly and in different ways to be sure) lead to "puritanical orderly world-reform and [[cognitive]] exploration," rather than to [[Wikipedia:Arthur Schopenhaue|Schopenhaurian]] [[pessimism]], [[aestheticism]], and [[mysticism]], on the one hand, or to indulgent hippie grooviness, on the other.
 +
 
 +
To those who [[imagine]] [[Buddhism]] to be [[Wikipedia:Arthur Schopenhaue|Schopenhaurian]], {{Wiki|pessimistic}}, [[mystical]], and so on, this claim will come as a [[shock]]. And, it is true that much of the [[Buddhist tradition]] has been all these things. Yet, [[Jayatilleke's]] research, for one, has done much to rectify this {{Wiki|image}} of Buddhism—at least as it seems to have taken shape in the [[Pali Canon]]. The Utilitarians, for example, "took the [[world]] seriously." But, this meant [[attention]] to {{Wiki|political}} reform, technological [[development]], and [[cognitive]] exploration in the natural {{Wiki|sciences}}. With the early [[Buddhists]], this earnest [[spirit]] took the [[form]] of {{Wiki|individual}} [[ethical]] and [[psychological]] reform, the establishment of an alternative model society—the [[Buddhist]] [[monastic community]], the [[Sangha]]—[[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] exploration and therapy aimed at seeking the [[psychological]] [[roots]] of [[suffering]] morein the style of {{Wiki|Freud}} and the {{Wiki|psychotherapists}}.
 +
 
 +
This is not to deny the differences between [[Gellner's]] compromised {{Wiki|empiricism}} and early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}}; it is only to show that they are not differences of "[[spirit]]." Moreover, in some ways, [[early Buddhism]] is even more {{Wiki|optimistic}} than its counterparts in {{Wiki|European}} {{Wiki|empiricism}}. It stands for the possibility of the radical [[development]] of [[human]] [[cognitive]] potentials: Men can know the {{Wiki|real}} {{Wiki|nature}} of the [[world]] and [[nirvāna]]. This enlarges the range of experiential [[knowledge]], taking in [[meditational]] states, kinds of ESP, and states [[transcendental]] to the [[ordinary man]].
 +
 
 +
The [[cognitive]] {{Wiki|optimism}} of [[early Buddhism]] rests, in turn, on the presuppositions underlying the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[meditation]] outlined earlier. The [[Buddhists]] [[thought]] they knew how the [[mind]] worked and what techniques would best serve to enable it to work for [[human]] [[happiness]]. Insofar as early [[Buddhist meditation]] methods are concerned, they are specific to the compromised [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[knowledge]] spelled out by [[Gellner]]. One can, in fact, generate the model of early [[Buddhist meditation]] merely by reversing the [[order]] of the [[empiricist]] model of critical [[accumulation]] of sense-data. As one had gradually [[accumulated]] sense-data and passed them before the inner censor, the "[[ghost]]," before risking knowledge-claims, so also in [[meditation]] one gradually surpasses classes of sense-data [[experience]] and [[knowledge]]. Urged on by [[vipāssana]] [[criticism]], the [[meditator]] presses along the [[jhānic]] route to higher [[meditational]] levels, completely stripped of sense-data [[information]].
 +
 
 +
Thus, reliable ordinary [[knowledge]] as well as [[nirvāna]] require [[gradual]], diligent, and critical attention—analytic care in sifting our [[perceptions]] and [[beliefs]]. In [[meditation]], this becomes even more severe as the [[meditator]] empties the [[mind]] of these {{Wiki|data}}, noting their content and [[form]] as they are transcended until [[nirvāna]] itself is [[attained]]. One is not typically encouraged to leap to {{Wiki|conclusions}} (or [[nirvāna]]) in [[early Buddhism]]. One is invited to analyze and verify the [[dhamma]] experientially and ultimately in [[meditation]]. The [[meditator]] [[initiates]] a relentless and deliberate selection process, which seeks to {{Wiki|liberate}} the {{Wiki|perceiver}} from the bondage of the inward flowof [[causally]] agent [[sensations]]. In [[meditation]], a [[Buddhist]] tries to understand sense-data, and therefore [[knowledge]], in their [[own]] terms, and declare them for what they are.
 +
 
 +
All this makes for a measured and certain {{Wiki|optimism}} about man's potential for {{Wiki|salvation}} unaided by [[occult]] [[power]] or [[cosmic]] [[fate]]. In the context of this analytic, trial-and-error [[cognitive]] quest, one is advised not to expect rapid results, although these could, of course, occur. The early [[Buddhists]] encouraged persistence. [[Effort]] brought results. The point was to keep at it, to [[form]] the [[habits]] of [[mind]] and [[action]] which would surely (but not automatically) bring results.
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
==V. [[Gradual Enlightenment]] And [[Sudden Enlightenment]]: Historic [[Debates]] 1: [[China]]==
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
Thus far, I have tried to [[illuminate]] the {{Wiki|nature}} of early [[Buddhist meditation]] and the [[belief]] in [[gradual enlightenment]] by appealing to the notion of early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}}. In a nutshell, I have argued that early [[Buddhist meditation]] {{Wiki|theory}} is imbedded in a compromised [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|epistemology}} and, as such, will  reflect salient {{Wiki|characteristics}} of this {{Wiki|epistemological}} syndrome. Even though ordinary [[knowledge]] requires accumulating sense-data, both {{Wiki|processes}} occur by '[[gradual]]' means—in both the descriptive and prescriptive [[senses]] of that term. As a structuralist, I have shown that [[Gellner's]] compromised version of {{Wiki|empiricism}} is homologous to early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}} in both descriptive and prescriptive {{Wiki|dimensions}}.
 +
 
 +
[[Meditation]] in [[early Buddhism]] constitutes a counterpoint variant of this common theme, seeming for the most part a structural [[inversion]] of the [[empiricist]] statement about ordinary acquisition of [[knowledge]].
 +
 
 +
The critical reader will want some test of this {{Wiki|thesis}}. And, if structuralism is not to become just another occasion for clever [[dialectical]] [[shenanigans]], structuralists must offer some check on their [[own]] method. The {{Wiki|perfect}} test of this {{Wiki|thesis}} would be a [[debate]] between a proponent of early [[Buddhist empiricism]] who held the [[gradualist]] position, and another kind of [[Buddhist]] who held the sudden position—typically a [[Rinzai]] [[Zen]] [[Buddhist]]. The {{Wiki|nature}} of the test would be to see if one could correlate opposed [[beliefs]] about the [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]] with opposed {{Wiki|epistemological}} beliefs—understanding all the while that both kinds of [[epistemologies]] may operate in these contexts in compromised [[forms]].
 +
In the {{Wiki|history}} of [[Buddhism]], the issue of [[gradual]] and [[sudden enlightenment]] has arisen on two conspicuous occasions: the eighth-century controversies between the [[Northern]] and [[Southern schools]] of [[Ch'an Buddhism]] in [[China]], and between the [[Indian]] and {{Wiki|Chinese}} parties at the {{Wiki|Council}} of [[bSamYas]] (792-794) (the so-called {{Wiki|Council}} of {{Wiki|Lhasa}}) in [[Tibet]]. Of the two, the {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[controversy]] gives fullest treatment to the sudden position. Indeed, the focus classicus of the sudden [[view]] {{Wiki|remains}} the [[Platform Sutra of the Sixth Patriarch]], attributed to the 'victor' of the [[debate]] and founder of the [[Southern school]] of [[Ch'an]], [[Hui-Neng]] (638-713). Thanks to [[Yampolsky's]] recent research of this text and its historical context, much has become clear. For one, [[Yampolsky]] argues that one should attribute the authorship of the [[sūtra]] to [[Shen-hui]], one of [[Hui-Neng's]] [[disciples]], rather than to the [[sixth patriarch]] himself. Together with [[Dumoulin's]] work in this area, one can be reasonably certain in correlating [[Hui-Neng's]] sudden {{Wiki|theory}} of [[enlightenment]] with a certain epistemological-cum-ontological position opposed to that of [[early Buddhism]].
 +
 
 +
We know that [[Hui-Neng]] ([[Shen-hui]]) [[taught]] the "sudden" [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]] against the celebrated [[Ch'an]] [[teacher]], and [[sixth patriarch]] according to the [[Northern school]], [[Shen-hsiu]]. But, what did he mean? [[Dumoulin]] claims that [[Hui-Neng]] even makes it the sole criterion for {{Wiki|orthodoxy}}! What can be contained in this cryptic claim to [[merit]] such importance? And what can explain the fierce attacks [[Hui-Neng]] aimed at [[Shen-hsiu]]? Well, [[Hui-Neng]] most certainly did not mean [[enlightenment]] was "easily obtainable" or even quickly won,"  although these were not ruled out. Like the early [[Buddhists]], [[Hui-Neng]] had higher purposes in [[mind]]. Both were concerned to make certain points about [[human]] {{Wiki|psychology}} and [[knowledge]], using the idioms of {{Wiki|temporal}} duration and spatial levels when these suited their purposes. Both seem to insist, quite often without apparent {{Wiki|purpose}}, that [[enlightenment]] occurred in a way harmonious with their practices and basic [[views]].
 +
 
 +
[[Dumoulin]] and [[Yampolsky]] agree that the [[belief]] in [[sudden enlightenment]] has two sides. Negatively, it denies that the goal, [[prajñā]], can be produced by a "step-by-step process of [[meditation]]," [[dhyāna]]—odd, one would have [[thought]], for the [[Dhyāna]] school ([[Ch'an]]) to assert. Positively, it was a way of asserting the [[truth]] of {{Wiki|a priori}} [[nonduality]]—that [[prajñā]] is "something possessed from the outset by everyone." The point is to realize the imminent {{Wiki|a priori}} {{Wiki|nature}} of [[enlightenment]] and to let it shine through. [[Meditation]] cannot effect [[enlightenment]] because, strictly {{Wiki|speaking}}, [[meditation]] and the [[passions]] it seeks to purge are {{Wiki|ontologically}} [[empty]] and [[illusory]].
 +
 
 +
Thus, at bottom, the [[doctrine]] of [[sudden enlightenment]] is a way of denying the [[jhanās]] and of asserting the {{Wiki|a priori}} {{Wiki|nature}} of [[enlightenment]] in the idiom of [[meditational]] practice. As the early [[Buddhists]] set out to operationalize early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}} with the descriptive and prescriptive [[senses]] of [[gradualism]], so also does [[Hui-Neng]] seem intent on operationalizing his [[own]] [[philosophical]] position in the sudden [[view]] of the [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]]: there are no real—even impermanent—grades of [[enlightenment]]; thus there is no need to test for {{Wiki|a priori}} [[enlightenment]], since all [[beings]] are [[enlightened]] by {{Wiki|nature}}.
 +
One will recall that the [[Pali Canon]] would certainly tell another kind of story. Although [[meditational]] progress through the [[jhanās]] does not [[causally]] produce [[nirvāna]] on the early [[Buddhist]] [[view]], in {{Wiki|conjunction}} with [[vipāssana]], it is one important way to attain it. However [[impermanent]] they may be, one seeks to transcend the constraints of {{Wiki|real}} (though [[impermanent]]) [[mind]] and [[world]]. [[Impermanence]] itself signals that progress can be made. But, early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|soteriological}} {{Wiki|optimism}} could not lead to the seemingly exaggerated {{Wiki|optimism}} [[embodied]] in the [[belief]] in {{Wiki|a priori}} enlightenment—that the {{Wiki|battle}} was already won, or that virtually no {{Wiki|battle}} needed to be fought. [[Nirvāna]], on the other hand, {{Wiki|transcends}} [[experience]] without {{Wiki|being}} prior to [[experience]]. It is not, strictly {{Wiki|speaking}}, posterior to [[experience]] either, since it is not, as it were, an inductive, [[empirical]] generalization, or [[caused]] by [[meditation]].
 +
 
 +
If I may be permitted a neologism, the [[word]] 'transposterior' (to [[experience]]) may capture the {{Wiki|flavor}} of the relationship of [[nirvāna]] to ordinary [[experience]]. By this I mean that [[nirvāna]] is not {{Wiki|a priori}}, and only can be said to be [[Wikipedia:Empirical evidence|a posteriori]] if one stipulates that it is held to transcend [[experience]]. Historically, this position may have arisen from conflict with {{Wiki|brahminical}} [[Wikipedia:rationalism|rationalists]], if we follow ppJayatilleke's[[  suggestion. What {{Wiki|remains}} important is the early [[Buddhist]] [[aversion]] to [[apriorism]] —even if it meant constructing an {{Wiki|empiricism}} which finally may have (to put it charitably) transcended itself in the special case of the {{Wiki|nature}} of [[nirvana]]. [[Hui-Neng]] and the [[Southern school]] of [[Ch'an Buddhism]] felt no such [[aversion]] for the {{Wiki|a priori}}. In fact, they celebrated it, and consequently [[thought]] that it merely had to be seen beneath the surface of an already [[illusory]] [[world]]. [[Enlightenment was sudden]]' because it was {{Wiki|a priori}} and without even {{Wiki|ontological}} competition from an [[impermanent]] [[world]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
==Vi. [[Gradual Enlightenment]] and [[Sudden Enlightenment]]: Historic [[Debates]] Ii: [[Tibet]]==
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
The second classic locus of this [[debate]] is the late eighth-century [[controversy]] which occasioned the {{Wiki|Council}} of [[bSam Yas]] (so-called [[Council of Lhasa]]).
 +
 
 +
Here, the [[Indian]] [[Mādhyamika]] [[logician]], [[Kamalaśīla]] (742-804) argued a [[gradualist]] position against a {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Ch'an]] [[teacher]], [[Hva San]], and his [[Tibetan]] allies, the [[rDzogs-chen]].
 +
 
 +
Far more importance is [[attached]] to this [[debate]] than may seem warranted. Yet, the issue was clearly [[thought]] to have been {{Wiki|central}} to the subsequent [[development]] of [[Buddhism]] in [[Tibet]]. Our accounts of the [[debate]] records the point of [[view]] of the victor, in this case [[Kamalaśīla]] in his [[own]] [[Bhāvanākrama]] .
 +
 
 +
We learn little of the [[views]] of [[Hva-San]] and his company from this text and are thus led to speculate about their fuller [[form]] and the possible relationship with the earlier teachings of [[Hui-Neng]] and his school.
 +
 
 +
Although the connections between these two are not certain, many similarities of points of [[view]] can be established, which in themselves may point in the [[direction]] of relationship.
 +
 
 +
The [[interesting]] thing about [[Kamalaśīla]] is that he seems to argue a [[gradualism]] similar to what we have discovered in early [[Buddhist meditation]] but, at first [[sight]], without sufficient {{Wiki|theoretical}} basis to do so.
 +
 
 +
His [[philosophical]] position, as best one can make out from the often conflicting accounts of it, is exceedingly rich and complex.
 +
 
 +
He seems at once a [[Svatāntrika]] [[Mādhyamakin]], [[Śūnyavādin]], as well as [[logician]] and {{Wiki|pragmatist}} in the [[tradition]] of [[Dharmakīrti]].
 +
 
 +
{{Wiki|Historians}} of [[Indian philosophy]] have also identified him as a critic of the [[Yogācārins]]. [[Kamalaśīla]], himself,  seems to [[recognize]] that these [[philosophical]] positions produce in him a certain amount of [[intellectual]] and {{Wiki|practical}} tension.
 +
 
 +
This is so especially in {{Wiki|connection}} with his [[desire]] both to [[acknowledge]] the [[transcendent]] primacy of [[Śūnyavāda]] {{Wiki|monism}}, along with the rather [[mundane]], though nonetheless wholehearted, [[devotion]] to the [[bodhisattva ideal]] of [[compassion]] and [[meditation]].
 +
 
 +
What makes [[Kamalaśīla]] [[interesting]] then, is his conviction that [[enlightenment comes gradually]] and that one should press on with [[dhyāna]] and [[karunā]], despite the awkward higher [[truth]] of the [[Śūnyatā]].
 +
 
 +
This cannot have been a [[concern]] original to [[Kamalaśīla]]. Other [[Mādhyamikas]] must have shared it.
 +
 
 +
But, it must have been especially acute in th like [[Hui-Neng]], [[taught]] [[sudden enlightenment]] in the [[sense]] that [[meditation]] in the progressive [[manner]] was unnecessary.
 +
 
 +
Perhaps {{Wiki|reflecting}} the supposed [[Yogācāra]] background of [[Ch'an]], [[Hva-San]] teaches the {{Wiki|idealist}} [[view]] that [[thought]] is at the [[root]] of all se face of [[Hva-San's]] {{Wiki|idealist}} {{Wiki|monistic}} teachings which reflected no such qualms about pressing on with the [[worldly]] exercises of [[dhyāna]] and [[karūna]].
 +
 
 +
One need merely stop [[thinking]] to stop [[suffering]].
 +
 
 +
And [[thinking]] could be stopped suddenly—without progress through the [[jhānas]] or [[bodhisattvabhūmis]].
  
 +
In this way {{Wiki|a priori}} [[enlightenment]] simply shines through. [[Hva-San]] {{Wiki|sounds}} very much the [[Yogacārin]] or close [[relative]] of [[Hui-Neng's]] [[Ch'an Buddhism]] in this passage:
  
[[Gellner]] believes one ought to distinguish two moments in the [[life]] of {{Wiki|empiricism}} as it has developed in certain favored contexts: {{Wiki|empiricism}} is both a description of how [[knowledge]] works and a prescription about what ought to count as [[knowledge]]. As a description, {{Wiki|empiricism}} offers a mere "toddler's toy" model,[19] far too crude and simple to reflect the complexity of [[cognition]]; but, as a prescription, it provides a useful "touchstone,"[20] admirably stating a clear normative [[attitude]] toward the limits of [[cognition]]. In this [[latter]] [[sense]], {{Wiki|empiricism}} actsas a "censor" or "selector,"[21] laying downtwo {{Wiki|imperatives}}: "Be [[sensitive]] to whether or not assertions are testable (in the specified approved [[manner]])! Spurn those which are not". [22] Gellner realizes that an [[empiricist]] would not typically [[recognize]] that {{Wiki|empiricism}} itself rests of prescriptions. Indeed, part of what {{Wiki|being}} an [[empiricist]] has meant in the {{Wiki|past}}, has been [[bound]] up with the conviction that our [[cognitive]] situation is grounded in unbiased observations.  
+
We ourselves [are] coessential with the [[Buddha]], and all {{Wiki|representations}} which constitute the [[world]] {{Wiki|being}} [[illusory]] or a [[magic]] play of the [[Absolute]]....  
  
 +
What we need is only to jump ... from the plane of {{Wiki|representations}} into that [[Buddhahood]], our [[true nature]], by sudden elimination of those [[mental]] {{Wiki|representations}}.
  
But, for Gellner and any one of the numerous critics of {{Wiki|empiricism}} today, this is just not so.
+
We must arrest the play of their [[emanation]], stop our [[mind]], and see into our [[own]] {{Wiki|nature}}.
  
    As for the [[empiricist]] "toddler's toy" model, it can be summarized along the lines of an acquisitive enterprise. Beginning with an active {{Wiki|external}} [[world]] and a passive {{Wiki|internal}} one, the [[inner world]] of '[[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]' or '[[knowledge]]' is built up by accumulating sense-data. But, since all one '[[knows]]' consists of sense-data, the [[existence]] of a [[world]] behind sense-data becomes theoretically problematic, and unless something intervenes, one is led down the primrose [[path]] to {{Wiki|phenomenalism}} and {{Wiki|nominalism}}. In this [[condition]] one can still 'generalize,' by assembling sense-data into complex '[[beliefs]]' or '[[ideas]]' by 'induction.'
+
But, what is it about having the [[Buddha-nature]] within us that requires a sudden [[interpretation]] of the [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]], along with the rejection of the [[jhānas]], {{Wiki|analysis}}, and the [[compassion]] of the [[bodhisattva]]?
  
The [[truth]] of these [[beliefs]] is tested or verified by '[[correspondence]]' with the facts of [[sense]] [[experience]]. This comparison of simple and complex is achieved through the process of 'analyzing' complex '[[beliefs]]' into their constituent sense-data. Normative statements analyzed in this fashion reveal no [[world]] of 'good' or [['bad]],' but mere [[pleasures]], [[pains]], or [[emotions]]. [[Science]], especially in its reductionist and impersonalist moods, represents the kind of model explanation of the [[world]] of [[experience]] to which all other [[cognitive]] enterprises should aspire.
+
Except for the [[doctrine]] of {{Wiki|a priori}} [[enlightenment]], grounded in the possession of the [[Buddha-nature]], [[Kamalaśīla]] and [[Hva-San]] would seem to share at least the [[transcendental]] {{Wiki|monism}}, [[characteristic]] of both [[Śūnyavāda]] and [[Yogācāra]], respectively.  
  
    For [[Gellner]], {{Wiki|empiricism}} tends toward {{Wiki|solipsism}} and eventually idealism—as long as it {{Wiki|remains}} [[pure]]. After all, [[experience]] is just my [[experience]]. My [[experience]] is composed of private sense-data, and the [[existence]] of the {{Wiki|external}} [[world]] is necessarily left in [[doubt]]. Yet, historically and, in [[Gellner's]] [[view]], happily, {{Wiki|empiricism}} did not in every case actually retain its [[purity]] and develop into {{Wiki|idealism}} and {{Wiki|solipsism}}; {{Wiki|Bishop}} {{Wiki|Berkeley}} was not the sole heir to the [[empiricist]] [[tradition]].  
+
One will, of course, want to make [[appropriate]] qualifications for differences in these {{Wiki|characteristics}} of the [[Absolute]].  
  
The Utilitarians, Locke, Russell, and others, claim this birthright as well. Their [[thought]] [[embodies]] a salutary convergence of {{Wiki|empiricism}} and materialism—the "[[ghost]]" and the "machine," in [[Gellner's]] words. These thinkers sought a "{{Wiki|stable}}, recognisable {{Wiki|structure}} that could somehow be reached through the qualitative sense-data available to the [[ghost]]."[23] Because of their [[confidence]] in [[knowing]] the [[world]], they also believed that the [[world]] was improvable, and that {{Wiki|analysis}} and [[scrutiny]] were both worthwhile and [[appropriate]] [[activities]] for [[human beings]].
+
Yet, in [[spite]] of that, one wonders how and why [[Kamalaśīla]] can commit himself so thoroughly to the [[worldly]] practices of [[dhyāna]] and [[karūna]], [[knowing]] full well that these are onto-logically insubstantial?
  
IV. EARLY [[BUDDHIST]] EMPIRICISM AND [[MEDITATION]]
+
Has not [[Hva-San]] really drawn the natural {{Wiki|consequences}} of [[transcendental]] {{Wiki|monism}}?
  
    [[Gellner's]] [[myth]] about this compromised {{Wiki|empiricism}} fits remarkably well with [[K.. N. Jayatilleke's]] account of early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of knowledge—especially in the way it resists {{Wiki|idealism}} (as later [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] does not) and allies itself with {{Wiki|materialism}}.[24] [[Early Buddhism]] populates the {{Wiki|vacuum}} between [[experience]] and the otherwise [[noumenal]] [[world]] with {{Wiki|real}}, though [[impermanent]] and [[causally]] [[conditioned]], [[causally]] agent, {{Wiki|material}} sense-data. These sense-data, in turn, activate the [[causally]] passive (initially, at any rate) and {{Wiki|material}} [[mind]], producing '[[knowledge]]' of the [[world]]. For both [[Gellner]] and [[early Buddhism]] this convergence of "[[ghost]]" and "machine" reinforces the [[characteristic]] [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[attitude]] of {{Wiki|analysis}}.[25] This analytic spirit—like perhaps the "[[spirit]]" of {{Wiki|Protestantism}} or capitalism in Weber—fits with the [[spirit]] of the [[development]] of [[traditional]] {{Wiki|empiricism}} and [[early Buddhism]].
+
Is not [[Kamalaśīla]] quixotically supporting some [[venerable]], but outmoded, [[tradition]] of the [[sūtras]], which by some kind of [[intellectual]] {{Wiki|inertia}}, now soldiers on without adequate {{Wiki|theoretical}} basis?
  
Both take the [[world]] seriously, because it is not [[illusory]]; both exhibit a "salutary censoriousness" which "seems only to come when [[cognitive]] {{Wiki|hope}} and [[confidence]] have already been raised high."[26] This is why both [[Gellner's]] compromised {{Wiki|empiricism}} and [[early Buddhism]] (surprisingly and in different ways to be sure) lead to "puritanical orderly world-reform and [[cognitive]] exploration," rather than to [[Wikipedia:Arthur Schopenhaue|Schopenhaurian]] [[pessimism]], [[aestheticism]], and [[mysticism]], on the one hand, or to indulgent hippie grooviness, on the other.[27]
+
[[Tucci]] is one of the few [[scholars]] to have appreciated the awkwardness and poignancy of [[Kamalaśīla]] position.
  
    To those who [[imagine]] [[Buddhism]] to be [[Wikipedia:Arthur Schopenhaue|Schopenhaurian]], {{Wiki|pessimistic}}, [[mystical]], and so on, this claim will come as a shock. And, it is true that much of the [[Buddhist tradition]] has been all these things. Yet, [[Jayatilleke's]] research, for one, has done much to rectify this {{Wiki|image}} of Buddhism—at least as it seems to have taken shape in the [[Pali Canon]]. The Utilitarians, for example, "took the [[world]] seriously." But, this meant [[attention]] to {{Wiki|political}} reform, technological [[development]], and [[cognitive]] exploration in the natural {{Wiki|sciences}}. With the early [[Buddhists]], this earnest [[spirit]] took the [[form]] of {{Wiki|individual}} [[ethical]] and [[psychological]] reform, the establishment of an alternative model society—the [[Buddhist]] [[monastic community]], the [[Sangha]]—[[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] exploration and therapy aimed at seeking the [[psychological]] [[roots]] of [[suffering]] morein the style of {{Wiki|Freud}} and the {{Wiki|psychotherapists}}.[28]
+
But, his rather oblique {{Wiki|solution}} to [[Kamalaśīla's]] quandry only precipitates a puzzle of his [[own]]. {{Wiki|Speaking}} first of [[Hva-San]], [[Tucci]] claims the [[sudden enlightenment doctrine]] follows from the simultaneous granting of {{Wiki|ontological}} {{Wiki|status}} to both [[abhūtapariikalpita]] ("[[power]] of [[subjective]] [[representation]]") and [[Śūnyatā]].  
  
    This is not to deny the differences between [[Gellner's]] compromised {{Wiki|empiricism}} and early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}}; it is only to show that they are not differences of "[[spirit]]." Moreover, in some ways, [[early Buddhism]] is even more {{Wiki|optimistic}} than its counterparts in {{Wiki|European}} {{Wiki|empiricism}}. It stands for the possibility of the radical [[development]] of [[human]] [[cognitive]] potentials: Men can know the {{Wiki|real}} {{Wiki|nature}} of the [[world]] and [[nirvāna]]. This enlarges the range of experiential [[knowledge]], taking in [[meditational]] states, kinds of ESP, and states [[transcendental]] to the [[ordinary man]].[29]
+
By contrast, [[Kamalaśīla]] then would be said to hold [[gradualism]] because he maintains loyalty to [[Śūnyavāda]] {{Wiki|monism}} by refusing to grant {{Wiki|ontological}} {{Wiki|status}} to anything but the [[Absolute]].
  
    The [[cognitive]] {{Wiki|optimism}} of [[early Buddhism]] rests, in turn, on the presuppositions underlying the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[meditation]] outlined earlier. The [[Buddhists]] [[thought]] they knew how the [[mind]] worked and what techniques would best serve to enable it to work for [[human]] [[happiness]]. Insofar as early [[Buddhist meditation]] methods are concerned, they are specific to the compromised [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[knowledge]] spelled out by [[Gellner]]. One can, in fact, generate the model of early [[Buddhist meditation]] merely by reversing the [[order]] of the [[empiricist]] model of critical [[accumulation]] of sense-data. As one had gradually [[accumulated]] sense-data and passed them before the inner censor, the "[[ghost]]," before risking knowledge-claims, so also in [[meditation]] one gradually surpasses classes of sense-data [[experience]] and [[knowledge]]. Urged on by [[vipāssana]] [[criticism]], the [[meditator]] presses along the [[jhānic]] route to higher [[meditational]] levels, completely stripped of sense-data [[information]].
+
Yet, it seems [[Wikipedia:Coherentism|incoherent]] of [[Wikipedia:Giuseppe Tucci |Tucci]] to say that it is [[Hva-San]]'s simultaneous admission of {{Wiki|ontological}} {{Wiki|status}} to both these {{Wiki|principles}} which breaks "the {{Wiki|monism}} of [[Mahāyāna]],"  causing [[meditation]] to recede into the background and dictating a [[subitist]] [[view]] of the [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]].  
  
    Thus, reliable ordinary [[knowledge]] as well as [[nirvāna]] require [[gradual]], diligent, and critical attention—analytic care in sifting our [[perceptions]] and [[beliefs]]. In [[meditation]], this becomes even more severe as the [[meditator]] empties the [[mind]] of these {{Wiki|data}}, noting their content and [[form]] as they are transcended until [[nirvāna]] itself is [[attained]]. One is not typically encouraged to leap to {{Wiki|conclusions}} (or [[nirvāna]]) in [[early Buddhism]]. One is invited to analyze and verify the [[dhamma]] experientially and ultimately in [[meditation]]. The [[meditator]] initiates a relentless and deliberate selection process, which seeks to {{Wiki|liberate}} the {{Wiki|perceiver}} from the bondage of the inward flowof [[causally]] agent [[sensations]]. In [[meditation]], a [[Buddhist]] tries to understand sense-data, and therefore [[knowledge]], in their own terms, and declare them for what they are.
+
If anything, the {{Wiki|opposite}} should occur; if one breaks the {{Wiki|monism}} of the [[Mahāyāna]] into such a [[dualism]], how then can either of these [[realities]] pass away suddenly?
  
    All this makes for a measured and certain {{Wiki|optimism}} about man's potential for {{Wiki|salvation}} unaided by [[occult]] [[power]] or [[cosmic]] [[fate]]. In the context of this analytic, trial-and-error [[cognitive]] quest, one is advised not to expect rapid results, although these could, of course, occur. The early [[Buddhists]] encouraged persistence. [[Effort]] brought results. The point was to keep at it, to [[form]] the [[habits]] of [[mind]] and [[action]] which would surely (but not automatically) bring results.
+
If the [[abhūtapariikalpita]] is [[empowered]] to project the [[world]] of [[representation]], how does it also pass away in the face of [[sūnyatā]] which [[Wikipedia:Giuseppe Tucci |Tucci]] implies is {{Wiki|ontologically}} {{Wiki|distinct}}?
  
V. GRADUAL AND [[SUDDEN ENLIGHTENMENT]]: HISTORIC DEBATES 1: [[CHINA]]
+
It seems that either the "{{Wiki|monism}} of [[Mahāyāna]]" is not really broken, in which case [[Wikipedia:Giuseppe Tucci |Tucci's]] {{Wiki|solution}} does not even get started, or that it is broken, in which case one is not yet [[enlightened]], because one has not yet penetrated into  [[sūnyatā]].
  
    Thus far, I have tried to [[illuminate]] the {{Wiki|nature}} of early [[Buddhist meditation]] and the [[belief]] in [[gradual enlightenment]] by appealing to the notion of early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}}. In a nutshell, I have argued that early [[Buddhist meditation]] {{Wiki|theory}} is imbedded in a compromised [[empiricist]] {{Wiki|epistemology}} and, as such, will  reflect salient {{Wiki|characteristics}} of this {{Wiki|epistemological}} syndrome. Even though ordinary [[knowledge]] requires accumulating sense-data, both {{Wiki|processes}} occur by '[[gradual]]' means—in both the descriptive and prescriptive [[senses]] of that term. As a structuralist, I have shown that [[Gellner's]] compromised version of {{Wiki|empiricism}} is homologous to early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}} in both descriptive and prescriptive {{Wiki|dimensions}}.  
+
Either way, [[Wikipedia:Giuseppe Tucci |Tucci]] does not seem to have succeeded in his [[aim]]. Moreover, in the fact of his [[own]] supposed {{Wiki|monism}} [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[gradualism]] becomes all the more mysterious, and not less so.
  
[[Meditation]] in [[early Buddhism]] constitutes a counterpoint variant of this common theme, seeming for the most part a structural inversion of the [[empiricist]] statement about ordinary acquisition of [[knowledge]].
+
I would merely point out that the text of the [[Bhāvanākrama]] gives no indication that [[Hva-San]] is any kind critic of {{Wiki|monism}}.  
  
    The critical reader will want some test of this {{Wiki|thesis}}. And, if structuralism is not to become just another occasion for clever [[dialectical]] [[shenanigans]], structuralists must offer some check on their own method. The {{Wiki|perfect}} test of this {{Wiki|thesis}} would be a [[debate]] between a proponent of early [[Buddhist empiricism]] who held the gradualist position, and another kind of [[Buddhist]] who held the sudden position—typically a [[Rinzai]] [[Zen]] [[Buddhist]]. The {{Wiki|nature}} of the test would be to see if one could correlate opposed [[beliefs]] about the [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]] with opposed {{Wiki|epistemological}} beliefs—understanding all the while that both kinds of [[epistemologies]] may operate in these contexts in compromised [[forms]].
+
And, if he were, he would probably prefer [[gradual enlightenment]] over the sudden [[view]]. [[Kamalaśīla]], on the other hand, does give indications of having watered down the [[transcendental]] {{Wiki|monism}} one might expect him to have observed.
  
    In the {{Wiki|history}} of [[Buddhism]], the issue of [[gradual]] and [[sudden enlightenment]] has arisen on two conspicuous occasions: the eighth-century controversies between the Northern and [[Southern schools]] of [[Ch'an Buddhism]] in [[China]], and between the [[Indian]] and {{Wiki|Chinese}} parties at the {{Wiki|Council}} of [[bSamYas]] (792-794) (the so-called {{Wiki|Council}} of {{Wiki|Lhasa}}) in [[Tibet]].[30] Of the two, the {{Wiki|Chinese}} controversy gives fullest treatment to the sudden position. Indeed, the focus classicus of the sudden [[view]] {{Wiki|remains}} the [[Platform Sutra of the Sixth Patriarch]], attributed to the 'victor' of the [[debate]] and founder of the [[Southern school]] of [[Ch'an]], [[Hui-Neng]] (638-713). Thanks to [[Yampolsky's]] recent research of this text and its historical context,[31] much has become clear. For one, [[Yampolsky]] argues that one should attribute the authorship of the [[sūtra]] to [[Shen-hui]], one of [[Hui-Neng's]] [[disciples]], rather than to the [[sixth patriarch]] himself. Together with [[Dumoulin's]] work in this area, one can be reasonably certain in correlating [[Hui-Neng's]] sudden {{Wiki|theory}} of [[enlightenment]] with a certain epistemological-cum-ontological position opposed to that of [[early Buddhism]].
+
This stems from [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[philosophical]] indebtedness to [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]] through his [[teacher]], [[Sāntaraksita]].  
  
    We know that [[Hui-Neng]] ([[Shen-hui]])[32] [[taught]] the "sudden" [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]] against the celebrated [[Ch'an]] [[teacher]], and [[sixth patriarch]] according to the [[Northern school]], [[Shen-hsiu]]. But, what did he mean? [[Dumoulin]] claims that [[Hui-Neng]] even makes it the sole criterion for {{Wiki|orthodoxy}}![33] What can be contained in this cryptic claim to [[merit]] such importance? And what can explain the fierce attacks [[Hui-Neng]] aimed at [[Shen-hsiu]]? Well, [[Hui-Neng]] most certainly did not mean [[enlightenment]] was "easily obtainable" or even quickly won," [34] although these were not ruled out. Like the early [[Buddhists]], [[Hui-Neng]] had higher purposes in [[mind]]. Both were concerned to make certain points about [[human]] {{Wiki|psychology}} and [[knowledge]], using the idioms of {{Wiki|temporal}} duration and spatial levels when these suited their purposes. Both seem to insist, quite often without apparent {{Wiki|purpose}}, that [[enlightenment]] occurred in a way harmonious with their practices and basic [[views]].
+
Potter  and Warder argue {{Wiki|independently}} that [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[thought]] represents a partial {{Wiki|synthesis}} of the {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[traditions]] of the [[Pramānavarttikam]] of [[Dharmakīrti]] and the [[Svatāntrika]] [[Mādhayamaka]] of [[Bhāvaviveka]].  
  
    [[Dumoulin]][35] and [[Yampolsky]] agree that the [[belief]] in [[sudden enlightenment]] has two sides. Negatively, it denies that the goal, [[prajñā]], can be produced by a "step-by-step process of [[meditation]],"[36] [[dhyāna]]—odd, one would have [[thought]], for the [[Dhyāna]] school ([[Ch'an]]) to assert. Positively, it was a way of asserting the [[truth]] of {{Wiki|a priori}} [[nonduality]]—that [[prajñā]] is "something possessed from the outset by everyone."[37] The point is to realize the imminent {{Wiki|a priori}} {{Wiki|nature}} of [[enlightenment]] and to let it shine through. [[Meditation]] cannot effect [[enlightenment]] because, strictly {{Wiki|speaking}}, [[meditation]] and the [[passions]] it seeks to purge are {{Wiki|ontologically}} [[empty]] and [[illusory]].
+
Taken together, these [[influences]] seem to confirm [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[belief]] in the worth of [[logic]] and {{Wiki|analysis}}, against what Potter believes to have been the [[Yogācārin]] attempt to downgrade them.
  
    Thus, at bottom, the [[doctrine]] of [[sudden enlightenment]] is a way of denying the [[jhanās]] and of asserting the {{Wiki|a priori}} {{Wiki|nature}} of [[enlightenment]] in the idiom of [[meditational]] practice. As the early [[Buddhists]] set out to operationalize early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|empiricism}} with the descriptive and prescriptive [[senses]] of gradualism, so also does [[Hui-Neng]] seem intent on operationalizing his own [[philosophical]] position in the sudden [[view]] of the [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]]: there are no real—even impermanent—grades of [[enlightenment]]; thus there is no need to test for {{Wiki|a priori}} [[enlightenment]], since all [[beings]] are [[enlightened]] by {{Wiki|nature}}.
+
[[Bhāvaviveka]] is said to have made this kind of point by advancing the unique [[view]] of graded levels of [[truth]] within [[sūnyatā]]—as well as within the [[empirical]] [[realm]].
  
    One will recall that the [[Pali Canon]] would certainly tell another kind of story. Although [[meditational]] progress through the [[jhanās]] does not [[causally]] produce [[nirvāna]] on the early [[Buddhist]] [[view]], in {{Wiki|conjunction}} with [[vipāssana]], it is one important way to attain it. However [[impermanent]] they may be, one seeks to transcend the constraints of {{Wiki|real}} (though [[impermanent]]) [[mind]] and [[world]]. [[Impermanence]] itself signals that progress can be made. But, early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|soteriological}} {{Wiki|optimism}} could not lead to the seemingly exaggerated {{Wiki|optimism}} [[embodied]] in the [[belief]] in {{Wiki|a priori}} enlightenment—that the {{Wiki|battle}} was already won, or that virtually no {{Wiki|battle}} needed to be fought. [[Nirvāna]], on the other hand, {{Wiki|transcends}} [[experience]] without {{Wiki|being}} prior to [[experience]]. It is not, strictly {{Wiki|speaking}}, posterior to [[experience]] either, since it is not, as it were, an inductive, [[empirical]] generalization, or [[caused]] by [[meditation]].  
+
If this be {{Wiki|monism}}, it is certainly highly modified.  
  
If I may be permitted a neologism, the [[word]] 'transposterior' (to [[experience]]) may capture the {{Wiki|flavor}} of the relationship of [[nirvāna]] to ordinary [[experience]]. By this I mean that [[nirvāna]] is not {{Wiki|a priori}}, and only can be said to be [[Wikipedia:Empirical evidence|a posteriori]] if one stipulates that it is held to transcend [[experience]].[38] Historically, this position may have arisen from conflict with {{Wiki|brahminical}} [[Wikipedia:rationalism|rationalists]], if we follow ppJayatilleke's[[ [39] suggestion. What {{Wiki|remains}} important is the early [[Buddhist]] [[aversion]] to [[apriorism]] —even if it meant constructing an {{Wiki|empiricism}} which finally may have (to put it charitably) transcended itself in the special case of the {{Wiki|nature}} of [[nirvana]]. [[Hui-Neng]] and the [[Southern school]] of [[Ch'an Buddhism]] felt no such [[aversion]] for the {{Wiki|a priori}}. In fact, they celebrated it, and consequently [[thought]] that it merely had to be seen beneath the surface of an already [[illusory]] [[world]]. [[Enlightenment was sudden]]' because it was {{Wiki|a priori}} and without even {{Wiki|ontological}} competition from an [[impermanent]] [[world]].
+
To admit grades of {{Wiki|being}} is virtually to admit kinds of {{Wiki|being}}, which is really to break the purer [[forms]] of the {{Wiki|monism}} of [[Mahāyāna]].  
  
 +
For [[Dharmakīrti]], the {{Wiki|ontological}} basis of his positive [[attitude]] toward [[reason]] seems to be a certain {{Wiki|materialist}} or physicalist—tending convictions.
  
VI. GRADUAL AND [[SUDDEN ENLIGHTENMENT]]: HISTORIC DEBATES II: [[TIBET]]
+
Against the [[Yogācārins]], [[Dharmakīrti]]  argued the "[[relative]] {{Wiki|independent}} [[reality]] of [[objects]]," and that [[reality]] has "[[arthakryātra]], the [[character]] of doing something ... of making a difference."
  
    The second classic locus of this [[debate]] is the late eighth-century controversy which occasioned the {{Wiki|Council}} of [[bSam Yas]] (so-called [[Council of Lhasa]]). Here, the [[Indian]] [[Mādhyamika]] [[logician]], [[Kamalaśīla]] (742-804) argued a gradualist position against a {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[Ch'an]] [[teacher]], [[Hva San]], and his [[Tibetan]] allies, the [[rDzogs-chen]]. Far more importance is [[attached]] to this [[debate]] than may seem warranted. Yet, the issue was clearly [[thought]] to have been {{Wiki|central}} to the subsequent [[development]] of [[Buddhism]] in [[Tibet]]. Our accounts of the [[debate]] records the point of [[view]] of the victor, in this case [[Kamalaśīla]] in his own [[Bhāvanākrama]] . We learn little of the [[views]] of [[Hva-San]] and his company from this text and are thus led to speculate about their fuller [[form]] and the possible relationship with the earlier teachings of [[Hui-Neng]] and his school. Although the connections between these two are not certain, many similarities of points of [[view]] can be established, which in themselves may point in the [[direction]] of relationship.
+
[[Empirical]] [[perception]] ([[pratyakna]]) is therefore a [[pramāna]] (a means of [[knowledge]]), and '"effect of [[reality]]"' and not an [[illusion]].
  
    The [[interesting]] thing about [[Kamalaśīla]] is that he seems to argue a gradualism similar to what we have discovered in early [[Buddhist meditation]] but, at first [[sight]], without sufficient {{Wiki|theoretical}} basis to do so. His [[philosophical]] position, as best one can make out from the often conflicting accounts of it, is exceedingly rich and complex. He seems at once a [[Svatāntrika]] [[Mādhyamakin]],[40] [[Śūnyavādin]], as well as [[logician]] and {{Wiki|pragmatist}} in the [[tradition]] of [[Dharmakīrti]].[41] {{Wiki|Historians}} of [[Indian philosophy]] have also identified him as a critic of the [[Yogācārins]].[42] [[Kamalaśīla]], himself,[43] seems to [[recognize]] that these [[philosophical]] positions produce in him a certain amount of [[intellectual]] and {{Wiki|practical}} tension. This is so especially in {{Wiki|connection}} with his [[desire]] both to [[acknowledge]] the [[transcendent]] primacy of [[Śūnyavāda]] {{Wiki|monism}}, along with the rather [[mundane]], though nonetheless wholehearted, [[devotion]] to the [[bodhisattva ideal]] of [[compassion]] and [[meditation]]. What makes [[Kamalaśīla]] [[interesting]] then, is his conviction that [[enlightenment comes gradually]] and that one should press on with [[dhyāna]] and [[karunā]], despite the awkward higher [[truth]] of the [[Śūnyatā]].[44]
+
In this way [[Dharmakīrti]] undercuts any attempt to [[empower]] [[thought]] alone to make {{Wiki|real}} changes in the {{Wiki|status}} of a [[person]] seeking [[enlightenment]].
  
    This cannot have been a [[concern]] original to [[Kamalaśīla]]. Other [[Mādhyamikas]] must have shared it. But, it must have been especially acute in th like [[Hui-Neng]], [[taught]] [[sudden enlightenment]] in the [[sense]] that [[meditation]] in the progressive [[manner]] was unnecessary.[45] Perhaps {{Wiki|reflecting}} the supposed [[Yogācāra]] background of [[Ch'an]], [[Hva-San]] teaches the {{Wiki|idealist}} [[view]] that [[thought]] is at the [[root]] of all se face of [[Hva-San's]] {{Wiki|idealist}} {{Wiki|monistic}} teachings which reflected no such qualms about pressing on with the [[worldly]] exercises of [[dhyāna]] and [[karūna]]. One need merely stop [[thinking]] to stop [[suffering]]. And [[thinking]] could be stopped suddenly—without progress through the [[jhānas]] or [[bodhisattvabhūmis]].[46] In this way {{Wiki|a priori}} [[enlightenment]] simply shines through. [[Hva-San]] {{Wiki|sounds}} very much the [[Yogacārin]] or close [[relative]] of [[Hui-Neng's]] [[Ch'an Buddhism]] in this passage:
+
The [[views]] of [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]], then, seem remarkably similar to [[Kamalaśīla's]] conviction, throughout the [[Bhāvanākrama]], that the [[world]] and ordinary [[knowledge]] could not merely be [[thought]] away,
  
    [We] ourselves [are] coessential with the [[Buddha]], and all {{Wiki|representations}} which constitute the [[world]] {{Wiki|being}} [[illusory]] or a [[magic]] play of the [[Absolute]].... What we need is only to jump ... from the plane of {{Wiki|representations}} into that [[Buddhahood]], our [[true nature]], by sudden elimination of those [[mental]] {{Wiki|representations}}. We must arrest the play of their [[emanation]], stop our [[mind]], and see into our own {{Wiki|nature}}.[47]
+
but had to be undermined by serious [[meditative]] and analytic praxis.  
  
    But, what is it about having the [[Buddha-nature]] within us that requires a sudden interpretation of the [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]], along with the rejection of the [[jhānas]], {{Wiki|analysis}}, and the [[compassion]] of the [[bodhisattva]]? Except for the [[doctrine]] of {{Wiki|a priori}} [[enlightenment]], grounded in the possession of the [[Buddha-nature]], [[Kamalaśīla]] and [[Hva-San]] would seem to share at least the [[transcendental]] {{Wiki|monism}}, [[characteristic]] of both [[Śūnyavāda]] and [[Yogācāra]], respectively. One will, of course, want to make [[appropriate]] qualifications for differences in these {{Wiki|characteristics}} of the [[Absolute]].  
+
[[Dharmakīrti]] even explicitly holds this [[view]].  
  
Yet, in [[spite]] of that, one wonders how and why [[Kamalaśīla]] can commit himself so thoroughly to the [[worldly]] practices of [[dhyāna]] and [[karūna]], [[knowing]] full well that these are onto-logically insubstantial? Has not [[Hva-San]] really drawn the natural {{Wiki|consequences}} of [[transcendental]] {{Wiki|monism}}? Is not [[Kamalaśīla]] quixotically supporting some [[venerable]], but outmoded, [[tradition]] of the [[sūtras]], which by some kind of [[intellectual]] {{Wiki|inertia}}, now soldiers on without adequate {{Wiki|theoretical}} basis?
+
In Potter's words, "one obtains [[yogic]] [[insight]] ... by sharpening one's [[understanding]] or [[insight]] by [[meditation]] and [[dialectic]],"
  
    [[Tucci]] is one of the few [[scholars]] to have appreciated the awkwardness and poignancy of [[Kamalaśīla]] position.[48] But, his rather oblique {{Wiki|solution}} to [[Kamalaśīla's]] quandry only precipitates a puzzle of his own. {{Wiki|Speaking}} first of [[Hva-San]], [[Tucci]] claims the [[sudden enlightenment doctrine]] follows from the simultaneous granting of {{Wiki|ontological}} {{Wiki|status}} to both [[abhūtapariikalpita]] ("[[power]] of [[subjective]] [[representation]]") and [[Śūnyatā]]. By contrast, [[Kamalaśīla]] then would be said to hold gradualism because he maintains loyalty to [[Śūnyavāda]] {{Wiki|monism}} by refusing to grant {{Wiki|ontological}} {{Wiki|status}} to anything but the [[Absolute]].
+
For both [[Dharmakīrti]] and [[Kamalaśīla]] this seemed also to mean that testing and a [[spirit]] of censoriousness ([[Gellner]]) become important. In classic [[empiricist]] style, [[Dharmakīrti]] believed a {{Wiki|theory}} of [[knowledge]] ought to stand the test of [[experience]]" and "practice."
  
    Yet, it seems [[Wikipedia:Coherentism|incoherent]] of [[Wikipedia:Giuseppe Tucci |Tucci]] to say that it is [[Hva-San]]'s simultaneous admission of {{Wiki|ontological}} {{Wiki|status}} to both these {{Wiki|principles}} which breaks "the {{Wiki|monism}} of [[Mahāyāna]],"[49] causing [[meditation]] to recede into the background and dictating a subitist [[view]] of the [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]]. If anything, the {{Wiki|opposite}} should occur; if one breaks the {{Wiki|monism}} of the [[Mahāyāna]] into such a [[dualism]], how then can either of these [[realities]] pass away suddenly?
+
Quite probably {{Wiki|reflecting}} this influence while quoting the [[sutras]] in his [[Nyāyabindupūrvapaksasanksipiti]], [[Kamalaśīla]] reports the [[Buddha]] saying: " 0 Brethern! . .. never do accept my words from sheer reverential [[feelings]]! Let learned [[scholars]] test them... ."
  
If the [[abhūtapariikalpita]] is [[empowered]] to project the [[world]] of [[representation]], how does it also pass away in the face of [[sūnyatā]] which [[Wikipedia:Giuseppe Tucci |Tucci]] implies is {{Wiki|ontologically}} {{Wiki|distinct}}? It seems that either the "{{Wiki|monism}} of [[Mahāyāna]]" is not really broken, in which case [[Wikipedia:Giuseppe Tucci |Tucci's]] {{Wiki|solution}} does not even get started, or that it is broken, in which case one is not yet [[enlightened]], because one has not yet penetrated into  [[sūnyatā]]. Either way, [[Wikipedia:Giuseppe Tucci |Tucci]] does not seem to have succeeded in his [[aim]]. Moreover, in the fact of his own supposed {{Wiki|monism}} [[Kamalaśīla's]] gradualism becomes all the more mysterious, and not less so.
 
  
    I would merely point out that the text of the [[Bhāvanākrama]] gives no indication that [[Hva-San]] is any kind critic of {{Wiki|monism}}. And, if he were, he would probably prefer [[gradual]] [[enlightenment]] over the sudden [[view]]. [[Kamalaśīla]], on the other hand, does give indications of having watered down the [[transcendental]] {{Wiki|monism}} one might expect him to have observed.
+
In the [[Bhāvanākrama]], [[Kamalaśīla]] himself brings [[meditation]] into play with experiential testing: "
  
    This stems from [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[philosophical]] indebtedness to [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]] through his [[teacher]], [[Sāntaraksita]]. Potter[50] and Warder[51] argue {{Wiki|independently}} that [[Kamalaśīla's]]  [[thought]] represents a partial {{Wiki|synthesis}} of the {{Wiki|epistemological}} [[traditions]] of the [[Pramānavarttikam]] of [[Dharmakīrti]] and the [[Svatāntrika]] [[Mādhayamaka]] of [[Bhāvaviveka]]. Taken together, these [[influences]] seem to confirm [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[belief]] in the worth of [[logic]] and {{Wiki|analysis}},[52] against what Potter believes to have been the [[Yogācārin]] attempt to downgrade them.[53] [[Bhāvaviveka]] is said to have made this kind of point by advancing the unique [[view]] of graded levels of [[truth]] within [[sūnyatā]]—as well as within the [[empirical]] [[realm]].[54] If this be {{Wiki|monism}}, it is certainly highly modified.  
+
Having thus ascertained [[reality]] by means of [[gnosis]] consisting in [[investigation]], in [[order]] to make this evident, one should have recourse to the [[gnosis]] consisting in {{Wiki|contemplation}}. .. ."
  
To admit grades of {{Wiki|being}} is virtually to admit kinds of {{Wiki|being}}, which is really to break the purer [[forms]] of the {{Wiki|monism}} of [[Mahāyāna]]. For [[Dharmakīrti]], the {{Wiki|ontological}} basis of his positive [[attitude]] toward [[reason]] seems to be a certain {{Wiki|materialist}} or physicalist—tending convictions. Against the [[Yogācārins]], [[Dharmakīrti]]  argued the "[[relative]] {{Wiki|independent}} [[reality]] of [[objects]],"[55] and that [[reality]] has "[[arthakryātra]], the [[character]] of doing something ... of making a difference."[56] [[Empirical]] [[perception]] ([[pratyakna]]) is therefore a [[pramāna]] (a means of [[knowledge]]), and '"effect of [[reality]]"' and not an [[illusion]].[57] In this way [[Dharmakīrti]] undercuts any attempt to [[empower]] [[thought]] alone to make {{Wiki|real}} changes in the {{Wiki|status}} of a [[person]] seeking [[enlightenment]].
 
  
    The [[views]] of [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]], then, seem remarkably similar to [[Kamalaśīla's]] conviction, throughout the [[Bhāvanākrama]], that the [[world]] and ordinary [[knowledge]] could not merely be [[thought]] away, but had to be undermined by serious [[meditative]] and analytic praxis. [[Dharmakīrti]] even explicitly holds this [[view]]. In Potter's words, "one obtains [[yogic]] [[insight]] ... by sharpening one's [[understanding]] or [[insight]] by [[meditation]] and [[dialectic]],"[58]
+
[[Kamalaśīla]] even seems to share the [[view]] of [[King]] about the complementary roles of the [[jhānas]] and [[vipāssana]] in [[Theravāda Buddhism]]. Here {{Wiki|speaking}} of the [[jhānas]] in terms of [[samādhi]],  
  
    For both [[Dharmakīrti]] and [[Kamalaśīla]] this seemed also to mean that testing and a [[spirit]] of censoriousness (Gellner) become important. In classic [[empiricist]] style, [[Dharmakīrti]] believed a {{Wiki|theory}} of [[knowledge]] ought to stand the test of [[experience]]" and "practice."[59] Quite probably {{Wiki|reflecting}} this influence while quoting the [[sutras]] in his [[Nyāyabindupūrvapaksasanksipiti]], [[Kamalaśīla]] reports the [[Buddha]] saying: " 0 Brethern! . .. never do accept my words from sheer reverential [[feelings]]! Let learned [[scholars]] test them... ."[60]
+
[[Kamalaśīla]] seems to repeat the [[division]] of labor between these two branches of [[meditation]] which I also linked with [[Gellner's]] claims about the descriptive and prescriptive aspects of {{Wiki|empiricism}}:  
  
In the [[Bhāvanākrama]], [[Kamalaśīla]] himself brings [[meditation]] into play with experiential testing: " Having thus ascertained [[reality]] by means of [[gnosis]] consisting in [[investigation]], in [[order]] to make this evident, one should have recourse to the [[gnosis]] consisting in {{Wiki|contemplation}}. .. ."[61]
+
" ... when his [[mind]] has been taken hold of by the hand, as it were, of [[samādhi]], the [[yogin]], by using the sharper weapon of [[gnosis]] should [[root]] out the [[seeds]] of false [[imagination]]. .. ."
  
    [[Kamalaśīla]] even seems to share the [[view]] of [[King]] about the complementary roles of the [[jhānas]] and [[vipāssana]] in [[Theravāda Buddhism]]. Here {{Wiki|speaking}} of the [[jhānas]] in terms of [[samādhi]], [[Kamalaśīla]] seems to repeat the [[division]] of labor between these two branches of [[meditation]] which I also linked with Gellner's claims about the descriptive and prescriptive aspects of {{Wiki|empiricism}}: " ... when his [[mind]] has been taken hold of by the hand, as it were, of [[samādhi]], the [[yogin]], by using the sharper weapon of [[gnosis]] should [[root]] out the [[seeds]] of false [[imagination]]. .. ."[62]
+
In these ways, [[Kamalaśīla]] seems to conform to much of the empiricist-cum-materiahst [[spirit]] of [[early Buddhism]] through the influence of [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]].  
  
    In these ways, [[Kamalaśīla]] seems to conform to much of the empiricist-cum-materiahst [[spirit]] of [[early Buddhism]] through the influence of [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]]. To the extent that these [[empiricist]] and {{Wiki|materialist}} {{Wiki|tendencies}} inform [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[thinking]] about [[meditation]] one would explain [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[teaching]] of the [[doctrine]] of [[gradual]] [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]] on the same grounds as I have tried to do with the early [[Buddhists]].
+
To the extent that these [[empiricist]] and {{Wiki|materialist}} {{Wiki|tendencies}} inform [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[thinking]] about [[meditation]] one would explain [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[teaching]] of the [[doctrine]] of [[gradual]] [[attainment]] of [[enlightenment]] on the same grounds as I have tried to do with the early [[Buddhists]].
  
VII. CONCLUSION: BELIEF, PRACTICE, AND STRUCTURE
 
  
    To gain a unifying structural [[insight]] into [[Kamalaśīla's]] situation I want to conclude this [[discussion]] by pushing [[beyond]] the rather straightforward [[discussion]] of the {{Wiki|history}} and content of [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[thought]]. Granted that [[Kamalaśīla]] was influenced by both [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]], one might go on to ask what [[conditions]] of [[Kamalaśīla's]] {{Wiki|practical}} situation reinforced his adherence to an [[empiricist]] and materialist-tending [[tradition]]?
 
  
Here, I want to suggest that [[Kamalaśīla's]] {{Wiki|practical}} [[discipline]] of {{Wiki|analysis}} and [[compassion]] may have 'fit' better with the world-view he inherited from [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]], and thus that, in consequence, it was favored. [[Kamalaśīla]] could not have been a [[pure]] [[Śūnyavādin]] [[Absolutist]] without [[suffering]] substantial disharmonies in his overall approach to the [[world]]. [[Kamalaśīla]] may have [[thought]] and [[taught]] more like an empiricist-cum-materialist early [[Buddhist]], partly because he also acted like one. In taking the [[world]] of [[thought]] and {{Wiki|being}} as at least provisionally {{Wiki|real}} in [[meditation]], {{Wiki|analysis}}, and [[compassionate]] {{Wiki|behavior}}, [[Kamalaśīla]] may very well have come to think about the [[appropriate]] means of [[release]] as gradual—much as did the early [[Buddhists]].
+
==Vii. Conclusion: [[Belief]], Practice, And Structure==
  
    I am suggesting that [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[belief]] in [[gradual]] [[enlightenment]] may have been connected to his practice in somewhat the same way some [[beliefs]] might be said to be induced by certain practices. In the [[Buddhist tradition]] one [[thinks]] of the [[belief]] in the [[transcendental]] [[Buddha]] as having possibly been induced by the practice of [[buddhapūjā]], which does not in itself require such a [[transcendental]] objectof {{Wiki|worship}}. Although [[buddhapūjā]] is, strictly {{Wiki|speaking}}, an act of [[remembrance]], such practices tend, quite often, to induce a [[belief]] in the [[existence]] of their [[object]]. Gombrich suggests that in {{Wiki|modern}} [[Theravādin]] countries one can observe this {{Wiki|movement}} from mere [[recollection]] of the exemplary [[earthly]] [[life]] of the long-deceased [[historical Buddha]] to the [[belief]] in the [[transcendental]] [[existence]] of the [[Buddha]], now [[thought]] to be available to [[human]] entreaties.[63]
 
  
    I do not believe these {{Wiki|processes}} happen mechanically or through [[Wikipedia:Causality|causal]] connections, as typically [[conceived]]. [[Human]] {{Wiki|culture}} seems too intricate and [[human beings]] too {{Wiki|subtle}} for the mechanistic process to be the strongest candidate explanation here. A likelier model might be one which takes its rise from Levi-Strauss[64]: to the {{Wiki|degree}} one finds structural affinities between practices and [[beliefs]], perhaps one should consider such affinities either a working out of certain deep common structures, or perhaps related by a sort of formal or structural [[causality]]. Men often do things for structural reasons—whether the structures lie behind the things in question or whether they operate on the same level. In [[Kamalaśīla's]] case, he may have advocated the [[belief]] in [[gradual]] [[release]] and the practice of [[meditation]], {{Wiki|analysis}}, and [[compassion]] because of some deep common {{Wiki|structure}}, or because either [[belief]] or practice were [[causally]] prior, and same in [[form]].
+
 
     This speculation suggests that a kind of formal [[causality]] may be at work in the passage from deeper levels of {{Wiki|culture}} to other more accessible to {{Wiki|common sense}}, or between things on the same level of {{Wiki|culture}}. In the context of [[Buddhist meditation]] and theories of [[release]], I offer that one does not practice analytic methods of [[meditation]] and painstaking [[human]] [[compassion]] for lengths of [[time]] without having something of those [[activities]] 'rub off' on other levels of life—in our case the gradualist {{Wiki|theory}} of the [[attainment]] of [[release]]. (The same also goes for the effect of [[beliefs]] on practices.) Among the things which 'rub off', I want to identify the notion of [[form]] or {{Wiki|structure}}. Critical analytic [[meditational]] methods and serious [[concern]] for ordinary [[human]] well-being, conform to the [[gradual]] kind of [[enlightenment]], at once described as a graded route and prescribed as a critical, analytic censoriousness about claims to, [[knowledge]].
+
To gain a unifying structural [[insight]] into [[Kamalaśīla's]] situation I want to conclude this [[discussion]] by pushing [[beyond]] the rather straightforward [[discussion]] of the {{Wiki|history}} and content of [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[thought]].
 +
 
 +
Granted that [[Kamalaśīla]] was influenced by both [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]], one might go on to ask what [[conditions]] of [[Kamalaśīla's]] {{Wiki|practical}} situation reinforced his adherence to an [[empiricist]] and materialist-tending [[tradition]]?
 +
 
 +
Here, I want to suggest that [[Kamalaśīla's]] {{Wiki|practical}} [[discipline]] of {{Wiki|analysis}} and [[compassion]] may have 'fit' better with the world-view he inherited from [[Bhāvaviveka]] and [[Dharmakīrti]],
 +
 
 +
and thus that, in consequence, it was favored. [[Kamalaśīla]] could not have been a [[pure]] [[Śūnyavādin]] [[Absolutist]] without [[suffering]] substantial disharmonies in his overall approach to the [[world]].
 +
 
 +
[[Kamalaśīla]] may have [[thought]] and [[taught]] more like an empiricist-cum-materialist early [[Buddhist]], partly because he also acted like one.
 +
 
 +
In taking the [[world]] of [[thought]] and {{Wiki|being}} as at least provisionally {{Wiki|real}} in [[meditation]], {{Wiki|analysis}}, and [[compassionate]] {{Wiki|behavior}}, [[Kamalaśīla]] may very well have come to think about the [[appropriate]] means of [[release]] as gradual—much as did the early [[Buddhists]].
 +
 
 +
I am suggesting that [[Kamalaśīla's]] [[belief]] in [[gradual]] [[enlightenment]] may have been connected to his practice in somewhat the same way some [[beliefs]] might be said to be induced by certain practices.
 +
 
 +
In the [[Buddhist tradition]] one [[thinks]] of the [[belief]] in the [[transcendental]] [[Buddha]] as having possibly been induced by the practice of [[buddhapūjā]], which does not in itself require such a [[transcendental]] objectof {{Wiki|worship}}.
 +
 
 +
Although [[buddhapūjā]] is, strictly {{Wiki|speaking}}, an act of [[remembrance]], such practices tend, quite often, to induce a [[belief]] in the [[existence]] of their [[object]].
 +
 
 +
Gombrich suggests that in {{Wiki|modern}} [[Theravādin]] countries one can observe this {{Wiki|movement}} from mere [[recollection]] of the exemplary [[earthly]] [[life]] of the long-deceased [[historical Buddha]] to the [[belief]] in the [[transcendental]] [[existence]] of the [[Buddha]], now [[thought]] to be available to [[human]] entreaties.
 +
 
 +
I do not believe these {{Wiki|processes}} happen mechanically or through [[Wikipedia:Causality|causal]] connections, as typically [[conceived]].  
 +
 
 +
[[Human]] {{Wiki|culture}} seems too intricate and [[human beings]] too {{Wiki|subtle}} for the mechanistic process to be the strongest candidate explanation here.  
 +
 
 +
A likelier model might be one which takes its rise from Levi-Strauss: to the {{Wiki|degree}} one finds structural affinities between practices and [[beliefs]], perhaps one should consider such affinities either a working out of certain deep common structures, or perhaps related by a sort of formal or structural [[causality]].  
 +
 
 +
Men often do things for structural reasons—whether the structures lie behind the things in question or whether they operate on the same level.  
 +
 
 +
In [[Kamalaśīla's]] case, he may have advocated the [[belief]] in [[gradual]] [[release]] and the practice of [[meditation]], {{Wiki|analysis}}, and [[compassion]] because of some deep common {{Wiki|structure}}, or because either [[belief]] or practice were [[causally]] prior, and same in [[form]].
 +
      
 +
 
 +
This speculation suggests that a kind of formal [[causality]] may be at work in the passage from deeper levels of {{Wiki|culture}} to other more accessible to {{Wiki|common sense}}, or between things on the same level of {{Wiki|culture}}.  
 +
 
 +
In the context of [[Buddhist meditation]] and theories of [[release]], I offer that one does not practice analytic methods of [[meditation]] and painstaking [[human]] [[compassion]] for lengths of [[time]] without having something of those [[activities]] 'rub off' on other levels of life—in our case the [[gradualist]] {{Wiki|theory}} of the [[attainment]] of [[release]].  
 +
 
 +
(The same also goes for the effect of [[beliefs]] on practices.)  
 +
 
 +
Among the things which 'rub off', I want to identify the notion of [[form]] or {{Wiki|structure}}. Critical analytic [[meditational]] methods and serious [[concern]] for ordinary [[human]] well-being,  
 +
 
 +
conform to the [[gradual]] kind of [[enlightenment]], at once described as a graded route and prescribed as a critical, analytic censoriousness about claims to, [[knowledge]].
  
  
 
NOTES
 
NOTES
 +
 
[1]. D. Goleman, "Perspectives on {{Wiki|Psychology}}, [[Reality]], and the Study of [[Consciousness]]." Journal of {{Wiki|Transpersonal Psychology}} 4 (1974): 4.   
 
[1]. D. Goleman, "Perspectives on {{Wiki|Psychology}}, [[Reality]], and the Study of [[Consciousness]]." Journal of {{Wiki|Transpersonal Psychology}} 4 (1974): 4.   
 
[2]. W. [[King]], "A Comparison of [[Theravāda]] and [[Zen]] [[Meditation]]." {{Wiki|History}} of [[Religions]], (1969); 310.
 
[2]. W. [[King]], "A Comparison of [[Theravāda]] and [[Zen]] [[Meditation]]." {{Wiki|History}} of [[Religions]], (1969); 310.
 
[3]. Ibid., p. 311.  
 
[3]. Ibid., p. 311.  
 
   
 
   
[4]. K. N. Jayatilleke, Early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Knowledge]] ({{Wiki|London}}: George Alien and Unwin, 1963). See also D. [[Kalupahana]], "A [[Buddhist]] Tract on {{Wiki|Empiric}} ism," [[Philosophy]] {{Wiki|East}} and {{Wiki|West}} 19, N6. 1 (1969). and [[Causality]]: The {{Wiki|Central}} [[Philosophy]] of [[Buddhism]] (Honolulu: {{Wiki|University of Hawaii}}, 1975) and [[Buddhist Philosophy]] (Honolulu: {{Wiki|University of Hawaii}}, 1976).   
+
[4]. K. N. [[Jayatilleke]], Early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Knowledge]] ({{Wiki|London}}: George Alien and Unwin, 1963). See also D. [[Kalupahana]], "A [[Buddhist]] Tract on {{Wiki|Empiric}} ism," [[Philosophy]] {{Wiki|East}} and {{Wiki|West}} 19, N6. 1 (1969). and [[Causality]]: The {{Wiki|Central}} [[Philosophy]] of [[Buddhism]] ([[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University of Hawaii}}, 1975) and [[Buddhist Philosophy]] ([[Honolulu]]: {{Wiki|University of Hawaii}}, 1976).   
[5]. V, Trenckner, A Critical [[Pali]] {{Wiki|Dictionary}}, Volume 1 (Copenhagen: {{Wiki|Royal}} {{Wiki|Danish}} {{Wiki|Academy}} of {{Wiki|Sciences}} and Letters. 1924-1948): 201-202.  
+
[5]. V, [[Trenckner]], A Critical [[Pali]] {{Wiki|Dictionary}}, Volume 1 ([[Copenhagen]]: {{Wiki|Royal}} {{Wiki|Danish}} {{Wiki|Academy}} of {{Wiki|Sciences}} and Letters. 1924-1948): 201-202.  
  
 
[6]. T. Rhys-Davids and W. Stede, eds., [[Pali]] Text Society's [[Pali]] {{Wiki|English}} {{Wiki|Dictionary}} ({{Wiki|London}}: Luzac, 1966): 39.  
 
[6]. T. Rhys-Davids and W. Stede, eds., [[Pali]] Text Society's [[Pali]] {{Wiki|English}} {{Wiki|Dictionary}} ({{Wiki|London}}: Luzac, 1966): 39.  
 
[7]. Ibid., pp. 39,101. [[Nyanatiloka]], [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Dictionary}} ({{Wiki|Colombo}}, [[Sri Lanka]]: Frewin, 1972): 17.  
 
[7]. Ibid., pp. 39,101. [[Nyanatiloka]], [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Dictionary}} ({{Wiki|Colombo}}, [[Sri Lanka]]: Frewin, 1972): 17.  
[8]. Jayatilleke, Early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Knowledge]], p. 40.   
+
[8]. [[Jayatilleke]], Early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Knowledge]], p. 40.   
 
[9]. Ibid., chap. 8.  
 
[9]. Ibid., chap. 8.  
  
[10]. Ibid.,p- 277.   
+
. Ibid.,p- 277.   
[11]. Ibid., p. 466.       
+
. Ibid., p. 466.       
[12]. W, [[King]], "The Structure and [[Function]] of the [[Trance]] of [[Cessation]] in [[Theravada]] [[Meditation]]," {{Wiki|manuscript}} read at Annual Meeting of the American {{Wiki|Academy}} of [[Religion]], {{Wiki|Chicago}}, November, 1975.  
+
. W, [[King]], "The Structure and [[Function]] of the [[Trance]] of [[Cessation]] in [[Theravada]] [[Meditation]]," {{Wiki|manuscript}} read at Annual Meeting of the [[American]] {{Wiki|Academy}} of [[Religion]], {{Wiki|Chicago}}, November, 1975.  
[13]. Ibid., p. 4.  
+
. Ibid., p. 4.  
 
   
 
   
[14]. Ibid., p. 11.   
+
. Ibid., p. 11.   
[15]. Ibid., p. 7.     
+
. Ibid., p. 7.     
[16]. Ibid., p. 8.     
+
. Ibid., p. 8.     
[17]. Ibid,, pp. 14f.   
+
. Ibid,, pp. 14f.   
[18]. E. Gellner, Legitimation of [[Belief]] ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: {{Wiki|Cambridge University Press}}, 1974).  
+
. E. [[Gellner]], Legitimation of [[Belief]] ({{Wiki|Cambridge}}: {{Wiki|Cambridge University Press}}, 1974).  
[19]. Ibid., p. 36.  
+
. Ibid., p. 36.  
 
        
 
        
[20]. Ibid.                       
+
. Ibid.                       
[21]. Ibid., pp. 32f.         
+
. Ibid., pp. 32f.         
[22]. Ibid., p. 38.           
+
. Ibid., p. 38.           
[23]. Ibid., p. 115.         
+
. Ibid., p. 115.         
[24]. Ibid., chaps. 5, 6.       
+
. Ibid., chaps. 5, 6.       
[25]. Ibid., p. 124.                   
+
. Ibid., p. 124.                   
[26]. A. K.. Warder, "[[Early Buddhism]] and Other Contemporary Systems," Bulletin of the School of {{Wiki|Oriental}} and African Studies, 17 (1956); 43-63.                   
+
. A. K.. Warder, "[[Early Buddhism]] and Other Contemporary Systems," Bulletin of the School of {{Wiki|Oriental}} and African Studies, 17 (1956); 43-63.                   
[27]. Gellner, Legitimation, p. 120.  
+
. [[Gellner]], Legitimation, p. 120.  
 
      
 
      
[28]. P. De Silva, [[Buddhist]] and Freudian {{Wiki|Psychology}} ({{Wiki|Colombo}}: [[Lake]] House, 1974).  
+
. P. De Silva, [[Buddhist]] and [[Freudian]] {{Wiki|Psychology}} ({{Wiki|Colombo}}: [[Lake]] House, 1974).  
[29]. R. Johanssen, The {{Wiki|Psychology}} of [[Nirvana]]. ({{Wiki|London}}: Alien and Unwin, 1969).   
+
. R. Johanssen, The {{Wiki|Psychology}} of [[Nirvana]]. ({{Wiki|London}}: Alien and Unwin, 1969).   
[30]. P. Demieville, Le Concile du {{Wiki|Lhasa}} ({{Wiki|Paris}}: Imprimerie Nationale, 1952). [[E. Obermiller]], "A [[Sanskrit]] Ms. from Tibet—Kamalasila's [[Bhavana-krama]]," Journal of the [[Greater]] [[India]] {{Wiki|Society}} 2(1935): 1-11. G. [[Tucci]], trans., Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], Part 11. The First Bhavana-Krama of [[Kamalasila]], Serie Orientale 9 (2) ({{Wiki|Rome}}: Institute Italiano per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente, 1958).
+
. [[P. Demieville]], Le Concile du {{Wiki|Lhasa}} ({{Wiki|Paris}}: Imprimerie Nationale, 1952). [[E. Obermiller]], "A [[Sanskrit]] Ms. from Tibet—Kamalasila's [[Bhavana-krama]]," Journal of the [[Greater]] [[India]] {{Wiki|Society}} 2(1935): 1-11. G. [[Tucci]], trans., Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], Part 11. The First Bhavana-Krama of [[Kamalasila]], Serie Orientale 9 (2) ({{Wiki|Rome}}: Institute Italiano per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente, 1958).
  
[31]. P. Yampolsky, trans.. The [[Platform Sūtra]] of the [[Sixth Patriarch]] ({{Wiki|New York}}: {{Wiki|Columbia University Press}}, 1967).     
+
. P. [[Yampolsky]], trans.. The [[Platform Sūtra]] of the [[Sixth Patriarch]] ({{Wiki|New York}}: {{Wiki|Columbia University Press}}, 1967).     
[32]. For "[[Hui-Neng]]" one may therefore read "[[Shen-hui]]," the historical proponent and/or source of the [[teaching]] attributed to [[Hui-Neng]].       
+
. For "[[Hui-Neng]]" one may therefore read "[[Shen-hui]]," the historical proponent and/or source of the [[teaching]] attributed to [[Hui-Neng]].       
[33]. H. [[Dumoulin]], {{Wiki|History}} of [[Zen Buddhism]], P. Peachev, trans., ({{Wiki|New York}}: {{Wiki|Pantheon}}, 1963), 87.   
+
. H. [[Dumoulin]], {{Wiki|History}} of [[Zen Buddhism]], P. Peachev, trans., ({{Wiki|New York}}: {{Wiki|Pantheon}}, 1963), 87.   
[34]. Yampolsky. [[Platform Sūtra]]. p. 116.  
+
. [[Yampolsky]]. [[Platform Sūtra]]. p. 116.  
  
[35]. [[Dumoulin]], {{Wiki|History}} of [[Zen]], p. 95.   
+
. [[Dumoulin]], {{Wiki|History}} of [[Zen]], p. 95.   
[36]. Yampolsky. [[Platform Sutra]], p. 116.   
+
. [[Yampolsky]]. [[Platform Sutra]], p. 116.   
[37]. Ibid..p. 115.
+
. Ibid..p. 115.
  
[38]. G. [[Dharmasiri]], A [[Buddhist]] Critique of the {{Wiki|Christian}} {{Wiki|Concept}} of [[God]] ({{Wiki|Colombo}}, [[Sri Lanka]]: [[Lake]] House. 1975), pp. 199ff.
+
. G. [[Dharmasiri]], A [[Buddhist]] Critique of the {{Wiki|Christian}} {{Wiki|Concept}} of [[God]] ({{Wiki|Colombo}}, [[Sri Lanka]]: [[Lake]] House. 1975), pp. 199ff.
[39]. Jayatilleke, Early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Knowledge]], chap. 5.   
+
. [[Jayatilleke]], Early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Knowledge]], chap. 5.   
[40]. Obermiller, "A [[Sanskrit]] Ms.." p. 5.   
+
. Obermiller, "A [[Sanskrit]] Ms.." p. 5.   
[41]. A. K. Warder, [[Indian Buddhism]] ({{Wiki|Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1970). pp. 467f.   
+
. A. K. Warder, [[Indian Buddhism]] ({{Wiki|Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1970). pp. 467f.   
[42]. Ibid.,pp.477ff.  
+
. Ibid.,pp.477ff.  
  
[43]. [[Tucci]]. Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], pp. 173-175.   
+
. [[Tucci]]. Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], pp. 173-175.   
[44]. Ibid., pp. 175f.
+
. Ibid., pp. 175f.
[45]. Ibid- p. 60.
+
. Ibid- p. 60.
[46]. Ibid.. p, 105.  
+
. Ibid.. p, 105.  
 
   
 
   
[47]. Ibid., pp. 64. 103', 104-111.   
+
. Ibid., pp. 64. 103', 104-111.   
[48]. Ibid., pp. 104-111.   
+
. Ibid., pp. 104-111.   
[49]. Ibid.. p. 105.  
+
. Ibid.. p. 105.  
  
[50]. K, Potter, Presuppositions of [[India's]] [[Philosophies]] (Englewood Cliffs, {{Wiki|New Jersey}}: Prentice-Hall. 1963),pp.239f.   
+
. K, Potter, Presuppositions of [[India's]] [[Philosophies]] (Englewood Cliffs, {{Wiki|New Jersey}}: Prentice-Hall. 1963),pp.239f.   
[51]. Warder, [[Indian Buddhism]], pp. 476f.   
+
. Warder, [[Indian Buddhism]], pp. 476f.   
[52]. [[Tucci]], Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], p. 160.   
+
. [[Tucci]], Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], p. 160.   
[53]. Potter, Presuppositions, p. 233.           
+
. Potter, Presuppositions, p. 233.           
[54]. Ibid., p. 240.   
+
. Ibid., p. 240.   
[55]. Ibid., p. 233.  
+
. Ibid., p. 233.  
  
 
[56. Ibid., p. 141.     
 
[56. Ibid., p. 141.     
[57]. Warder, [[Indian Buddhism]], p. 468.   
+
. Warder, [[Indian Buddhism]], p. 468.   
[58]. Potter, Presuppositions, p. 194. Also [[Kalupahana]], [[Buddhist Philosophy]], pp. 138f., that [[Kamalaśīla]] held the [[principle]] of [[causality]] to be {{Wiki|central}} to [[Buddhist]] conceptions of [[reality]].   
+
. Potter, Presuppositions, p. 194. Also [[Kalupahana]], [[Buddhist Philosophy]], pp. 138f., that [[Kamalaśīla]] held the [[principle]] of [[causality]] to be {{Wiki|central}} to [[Buddhist]] conceptions of [[reality]].   
[59]. Warder, [[Indian Buddhism]], p. 468.  
+
. Warder, [[Indian Buddhism]], p. 468.  
 
   
 
   
[60]. T. [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]], [[Buddhist Logic]], 2 volumes ({{Wiki|New York}}: Dover, 1962 of original 1930), 1: 76f.   
+
. T. [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Stcherbatsky]], [[Buddhist Logic]], 2 volumes ({{Wiki|New York}}: Dover, 1962 of original 1930), 1: 76f.   
[61]. [[Tucci]], Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], p. 477.   
+
. [[Tucci]], Minor [[Buddhist Texts]], p. 477.   
[62]. Ibid., p. 170.   
+
. Ibid., p. 170.   
[63]. R. Gombrich. [[Precept]] and Practice. ({{Wiki|Oxford}}: {{Wiki|Oxford University Press}}, 1971), pp. 121f.   
+
. [[R. Gombrich]]. [[Precept]] and Practice. ({{Wiki|Oxford}}: {{Wiki|Oxford University Press}}, 1971), pp. 121f.   
[64]. C. Levi-Strauss, Structural {{Wiki|Anthropology}} ({{Wiki|New York}}: Doubleday, 1967), chaps. 1-4, 11,15, 16.  
+
. C. Levi-Strauss, Structural {{Wiki|Anthropology}} ({{Wiki|New York}}: Doubleday, 1967), chaps. 1-4, 11,15, 16.  
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
 
{{R}}
 
{{R}}
 
[[Category:Zen]]
 
[[Category:Zen]]
 
[[Category:Buddhist Studies]]
 
[[Category:Buddhist Studies]]

Revision as of 07:29, 2 March 2016

Zh 9665.JPG





 By Ivan Strenski
Ivan Strenski is an associate professor in the College, New London, Connecticut.

Note. This article was first read in another version at the International History of Religious Congress, August. 1975 at the University of Lancaster, Lancaster, England. All references to the life Pali Canon are given in standard form and are quoted from the translations of I. B. Horner, Middle Length Sayings, 3 volumes (London: Luzuc, 1959. 1957, 1954).

Philosophy East and West
v.30 n.1 (January 1980) pp.3-20

ZenPo5ems.jpg

In its history, the scholarly study of meditation has been the preserve of orientalists, historians and phenomenologists of religion, and, more recently, psychologists of consciousness. These investigators have, on the whole, been mindful of philological, textual, and descriptive matters. Little attention has been given to philosophical, theoretical, or sociological aspects of meditation. In particular, the many possible connections between characteristics of meditational practice and institutionalized theories of knowledge, brought to light in other areas by the sociology of knowledge, have been ignored.

Zenart3 4 94.jpg


By way of innovation, I want to see how epistemological perspectives might illuminate the shape of Buddhist attitudes toward the gradual or sudden attainment of enlightenment. Using a modified and rather informal structuralism, I want to compare the structures of institutionalized theories of knowledge with the structures of meditational practices and beliefs to see whether one might understand the characteristics of these practices and beliefs in terms of their underlying epistemological structure. I want to argue that one can plot the salient characteristics of meditational practices—here, whether enlightenment occurs gradually or suddenly—as symptoms of the presupposed structure of their institutionalized theory of knowledge.
But before embarking on the critical study of meditational practices we ought to first clarify just what the Buddhists themselves thought about gradual and sudden enlightenment, and how they conceived the relation of these aspects of meditational practice to their beliefs about the acquisition of knowledge.

Zen478l.jpg




==I. Approaches To The Problem Of Gradual Enlightenment And Sudden Enlightenment: Naturalism And Phenomenology==



Zen-Bu4hism.jpg

It is commonplace to read that Theravāda Buddhism teaches that nirvāna is attained gradually and that Chan or Zen Buddhism teaches 'sudden' enlightenment. Little is said about the bases for studying what such meditational claims mean, and less is said about the logical grammar of words as peculiar as 'gradual'. Typically, it is facilely assumed that this problem is merely a factual matter about temporal duration. On this view, to say enlightenment is gradual' usually means that it takes a long time for this quasi-mental state to occur.

Such a claim does not seem logically different than saying that it took a person a long time to get 'dizzy' or 'drunk,' and so on. Now, to put a factual stress on this matter should immediately strike anyone familiar with the pragmatic attitude of (early) Buddhism as odd. Surely, it must have been unedifying for an early Buddhist to be concerned with rather speculative matters of fact. Is this just an example of 'corruption' in early Buddhism, analogous to the storied medieval Christian scholastic problem of angels on the head of a pin? What could be the practical salvific value of talk of gradualism in various Buddhist contexts? What could have been the possible interest for an early Buddhist in saying that enlightenment was to be attained gradually?

Xin 9194.jpg


Despite such considerations, scholars of meditation have persisted in treating meditational discourses as mere descriptive matters of fact. This is true, even though these scholars disagree implicitly about what counts as a 'fact', or, perhaps more accurately, stress different views about what counts as a fact. Basically, two such emphases seem current. As applied to my earlier example of dizziness, one may take the fact of dizziness to be an experience in which case one might term such an approach 'phenomenological.' However, one might feel required to seek facts in some supposedly underlying neurophysiological process, in which case one might term such an approach 'naturalist.' Although both naturalist and phenomenologist would agree that temporal duration was crucial to the meaning of 'gradual', they would not agree about the nature of what endured in time.

X145.jpg


I am convinced both these approaches emphasize the wrong things about Buddhist gradualism—for whatever different reasons. Not only does the Pali Canon tell a more complete story, but another order of analysis of the texts is required. Basically, I believe those tempted by either of these two approaches mistake a norm for a matter of fact, and that where a fact may be indicated, it tends more often to be a spatial fact, rather than a temporal one. Although the temporal and the factual question may not be without interest, it does not seem to be the chief concern of the Pali Suttas. Here, the Buddha recommends a particular mode of life—an issue which reads far beyond any such unedifying factual matter of the speed of the attainment of nirvāna.

Tr-high-go chonb.jpg


Taking the temporal point first, it would seem important to note that the term 'gradual' is ordinarily used in two quite different ways: Insofar as 'gradual' is used factually, it may indeed mean something temporal, like 'slow.' But, it may also mean 'graded.' It may be a temporal word just as easily as it may be a spatial one. The same is true of the Pali term anupubba, as I shall show in the discussion of the Pali Canon's view of "gradual enlightenment. Thus, "gradual' is like other words that play across the temporal and spatial conditions of experience. Does a 'dashing' man need to be fleet of foot? Does a 'snappy' dresser need to be quick with buttons and zippers?

Although spatial and temporal uses of 'gradual' often coincide, they need not do so. Doing something gradually—by degrees, in stages—may take less time than trying to do the same task at one go. Gradual methods are, indeed, often devised to save time—say, in building a house, taming a horse, writing a book, or attaining nirvāna—especially when contrasted to available alternatives in achieving the same sophisticated result. Perhaps, part of the reason this spatial sense of 'gradual' escapes our attention may have something to do with the fact that the ordinary English contrast word, 'sudden,' does not seem to have a spatial sense at all. It only seems to have temporal uses, and thus by analogy, we think of 'gradual' in the same way. Attention to the contexts of the discourses on gradualism tells another story.

Tea-And-Zen.jpg

As one might emphasize either temporal or spatial aspects of gradualism so also have scholars of meditation emphasized different senses in which meditational forces are facts. Through their reliance on neurological research, the psychologists of consciousness exemplify a naturalistic approach. The question of gradual attainment of enlightenment would become a question to be settled by measuring the duration of 'extent' of certain neurological processes. Now, the psychologists of consciousness have not, to my knowledge, dealt with our particular problem. Yet, it would seem important—at least in passing—to represent their increasingly popular work in this context— even if I am forced to extrapolate from their more general work on meditation. They seem to exemplify an extreme contrast to the kind of epistemological approach I advocate, since they seem to avoid the whole issue of the theory-ladenness of meditational "facts."

Shuixin Zen CF8739.JPG

A characteristic of this loosely related group of writers is their reliance on quantitative neurological investigation of meditation. Typical of this view is the work of Dan Goleman. Here, EEGs supposedly get the investigator behind "abstract concept"—'the realm of discourse' (the beliefs and reports of meditators) to the "raw data." [1] Conveniently, this move (if possible) liberates the investigator from the need to deal with troublesome institutions, beliefs, theories, and critics! Thanks to the EEG one reaches the promised land-of-value-free inquiry. Consistent with this supralinguistic approach, no arguments will be found supporting such claims that a conceptually neutral realm has been reached. In their stead one finds pronouncements and decrees—poor surrogates for solutions to our awkward epistemological position. But, instead of evading epistemological issues, I believe we ought to face them squarely: What presuppositions, theories, beliefs, and institutions condition mystical or meditative experience? What sense can one make of truth claims made under such conditions?

Sha ung-fu.jpg


It is to the phenomenologists of religion, like Winston King, however, that one must look for the most direct discussion of our problem. In a comparison of Theravāda and Zen meditation, King concludes that there is really no difference between sudden and gradual attainments of enlightenment. As one might expect from a phenomenologist, King believes that there is in fact no difference, because there is no experiential difference between sudden and gradual attainment of enlightenment.

Sha 53924658.jpg

"suddenness" or "gradualness" of enlightenment ... appears to depend primarily upon emphasis and/or point of specification. One may choose to emphasize the prior preparation .. . and call it "gradual"; or one may stress the experiential breakthrough and call it "sudden." But in both Theravada and Zen, there are development and pinpointed breakthrough.

Samgak-san-07.jpg

For King, this virtually closes the case. If, however, one takes seriously the theory-ladenness of meditational experiences, the hard questions just begin. Why, indeed, the differences in "stress," as King himself is compelled to ask? Why the canonical, commentarial, and modern norm among Theravādins that nirvāna comes gradually? King's reply to his own question is couched in terms of "the Indian penchant for classification and analysis" versus the "Sino-Japanese impatience with metaphysical speculation and a fundamental reliance upon intuitional apprehension of existential truth." One wonders what the Buddha would say to the implication that he was not impatient with metaphysical speculation. Or what the Hua-Yen philosophers would say to the implication that they were not among the most supreme speculative metaphysicians of all time.

Samgak-san-06.jpg

But, like many cultural generalizations, King's also contains an unexpected germ of truth.

Surprisingly, King drops the matter at this point. Yet, one should not be altogether puzzled, since King's approach will not let him push beyond the reports of experiences to levels of structuring which may give rise to these experiences.

I want to suggest that an appreciation of fundamental attitudes toward knowledge may help stimulate understanding of these divergent views of what may or may not be identical processes or experiences- In part, I aim to reinforce Jayatilleke's views about early Buddhist empiricism by arguing that its underlying structural pervasiveness accounts for much of the character of early Buddhist belief in the gradual attainment of nirvāna.

Contrary to what Buddhist empiricists themselves might believe, I believe that their empiricist epistemology is symptomatic of a deep yet compromised empiricist structure.



S5onk.jpg

Ii. The Pali Canon On Gradualism



Pr1ctice3.jpg

The classical and principal discussions of gradualism occur in four places in the Majjhima Nikāya (MN). In two condensed analogies, the Buddha teaches what has become known crudely as "gradual enlightenment." Both these analogies—taming a thoroughbred colt (MN 1.445-446; MN III.1-6) and mastering complex skills (calculating and archery: MN III.1-6)—indicate much of the character of gradualism, which I shall explain shortly. In MN 1 (480-481), the Buddha deals directly with gradual attainment of paññā. Contrary to popular misconception, this shows that the distinction between gradual and sudden enlightenment differs from the distinction between those who attain nirvāna by paññā. and the jhānas, respectively. As the Buddha implies in MN I(478ff), the paññāvimutta seems to achieve nirvana immediately (in both spatial and temporal senses), because he has previously achieved those stages of sanctity which others may only now be set to achieve.

Pjnner1.jpg

    The compounds of the Pali anupubba (Skt., anu-pūrva) "gradual" are numerous, and occupy nearly three columns in Trenckner's Critical Pali Dictionary.[5] For the purposes of this article, I shall treat only the relevant compounds and deal with the pertinent aspects of their logical grammar. This pragmatic approach may leave the linguistic survey of these compounds incomplete, but I believe I have covered all pertinent issues from the philosophical point of view. The compounds of anupubba have both broad and narrow references: they may refer to the entire effort of attaining enlightenment as well as to the stages of meditational attainment and pedagogical practice.

Mpp ra-33.jpg


Thus, terms like anupubba-kārana, "gradual training," anupubba-kiriyā, "gradual working," anupubba-patipadā, "gradual progress, "anupubba-samā-patti, "gradual attainment," and anupubba-sikkhā, "gradual training" refer broadly to the systematic or successive character of the whole Buddhist way of life, from first silas to final release. Considering the narrower context of the jhānas, one completes a gradual cessation of consciousness (anupubba-nirodha), or one is said to come to dwell in certain graded levels of meditational abodes (anupubba-vihāra). Finally, one may speak about pedagogical matters, in what seems a prescriptive epistemological way, about the Buddha's normative gradual method of instruction (anupubba-kathā) and its correlative, the student's gradual method of study or training (anupubba-sikkhā).[6]

Mas5ter16.jpg


Some of these notions need explaining. The early Buddhists held definite beliefs about the details and reality of the mental landscape. The meditator was thought to ascend a graded trail of real, though impermanent, mental steps (jhānas), one after another, until the summit of nirvāna was won. It is true that nirvāna is not itself another jhāna and, that, strictly speaking, is not necessarily 'won' by meditation: it is not the causal product of the process of meditation. Yet, there is some relation between meditation and nirvāna, although the precise nature of it is often difficult to make out. More on this matter shortly. Moreover, the progress of the meditator through the jhānas was also thought to be open to precise location in terms of a psychological map of the real, though impermanent, mind.

Majgyen.jpg


To follow the Buddha meant, in part, to accept his map of the mind—at least provisionally for the purpose of testing its accuracy and its utility for attaining release. In meditation, these directions were, in turn, tested for their truth—although, of course, the question of vicious circularity is conveniently passed over by the Buddhists. One might also add that as the route to nirvāna by meditation was graded, so was the goal itself, in some sense, graded. Early Buddhist notions of levels of accomplishment, like "Streamwinner," "Once-returner," and so on, seem to point in the same direction of gradual-graded-attainment.

Ko5ino.jpg

Apart from these descriptive uses of the grades of attainment, two aspects of the early Buddhist attitude to saving knowledge are also termed "gradual" although in a different sense than we have seen thus far. The context of this new sense of "gradual" is the classical Buddhist milieu of learning and teaching. Gradual teaching or instruction (anupubba-kathā) refers to the Buddha's normative analytical and graded pedagogy.[7] This method of instruction exemplifies the Buddha's use of skill-in-means (upāya-kosalla0) [8] which, as Jayatilleke has argued, encompasses a kind of openness to falsification and corresponding obligation for verification.[9]

Ink45wing.jpg


Because of his compassionate care and sympathy for humanity and its physical and intellectual suffering, the Buddha prescribed teaching the dhamma in orderly and logical ways, tailored to the needs and capacities of his listeners, and open, in large measure, to dispute and verification. Although, at times he speaks in the didactic mode, the Buddha eschewed an abrupt, paradoxical, or esoteric mode, typical of the thwacks and slaps of some Zen Buddhist pedagogy and the later Mahāyāna uses of upāya, respectively.

Im;lages.jpg


From the perspective of the student, gradualism requires a correspondingly earnest methodical and analytic study of the dhamma. A student is responsible for testing and verifying the dhamma experientially. If one follows Jayatilleke here, epistemological gradualism—this attitude of experiential scrutiny—applies to all aspects of the dhamma—both to preliminary matters as well as to those which arise at rarified meditational levels.

One cannot then conclude that the gradual attainment of enlightenment primarily meant that nirvāna came slowly, or that it was the norm of the slow-witted. This, at any rate, is not the view of the Pali Canon. For the early Buddhists, gradualism was a complex notion, involving both the description of a graded model of the meditational and cognitive landscape, along with certain values or prescriptions about the proper epistemological attitude of scrutiny and experiential testing needed at all levels of the teaching and learning process of attaining release.

Hgmages.jpg


In another discussion on Theravāda meditation, Winston King underscores this opposition of description and prescription by repeating it in terms of the contrast between jhānic and vipāssanic aspects of meditation. Although these two aspects are "set in tension with each other," they also complement each other. Vipāssana (insight) supplies "critical awareness" of the jhānic attainments, a "reviewing of the path." The jhānic route thus describes a journey through a series of gradually ascending stages, while vipāssana censors and scrutinizes the quality of those achievements.

Ha4ddha.jpg


For King, the central question still remains why these two disciplines are combined at all. What is achieved by their combination in the trance of cessation (nirodha-sampātti), or in the Theravāda tradition as a whole? Once again King couches his explanation in experiential or phenomenological terms:

Gon4gfu13.jpg


The jhānic discipline contributes meditational expertise, which may strengthen the concentration of the vipassanic meditator ... and very importantly gives a quality of depth and lastingness of experiential attainment... . On the reverse sides, vipāssana keeps the whole jhānic progression within Buddhist bounds so that none of its utterly peaceful states will be construed as the final goal of meditation.

Flo 009.jpg


Now,I do not wish to quibble with these admirable conclusions. They strike me as sensitive and germane. Indeed. I should like to confirm them and also take them a step further beyond the phenomenological level which they occupy. I am urging the reader to consider that there are deeper reasons behind this felicitous conjunction of meditational modes, which I, first of all, identify as epistemological in nature. My 'hunch' is that the connection between the jhānic description of cognitive growth with the vipassanic epistemological scrutiny suggests a fundamental connection with a comprised empiricist syndrome recently spelled out by Ernest Gellner. There are parallels to the specific conjunction of the jhānic and vipāssanic modes of meditation in similar conjunctions in the general development of empiricist approaches to the growth of knowledge. Jhānic and vipāssanic modes of meditation are joined for the same reason similar aspects of the general empiricist theory of knowledge are joined.

Ea ilFP.jpg




==Iii. The "Ghost" Meets The "Machine"==



Dayi Daoxin.jpg

One can speak of an 'empiricist syndrome' today largely because it has been the subject of intense debate by modern epistemologists. This is perhaps especially true of north Atlantic analytic philosophy, although the ferment on the continent in Marxist and structuralist circles seems to focus on similar issues from the opposite philosophical shore. Among philosophers of science, Ernest Gellner has been particularly active in recent years in this area.


Gellner believes one ought to distinguish two moments in the life of empiricism as it has developed in certain favored contexts: empiricism is both a description of how knowledge works and a prescription about what ought to count as knowledge. As a description, empiricism offers a mere "toddler's toy" model, far too crude and simple to reflect the complexity of cognition; but, as a prescription, it provides a useful "touchstone," admirably stating a clear normative attitude toward the limits of cognition. In this latter sense, empiricism actsas a "censor" or "selector," laying downtwo imperatives: "Be sensitive to whether or not assertions are testable (in the specified approved manner)! Spurn those which are not". Gellner realizes that an empiricist would not typically recognize that empiricism itself rests of prescriptions. Indeed, part of what being an empiricist has meant in the past, has been bound up with the conviction that our cognitive situation is grounded in unbiased observations.


But, for Gellner and any one of the numerous critics of empiricism today, this is just not so.

As for the empiricist "toddler's toy" model, it can be summarized along the lines of an acquisitive enterprise. Beginning with an active external world and a passive internal one, the inner world of 'concepts' or 'knowledge' is built up by accumulating sense-data. But, since all one 'knows' consists of sense-data, the existence of a world behind sense-data becomes theoretically problematic, and unless something intervenes, one is led down the primrose path to phenomenalism and nominalism. In this condition one can still 'generalize,' by assembling sense-data into complex 'beliefs' or 'ideas' by 'induction.'

The truth of these beliefs is tested or verified by 'correspondence' with the facts of sense experience. This comparison of simple and complex is achieved through the process of 'analyzing' complex 'beliefs' into their constituent sense-data. Normative statements analyzed in this fashion reveal no world of 'good' or 'bad,' but mere pleasures, pains, or emotions. Science, especially in its reductionist and impersonalist moods, represents the kind of model explanation of the world of experience to which all other cognitive enterprises should aspire.

For Gellner, empiricism tends toward solipsism and eventually idealism—as long as it remains pure. After all, experience is just my experience. My experience is composed of private sense-data, and the existence of the external world is necessarily left in doubt. Yet, historically and, in Gellner's view, happily, empiricism did not in every case actually retain its purity and develop into idealism and solipsism; Bishop Berkeley was not the sole heir to the empiricist tradition.

The Utilitarians, Locke, Russell, and others, claim this birthright as well. Their thought embodies a salutary convergence of empiricism and materialism—the "ghost" and the "machine," in Gellner's words. These thinkers sought a "stable, recognisable structure that could somehow be reached through the qualitative sense-data available to the ghost." Because of their confidence in knowing the world, they also believed that the world was improvable, and that analysis and scrutiny were both worthwhile and appropriate activities for human beings.



==Iv. Early Buddhist Empiricism And Meditation==



Gellner's myth about this compromised empiricism fits remarkably well with K.. N. Jayatilleke's account of early Buddhist theory of knowledge—especially in the way it resists idealism (as later Buddhist thought does not) and allies itself with materialism. Early Buddhism populates the vacuum between experience and the otherwise noumenal world with real, though impermanent and causally conditioned, causally agent, material sense-data. These sense-data, in turn, activate the causally passive (initially, at any rate) and material mind, producing 'knowledge' of the world. For both Gellner and early Buddhism this convergence of "ghost" and "machine" reinforces the characteristic empiricist epistemological attitude of analysis. This analytic spirit—like perhaps the "spirit" of Protestantism or capitalism in Weber—fits with the spirit of the development of traditional empiricism and early Buddhism.

Both take the world seriously, because it is not illusory; both exhibit a "salutary censoriousness" which "seems only to come when cognitive hope and confidence have already been raised high." This is why both Gellner's compromised empiricism and early Buddhism (surprisingly and in different ways to be sure) lead to "puritanical orderly world-reform and cognitive exploration," rather than to Schopenhaurian pessimism, aestheticism, and mysticism, on the one hand, or to indulgent hippie grooviness, on the other.

To those who imagine Buddhism to be Schopenhaurian, pessimistic, mystical, and so on, this claim will come as a shock. And, it is true that much of the Buddhist tradition has been all these things. Yet, Jayatilleke's research, for one, has done much to rectify this image of Buddhism—at least as it seems to have taken shape in the Pali Canon. The Utilitarians, for example, "took the world seriously." But, this meant attention to political reform, technological development, and cognitive exploration in the natural sciences. With the early Buddhists, this earnest spirit took the form of individual ethical and psychological reform, the establishment of an alternative model society—the Buddhist monastic community, the Sanghacognitive exploration and therapy aimed at seeking the psychological roots of suffering morein the style of Freud and the psychotherapists.

This is not to deny the differences between Gellner's compromised empiricism and early Buddhist empiricism; it is only to show that they are not differences of "spirit." Moreover, in some ways, early Buddhism is even more optimistic than its counterparts in European empiricism. It stands for the possibility of the radical development of human cognitive potentials: Men can know the real nature of the world and nirvāna. This enlarges the range of experiential knowledge, taking in meditational states, kinds of ESP, and states transcendental to the ordinary man.

The cognitive optimism of early Buddhism rests, in turn, on the presuppositions underlying the theory of meditation outlined earlier. The Buddhists thought they knew how the mind worked and what techniques would best serve to enable it to work for human happiness. Insofar as early Buddhist meditation methods are concerned, they are specific to the compromised empiricist theory of knowledge spelled out by Gellner. One can, in fact, generate the model of early Buddhist meditation merely by reversing the order of the empiricist model of critical accumulation of sense-data. As one had gradually accumulated sense-data and passed them before the inner censor, the "ghost," before risking knowledge-claims, so also in meditation one gradually surpasses classes of sense-data experience and knowledge. Urged on by vipāssana criticism, the meditator presses along the jhānic route to higher meditational levels, completely stripped of sense-data information.

Thus, reliable ordinary knowledge as well as nirvāna require gradual, diligent, and critical attention—analytic care in sifting our perceptions and beliefs. In meditation, this becomes even more severe as the meditator empties the mind of these data, noting their content and form as they are transcended until nirvāna itself is attained. One is not typically encouraged to leap to conclusions (or nirvāna) in early Buddhism. One is invited to analyze and verify the dhamma experientially and ultimately in meditation. The meditator initiates a relentless and deliberate selection process, which seeks to liberate the perceiver from the bondage of the inward flowof causally agent sensations. In meditation, a Buddhist tries to understand sense-data, and therefore knowledge, in their own terms, and declare them for what they are.

All this makes for a measured and certain optimism about man's potential for salvation unaided by occult power or cosmic fate. In the context of this analytic, trial-and-error cognitive quest, one is advised not to expect rapid results, although these could, of course, occur. The early Buddhists encouraged persistence. Effort brought results. The point was to keep at it, to form the habits of mind and action which would surely (but not automatically) bring results.



==V. Gradual Enlightenment And Sudden Enlightenment: Historic Debates 1: China==



Thus far, I have tried to illuminate the nature of early Buddhist meditation and the belief in gradual enlightenment by appealing to the notion of early Buddhist empiricism. In a nutshell, I have argued that early Buddhist meditation theory is imbedded in a compromised empiricist epistemology and, as such, will reflect salient characteristics of this epistemological syndrome. Even though ordinary knowledge requires accumulating sense-data, both processes occur by 'gradual' means—in both the descriptive and prescriptive senses of that term. As a structuralist, I have shown that Gellner's compromised version of empiricism is homologous to early Buddhist empiricism in both descriptive and prescriptive dimensions.

Meditation in early Buddhism constitutes a counterpoint variant of this common theme, seeming for the most part a structural inversion of the empiricist statement about ordinary acquisition of knowledge.

The critical reader will want some test of this thesis. And, if structuralism is not to become just another occasion for clever dialectical shenanigans, structuralists must offer some check on their own method. The perfect test of this thesis would be a debate between a proponent of early Buddhist empiricism who held the gradualist position, and another kind of Buddhist who held the sudden position—typically a Rinzai Zen Buddhist. The nature of the test would be to see if one could correlate opposed beliefs about the attainment of enlightenment with opposed epistemological beliefs—understanding all the while that both kinds of epistemologies may operate in these contexts in compromised forms.
In the history of Buddhism, the issue of gradual and sudden enlightenment has arisen on two conspicuous occasions: the eighth-century controversies between the Northern and Southern schools of Ch'an Buddhism in China, and between the Indian and Chinese parties at the Council of bSamYas (792-794) (the so-called Council of Lhasa) in Tibet. Of the two, the Chinese controversy gives fullest treatment to the sudden position. Indeed, the focus classicus of the sudden view remains the Platform Sutra of the Sixth Patriarch, attributed to the 'victor' of the debate and founder of the Southern school of Ch'an, Hui-Neng (638-713). Thanks to Yampolsky's recent research of this text and its historical context, much has become clear. For one, Yampolsky argues that one should attribute the authorship of the sūtra to Shen-hui, one of Hui-Neng's disciples, rather than to the sixth patriarch himself. Together with Dumoulin's work in this area, one can be reasonably certain in correlating Hui-Neng's sudden theory of enlightenment with a certain epistemological-cum-ontological position opposed to that of early Buddhism.

We know that Hui-Neng (Shen-hui) taught the "sudden" attainment of enlightenment against the celebrated Ch'an teacher, and sixth patriarch according to the Northern school, Shen-hsiu. But, what did he mean? Dumoulin claims that Hui-Neng even makes it the sole criterion for orthodoxy! What can be contained in this cryptic claim to merit such importance? And what can explain the fierce attacks Hui-Neng aimed at Shen-hsiu? Well, Hui-Neng most certainly did not mean enlightenment was "easily obtainable" or even quickly won," although these were not ruled out. Like the early Buddhists, Hui-Neng had higher purposes in mind. Both were concerned to make certain points about human psychology and knowledge, using the idioms of temporal duration and spatial levels when these suited their purposes. Both seem to insist, quite often without apparent purpose, that enlightenment occurred in a way harmonious with their practices and basic views.

Dumoulin and Yampolsky agree that the belief in sudden enlightenment has two sides. Negatively, it denies that the goal, prajñā, can be produced by a "step-by-step process of meditation," dhyāna—odd, one would have thought, for the Dhyāna school (Ch'an) to assert. Positively, it was a way of asserting the truth of a priori nonduality—that prajñā is "something possessed from the outset by everyone." The point is to realize the imminent a priori nature of enlightenment and to let it shine through. Meditation cannot effect enlightenment because, strictly speaking, meditation and the passions it seeks to purge are ontologically empty and illusory.

Thus, at bottom, the doctrine of sudden enlightenment is a way of denying the jhanās and of asserting the a priori nature of enlightenment in the idiom of meditational practice. As the early Buddhists set out to operationalize early Buddhist empiricism with the descriptive and prescriptive senses of gradualism, so also does Hui-Neng seem intent on operationalizing his own philosophical position in the sudden view of the attainment of enlightenment: there are no real—even impermanent—grades of enlightenment; thus there is no need to test for a priori enlightenment, since all beings are enlightened by nature.
One will recall that the Pali Canon would certainly tell another kind of story. Although meditational progress through the jhanās does not causally produce nirvāna on the early Buddhist view, in conjunction with vipāssana, it is one important way to attain it. However impermanent they may be, one seeks to transcend the constraints of real (though impermanent) mind and world. Impermanence itself signals that progress can be made. But, early Buddhist soteriological optimism could not lead to the seemingly exaggerated optimism embodied in the belief in a priori enlightenment—that the battle was already won, or that virtually no battle needed to be fought. Nirvāna, on the other hand, transcends experience without being prior to experience. It is not, strictly speaking, posterior to experience either, since it is not, as it were, an inductive, empirical generalization, or caused by meditation.

If I may be permitted a neologism, the word 'transposterior' (to experience) may capture the flavor of the relationship of nirvāna to ordinary experience. By this I mean that nirvāna is not a priori, and only can be said to be a posteriori if one stipulates that it is held to transcend experience. Historically, this position may have arisen from conflict with brahminical rationalists, if we follow ppJayatilleke's[[ suggestion. What remains important is the early Buddhist aversion to apriorism —even if it meant constructing an empiricism which finally may have (to put it charitably) transcended itself in the special case of the nature of nirvana. Hui-Neng and the Southern school of Ch'an Buddhism felt no such aversion for the a priori. In fact, they celebrated it, and consequently thought that it merely had to be seen beneath the surface of an already illusory world. Enlightenment was sudden' because it was a priori and without even ontological competition from an impermanent world.



==Vi. Gradual Enlightenment and Sudden Enlightenment: Historic Debates Ii: Tibet==



The second classic locus of this debate is the late eighth-century controversy which occasioned the Council of bSam Yas (so-called Council of Lhasa).

Here, the Indian Mādhyamika logician, Kamalaśīla (742-804) argued a gradualist position against a Chinese Ch'an teacher, Hva San, and his Tibetan allies, the rDzogs-chen.

Far more importance is attached to this debate than may seem warranted. Yet, the issue was clearly thought to have been central to the subsequent development of Buddhism in Tibet. Our accounts of the debate records the point of view of the victor, in this case Kamalaśīla in his own Bhāvanākrama .

We learn little of the views of Hva-San and his company from this text and are thus led to speculate about their fuller form and the possible relationship with the earlier teachings of Hui-Neng and his school.

Although the connections between these two are not certain, many similarities of points of view can be established, which in themselves may point in the direction of relationship.

The interesting thing about Kamalaśīla is that he seems to argue a gradualism similar to what we have discovered in early Buddhist meditation but, at first sight, without sufficient theoretical basis to do so.

His philosophical position, as best one can make out from the often conflicting accounts of it, is exceedingly rich and complex.

He seems at once a Svatāntrika Mādhyamakin, Śūnyavādin, as well as logician and pragmatist in the tradition of Dharmakīrti.

Historians of Indian philosophy have also identified him as a critic of the Yogācārins. Kamalaśīla, himself, seems to recognize that these philosophical positions produce in him a certain amount of intellectual and practical tension.

This is so especially in connection with his desire both to acknowledge the transcendent primacy of Śūnyavāda monism, along with the rather mundane, though nonetheless wholehearted, devotion to the bodhisattva ideal of compassion and meditation.

What makes Kamalaśīla interesting then, is his conviction that enlightenment comes gradually and that one should press on with dhyāna and karunā, despite the awkward higher truth of the Śūnyatā.

This cannot have been a concern original to Kamalaśīla. Other Mādhyamikas must have shared it.

But, it must have been especially acute in th like Hui-Neng, taught sudden enlightenment in the sense that meditation in the progressive manner was unnecessary.

Perhaps reflecting the supposed Yogācāra background of Ch'an, Hva-San teaches the idealist view that thought is at the root of all se face of Hva-San's idealist monistic teachings which reflected no such qualms about pressing on with the worldly exercises of dhyāna and karūna.

One need merely stop thinking to stop suffering.

And thinking could be stopped suddenly—without progress through the jhānas or bodhisattvabhūmis.

In this way a priori enlightenment simply shines through. Hva-San sounds very much the Yogacārin or close relative of Hui-Neng's Ch'an Buddhism in this passage:

We ourselves [are] coessential with the Buddha, and all representations which constitute the world being illusory or a magic play of the Absolute....

What we need is only to jump ... from the plane of representations into that Buddhahood, our true nature, by sudden elimination of those mental representations.

We must arrest the play of their emanation, stop our mind, and see into our own nature.

But, what is it about having the Buddha-nature within us that requires a sudden interpretation of the attainment of enlightenment, along with the rejection of the jhānas, analysis, and the compassion of the bodhisattva?

Except for the doctrine of a priori enlightenment, grounded in the possession of the Buddha-nature, Kamalaśīla and Hva-San would seem to share at least the transcendental monism, characteristic of both Śūnyavāda and Yogācāra, respectively.

One will, of course, want to make appropriate qualifications for differences in these characteristics of the Absolute.

Yet, in spite of that, one wonders how and why Kamalaśīla can commit himself so thoroughly to the worldly practices of dhyāna and karūna, knowing full well that these are onto-logically insubstantial?

Has not Hva-San really drawn the natural consequences of transcendental monism?

Is not Kamalaśīla quixotically supporting some venerable, but outmoded, tradition of the sūtras, which by some kind of intellectual inertia, now soldiers on without adequate theoretical basis?

Tucci is one of the few scholars to have appreciated the awkwardness and poignancy of Kamalaśīla position.

But, his rather oblique solution to Kamalaśīla's quandry only precipitates a puzzle of his own. Speaking first of Hva-San, Tucci claims the sudden enlightenment doctrine follows from the simultaneous granting of ontological status to both abhūtapariikalpita ("power of subjective representation") and Śūnyatā.

By contrast, Kamalaśīla then would be said to hold gradualism because he maintains loyalty to Śūnyavāda monism by refusing to grant ontological status to anything but the Absolute.

Yet, it seems incoherent of Tucci to say that it is Hva-San's simultaneous admission of ontological status to both these principles which breaks "the monism of Mahāyāna," causing meditation to recede into the background and dictating a subitist view of the attainment of enlightenment.

If anything, the opposite should occur; if one breaks the monism of the Mahāyāna into such a dualism, how then can either of these realities pass away suddenly?

If the abhūtapariikalpita is empowered to project the world of representation, how does it also pass away in the face of sūnyatā which Tucci implies is ontologically distinct?

It seems that either the "monism of Mahāyāna" is not really broken, in which case Tucci's solution does not even get started, or that it is broken, in which case one is not yet enlightened, because one has not yet penetrated into sūnyatā.

Either way, Tucci does not seem to have succeeded in his aim. Moreover, in the fact of his own supposed monism Kamalaśīla's gradualism becomes all the more mysterious, and not less so.

I would merely point out that the text of the Bhāvanākrama gives no indication that Hva-San is any kind critic of monism.

And, if he were, he would probably prefer gradual enlightenment over the sudden view. Kamalaśīla, on the other hand, does give indications of having watered down the transcendental monism one might expect him to have observed.

This stems from Kamalaśīla's philosophical indebtedness to Bhāvaviveka and Dharmakīrti through his teacher, Sāntaraksita.

Potter and Warder argue independently that Kamalaśīla's thought represents a partial synthesis of the epistemological traditions of the Pramānavarttikam of Dharmakīrti and the Svatāntrika Mādhayamaka of Bhāvaviveka.

Taken together, these influences seem to confirm Kamalaśīla's belief in the worth of logic and analysis, against what Potter believes to have been the Yogācārin attempt to downgrade them.

Bhāvaviveka is said to have made this kind of point by advancing the unique view of graded levels of truth within sūnyatā—as well as within the empirical realm.

If this be monism, it is certainly highly modified.

To admit grades of being is virtually to admit kinds of being, which is really to break the purer forms of the monism of Mahāyāna.

For Dharmakīrti, the ontological basis of his positive attitude toward reason seems to be a certain materialist or physicalist—tending convictions.

Against the Yogācārins, Dharmakīrti argued the "relative independent reality of objects," and that reality has "arthakryātra, the character of doing something ... of making a difference."

Empirical perception (pratyakna) is therefore a pramāna (a means of knowledge), and '"effect of reality"' and not an illusion.

In this way Dharmakīrti undercuts any attempt to empower thought alone to make real changes in the status of a person seeking enlightenment.

The views of Bhāvaviveka and Dharmakīrti, then, seem remarkably similar to Kamalaśīla's conviction, throughout the Bhāvanākrama, that the world and ordinary knowledge could not merely be thought away,

but had to be undermined by serious meditative and analytic praxis.

Dharmakīrti even explicitly holds this view.

In Potter's words, "one obtains yogic insight ... by sharpening one's understanding or insight by meditation and dialectic,"

For both Dharmakīrti and Kamalaśīla this seemed also to mean that testing and a spirit of censoriousness (Gellner) become important. In classic empiricist style, Dharmakīrti believed a theory of knowledge ought to stand the test of experience" and "practice."

Quite probably reflecting this influence while quoting the sutras in his Nyāyabindupūrvapaksasanksipiti, Kamalaśīla reports the Buddha saying: " 0 Brethern! . .. never do accept my words from sheer reverential feelings! Let learned scholars test them... ."


In the Bhāvanākrama, Kamalaśīla himself brings meditation into play with experiential testing: "

Having thus ascertained reality by means of gnosis consisting in investigation, in order to make this evident, one should have recourse to the gnosis consisting in contemplation. .. ."


Kamalaśīla even seems to share the view of King about the complementary roles of the jhānas and vipāssana in Theravāda Buddhism. Here speaking of the jhānas in terms of samādhi,

Kamalaśīla seems to repeat the division of labor between these two branches of meditation which I also linked with Gellner's claims about the descriptive and prescriptive aspects of empiricism:

" ... when his mind has been taken hold of by the hand, as it were, of samādhi, the yogin, by using the sharper weapon of gnosis should root out the seeds of false imagination. .. ."

In these ways, Kamalaśīla seems to conform to much of the empiricist-cum-materiahst spirit of early Buddhism through the influence of Bhāvaviveka and Dharmakīrti.

To the extent that these empiricist and materialist tendencies inform Kamalaśīla's thinking about meditation one would explain Kamalaśīla's teaching of the doctrine of gradual attainment of enlightenment on the same grounds as I have tried to do with the early Buddhists.



==Vii. Conclusion: Belief, Practice, And Structure==



To gain a unifying structural insight into Kamalaśīla's situation I want to conclude this discussion by pushing beyond the rather straightforward discussion of the history and content of Kamalaśīla's thought.

Granted that Kamalaśīla was influenced by both Bhāvaviveka and Dharmakīrti, one might go on to ask what conditions of Kamalaśīla's practical situation reinforced his adherence to an empiricist and materialist-tending tradition?

Here, I want to suggest that Kamalaśīla's practical discipline of analysis and compassion may have 'fit' better with the world-view he inherited from Bhāvaviveka and Dharmakīrti,

and thus that, in consequence, it was favored. Kamalaśīla could not have been a pure Śūnyavādin Absolutist without suffering substantial disharmonies in his overall approach to the world.

Kamalaśīla may have thought and taught more like an empiricist-cum-materialist early Buddhist, partly because he also acted like one.

In taking the world of thought and being as at least provisionally real in meditation, analysis, and compassionate behavior, Kamalaśīla may very well have come to think about the appropriate means of release as gradual—much as did the early Buddhists.

I am suggesting that Kamalaśīla's belief in gradual enlightenment may have been connected to his practice in somewhat the same way some beliefs might be said to be induced by certain practices.

In the Buddhist tradition one thinks of the belief in the transcendental Buddha as having possibly been induced by the practice of buddhapūjā, which does not in itself require such a transcendental objectof worship.

Although buddhapūjā is, strictly speaking, an act of remembrance, such practices tend, quite often, to induce a belief in the existence of their object.

Gombrich suggests that in modern Theravādin countries one can observe this movement from mere recollection of the exemplary earthly life of the long-deceased historical Buddha to the belief in the transcendental existence of the Buddha, now thought to be available to human entreaties.

I do not believe these processes happen mechanically or through causal connections, as typically conceived.

Human culture seems too intricate and human beings too subtle for the mechanistic process to be the strongest candidate explanation here.

A likelier model might be one which takes its rise from Levi-Strauss: to the degree one finds structural affinities between practices and beliefs, perhaps one should consider such affinities either a working out of certain deep common structures, or perhaps related by a sort of formal or structural causality.

Men often do things for structural reasons—whether the structures lie behind the things in question or whether they operate on the same level.

In Kamalaśīla's case, he may have advocated the belief in gradual release and the practice of meditation, analysis, and compassion because of some deep common structure, or because either belief or practice were causally prior, and same in form.
    

This speculation suggests that a kind of formal causality may be at work in the passage from deeper levels of culture to other more accessible to common sense, or between things on the same level of culture.

In the context of Buddhist meditation and theories of release, I offer that one does not practice analytic methods of meditation and painstaking human compassion for lengths of time without having something of those activities 'rub off' on other levels of life—in our case the gradualist theory of the attainment of release.

(The same also goes for the effect of beliefs on practices.)

Among the things which 'rub off', I want to identify the notion of form or structure. Critical analytic meditational methods and serious concern for ordinary human well-being,

conform to the gradual kind of enlightenment, at once described as a graded route and prescribed as a critical, analytic censoriousness about claims to, knowledge.


NOTES

[1]. D. Goleman, "Perspectives on Psychology, Reality, and the Study of Consciousness." Journal of Transpersonal Psychology 4 (1974): 4.
[2]. W. King, "A Comparison of Theravāda and Zen Meditation." History of Religions, (1969); 310.
[3]. Ibid., p. 311.
 
[4]. K. N. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge (London: George Alien and Unwin, 1963). See also D. Kalupahana, "A Buddhist Tract on Empiric ism," Philosophy East and West 19, N6. 1 (1969). and Causality: The Central Philosophy of Buddhism (Honolulu: University of Hawaii, 1975) and Buddhist Philosophy (Honolulu: University of Hawaii, 1976).
[5]. V, Trenckner, A Critical Pali Dictionary, Volume 1 (Copenhagen: Royal Danish Academy of Sciences and Letters. 1924-1948): 201-202.

[6]. T. Rhys-Davids and W. Stede, eds., Pali Text Society's Pali English Dictionary (London: Luzac, 1966): 39.
[7]. Ibid., pp. 39,101. Nyanatiloka, Buddhist Dictionary (Colombo, Sri Lanka: Frewin, 1972): 17.
[8]. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge, p. 40.
[9]. Ibid., chap. 8.

. Ibid.,p- 277.
. Ibid., p. 466.
. W, King, "The Structure and Function of the Trance of Cessation in Theravada Meditation," manuscript read at Annual Meeting of the American Academy of Religion, Chicago, November, 1975.
. Ibid., p. 4.
 
. Ibid., p. 11.
. Ibid., p. 7.
. Ibid., p. 8.
. Ibid,, pp. 14f.
. E. Gellner, Legitimation of Belief (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974).
. Ibid., p. 36.
       
. Ibid.
. Ibid., pp. 32f.
. Ibid., p. 38.
. Ibid., p. 115.
. Ibid., chaps. 5, 6.
. Ibid., p. 124.
. A. K.. Warder, "Early Buddhism and Other Contemporary Systems," Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, 17 (1956); 43-63.
. Gellner, Legitimation, p. 120.
    
. P. De Silva, Buddhist and Freudian Psychology (Colombo: Lake House, 1974).
. R. Johanssen, The Psychology of Nirvana. (London: Alien and Unwin, 1969).
. P. Demieville, Le Concile du Lhasa (Paris: Imprimerie Nationale, 1952). E. Obermiller, "A Sanskrit Ms. from Tibet—Kamalasila's Bhavana-krama," Journal of the Greater India Society 2(1935): 1-11. G. Tucci, trans., Minor Buddhist Texts, Part 11. The First Bhavana-Krama of Kamalasila, Serie Orientale 9 (2) (Rome: Institute Italiano per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente, 1958).

. P. Yampolsky, trans.. The Platform Sūtra of the Sixth Patriarch (New York: Columbia University Press, 1967).
. For "Hui-Neng" one may therefore read "Shen-hui," the historical proponent and/or source of the teaching attributed to Hui-Neng.
. H. Dumoulin, History of Zen Buddhism, P. Peachev, trans., (New York: Pantheon, 1963), 87.
. Yampolsky. Platform Sūtra. p. 116.

. Dumoulin, History of Zen, p. 95.
. Yampolsky. Platform Sutra, p. 116.
. Ibid..p. 115.

. G. Dharmasiri, A Buddhist Critique of the Christian Concept of God (Colombo, Sri Lanka: Lake House. 1975), pp. 199ff.
. Jayatilleke, Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge, chap. 5.
. Obermiller, "A Sanskrit Ms.." p. 5.
. A. K. Warder, Indian Buddhism (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1970). pp. 467f.
. Ibid.,pp.477ff.

. Tucci. Minor Buddhist Texts, pp. 173-175.
. Ibid., pp. 175f.
. Ibid- p. 60.
. Ibid.. p, 105.
 
. Ibid., pp. 64. 103', 104-111.
. Ibid., pp. 104-111.
. Ibid.. p. 105.

. K, Potter, Presuppositions of India's Philosophies (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall. 1963),pp.239f.
. Warder, Indian Buddhism, pp. 476f.
. Tucci, Minor Buddhist Texts, p. 160.
. Potter, Presuppositions, p. 233.
. Ibid., p. 240.
. Ibid., p. 233.

[56. Ibid., p. 141.
. Warder, Indian Buddhism, p. 468.
. Potter, Presuppositions, p. 194. Also Kalupahana, Buddhist Philosophy, pp. 138f., that Kamalaśīla held the principle of causality to be central to Buddhist conceptions of reality.
. Warder, Indian Buddhism, p. 468.
 
. T. Stcherbatsky, Buddhist Logic, 2 volumes (New York: Dover, 1962 of original 1930), 1: 76f.
. Tucci, Minor Buddhist Texts, p. 477.
. Ibid., p. 170.
. R. Gombrich. Precept and Practice. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971), pp. 121f.
. C. Levi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology (New York: Doubleday, 1967), chaps. 1-4, 11,15, 16.

Source